You are on page 1of 10

Schenkerian Theory's Empiricist Image

MARK DEBELLIS

Drawing on logical positivism and recent philosophy, Matthew Brown, Douglas Dempster, and
Dave Headlam interpret Schenkerian theory as empirical science. They view the theory as a gen-
erative system. An empirical theory of music would have the virtue of being intersubjective and
grounded in sense experience. But Brown et al. do not specify a generative system in terms explicit
or rigorous enough to yield a theory that is observationally adequate. Their test of the #IV(W)
Hypothesis, which relies on the notion of a plausible interpretation, is inconsistent with the generative-
system view. Because that view does not account for what it is for an analysis to be correct or incor-
rect, it fails as a rational reconstruction. If Schenkerian theory is empirical, then its analytical terms
should be regarded not as theoretical, but as observational. That construal is plausible, however, only
if theorists' arrival at judgments about structure is best explained on the hypothesis that the works
really do have that structure.

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


Keywords: Schenker, empiricism, metatheory, science, philosophy

B OTH INDIVIDUALLY AND IN VARIOUS COMBINATIONS,


Matthew Brown, Douglas Dempster, and Dave Headlam
an empirical theory to be one that is testable, that is, it makes
predictions that may confirm or disconfirm it.4 Such predictions
have argued that Schenkerian theory is an empirical, are based on laws, or "law-like generalization[s]."5 (Laws are an
scientific theory of the kind outlined in positivist or logical- essential element in Carl Hempel's deductive-nomological
empiricist philosophy.1 The question of whether Schenkerian model of scientific explanation, on which model Brown et al. lay
theory is empirical is foundational and important, and we are great, perhaps excessive, emphasis.6) In addition, Brown et al.
indebted to Brown et al. for raising it. In this article I shall ex- take Schenkerian theory to be (at least approximately) empiri-
amine the claim and their arguments for it, and point out some cally adequate,7 which is to say that it makes true, and only true,
difficulties with their interpretation. I shall go on to suggest— predictions.
with some caveats—that, if Schenkerian theory is. indeed to be More specifically, Brown et al. regard Schenkerian theory as
understood as empirical and scientific, then we should con- a generative system, or, rather, as a theory based on such a sys-
ceive of analyses and their theoretical role in a way different tem. In their view, Schenkerian theory "claims that any piece of
from that of Brown et al. music is tonal if and only if it is derivable within [a certain axi-
omatic] system."8 In that system, "any complete, continuous,
I. BROWN ET AL.'S INTERPRETATION OF SCHENKERIAN functional monotonal piece can be generated from a single pro-
THEORY AS EMPIRICAL totype by the recursive application of certain transformations",9
moreover, the system generates "all and only" such pieces.1°
Brown et al.'s conception of empirical science stems from a Brown et al.'s conception of Schenkerian theory is, then, es-
movement known as logical empiricism, or logical positivism, sentially that of an (at least) observationally adequate generative
which included such figures as Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, grammar. A grammar for a language is observationally adequate
Otto Neurath (all members of the Vienna Circle), and Hans if it generates all and only the sentences of the language, that is,
Reichenbach.2 Brown et al.'s assimilation of Schenkerian theory utterances that would be judged grammatical by a qualified
to this framework is offered not as exegesis, but as rational recon-
struction.3 Following empiricist tenets, Brown et al. understand
4 Brown (2005, 12); Brown and Dempster (1990, 69); cf. Hempel (1965, 3).
5 Brown and Dempster (1989, 69); cf. Hempel (1965, 264-65). Not all em-
I am indebted to Joseph Dubiel and Dmitri Tymoczko for advice and pirical theories need be scientific, but Brown et al. do not put much weight
criticism. on the distinction, and neither shall I, or at least not until the last section
Brown (2005, 1-25), Brown et al. (1997), Brown (1997, 340-341), Demp- of this article.
ster and Brown (1990, 256-260), and Brown and Dempster (1989, 85-92). 6 Brown and Dempster (1989, 68-69 and 96). In Hempel's deductive-nomo-
2 For useful background, see Ray (2000), Salmon (2000), Passmore (1967), logical model, an event is explained by deducing its occurrence from laws
and Suppe (1977, 3-56). Some writers treat the terms "logical empiricism" and initial conditions (or other particular facts); see Hempel (1965, 232
and "logical positivism" as synonymous, though others, e.g. Salmon, do not; and 336).
I draw no distinction. 7 Brown and Dempster (1989, 88 and 92-93).
3 Brown et al. (1997, 156, Note 2), citing Brown (1989). For the notion of 8 Ibid. (88).
rational reconstruction, see Carnap (1967, v), and, for useful discussion, 9 Brown (2005, 91).
Beaney (2004, 125-28). Ibid. (12 and 67).

III
II2 MUSIC THEORY SPECTRUM 32 (20I0)

B: tonal, not generated POSTULATES

PRIMITIVE
CONCEPTS

• I A: generated, not tonal i


1 1 DEFINED
CONCEPTS
n 1

Tonal Generated

EXAMPLE I. A generative system that is not observationally adequate EMPIRICAL


1 CONCEPTS

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


"SOIL" of
OBSERVATION
(EXPERIENCE)

EXAMPLE 3. The positivist picture of a scientc theory.


Reproduced by permission from Feigl (1970, 6). 1970
University of Minnesota Press

EXAMPLE 2. An observationally adequate generative system 2. THE EMPIRICIST CONCEPTION OF MEANING

