You are on page 1of 10

J

FS
O
O
a certain rule or not. So, in a cognitive judg-
Judgment ment, one judges the object before one to be,
Linda M. G. Zerilli

PR
say, a table based on knowledge of the concept
and the ability to apply it. But cognitive judg-
Judgment as a crucial issue for political theory ments, though they can be politically relevant,
is longstanding. What it means to have good are not our main focus. We are more concerned
political judgment is a topic debated by ancient with judgments of right and wrong, bad and
D
to modern and contemporary thinkers as they good, just and unjust, etc. To declare a
attempt to answer that which most take to be particular war wrong, one first needs to know
TE

the premiere question of politics, namely, who that it is a war – hence a cognitive judgment is
should rule? If good judgment is equated with called for. But to declare that particular war
superior theoretical knowledge and the ability wrong or unjust, something else is required.
EC

to reason based on the grasp of universals, then On what basis do we make such judgments?
an argument for Plato’s “philosopher-kings” or In the Nicomachean Ethics, for example,
their modern equivalents can be made (Plato Aristotle (2009) puts forward the idea of phro-
1991). But if the power to judge is viewed more nesis, which is translated into Latin as pruden-
R

as the ability to know when concepts apply tia and which derives from jurisprudentia,
than to know the concepts themselves or, whose task is to judge or apply a law to a
R

further, to create concepts where they are lack- particular case. In English, phronesis is nor-
ing altogether, then it is not clear that knowing mally translated as “practical wisdom.” The
O

and acting appropriately are connected in the source of later modern and contemporary
way Plato assumed. accounts of judgment such as that of Hans-
C

Before turning to the different ways in which Georg Gadamer, Jürgen Habermas, Richard
political thinkers have linked the capacity to Bernstein, Ronald Beiner, and Seyla Benhabib,
N

judge with the question of rule, let’s get a bit phronesis becomes a way of questioning the
U

clearer about what is meant by the power of unity of knowing and acting, which constituted
judgment. In philosophical terms, judgment is the core of Plato’s ethics and his theory of
understood as the ability to apply concepts as politics. For Aristotle, by contrast with Plato,
rules to particulars, that is, to determine what practical wisdom (phronesis) is distinct from
something is by deciding whether it falls under theoretical wisdom (sophia). Phronesis is

The Encyclopedia of Political Thought, First Edition. Edited by Michael T. Gibbons.


© 2015 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Published 2015 by John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

0002106123.INDD 1 3/1/2014 9:05:45 PM


2 judgment

knowledge of a different kind from theoretic capacity for judgment and try to find another
knowledge, for it requires an ability to know public standard around which citizens might
how to judge and act in a particular context. It orient themselves? Or might we think of it as
is not just knowledge of universals but know- the occasion for exercising judgment reflec-
ing when to apply something universal to a tively, precisely in the absence of shared criteria
particular situation. Thus practical wisdom is or rules for making sense of the particulars
the ability to know how to judge and act in of  public life? Is good political judgment
a  concrete and, in principle, unrepeatable something that can be taught and learned? Is it
situation. Absent such practical knowledge, the a form of knowledge that can be systematized

FS
Platonic idea of the good becomes “an empty into a science?
generality” (Gadamer 2004: 312).
Judgment in Modern

O
The Problem of Judgment Political Thought

O
Notwithstanding their differences, what most In the view of Michel de Montaigne (1958
ancient thinkers (save the ancient skeptics) [1580]), uncritical reliance on custom too often

PR
share is the assumption that natural, transcen- guides our moral and political judgments.
dent standards of judgment exist and that they Wary of the Scholastic way of philosophizing,
can be applied by statesmen to the unstable, which took Aristotle as authoritative, and of a
contingent world of politics. It is this idea of university model of science that placed disci-
transcontextual criteria of judgment that ples in a hierarchical relation to masters and
D
comes into crisis in the modern period, giving did little more than confirm inherited beliefs,
rise to what might be called the problem of Montaigne called for the practice of free judg-
TE

judgment. For thinkers as diverse as Hannah ment. The freedom to philosophize, to criti-
Arendt, Isaiah Berlin, Jürgen Habermas, cally judge prevailing social and political
Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Michel de agreement, is stifled when we are bound to the
EC

