You are on page 1of 20

Thomas W. Dunfee, N. Craig Smith, & William T. Ross Jr.

Social Contracts and


X Marketing Ethics
In this article, the authors describe the need and the search to date for a normative moral foundation for market-
ing. Social contract theory appears promising because of its clear correspondence to the exchange relationships
central to marketing thought and practice. The authors introduce it in a specific formulation known as Integrative
Social Contracts Theory (ISCT). This theory provides a coherent framework for resolving ethical issues that arise
among different communities and is therefore particularly appropriate because marketers frequently engage in
boundary-spanning relationships and cross-cultural activities. The authors explore the application of ISCT to ethi-
cal decision making in marketing through the use of bribery as a major illustrative example. They discuss implica-
tions for managers and researchers.

T
he need for normative theory to provide guidance in approaches include attempts to describe or model ethical de-
evaluating ethical issues is particularly pressing in cision making (e.g., Ferrell and Gresham 1985; Hunt and
marketing. There have been many cases of unethical Vitell 1986) and empirical studies of the ethical attitudes
conduct in marketing; indeed, marketing is viewed by some and/or behaviors of different populations, such as marketing
as the worst offender of the business functions (LeClair, Fer- researchers (e.g., Akaah and Riordan 1989) or salespeople
rell, and Ferrell 1997; Tsalikis and Fritzsche 1989). Social (e.g., Bellizzi and Hite 1989). Normative approaches to
contract theory is evolving into one of the major alternatives ethics identify moral principles and methods of moral rea-
for approaching business ethics. Although it has received soning that justify judgments of what is right and wrong. It
limited attention from marketing scholars to date, its poten- is normative marketing ethics that is concerned with pre-
tial for analyzing marketing ethics deserves exploration. scribing what managers "ought to do" when faced with an
-In this article, our purpose is to show the relevance of so- ethical issue. Reviews of marketing ethics literature (e.g.,
cial contract theory to marketing, introduce a specific social Tsalikis and Fritzsche 1989) show that there have been a
contract-based approach, known as Integrative Social Con- substantial number of descriptive contributions but far few-
tracts Theory (ISCT) (Donaldson and Dunfee 1994, 1995, er normative contributions.
1999; Dunfee and Donaldson 1995), and demonstrate The relative scarcity of normative articles reflects the
ISCT's particular applicability to marketing ethics. We ex-
difficulty in making noncontroversial yet definitive ethical
amine the search to date for a normative moral foundation
evaluations of marketing decisions and practices, though
for marketing. We then introduce social contract theory and
this is both necessary and important (Ferrell and Gresham
discuss its pertinence to marketing. Next, we explain ISCT
1985). Consider the substantial physical and financial harm
and show in detail how it may be applied to one of the more
that can result from unethical decisions about product safe-
intractable problems of marketing ethics, that of bribery. Fi-
ty, truth in advertising, and fairness in pricing. The evalua-
nally, we identify implications for managers and researchers.
tion of these decisions as ethical or unethical—by the
decision maker(s), those affected by the decision, public
The Search for a Normative Moral policymakers, or researchers—may be better informed by
Foundation for Marketing sound theories of normative marketing ethics.
The literature on marketing ethics can be differentiated be- The normative marketing ethics literature parallels the
tween descriptive and normative approaches. Descriptive pluralistic approaches found in the broader business ethics
field. Business ethicists have sought to develop frameworks
for applying classical ethical theories to business dilemmas.
Thomas W. Dunfee is Kolodny Professor of Social Responsibility and Di- This work includes Kantian ethics (Bowie and Duska 1990;
rector, Carol and Lawrence Zicklin Center for Business Etfiics Research, Evan and Freeman 1988), virtue (Solomon 1993), rights
The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania. N. Craig Smith is Asso- (Werhane 1984), utilitarianism (Buchanan 1988), justice
ciate Professor of Marketing, The McDonough Schooi of Business, (Hartman 1996), and social contract theory (Donaldson
Georgetown University. William T Ross Jr. is Associate Professor of Mar-
keting and Assistant Dean for Research and Doctoral Programs, Fox
1982, 1989; Donaldson and Dunfee 1994, 1995, 1999; Kee-
School of Business and Management, Temple University. The authors ley 1988). Each of these frameworks incorporates founda-
thank Thomas Donaldson, Diana Robertson, participants In the Kennedy tional principles such as impartiality or consent as a basis
Institute of Ethics Seminar at Georgetown University, and three anony- for moral guidance. Advocates of individual theories argue
mous JM reviewers for helpful comments on previous versions of this arti- for their superiority in dealing with at least a defined class
cle. Funding by the Carol and Lawrence Zicklin Center for Business Ethics
of ethical problems, whereas others take a more ecumenical
Research and the Georgetown University School of Business summer re-
search fund is gratefully acknowledged. approach, looking for a convergence of judgment among al-
ternative theories (Hosmer 1994).