speaker. 11 In the case of Schenkerian theory, the property of But why should we regard it as a good thing if a theory of
being tonal—or, more precisely, the property of being judged music is empirical? It is in part because empirical theories are
tonal by qualified listeners—corresponds to grammaticality. "testable" and "explanatory," but the reason runs deeper. It lies in
Brown et al.'s view is equivalent to the claim, then, that the fact that empiricism is centrally concerned with meaning.
Schenkerian theory is observationally adequate, reading "tonal" Empiricism begins with the thought that the content of our
for "grammatical." 12 ideas is derived from sense experience. Language, then, is
Notice that there are two ways in which a theory of tonality grounded in experience: the meaning of an expression is derived
could fail to be observationally adequate: it could generate a from the sense experiences that give rise to its use. Some expres-
piece that is not tonal (Example 1 [see A] ), or fail to generate sions, such as "That's red," are connected more or less directly to
one that is (Example 1 [see B]). In Brown et al.'s view of experience; others, such as "That's an electron," are indirect.
Schenkerian theory, the system does not fail in either of those It follows, then, that a scientific theory has a structure, one
ways: everything that it generates is tonal, and every tonal piece that is determined by the relation between theoretical constructs
is generated (see Example 2). Thus construed, Schenkerian such as "electron," on the one hand, and data—what is given,
theory is straightforwardly empirical: it predicts that a piece will observable, or available to sense experience, comprising the
be judged tonal by qualified listeners if, and only if, it can be theory's epistemological starting point—on the other. In the
generated by the grammar. picture of a scientific theory advanced by the early positivists, a
II On the issue of observational adequacy I follow Allerton (1979, 60-61), theory contains, in addition to data, two components: the "pure
and Botha (1980, 218). The term originated with Chomsky (1964, 28-29). calculus," or theoretical apparatus in the form of an axiomatic
I say "at least" because, as a referee for this journal pointed out, Brown et al. system, and bridge principles. 13 The pure calculus makes state-
may well conceive of Schenkerian theory as adequate in a stronger sense, ments about some class of entities posited by the theory, and
that of descriptive adequacy. It is not necessary to adjudicate the question can be thought of as "hovering" over the data (see Example 3).
because observational adequacy is implied by descriptive adequacy, and the The bridge principles connect the pure calculus to the data.
weaker notion is sufficient for present purposes.
By virtue of that connection, meaning "seeps up" from observ-
12 To be sure, Brown and Dempster (1989, 88) grant that there can be bor-
derline cases, so the claim might be more accurately stated: Schenkerian ables to theoretical terms.
theory is at least approximately observationally adequate. I pass over this
complication. Feigl (1970, 5-7); Suppe (1977, 16-27); Hempel (1970b, 142).
SCHENKERIAN THEORY'S EMPIRICIST IMAGE 113

As an example, consider electrical experiments and their re- definition in terms of observables: in P. W. Bridgman's view as
lation to physics. Physics asserts laws governing subatomic par- explicated by Frederick Suppe, each concept was to be given an
ticles such as electrons: those laws are the pure calculus. Bridge C`operational definition,"2° for example, length or mass was de-
principles allow us to infer, from those laws and auxiliary hy- fined in terms of certain operations of measurement. Over time,
potheses about electrons in a wire, conclusions about pointer this requirement was seen to be too restrictive and was relaxed
readings on a voltmeter. It is in virtue of such inferential con- to the requirement that theoretical terms be "partially inter-
nections that statements about electrons have an empirical preted" through links to observables.21 Eventually, the notion of
meaning. This example serves to illustrate the positivists' view bridge principles as distinguishable from the rest of the theory
that statements about theoretical entities are meaningful inso- was called into question. In W. V. Quine's view, which is more
far, but only insofar, as they predict and explain observables. or less a natural outgrowth of logical empiricism, we find, in-
But why were the positivists so concerned with meaning? stead of Herbert Feigl's vertical arrangement, the metaphor of a
Influenced by Wittgenstein, they thought that many apparent web or fabric with theoretical constructs at the center and ob-
philosophical problems, such as abstruse questions of meta- servables at the periphery. In Quine, the unit of meaning is not
physics, were only "pseudoproblems" resulting from the misuse the term or sentence, but the theory, which "face[s] the tribunal
oflanguage. Hence they wanted to state conditions that must be of sense experience" as a whole.22

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


satisfied for discourse to be "cognitively meaningful." Carnap One key requirement of empiricism is worth emphasizing. A
branded claims about the Hegelian Absolute and Heidegger's theory is not empirical if it is compatible with any observation
dictum that "The Nothing itself nothings" as "metaphysical whatever, that is, if it cannot in principle be disconfirmed. An
pseudo-statements":14 positivists regarded such statements as empirical theory admits certain observable consequences and
strictly meaningless, because their truth or falsity could rnake no rules out others. A statement that excludes nothing is a tautol-
observable difference to experience. They endorsed a doctrine ogy; it does not "say anything about the world."23 This point was
known as the verification theory of meaning, which was ex- developed by Karl Popper, who emphasized falsifiability, in con-
pressed in the slogan, advanced by Moritz Schlick, "The mean- trast to verifiability, as a mark of science.24 A theory is falsifiable
ing of a proposition is its rnethod of verification."15 According if it is possible for there to be evidence that would show it to be
to Schlick, "Stating the meaning of a sentence amounts to stat- false. This does not mean that such evidence actually exists; it is
ing the rules according to which the sentence is to be used, and sufficient if we can clearly grasp what would count as evidence.
this is the same as stating the way in which it can be verified (or Popper wrote, "A theory which is not refutable by any conceiv-
falsified)."16 The empiricists saw the verification theory as a able event is non-scientific. Irrefutability is not a virtue of a the-
powerful principle that could be used to distinguish science ory (as people often think) but a vice."25 Astrology, Popper
from metaphysics.17 argued, makes predictions so vague as to be unfalsifiable, since
As empiricism developed, the notion of verification or falsi- any outcome whatever could be shoehorned into accordance
fication of any conclusive sort gave way to that of confirmation with them. For that reason, astrology is not science. Popper ar-
or disconfirmation, or evidence that was favorable or unfavor- gued that psychoanalytic theory was in much the same boat.26
able, though not necessarily conclusive.18 In connection with There is one further, crucial matter we need to take up,
science, the empiricist principle came to be that sentences using which is the vocabulary of observation reports. Hempel de-
"theoretical" terms (e.g., "electron") get their meaning from the scribes two alternative ways of conceiving of that vocabulary: a
"observation" sentences (e.g., "There's a cloud trail") that, in the phenomenalistic conception on which "experiential data [con-
context of the theory, they imply.19 sist of] sensations, perceptions, and similar phenomena of im-
The notion of bridge principles, and of the work they were mediate experience," and one on which the data are physical
meant to do in linking theoretical entities and observables, also facts "accessible to direct observation, such as the coincidence of
underwent change as empiricism developed. At a very early the pointer of an instrument with a numbered mark on a dial."27
stage, each theoretical term was held to receive an explicit In the first, the data are sensations; in the second, they are