Montaigne, and John Rawls, people do not task of justifying beliefs we already hold, rather
have access to natural or universally given cri- than opening our minds to the infinite variety
teria of judgment. This is a consequence of of beliefs that exist across human societies.
both the development of modern science, There are no universal rules of human conduct
R

which put the reliability of the senses into rad- and thus there is no way of systematizing
ical doubt, and the modern descriptive fact of beliefs, values, opinions, and practices into a
R

value pluralism. The idea that all individuals rational whole. The endless diversity of
reasoning properly will be led to the same con- humanity cannot be the object of a theory. To
O

clusions is no longer credible – which is not to exercise free judgment, argues Montaigne, one
say that it is no longer tempting; the idea of should actively seek out other opinions, many
C

perfectly attuned minds following the logic of of which can be discovered through the study
reason dies hard. In any case, modern and of different cultures. Skepticism as practiced by
N

especially contemporary political theorists are Montaigne does not lead to despair at the
U

writing in a context of a decayed rationalism, impossibility of absolute knowledge or to


in which the rules for judgment are no longer retreat from the public world altogether; rather,
obvious or given. a healthy skepticism towards received opinion
The decisive question is not whether these encourages a joyful openness to the world.
thinkers are right to highlight the loss of a Montaigne views the very idea of absolute
natural or shared criterion of judgment but, truth as deeply corrosive of human morals, for
rather, what consequences we should draw it leads towards an arrogant and intolerant atti-
from it. Should we think about that loss as tude towards other forms of belief, as indeed it
good reason to be deeply suspicious of citizens’ did in the persecution of heretics in his time.

0002106123.INDD 2 3/1/2014 9:05:45 PM


judgment 3

Deeply critical of the penchant to create such as John Locke. Like Hobbes, Locke argues
abstract theories that fail to take account of the that the move out of the state of nature into
myriad contingencies and particularities of civil society is based on the relinquishment of
human circumstances, Montaigne is suspicious each man’s right to judge in his own case and
not only of claims to absolute truth but also of the establishment of a public, authoritative
political actors whose practice of judgment is judge. So much does he share Hobbes’s con-
little more than that of subsuming particulars cern about the destructive effects of men’s
under universal rules. Often viewed as a rela- private judgment on a stable civil peace that,
tivist, he does not believe that a refusal to take in his early writings, Locke defends an account

FS
one’s own cultural standards as the rule leads to of absolute state power even in the case of a
a refusal or inability to judge at all. Rather, corrupt ruler (Locke 1967 [1660]). By contrast
a  comparative approach to cultures enables with Hobbes, however, Locke eventually

O
the  judging faculty to free itself from preju- comes to see that the capacity to judge, if
dices  and to develop itself as autonomous replaced wholly with the duty to obey, will

O
and critical. lead to the very anarchy and misery that obe-
Just this autonomy of judgment is what dience was supposed to contain. In his mature

PR
Thomas Hobbes (1994 [1651]) would curtail, and surely most famous political work, Two
for the power to judge in one’s own case is the Treatises on Government, Locke (1988 [1689])
source of the endless conflict and threat of argues that judgment both plays a crucial role
death that characterizes the state of nature in the development of liberal subjects whose
according to Hobbes. In this pre-political and desire is in accordance with the law and offers
D
pre-moral condition, there is no transcendent a crucial check on the exercise of the arbitrary
standard of judgment. Each has the right to power of the sovereign. Rather than divest cit-
TE

judge what is in his or her own best interest for izens of their right to judge, he seeks to bring
survival: “by natural law one is oneself the judge this all-important faculty in line with his
whether the means he is to use and the action vision of consensual government. Defining
EC

he intends to take are necessary to the preser- judgment as “the faculty which God has given
vation of his life and limbs or not” (Hobbes to man to supply the want of clear and certain
1998 [1642]: 27; emphasis in original). There is knowledge in cases where that cannot be had”
no normative account of what it means to judge (Locke 1979 [1690]: 653), Locke sees judg-
R

rightly in the state of nature, save what each ment as the faculty that enables us to find our
individual deems to be necessary in his or her way in the realm of the probable, as opposed to
R

own case. This supreme right of each to judge the certain, which is where human existence
produces a state of war. Thus the right to judge and especially the problems of politics are for
O

must be relinquished by the parties to the the most part housed.