14 Carnap (1959, 69-73). For another example, see Ayer (1946, 36). zo Suppe (1977, 18-19).
Schlick (1936, 341). See also Carnap (1936, 37); Ayer (1946, 5-16) and 21 Ibid. (22-23).
Chapter I; and Suppe (1977, 13). As Reichenbach (1938, 46-49) points 22 Quine (1961, 41-43), Quine (1960, 11); cited in Brown (2005, 15). Quine
out, there is an affinity between positivist conceptions of meaning and is to be regarded as a later empiricist, not a positivist.
those of pragmatists. 23 Ayer (1959, 12). For this notion of a tautology see Wittgenstein (1972,
16 Schlick (1936, 341). 68-69), and, for a worry about a tautology in Schenker, Kerman (1985, 82),
17 This line of thought can be traced back to Hume, who wrote, ca. 1748: "If we cited in Brown et al. (1997, 156, Note 4).
take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; 24 Popper (1959, §6, 17-20).
let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? 25 Popper (1989, 36).
No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of 'act and 26 Ibid. (34-38).
existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: For it can contain nothing but 27 Hempel (1970a, 673-74); for discussion, see Bogen (2009). Brown and
sophistry and Hume ([1748] 1993, 114, italics are Hume's). Dempster (1989, 70-71) suggest that logical positivism commits one to
18 Carnap (1936, 420-22), Hempel (1965, 3-4). phenomenalism, but it does not; cf. Carnap's remarks in Schilpp, ed. (1963,
19 Feigl (1970, 5-7). 50 and 870).
114 MUSIC THEORY SPECTRUM 32 (2010)

physical objects. Since sensations are necessarily private to, or what sort of fact is that? In what does this fact consist? What
accessible only by, the individual who has them, whereas physi- exactly do we assert or deny when we attribute a certain struc-
cal objects can be observed by several individuals, the latter con- ture to a piece? What, if anything, are theorists who disagree
ception has the advantage (as Hempel tells us) of explaining the about the structure of a piece disagreeing about? Answers to
objectivity of scientific discourse. It explains how scientists these questions are not obvious. This is evidenced by the "dark
mean the same things by their terms when they talk to each suspicions" aired by Joseph Kerman and others, 29 which point
other, and hence how they are genuinely able to communicate. out the need for clarification of the content of Schenkerian
Since there is intersubjective, or public, agreement on the mean- concepts. It is evidenced also by Joseph Dubiel's remark, "The
ing of observation terms, 28 and since the meanings of theoreti- hardest thing in this business . . . is knowing what to introspect
cal statements are rooted ultimately in observables in (at least for in order to tell whether you're having the experience that is
approximately) the same way for different speakers, the mean- supposed to go with some analytical description of a passage." 3 °
ings of theoretical statements are likewise intersubjective. Dubiel's remark suggests that the meanings of Schenkerian
Because the physical-object conception of the observational vo- terms, even if they are about experiences, are far from transpar-
cabulary explains this, I assume it in what follows. ent. Such considerations motivate a critical attitude toward
Schenkerian concepts.

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


3. WHY WE SHOULD CARE WHETHER OR NOT Empiricism, in turn, provides a way of answering those ques-
A MUSIC THEORY IS EMPIRICAL tions. If—following Brown et al. we construe Schenkerian
theory in terms of a generative grammar, then we can say that
What relevance can the empiricist conception of meaning what it is for a piece to have a certain structure is that a correct
have for music theory? Empiricism is given work to do when we grammar, one that generates all and only tonal pieces, assigns
adopt a critical attitude toward a concept. By a critical attitude I that structure to it. The structure of a piece, in this view, is just
mean one in which we do not take the meaning of the word or the structure that a successful theory associates with it, where
expression for granted, but ask what that meaning could consist the criterion of success is the prediction of listeners' judgments
in. Suppose, for example, in the context of casual conversation about what is tonal or non-tonal.
you and I take up the question of whether or not intelligence is
inherited. As is well known, the meaning of the word "intelli- 4. PROBLEMS WITH BROWN ET AL.'S INTERPRETATION
gence" is multivalent and vague. (By now, some people have re-
sorted to defining intelligence as whatever intelligence tests But is Brown et al.'s interpretation of Schenkerian theory a
measure. But there are different kinds of intelligence.) It is pos- plausible one? 31 If one is going to say that a theory is empirical,
sible that one or both of us might fail to attach any clear meaning then one has to be clear on two fronts: what the data are, and
to the word, or we might attach different meanings. If either of how the theory predicts the data. Insofar as Brown et al. inter-
those possibilities holds, then, when one of us says, "Intelligence pret Schenkerian theory as a generative grammar, the first point
is inherited," and the other says, "Intelligence is not inherited," we would seem, at least at first glance, not to be too much of an
are not actually disagreeing about anything. For that matter, if we issue: the data are judgments about whether or not a piece or
appear to agree about intelligence but fail to attach the same passage is tonal. 32 I shall argue, however, that it is obscure in
meaning to it, we are not agreeing either! We adopt a critical at- Brown et al.'s account what theoretical apparatus predicts the
titude toward the concept when we recognize this possibility and data, or how it predicts them. Furthermore, Brown et al.'s own
ask, "What exactly do we mean by intelligence?" We answer this presentation of their view is inconsistent: their procedure for
question in an empiricist spirit if we insist that intelligence must testing what they call the #IV(W) Hypothesis does not mesh
be specified in terms of what can be measured or observed, for with the generative-grammar view and points to a misunder-
example, by reference to behavior. In so doing, we associate the standing of empiricist principles. This inconsistency, however,
same empirical meaning with "intelligence," and this may pro- provides a clue to a better understanding of the theoretical func-
mote genuine communication between us. tion of analytical terms.
To take another example from psychology, Freudian theory The claim that a theory is an observationally adequate gen-
postulates the existence of unconscious desires. We may be erative system will not remain plausible for long, absent some
moved to ask: What might it mean to say that a person desires explicit statement of what that system is, one rigorous and de-
something unconsciously? An empiricist will insist that there is tailed enough for us to tell what is or is not generated by it. 33
no real content to this notion until it is connected, by bridge We cannot tell if a theory is observationally adequate if we do
principles, to statements about possible behavior (such as a slip
of the tongue). 29 Brown et al. (1997, 156).
There is good reason for the adoption of a critical attitude 3o Dubiel (1996, 31).
toward the concepts of Schenkerian theory. A central tenet of 31 One issue I shall pass over is the question of whether or not "tonal" is
that theory is that a piece has a structure of a certain kind. But observational. It is a crucial assumption of the generative-system view, but
I do not take it up here.
32 I shall register some caveats below.
28 Hempel (1965, 127 and 178-79). 33 Brown et al. (1997, 158, Note 14).
SCHENKERIAN THEORY'S EMPIRICIST IMAGE 115

not know what it is. Brown and Dempster mention Michael Brown et al.'s test produces the following results. The Chopin,
Kassler's formalization of Schenkerian theory, 34 but they pro- Beethoven, and Brahms examples can plausibly be interpreted
vide no argument that it is observationally adequate, and I have in terms of indirect relationships. (The Chopin and Brahms ex-
never seen any evidence that it is. Brown and Dempster do not amples are particularly challenging, since extant analyses by
give an explicit formulation of a generative system rigorous Felix Salzer and Allen Forte represent them as T-successions.)
enough to be tested for empirical adequacy. 35 As far as I am The Berlioz is tonal, but with qualifications. The Schubert can
aware, no one has. Fred Lerdahl and Ray Jackendoff explain be analyzed in terms of indirect relationships—though Brown
why they did not undertake the project of reconstructing et al. acknowledge that the interpretation is "strained"—or
Schenkerian theory as a generative grammar; 36 the complexity deemed ambiguous. Of the remaining examples, the Debussy
of their own system is an indication of what would be involved and Berg are plausibly interpreted in terms of indirect relation-
in the task. ships, and the Bartók and Webern are not tonal. 39 Hence, no
There is another problem. In their article on the #IV(1,V) counterexamples (except perhaps, if I read Brown et al. right,
Hypothesis, Brown et al. claim to subject Schenkerian theory the Schubert).
to empirical test, but their procedure is not in line with the But this testing procedure makes no sense if the theory is a
generative-grammar view. Brown et al. say that they are test- generative system. The notion of a plausible interpretation, in-

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


ing a claim about where the boundary between tonal and non- voked to support the claim that a piece contains no direct rela-
tonal music lies, which they call the #IV(1,V) Hypothesis. This tionships, has no role to play in such a system. If a generative
hypothesis states that if a piece is tonal, it will contain no "di- system is tested empirically, then the question is not whether a
rect and unmediated succession from I to #IV or t,V", at most, given structural description is plausible, but whether the piece is
it will contain some indirect relationship between I to #IV or generated by the system.
1,V. For convenience, I will abbreviate "direct and unmediated In order to subject a generative system to empirical test, one
succession from I to #IV or 1,V" to "T-succession"; the hypoth- must compare its output with the data in order to see whether
esis can thus be formulated: it generates what it is supposed to. This requires, in turn, an ex-
plicit formulation of the generative mechanism—the grammar
#IV(6V) Hypothesis: No tonal piece contains a T-succession.
so that it is clear what the system does or does not generate. As
Brown et al. argue that, though Schenker never explicitly for- we have noted already, no such formulation is to be found in the
mulated the Hypothesis, "scattered remarks" indicate that it is writings of Brown et al., or any other writer on Schenkerian
suggested by Schenkerian theory. 37 Hence, according to Brown theory.
et al., by testing the Hypothesis, we test Schenkerian theory. In order to remedy this indeterminacy, I think, Brown et al.
Brown et al.'s test of the Hypothesis considers several ex- appeal to the notion of a plausible interpretation. But in doing
amples: Chopin's Etude in F major, Op. 25, No. 3; Beethoven's so they invoke a hermeneutical paradigm rather than an em-
String Quartet No. 7 in F major, Op. 59, No. 1, II; Brahms's pirical or scientific one. The notion of plausibility, however im-
Ein deutsches Requiem, Op. 45, II; Berlioz's Symphonie Fantastique, portant it may be in the practice of interpretation, cannot
Op. 14, III: "March to the Scaffold"; Schubert's "Totengdbers legitimately be brought in as part of an empirical test of a gen-
Heimweh," D. 842; Debussy's Images Pour Orchestre, III: Rondes erative system, since that notion—or our intuitions about what
de printemps, Berg's "Nun ich der Riesen Sdrksten berwand," is plausible—would then be doing the work that the theory it-
Op. 2, No. 3; Bartók's Mikrokosmos, Book 4, No. 100; and self should be doing. A theory is supposed to formulate, explic-
Webern's "Dies ist een Lied far dich allein," Op. 3, No. 1. Their itly, the principles of some domain. A generative grammar is a
basic strategy is: kind of machine meant to encapsulate such principles. We test
to search . . . for examples in which direct relationships between I our attempt to formulate those principles by comparing the
and #IV or 6V seem to occur, then examine them for plausible inter- grammar's output with what we intuitively take to be tonal. If
pretations as indirect relationships. 38 output and intuitions agree, then the theory is confirmed; oth-
erwise not. Insofar as that output needs to be filtered further by
Alternatively, an example can be classified as not tonal, or "not intuitions about what interpretations are or are not plausible,
entirely tonal." The testing method consists, then, in attempting the theory has failed to make the principles explicit; hence fil-
to demonstrate that putative counterexamples, pieces that appear tering the output in that way defeats the purpose of a test. An
both to be tonal and to contain a T-succession, are not genuine empirical theory must be tested by examining its predictions
counterexamples, by arguing either that, despite appearances, just as they are; we should not be allowed to pick and choose
they are not tonal, or that they cannot be plausibly interpreted as only those we like. To do so would violate the principles of em-
containing a T-succession (but, at most, indirect relationships). piricism, and of good science.
The right way to test whether a generative system is obser-
34 Brown and Dempster (1989, 88), citing Kassier (1968) and (1977). vationally adequate is to examine its output and see if it gener-
35 Nor does Brown (2005). ates all and only tonal pieces. The salient worry, it seems to me,
36 Lerdahl and Jackendoff (1983, 111-12).
37 Brown et al. (1997, 160-62 and 170).
38 Ibid. (182). 39 Ibid. (170-80).
116 MUSIC THEORY SPECTRUM 32 (2010)