social compact when they agree to create a sov- In their diverse accounts of judgment,
C

ereign as the condition of peace. The right to Montaigne, Hobbes, and Locke were respond-
judge is replaced by the duty to obey. The nor- ing to the problems of religious strife that
N

mative authority of the sovereign to judge in all accompanied the growing diversity of values in
U

matters may be arbitrary – it is the very creation the early modern period. Deep concern about
of the sovereign that establishes what is held to the wars of religion that indelibly shaped their
be true – but it is absolute nonetheless. thinking persists into the late modern period.
Although his solution is draconian, Hobbes Although value conflicts are no longer restricted
is not alone in worrying about citizens’ power to religious beliefs, the complex relationship
of autonomous judgment. The ambivalence between private and public judgment remains
with which most modern political thinkers a problem for all political theorists concerned
view this power can be seen in the work of the with democratic rule. Confronting the undeni-
social contract theorists who followed Hobbes, able empirical fact of value pluralism, such

0002106123.INDD 3 3/1/2014 9:05:45 PM


4 judgment

theorists are faced with the apparent dilemma creativity. In his view, judging is a natural
of how to respect the diversity of opinions and ability that can be practiced but cannot be
beliefs while maintaining the social order taught. It is the ability to bring particulars
required by a democratic society. If it is no under rules, but there is no rule, as Kant
longer possible, in the face of such diversity, to shrewdly observed, for how to follow a rule.
advance a substantive vision of the good as the Although Kant’s theory of judgment is
standard according to which we judge com- worked out in crucial respects in the first
peting points of view, then on what basis can Critique (published in 1781 and 1787) and the
public forms of judgment be established and second Critique (published in 1788), it is the

FS
citizens be said to judge? Surely it cannot be on third, the Critique of Judgment (1987 [1790]),
the basis of what is narrowly in the interest of which had the largest influence on Arendt and
each, for thinking that something is norma- many other political theorists writing on that

O
tively right (for me) does not make it right (for topic. In the first part of the text, Kant attempts
others). But how can one avoid subjectivism in to answer the longstanding question of what, if

O
judgments without falling back into a form of any, kind of validity aesthetic judgments could
objectivism, whereby the claim to validity is have. Rejecting the idea that such judgments

PR
based on the assumption that there are fixed were rule-governed and based on the objective
features of the world that are independent of criteria that characterizes the cognitive and
human judgment and to which such judgment moral judgments that he had examined in his
must be held accountable? earlier work, Kant nonetheless holds that they
are not merely subjective. Far from being mere
D
Twentieth Century Approaches preferences that make no claim on others (de
gustibus non disputandum est), judgments of
TE

to Judgment
taste have “subjective validity” (Kant 1987
This was the central problem that concerned [1790]: §§18–22). Examples of a rule that we
Hannah Arendt (1992), whose unfinished work cannot state, aesthetic judgments cannot compel
EC

on judgment has had a profound influence on agreement with proofs but nonetheless antici-
debates in the late modern period. For her, the pate the assent of all. The claim, “This painting
problem of judgment arises in the wake of the is beautiful,” is different from the claim, “I like
collapse of inherited criteria for judgment or canary wine,” says Kant. It would be ridiculous
R

what she called the final break in tradition that to say, this painting “is beautiful to me,” for a
marked the definitive political event of the judgment of beauty posits the assent of others.
R

twentieth century, namely totalitarianism. Likewise, when I say, “this war is unjust,” I state
Indeed, totalitarianism (which is characterized more than a mere preference. I do not mean, it is
O

by the breakdown of inherited moral standards unjust to me but, rather, everyone else too ought
and common sense), Arendt argued, is the par- to find it unjust. Whether everyone else does so
C

adigmatic political event that at once calls for find it is another matter.
our critical judgment and ruptures the entire If aesthetic judgments have an anticipatory
N

inherited framework of such judgment. How structure in Kant’s view, this structure is quite
U

shall we judge an event that has brought to light different from what he called “determinative
the ruin of our categories of thought and stan- judgments,” which entail the application of
dards of judgment, she asks. shared concepts as rules to particulars. Aesthetic
Arendt turned for help in these matters to judgments are a species of what Kant calls
Kant, the first major thinker who made judg- “reflective judgments,” that is, judgments where
ment a central topic of his work. The “power of the rule is not given and must be found.
judgment” is established in Kant’s theory as Whereas agreement in cognitive judgments is
a  distinct and autonomous faculty of the more or less guaranteed by the shared criteria
mind that is characterized by spontaneity and governing those judgments – if you know