is that the grammar might generate too much: it might produce Here, Brown et al. invoke a supposed distinction between
a non-tonal surface, perhaps after sufficiently deep nesting of ‘`weak confirmation," which the #IV(W) Hypothesis is said to
the operations. In order to tell whether it does, we would need receive from a certain correlation of intuitions and "ease" of
definitions of the relevant operations that specify exactly which analytical discovery, and "strong confirmation," which concerns
pairs of passages belong to them. Only then would we be able psychological reality and parsing.42
to tell whether the operations are degned in a way that is inclu- This formulation betrays a basic misunderstanding of the
sive enough to allow all tonal pieces, yet restrictive enough to guiding ideas of empiricism. What Brown et al. are talking
exclude nested or iterated operations sufficiently complex to de- about are not two different ways of confirming the same hy-
stroy a sense of tonality. Doubt whether this could be done is pothesis, but two different hypotheses. One hypothesis says that
raised by the Schubert example, where Brown et al. have it both certain relationships can be found in tonal Music through anal-
ways: though the passage can plausibly be argu' ed to be non- ysis. The other says that certain relationships are grasped or
tonal, the system generates a structural description that repre- mentally represented by auditors. These are quite different hy-
sents it as tonal. This is just one example, of course, but Brown potheses, and empiricism readily captures the difference, in that
et al. give us no reason to think that the problem is not systemic. very different things would confirm them. A hypothesis about
If Schenkerian theory is a generative system, then the way to T-succession confirmed through analysis is not a hypothesis

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


test it is to try to break it. Let it crank away, and see if it gener- about "parsing" at all; any claim about parsing would be a dis-
ates any surfaces that are not intuitively tonal. (The intuitions to tinct claim and would be confirmed in a much different way.
be tapped here are intuitions about whether a piece is tonal, not This is not mere hair-splitting because, on the empiricist con-
whether an analysis is plausible.) If "indirect" relations between ception of meaning, the meaning of "That's a T-succession" is a
I and #IV or W are nested to many levels, will we still intuitively matter of what can count as evidence for the claim: the very iden-
find a passage tonal? An aggressive search for counterexamples, tity of the hypothesis depends on what data are relevant to it.
one that actively looks for possible weaknesses in the system, is (The meaning of a sentence is its method of verification.) Different
a better test than the examination of a few examples. Only in empirical connections, different conceptions of T-succession,
the context of such a search are confirming instances apt to be different hypotheses. If we are concerned to show that the #IV(W)
significant. We might initially think that counterexamples could Hypothesis is empirical, we must fix a steady gaze on it, and
be generated in a certain way; but if we found to our surprise avoid confusion with other hypotheses.
that they could not, this would tell us something. As Popper Brown et al. allege that the fact that indirect relations can be
writes, "Confirmations should count only if they are the result found or constructed through analysis "proves . . . the possibility
of riskypredictions."4° I recommend, then, a Popperian approach, that a qualified auditor could conceivably be parsing the piece in
one that puts the emphasis on falsification. a way that maintained its tonal coherence." But if this means
That Brown et al. do not test the theory in a way consistent that finding indirect relations through analysis provides evi-
with their construal of it as generative and empirical does not, dence that qualified auditors parse the piece in a corresponding
of course, prove that it is not generative or empirical. However, way, then why should we think that? The idea that parsing and
their appeal to the notion of a plausible interpretation suggests analyzing are somehow connected is certainly an interesting
that, despite themselves, they take Schenkerian theory to be empirical claim, but what is the evidence for it? This is precisely
fundamentally a hermeneutical rather than empirical enterprise. an area in which empirical research would be relevant, but
Before we turn away from Brown et al., we should observe Brown et al. cite none. In the absence of such evidence, the
one more problem with their argument: they misconstrue dif- analytical results prove nothing whatsoever about "parsing." The
ferent empirical hypotheses as different degrees of confirmation. claim that they do is no more than wishful thinking, and quite
They write, unempirical.43
We have claimed that the hypothesis is confirmed . . . because
our aural intuitions of tonal coherence or incoherence seem to cor-
relate with the relative ease of finding, through analysis, indirect 42 Ibid. As I read Brown et al., "parsing" is something that the qualified audi-
relations between the tonic and the #IV or W events. tor does even when he or she does not undertake analysis of the music, but
This sort of analytic test is, however, only weak confirmation of listens at a less reflective level.
the hypothesis. That some indirect relation between the tonic and 43 Another departure from empiricisrn might be mentioned in passing. An
#IV or [,\T can be found or constructed through analysis proves only empirical theory starts with a notion of the data or the phenomena to be
the possibility that a qualified auditor could conceivably be parsing explained. For the data we get, at various points in Brown et al.'s texts, a
the piece in a way that inaintained its tonal coherence. It does not wide array of candidates: properties of tonal surfaces, the property of being
prove that qualified auditors actually do so parse the piece or that tonal, and auditors' "judgments about closure, completion, openness, sta-
the mere analytical possibility of so parsing the piece is in fact an bility, transition, goal-directedness," and so on (Brown et al. [1997, 157—
aural possibility. In other words, however strongly the analytical 58]). See also Brown and Dempster (1989, 88) and Brown (2005, 4). This
evidence confirms the hypothesis, none of it shows that the #IV(W) inclusivity is not a virtue, but represents a certain indecisiveness, for with-
Hypothesis describes a psychological reality of qualified auditors.41 out a clear conception of precisely what constitute the data, and of how
the theoretical concepts link up with them (via bridge principles, or in
40 Popper (1989, 36). Italics are Popper's. some other way), we do not have a tenable empiricist construal of Schen-
41 Brown et al. (1997, 182). kerian theory.
SCHENKERIAN THEORY ' S EMPIRICIST IMAGE 117

Brown et al.'s invocation of the notion of a plausible inter- 5. SCHENKERIAN ANALYSES AS OBSERVATION SENTENCES
pretation betrays, I think, the real problem with their construal
of Schenkerian theory as a generative grammar. Their notion of It would be a good thing if Schenkerian theory were empiri-
a plausible interpretation is basically a foreign element in the cal, but Brown et al.'s construal of it as a generative system is
generative-grammar framework. Indeed, Brown points to this unsatisfactory. Can the claim that it is empirical be salvaged?
very problem: Can it be salvaged in a way, moreover, that gives a better ac-
[G]iven the complexity of most functional monotonal pieces, we have count of the notion of a correct analysis? Let me suggest the
every reason to suppose that there may be more than one way to de- outlines of such an account, although I do not know if it will
rive a particular surface from a given prototype, provided that each ultimately prove to be tenable.
derivational scheme follows the prescribed laws. In practice, however, Matters are complicated; the goals of theory and analysis are
it is clear that Schenker endorsed some derivations and not others." many and varied. What I propose to sketch is, as it were, an
The generative-system model, then, does not capture certain empirical strain in Schenkerian theory. What follows, then, is
distinctions between analyses significant to Schenker and an account meant to capture a substantial chunk of theoretical
Schenkerians. Such distinctions, or at least many of them, are activity, but not necessarily all of Schenkerianism.
not just peripheral to Schenkerian theory, but are centrally im- In order to proceed, however, we need to rethink one of