0002106123.INDD 4 3/1/2014 9:05:46 PM


judgment 5

mathematics, you will agree that two plus two is to truth based on demonstration or proof, but
four, lest you be accused of making a mistake – are appeals to other citizens. Citing Kant,
aesthetic judgments cannot compel the assent Arendt emphasizes that judgments of taste are
of all. There is always the possibility that based on “an anticipated communication with
someone will disagree with my judgment of others with whom I know I must finally come
beauty and no proof can be invoked to settle the to some agreement” (Arendt 1993a: 221). This
dispute objectively. Each of us must judge for anticipated agreement relies on sensus commu-
ourselves, yet each of us also anticipates that nis, “the very opposite of ‘private feelings’,” sen-
others will agree. sus privates (222). These appeals, which

FS
The non-rule-governed character of aesthetic anticipate the consent of others, are con-
judgments was deeply appealing to Arendt, stitutive of a sense of political community, in
who sought to make the faculty of judgment her view.

O
answerable to human plurality and to the unre- Wherever people judge the things of the
peatable events that characterize the realm of world that are common to them, there is

O
human affairs. Philosophers, seeking eternal more implied in their judgments than these
truth, disparaged this realm as a site for devel- things. By his manner of judging, the person

PR
oping the capacity of judgment, she argued, for discloses to an extent also himself, what kind
everything in it was viewed as too contingent of person he is, and this disclosure, which is
to be of any use to the quest for knowledge. In involuntary, gains in validity to the degree
Kant Arendt found just this emphasis on the that it has liberated itself from individual
particular, which calls for our judgment in the idiosyncracies. (221)
D
absence of a rule. “If you say, ‘What a beautiful What one discovers in the act of judging, says
rose!’ you do not arrive at this judgment by first Arendt, is both one’s differences with some
TE

saying, ‘All roses are beautiful, this flower is a judging persons and one’s commonalities with
rose, hence this rose is beautiful’” (Arendt others. “We all know very well how quickly
1992: 13–14). What confronts you in a reflec- people recognize each other, and how unequiv-
EC

tive judgment is not the general category “rose,” ocally they can feel that they belong [or do not
but the particular, “this rose.” Ronald Beiner belong] to each other, when they discover [or
explains: fail to discover] a kinship in questions of what
pleases and displeases” (223). Based in taste, the
R

Reflective judgment means attending to the


unique qualities of the particular, to the “it-pleases-or-displeases-me,” judging allows
differences and commonalities to emerge that
R

particular qua particular, rather than simply


subsuming particulars under some universal are by no means given in advance of the act
formula. Or, as Arendt would put it, judgment itself. Arendt refuses to specify what values
O

involves attending to the particular as an end must already be in place to serve as the ground
in itself – that is, as a singular locus of meaning for community. Judging may well call into
C

that isn’t reducible to universal causes or question my sense of political community with
universal consequences. (Beiner 2001: 94) some citizens and reveal a new sense of
N

That this rose is beautiful is not given in the community with others.
U

universal nature of roses. The claim about This discovery of community is not guaran-
beauty is not grounded in a property of the teed by the kind of rule-following Arendt asso-
object, which could be objectively ascertained ciates with what Kant calls a “determinative
(as is the case with cognitive judgments); such judgment,” i.e., a judgment in which a particular
a claim belongs to the structure of feeling is subsumed under a universal (Kant 1987
rather than concepts. This rose is beautiful [1790]: 18). The rule-following associated with
because it is judged to be beautiful. determinative (logical) judgments, says Arendt,
For Arendt, political judgments are like compels everyone who has the power of reason
aesthetic judgments in that they are not claims and could just as well be discovered in solitude.

0002106123.INDD 5 3/1/2014 9:05:46 PM


6 judgment

Political objectivity requires not simply that one The limits of a decisionistic treatment of
“be in agreement with one’s own self [logic’s practical questions are overcome as soon as
principle of noncontradiction], but … consist[s] argumentation is expected to test the general-
of being able to ‘think in the place of everybody izability of interests, instead of being resigned
to an impenetrable pluralism of apparently
else,’” she writes (Arendt 1993a: 220). That is what
ultimate value orientations. It is not the fact
it means “to see politically” (Arendt 1993c: 96).
of this pluralism that is here disputed, but the
The origins of this political way of seeing lie in assertion that it is impossible to separate by
“Homeric objectivity” (i.e., the ability to see the argumentation generalizable interests from
same thing from opposite points of view: to see those that remain particular. (Habermas

FS
the Trojan War from the standpoint of both of 1975: 108)
its greatest protagonists, Achilles and Hector)
(Arendt 1993b: 51). This is different from the Public reason, as it is elaborated in a “discourse
ethics” and grounded in certain universal

O
kind of seeing that ends with the cognition of
an object, which involves not seeing from the ontological assumptions about the intrinsically
rational and rule-governed structure of human

O
viewpoints of others, but the ability to subsume
particulars under rules. communication, becomes Habermas’s answer
to the threat of relativism and decisionism that

PR
Judgment raises the problem of what delibera-
tive democrats such as Habermas call intersub- he associates with the collapse of transcendent
jective validity. As Jennifer Nedelsky puts it, Kant criteria of judgment in the context of moder-
nity’s irreducible value pluralism.
identified the central problem of judgment: Rawls resists positing what he calls Habermas’s
how can a judgment that is genuinely and
D
comprehensive “philosophical analysis of the
irreducibly subjective also be valid. What
presuppositions of rational discourse” and
does the claim of validity mean if we do not
TE

transmute the subjective into something


restricts himself rather to articulating the limited
objective – and thus lose the essence of judg- idea of the “politically reasonable” (Rawls 1995:
ment as distinct from ascertaining a truth 139). Like Habermas, however, Rawls is equally
concerned with defending democratic values
EC

that can be demonstrably, and thus compel-


lingly proven? (Nedelsky 2001: 104) that reflect more than the convictions of his
How can we decide which judgments are political culture and that can instead, as
correct if the mark of political judgments is Habermas puts it, “lay claim to some sort of
R

that they cannot be adjudicated in the same normative binding force” (Habermas 1995: 124).
manner as truth claims, that is, by means of On what basis can liberal-democratic values be
R

universal criteria and the subsumption of par- defended? Though both of these thinkers reject
ticulars under rules? an objectivist conception of truth as a way of
O

In the context of modernity’s widespread grounding political judgments, they nonetheless


value pluralism, this question takes on particular seek ways of circumventing the threat of deci-
C

urgency, for it raises the threat of relativism sionism and relativism that they associate with
and decisionism. A critic of Arendt’s turn to the otherwise commendable loss of a transcen-
N

Kant’s third Critique for its rejection of truth dent standard of judgment.
U

criteria, Habermas argues that without these Judgment and the Question
we would have no way to adjudicate competing
of Objectivity
claims. The problem is not the plurality of
claims as such, which is a mark of a democratic The problem, in short, is how to rethink objec-
society, but the absence of a procedure tivity once transcendent criteria have collapsed
according to which one could judge their in the face of modern historicist presupposi-
validity. Needed is a procedure according to tions about value-centered judging. Once we
which we can decide on a rational rather than a see that judging is not possible from an abstract
decisionistic basis. Writes Habermas: point of view, devoid of human subjectivity

0002106123.INDD 6 3/1/2014 9:05:46 PM


judgment 7

and interests (as Kant first argued); once we to optimize agreement between ourselves and
see, further, that “the ways in which human those whom we try to interpret by taking for
minds conceptualize and apprehend reality are granted that they hold true beliefs.
plural and not single, and that culture and lan- Powerfully challenged in Davidson’s essay is
guage appear to play a major role in shaping a picture of the relation of language and world
categories we recognize,” as Martha Nussbaum that takes language to comprise a scheme of
describes the challenge to the “Kantian con- concepts that organizes an otherwise unstruc-
sensus” in her essay “Political Objectivity,” then tured world. According to the picture, the
we seem to “focus increasingly on the relativity scheme of concepts can be understood inde-