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


portant. They ought to be captured on any adequate rational Brown et al.'s central assumptions. Recall the positivists' dis-
reconstruction. If they are not, that is a defect of the reconstruc- tinction between theoretical and observational terms, between
tion. The generative-system model does not distinguish be- "electron" and "red." In Brown et al.'s account, Schenkerian
tween certain analyses that Schenker "endorsed," and others terms such as "middleground" and "implied dominant" desig-
that he did not or would not have endorsed. Or, to put it more nate theoretical entities. Such terms are, in the positivists' sense,
simply, it does not fully capture the distinction between correct theoretical terms. 47 This, it seems to me, is a fundamental mis-
and incorrect analyses. diagnosis of their function. Such terms are, I maintain, not
In what is perhaps an attempt to remedy this defect, Brown theoretical, but—if Schenkerian theory is empirical at all-
goes on to state the need to find "criteria" for determining which observational.
derivations, out of all those permitted by the laws, are "preferable" In defense of this claim, I should like to say, first, that it is
(i.e., correct). One important such criterion, he tells us, is the intuitively plausible. For how is a Schenkerian analysis justified,
principle of "hidden repetitions," or parallelism between levels. 45 that is, determined to be correct or incorrect? How is it deter-
But there are two problems with this response. First, it mined which tones are structurally important and which are
seems unlikely that the principle of hidden repetition can adju- embellishing, whether a certain chord expands tonic harmony
dicate more than a few cases in which we should wish to make or has a passing function? In an overwhelming range of cases,
a distinction between correct and incorrect analyses. Indeed, we use our ears: "I hear it that way." Perhaps not all analytical
nothing seems to rule out the possibility that there are cases decisions are justified by appeal to aural experience, but such
(though I shall not attempt to construct one here) in which experience is a common and indispensable justification in music
some unprepossessing piece is better analyzed in a way that theory and analysis, and in Schenkerian theory and analysis in
does not involve hidden repetition, than in some artificial, con- particular."
voluted way that does." Hence, on the face of it, it would seem that terms for
Second and more important, it is a mystery what "preferable" Schenkerian relations are observational. And, since the central
might even mean, or how the additional "criteria" would be mo- concept here is diminution, this boils down to the claim that
tivated, within the framework of a generative system. In such a diminution—the term "diminution" itself, as well as terms for
framework, the very notion of the correctness of a structural particular types of diminution, such as "arpeggiation," "passing
description depends on that of the predictive success of the motion," and so on—is observational. But in order to replace in-
theory as a whole. Within that paradigm, there is no basis for tuition with argument, we must invoke some account of what it
"endorsing one analysis over another, if each is generated by a
"
is for a term to be observational, and to explain how Schenkerian
theory that successfully predicts the data. (For at bottom, all terms come to have that status.
there is to a scientific statement's being true, according to em- It seems to me that if there is any such story to be had, then
piricism, is that it predicts the data.) But then it would seem it would have to follow in broad outline the behavioristic, em-
that, from the standpoint of the generative-grammar frame- piricist account of observation terms given by Quine." It would
work, any additional "criteria" would be ad hoc. say that our talk of diminution, our grasp of the concept, is

44 Brown (2005, 91). In saying that we have "reason to suppose" this, Brown 47 Brown and Dempster (1989, 97).
oddly distances himself from the theory; presumably it is a fact that can be 48 Interpretations are sometimes justified in other ways, for example, by ap-
checked straightforwardly by computation. peal to the principle of motivic parallelism or considerations of coherence.
45 Brown (2005, 91-92). But such principles are insufficient to decide more than a fraction of the
46 Brown (2005, 92) attributes to Milton Babbitt the claim that the principle cases in which there is, nonetheless, a right answer. Aural intuition is indis-
of hidden repetition is both normative and explanatory, but it is hard to see pensable.
how it can be both. 49 Quine (1960, 5-8 and 31-46).
118 MUSIC THEORY SPECTRUM 32 (2010)

Salto di Quinta Ascendente

• 0. • • ..• 0
*
d • dP°
(11

EXAMPLE 4. Giovanni Battista Bovicelli, Regole passaggi di musica (1594). Reproduced by permission from
Forte and Gilbert (1982, 8), 1970 W W Norton

typically rooted in exposure to paradigmatic cases, such as—I Hempel's distinction between "two levels of scientific systemati-