FS
of all judgments to a conceptual scheme, and pendently of the world to which it can give
on the human and cultural-historical character structure. On this view, judgment is seen as
of conceptual schemes” (Nussbaum 2001: 884). employing concepts to shape what is otherwise

O
The idea of a conceptual scheme as a way of meaningless experience. The problem with this
thinking about value-centered judging has way of thinking about the exercise of judg-

O
been at the heart of many debates in philos- ment, as the philosopher John McDowell has
ophy, anthropology, philosophy of science, and argued, is that our concepts seem to be

PR
linguistics. The basic idea, derived from a “spinning in a frictionless void,” as if they were
certain reading of Kant, is that what we know in no way answerable to the way things actually
of the world is based on our ability to process are in the world (McDowell 1996: 11). We do
external stimuli through concepts given by the better to think about experience as always
understanding. Insofar as concepts are seen as already conceptualized, rather than as raw
D
culturally and historically derived, people material awaiting conceptualization. The
living in very different cultures might well capacity to judge, in other words, is always
TE

judge the same empirical stimuli differently. As already in contact with the world, not an impo-
Donald Davidson, explains: sition of form on it. This is the true insight of
Conceptual schemes, we are told, are ways of
Kant, argues McDowell.
EC

organizing experience; they are systems of For political theorists, the intricacies of these
categories that give form to the data of sensa- philosophical debates about the nature of judg-
tion . . . There may be no translating from one ment may seem extrinsic to the subject matter
scheme to another, in which case the beliefs, of politics. But to the extent that such debates
R

desires, hopes and bits of knowledge that bear on the question of what it means to speak
characterize one person have no true coun- about a shared or common world as the basis
R

terparts for the subscriber to another scheme: for judging, philosophical accounts can cer-
what counts as real in one system may not in tainly be relevant. That said, the central ques-
O

another. (Davidson 1973–4: 5)


tions for political theory remain unanswered
In Davidson’s well-known critique, the very by most philosophical accounts of judgment,
C

idea of conceptual scheme relativism is inco- for these tend to concern themselves with dis-
herent. The condition of recognizing a puta- cerning stable features of the judging faculty
N

tively alternative conceptual scheme is our itself, whereas what matters for politics is the
U

ability to translate it into our own language. ever-changing, contingent context in which
But if we are able to so translate it, then we judgments are made.
cannot really maintain that it is an alternative
conceptual scheme. Davidson condenses this
Judging as a Democratic Practice
point into what he calls the “principle of
charity” that guides radical interpretation – When Isaiah Berlin writes that the mark of
our attempt to interpret a completely unknown good political judgment is the ability to “grasp
language. Making sense of someone means the unique combination of characteristics that
treating him or her as a rational agent. We try constitute this particular situation – this and no

0002106123.INDD 7 3/1/2014 9:05:46 PM


8 judgment

other,” he highlights the irreducible importance Contemporary liberal-democratic theory


of an ability to respond to what is specific and remains ambivalent towards each individual’s
unrepeatable in any context (Berlin 1998: 45). capacity to judge (Zerilli 2005; Garsten 2006;
Like Arendt, Berlin sees the capacity to judge Yack 2006; Casson 2011). Indeed, the problem of
without reliance on universal standards as cru- judgment can rightly be said to haunt liberal-
cial to democratic societies characterized by democratic thinkers. On the one hand, the future
widespread value pluralism. And though he of liberal-democratic regimes depends on the
does not turn to Kant in these matters, Berlin good political judgment of citizens, for without
clearly shares Arendt’s view that the kind of the continual vigilance that such judgment

FS
judging ability at stake in politics is not based enables, tyranny can easily take hold. On the
on “laws to be discovered, rules to be learnt” other hand, this dependence of liberal democracy
(40). The misguided tendency to think of good on the practice of citizen judgment rests uneasy

O
political judgment on the model of a science, he with most of its advocates, for lurking in the
argues, is symptomatic of the way in which the background they see each citizen secretly desiring

O
methods of the natural sciences have come to and perhaps actively seeking to be judge in his or
define what counts as rational behavior. But this her own case. If liberal-democratic government

PR
approach deprives political judgment of its sub- relies on the habits and dispositions of its citizens
ject matter, which is human action, for it treats and not just on the supposedly universal truth of
such action as subject to the same laws as liberal-democratic principles (Casson 2011),
natural occurrences, whereas action is charac- then there is no way around judgment as a crucial
terized by contingency. The idea that there is quotidian practice of civic life. Returning to the
D
one kind of rationality suited to all forms of earlier connection between the capacity to judge
human endeavor is the legacy of “monism – the and the question of political rule, we might say
TE

ancient belief that there is a single harmony of that at stake in learning to judge critically and
truths into which everything, if it is genuine, in reflectively, that is, in the absence of transcendent
the end must fit.” This “enemy of pluralism” can criteria of judgment, is the fundamental idea of
EC

never generate good political judgment, for it is democracy as rule by the people. Where that
indifferent to the particular (Berlin 2001: 14). practical truth leads depends on the thinker, but
Berlin’s advocacy of pluralism has been seen most are deeply cautious at best.
as defenseless against relativism in judgments,
R

but he is quite adamant that his comparative SEE ALSO: Arendt, Hannah (1906–75); Aristotle
approach does not reduce to the view that every (384–322 bce); Berlin, Isaiah (1909–98); Habermas,
R

opinion, practice, or belief is just as good as any Jürgen (1929–); Hobbes, Thomas (1588–1679); Kant,
other. There are certain values that are objec- Immanuel (1724–1804); Locke, John (1632–1704);
O

Montaigne, Michel de (1533–92); Nussbaum,


tively human for Berlin, values that cannot be
Martha Craven (1947–); Rawls, John (1921–2002)
breached without violating the human in his
C

view. Leo Strauss famously accuses Berlin of not References


acknowledging the dogmatic bottom line of his
N

pluralism: the value of negative liberty is not Arendt, H. (1992) Lectures on Kant’s Political
Philosophy, ed. R. Beiner. Chicago: Chicago
U

just one among many values for Berlin, argues


University Press.
Strauss, it is an absolute value for which Berlin
Arendt, H. (1993a) “The Crisis in Culture.” In
takes a final stand (Strauss 1989). Whether or
H. Arendt, Between Past and Future: Eight
not Strauss is right in his reading, what becomes Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Penguin
clear in Berlin’s work is that judgment arises as Books, pp. 197–226.
a problem for political theorists in response to Arendt, H. (1993b) “The Concept of History.” In
the loss of transcendental criteria, and this H. Arendt, Between Past and Future: Eight
problem admits of no easy answer in the con- Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Penguin
text of modernity’s value pluralism. Books, pp. 41–90.

0002106123.INDD 8 3/1/2014 9:05:46 PM


judgment 9

Arendt, H. (1993c) Was ist Politik? ed. U. Ludz. Locke, J. (1988 [1689]) Two Treatises of
Munich: Piper Verlag. Government, ed. P. Laslett. Cambridge:
Aristotle. (2009) The Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Cambridge University Press.
D. Ross, trans. L. Brown. Oxford: Oxford McDowell, J. (1996) Mind and World. Cambridge,
University Press. MA: Harvard University Press.
Beiner, R. (2001) “Rereading Hannah Arendt’s Kant Montaigne, M. de (1958 [1580]) The Complete
Lectures.” In R. Beiner and J. Nedelsky (Eds.), Essays of Montaigne, trans. D. M. Frame.
Judgment, Imagination, and Politics: Themes from Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Kant and Arendt. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Nedelsky, J. (2001) “Judgment, Diversity, and
Littlefield, pp. 91–102. Relational Autonomy.” In R. Beiner and

FS
Berlin, I. (1998) “On Political Judgment.” In J. Nedelsky (Eds.), Judgment, Imagination,
I. Berlin, The Sense of Reality: Studies in and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt.
Ideas and Their History, ed. H. Harvey. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield,

O
New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux, pp. 103–20.
pp. 40–53. Nussbaum, M. (2001) “Political Objectivity,”
Berlin, I. (2001). “My Intellectual Path.” In New Literary History, 32 (4), 883–906.

O
I. Berlin, The Power of Ideas, ed. H. Harvey. Plato. (1991) The Republic of Plato, ed. A. Bloom.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, New York: Basic Books.