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


would suggest—the illustrations by Bovicelli, Simpson and zation," which he calls "empirical generalization" and "theory
Handel given early in Forte and Gilbert's textbook, reproduced formation," respectively.53 He writes,
as Example 4.50 We latch on to the meaning of "diminution," It is a remarkable fact . . . that the greatest advances in scientific
the account would go, through exposure to simple, clear-cut ex- systematization have not been accomplished by means of laws refer-
amples such as these, and we then project the term to new ring explicitly to observables, i.e., to things and events which are as-
cases.51 We need not be exposed to exactly the same instances, certainable by direct observation, but rather by means of laws that
but our training must instill in us similar dispositions to apply speak of various hypothetical, or theoretical, entities, i.e., presumptive
the term "diminution," or terms for specific types of diminution, objects, events, and attributes which cannot be perceived or other-
to a wide range of unproblematic cases. Hence, even when ana- wise directly observed by us.54
lysts disagree on cases that are unclear or ambiguous, they have According to Hempel, the earlier and less advanced stage of
a basis for meaning—they are speaking the same language—by scientific systematization is that of empirical generalization,
virtue of, and to the extent of, their similar training and behav- which involves laws that apply to what is "directly observable."
ioral dispositions with respect to uncontroversial cases. At the second level, laws formulated "in terms of hypothetical
It would be in this way that structural descriptions entities . . . account for the uniformities established on the first
Schenkerian theory and analysis could come to function as ob- level."55 An example of a régularity on the first level would be,
servation reports. They would be (an important part of) the according to Hempel, "Wood floats on water"; on the second
data. And, when they function in this way, a "correct" analysis level, Galileo's or Kepler's laws.
would mean a true observation report, one that reports what we Hence, we move on to the more advanced, or theoretical,
observe.52 stage of science when we have some explanatory construct, at a
If this account of Schenkerian terms as observational is cor- remove from the data, that explains patterns and regularities we
rect, it could explain how their meaning is grounded in sense see in the data by means of unifying facts at a deeper, theoretical
experience, and how, or to what extent, theorists mean the same level. (This is what, in Feigl's picture, hovers above the data,
thing when they use the same term, and thereby communicate distinct from it.) But, to the extent that its constructs are obser-
and arrive at objective knowledge. But, even if this account is vational, Schenkerianism remains at the level of empirical gen-
correct, would we have then salvaged the view that Schenkerian eralization. To this extent, Schenkerian theory would be
theory is empirical science? analogous not so much to physics as to our ordinary talk of ta-
There are at least two reasons why we might hesitate to de- bles and chairs, not so much to cognitive science as to folk psy-
clare success. In order to understand the first, it is useful to note chology. Even if the data of musical experience can be explained
by reference to facts about linear progressions, passing motion,
50 Forte and Gilbert (1982,8-9). and so on, there is an important disanalogy between that expla-
51 The latter cases may in turn reshape our notion, but I shall suppress this nation and the way "electron" plays a role in the explanation of
complication. everyday phenomena, because the Schenkerian concepts are in
52 It should be noted that "observation" does not imply naive perception. the data. By analogy, it is not incorrect to say that the hypothesis
Typically we make such reports only after we adopt a certain analytical that there are tables and chairs—the "folk theory" of ordinary
posture toward the music, different from a naive or ordinary way of listen-
ing. This psychological attitude consists in a particular mode of attention physical objects—explains, at some level, its appearing to us that
to structure. We have the capacity to adopt this attitude partly as a result of
exposure to Schenkerian theory. See Hanson (1958,13-19), Kuhn (1970,
§ X, 111-35), and Suppe (1977,147-66). We may also call the relevant 53 Hempel (1965,178), italics omitted.
observations about structure "intuitions," as do Lerdahl and Jackendoff 54 Ibid. (177).
(1983,39); for discussion, see DeBellis (2009). Ibid. (178).
SCHENKERIAN THEORY'S EMPIRICIST IMAGE 119

there are tables and chairs; but that is not science (in Hempel's claim, look to its observable consequences, to see how it is
second sense). Insofar as its constructs are limited to the obser- tested. We may be living in a post-positivist era, but there is stil
vational, then, Schenkerian theory does not ascend to Hempel's much to be learned from empiricism.
second level of scientific systematization. 56
The second reason we should hesitate to declare Schenkerian WORKS CITED
theory empirical science is this: Schenkerian analyses are plau-
sibly understood as observation reports only if the fact that an Allerton, D. J. 1979. Essentials of Grammatical Theory: A Consen-
analyst judges that the piece has a certain structure is best ex- sus View of Syntax and Morphology. London: Routledge and
plained on the hypothesis that the piece really does have that Kegan Paul Ltd.
structure. 57 This reflects a general requirement on scientific ob- Ayer, A[lfred]. nules]. 1946. Language, Truth and Logic. 2nd ed.
servation. "Round" is observational only because the best expla- London: Victor Gollantz.
nation of things looking round to us is, in part, that they really . 1959. Editor's introduction to Logical Positivism. New
are round: the judgment results from a certain causal operation York: The Free Press.
of the roundness of the object on our senses. For this reason, Beaney, Michael. 2004. "Carnap's Conception of Explication:
Gilbert Harman has argued that ethics is not empirical: it is not From Frege to Husserl?" In Carnap Brought Home: The View

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


necessary to suppose that actions have ethical properties in from Jena. Ed. Steve Awodey and Carsten Klein. 117-50.
order to explain why people make the ethical judgments they Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company.
do, since their judgments are better explained by such factors as Bogen, Jim. 2009. "Theory and Observation in Science." In The
their upbringing. 58 In the case of music analysis, the question is Stanford Encydopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition). Ed.
whether an analyses belief that a piece contains certain middle- Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/
ground events is better explained on the hypothesis that there entries/science-theory-observation/ (accessed 10 August
are such events, or by the fact that the analyst believes that 2009).
Schenker claimed that there were such events, accepts his au- Botha, Rudolf P. 1980. The Conduct o Linguistic Inquiry: A Sys-
thority, and wishes to emulate him. We should construe tematic Introduction to the Methodology of Generative Gram-
Schenkerian concepts as observational only if analysts' arrival at mar. The Hague: Mouton Publishers. Originally published
beliefs about Schenkerian structure is best explained on the hy- as Generatiewe Taalondersoek: Sistematiese Inleiding. Kaaps-
pothesis that the words really do have that structure. 59 tad: Hollandsh Afrikaan Uitgevers Mif., 1978.
Brown, Matthew. 1989. "A Rational Reconstruction of Schen-
6. CONCLUSION kerian Theory." Ph.D. diss., Cornell University.
. 1997. "Adrift on Neurath's Boat': The Case for a Nat-
It has been said in music-theoretic circles that we are living uralized Music Theory." The Journal of Musicology 15 (3):
in a post-positivist era. 60 But it would be a naive historicism 330-42.
that allowed us to conclude that the positivists' insights must be . 2005. Explaining Tonality: Schenkerian Theory and
irrelevant to contemporary music theory. The positivists were Beyond. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
on to an important idea: that words become meaningful by vir- Brown, Matthew, and Douglas J. Dempster. 1989. "The Scien-
tue of their tether to experience. This principle expresses a deep tific Image of Music Theory." Journal of Music Theory 33 (1):
insight about the notions of cognitive significance and genuine 65-106.
communication, and can illuminate the content of our concepts Brown, Matthew, Douglas J. Dempster, and Dave Headlam.
where a critical attitude is called for. A critical attitude is not out 1997. "The #IV(I,V) Hypothesis: Testing the Limits of Schen-
of place with regard to the content of Schenkerian concepts. It ker's Theory of Tonality." Music Theory Spectrum 19 (2): 155-
is not pointless to ask what it means to say that a given passage 83.
is a prolongation of some simpler passage, or that a passage is Carnap, Rudolf. 1936-37. "Testability and Meaning." Pts. 1 and
correctly analyzed in this way rather than that. Insofar as there 2. Philosophy of Science 3 (4): 419-71 and 4 (1): 1-40.
is cognitive content to such assertions, an empiricist spirit can . 1959. "The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Log-
help us see what that content might be. Music theory has not ical Analysis of Language." Trans. Arthur Pap. In Logical
developed to the point where it has nothing to gain from the Positivism. Ed. A. J. Ayer. 60-81. New York: The Free Press.
empiricists' insights. To understand the meaning of a theoretical . 1967. The Logical Structure of the World: Pseudoproblems
in Philosophy. Trans. Rolf A. George. Berkeley: University of
56 On the "hypothesis of ordinary physical objects" and how physics goes be- California Press. Originally published as Logische Aufbau der
yond it, see also Quine (1960, 21-22). I am indebted to Joseph Dubiel for Welt: Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie. Hamburg: Felix Mei-
a discussion of this point. ner Verlag, 1928.
57 Cf. Harman (1977, 8). Chomsky, Noam. 1964. Current Issues in Linguistic Theory. The
58 Ibid. (4). Hague: Mouton Publishers.
59 The line of thought developed in this paragraph was prompted in part by
Cross, Ian. 2000-01. "Music(s), Science(s), Post-Positivist Plu-
discussions with Dmitri Tymoczko.
6o See, e.g., Cross (2000-01). ralities." Intégral 14/15: 20-26.
120 MUSIC THEORY SPECTRUM 32 (203[0)

DeBellis, Mark. 2009. "Perceptualism, Not Introspectionism: . 1989. Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scien-
The Interpretation of Intuition-Based Theories." Music Per- tific Knowledge. 5th ed. London: Routledge Classics.
ception 27 (2): 121-30. Quine, W[illard]. V[an Oman]. 1960. Word and Object. Cam-
Dempster, Douglas, and Matthew Brown. 1990. "Evaluating bridge [MA]: Technology Press of the Massachusetts Insti-
Musical Analyses and Theories: Five Perspectives." Journa/ of tute of Technology.
Music Theory 34 (2): 247-79. . 1961. From a Logical Point of View: Nine Logico Philo- -

Dubiel, Joseph. 1996. "Hearing, Remembering, Cold Storage, sophical Essays. 2nd ed. rev. Cambridge [MA]: Harvard Uni-
Purism, Evidence, and Attitude Adjustment." Current Musi- versity Press.
cology 60-61: 26-50. Ray, Christopher. 2000. "Logical Positivism." In A Companion
Feigl, Herbert. 1970. "The 'Orthodox' View of Theories: Re- to the Philosophy of Science. Ed. H. W. Newton Smith. 243
- -

marks in Defense as well as Critique." In Analyses of Theories 51. Malden [MA]: Blackwell Publishers.
and Methods of Physics and Psychology. Vol. 4 of Minnesota Reichenbach, Hans. 1938. Experience and Prediction: An Analysis
Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Ed. Michael Radner and of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. Chicago:
Stephen Winokur. 3-16. Minneapolis: University of Min- The University of Chicago Press.
nesota Press. Salmon, Wesley C. 2000. "Logical Empiricism." In A Compan-

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at Carleton University on June 13, 2015


Forte, Allen, and Steven E. Gilbert. 1982. Introduction to Schen- ion to the Philosophy of Science. Ed. H. W. Newton Smith. -

kerian Analysis. New York: W. W. Norton. 233 42. Malden [MA]: Blackwell Publishers.
-

Hanson, Norwood Russell. 1958. Patterns of Discovery: An In- Schilpp, Paul Arthur, ed. 1963. The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap.
quiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge: La Salle [IL]: Open Court Publishing Company.
Cambridge University Press. Schlick, Moritz. 1936. "Meaning and Verification." Philosophical
Harman, Gilbert. 1977. The Nature of Morality: An Introduction Review 45 (4): 339-69.
to Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. Suppe, Frederick, ed. 1977. The Structure of Scientific Theories.
Hempel, Carl G. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation, and 2nd ed. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: The Free Wittgenstein, Ludwig. [1921] 1972. Tractatus Logico Philosoph--

Press. icus: The German Text ofludwi g Wittgenstein's Logisch Philos- -

. 1970a. "Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Em- ophische Abhandlung. 2nd ed. London: Routledge and Kegan
pirical Science." In Foundations of the Unity of Science. Vol. 2. Paul.
Ed. Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap, and Charles W. Morris.
651-745. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
. 1970b. "On the 'Standard Conception' of Scientific
Theories." In Analyses of Theories and Methods of Physics and
Psychology. Vol. 4 of Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Sci-
ence. Ed. Michael Radner and Stephen Winokur. 142-63.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Hume, David. [1748] 1993. An Enquiry Concerning Human
Understanding. 2nd ed. Ed. Eric Steinberg. Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.
Kassler, Michael. 1968. "A Trinity of Essays: Toward a Theory that
is the Twelve-Note Class System, Toward a Development of a
Constructive Tonality Theory Based on Writings by Heinrich
Schenker, Toward a Simple Programming Language for Musi-
cal Information Retrieval." Ph.D. diss., Princeton University.
. 1977. "Explication of a Middleground of Schenker's
Theory of Tonality." Miscellanea Musicologica 9: 72-81.
Kerman, Joseph. 1985. Contemplating Music: Challenges to Mu-
sicology. Cambridge [MA]: Harvard University Press.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
2nd ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Lerdahl, Fred, and Ray Jackendoff. 1983.A Generative Theory of
Tonal Music. Cambridge [MA]: The MIT Press.
Music Theory Spectrum, Vol. 32, Issue 2, pp. 111-120, ISSN 0195-6167,
Passmore, John. 1967. "Logical Positivism." In The Encyclopedia
electronic ISSN 1533-8339. 2010 by The Society for Music Theory.
of Philosophy. Ed. Paul Edwards. 5: 52-57. New York: Mac- All rights reserved. Please direct all requests for permission to photocopy
millan Publishing Company. or reproduce article content through the University of California Press's
Popper, Karl. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Rights and Permissions website, at http://www.ucpressjournals.com/
Hutchinson. reprintinfo.asp. DOL 10.1525/mts.2010.32.2.111

You might also like