PR
pp. 1–23. Rawls, J. (1995) “Political Liberalism: Reply to
Casson, D. J. (2011) Liberating Judgment: Habermas,” The Journal of Philosophy, 92 (2),
Fanatics, Skeptics, and John Locke’s Politics 132–80.
of Probability. Princeton: Princeton Strauss, L. (1989) “Relativism.” In T. L. Pangle
University Press. (Ed.), The Rebirth of Classical Political
D
Davidson, D. (1973–4) “On the Very Idea of a Rationalism: An Introduction to the Thought of
Conceptual Scheme,” Proceedings and Addresses Leo Strauss. Chicago: University of Chicago
TE

of the American Philosophical Association, Press, pp. 13–26.


47, 5–20. Yack, B. (2006) “Rhetoric and Public Reasoning:
Gadamer, H.-G. (2004) Truth and Method, trans. An Aristotelian Understanding of
EC

J. Weinsheimer and D. G. Marshall. London: Political Deliberation,” Political Theory,


Continuum. 34 (4), 417–38.
Garsten, B. (2006) Saving Persuasion: A Defense of Zerilli, L. M. G. (2005) Feminism and the Abyss
Rhetoric and Judgment. Cambridge, MA: of Freedom. Chicago: University of
R

Harvard University Press. Chicago Press.


Habermas, J. (1975) Legitimation Crisis. Boston:
Beacon Press.
R

Further Reading
Habermas, J. (1995) “Reconciliation Through the
Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls’s Arendt, H. (2003) Responsibility and Judgment.
O

Political Liberalism,” The Journal of Philosophy, New York: Schocken.


92 (3), 109–31. Benhabib, S. (2003) The Reluctant Modernism of
C

Hobbes, T. (1994 [1651]) Leviathan, ed. E. Curley. Hannah Arendt. Lanham, MD: Rowman and
Indianapolis: Hackett. Littlefield.
N

Hobbes, T. (1998 [1642]) On the Citizen, ed. Ferguson, K. (1999) The Politics of Judgment:
R. Tuck and M. Silverthorne. Cambridge: Aesthetics, Identity, and Political Theory. Lanham,
U

Cambridge University Press. MD: Lexington.


Kant, I. (1987 [1790]) Critique of Judgment, trans. Ferrara, A. (2008) The Force of the Example:
W. S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett. Explorations in the Paradigm of Judgment.
Locke, J. (1967 [1660]) Two Tracts on Government, New York: Columbia University Press.
ed. P. Abrams. London: Cambridge University Habermas, J. (1994) “Hannah Arendt’s
Press. Communications Concept of Power.” In
Locke, J. (1979 [1690]) An Essay concerning Human L. Hinchman and S. Hinchman (Eds.), Hannah
Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Arendt, Critical Essays. Albany: SUNY Press,
Oxford University Press. pp. 211–30.

0002106123.INDD 9 3/1/2014 9:05:46 PM


10 judgment

Habermas, J. (1996) Between Facts and Norms: Rawls, J. (1993) Political Liberalism. New York:
Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Columbia University Press.
Law and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Steinberger, P. (1993) The Concept of Political
MIT Press. Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
McClure, K. (1996) Judging Rights: Lockean Politics Tetlock, P. (2005) Expert Political Judgment: How
and the Limits of Consent. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Good Is It? How Can We Know? Princeton:
University Press. Princeton University Press.

Abstract

FS
Judgment as a crucial issue for political theory is longstanding. What it means to have good political
judgment is a topic debated by ancient to modern and contemporary thinkers as they attempt to
answer that which most take to be the premiere question of politics, namely, who should rule? If

O
good judgment is equated with superior theoretical knowledge and the ability to reason based on
the grasp of universals, then an argument for Plato’s “philosopher-kings” or their modern equiva-

O
lents can be made. But if the power to judge is viewed more as the ability to know when concepts
apply than to know the concepts themselves or, further, to create concepts where they are lacking

PR
altogether, then it is not clear that knowing and acting appropriately are connected in the way Plato
assumed.

Keywords: citizenship, democratic theory, foundationalism, judgment, pluralism, political theory


D
TE
EC
R
R
O
C
N
U

0002106123.INDD 10 3/1/2014 9:05:47 PM

You might also like