Journal of Marketing
14 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999 Vol.63(July 1999), 14-32
Within the literature on marketing ethics, a creative vari- the strategic marketing planning process (Robin and Reiden-
ety of frameworks and theories has been developed, typical- bach 1987). Table 1 provides a selective sampling of this lit-
ly with reliance on one or more of the classical theories. erature and indicates the level of focus (individual, firm, or
Examples include a diagnostic framework.for assessing indi- societal), the primary orientation (normative or descriptive),
vidual responsibilities of marketing executives for the conse- any explicit normative approaches taken, major examples
quences of their unethical actions (Mascarenhas 1995); a test used, and the role, if any, of social contracts or norms. Half
that requires marketers to establish that consumers can exer- of the chosen frameworks are pluralistic, in that multiple eth-
cise informed choice (Smith 1995); a contingency factor ical theories are recognized. This may restrict their ability to
model of ethical behavior that incorporates an assumption predict outcomes, because results may vary, even with the
that "marketers develop guidelines and rules for ethical be- same contextual factors, depending on the normative theory
havior based on moral philosophy" (Ferrell and Gresham chosen by a given moral agent. However, pluralistic ap-
1985, p. 88); a framework presented as a series of questions proaches recognize a possible tendency for moral agents to
based on theories developed by Ross, Garrett, and Rawls either follow a multistep pluralistic analysis in their own rea-
(Laczniak 1983) and later revised to include additional theo- soning or go back and forth between theories, depending on
ries of moral philosophy (Laczniak and Murphy 1993); a de- the context of the decision required.
scriptive model of ethical decision making in marketing that The marketing-specific attempts at developing a norma-
assumes most people apply both a duty-based and a teleo- tive framework typically have incorporated general sum-
logical analysis (Hunt and Vitell 1986); and a framework maries of the classical ethical theories, particularly
suggested for integrating social responsibility and ethics into utilitarianism, Kantian or other duty-based approaches.

TABLE 1
Frameworks for Ethical Decision Making in Marketing

Normative Use of Detailed Role of Social


Article Level/Focus Orientation Approach(es) Examples Contracts/Norms
Chonko and Hunt Marketing Descriptive None None Implicit in
(1985) managers discussion of
industry and
professional
codes
Ferrell and Individual Descriptive Dependent on None Assumes group
Gresham marketers (framework) decision maker pressure may be
(1985) a greater
influence than
group norms

Hunt and Vitell Individual Descriptive Deontological/ Two short Industry and
(1986) marketers (model of teleological scenarios organizational
decision-making) (gifts, auto norms as source
safety) of deontological
rules

Laczniak (1983) Marketing Normative Nontelelogical Six short None


decision (Ross, Rawls, scenarios
makers and Garrett)
Mascarenbas Marketing Instrumental/ Pluralistic Breast implants, Standards for fault/
(1995) decision diagnostic consumer use accountability
makers profiles
Robin and Multilevel Normative Descriptive None Implicit in
Reidenbach (societal/ (contextual, descriptive
(1993) organizational/ bounded component
individual) relativism)
Smith (1995) Marketing Normative Consumer Suzuki Samurai Firm's obligation to
decision sovereignty roll-over, the consumer is
makers retailer hi-lo based on a social
pricing contract
Thompson (1995) Individual Instrumental/ Ethics of care/ None Source of cultural
marketer normative ethical relativism meanings
Williams and Multilevel Normative Virtue Johnson & Not explicit
Murphy (1990) (individual, Johnson,
organization) Nestid

Marketing Ethics/15
virtue, rights, and justice. They generally are agnostic as to deaths caused by the marketing of these pesticides overseas
the normative theory to be applied among those theories in- against the "benefits" of jobs retained in the United States.
cluded within a given pluralistic framework. In the proto- But it is surely fair to ask whether a trade-off of lives or
typical normative model, Laczniak (1983), as revised by physical well-being versus income is fully consistent with
Laczniak and Murphy (1993, pp. 49-51), would apply the commonsense morality. Although rule utilitarianism—using
following questions in evaluating the ethics of marketing predefined rules to deal with repetitive ethical issues—may
practices: resolve some of these problems, the inherent complexity of
modern business and professional life vastly complicates its
1. Does the contemplated action violate the law? (legal test) use as a realistic guide.
2. Is this action contrary to widely accepted moral obligations?
(duties test) Duty-based (or deontological) approaches avoid some of
the problems with utilitarianism by establishing clear duties,
3. Does the proposed action violate any other special obliga-
tions that stem from the type of marketing organization at often based on some rational criteria or assumptions regard-
focus? (special obligations test) ing the nature of humanity. Even so, in some situations, it
4. Is the intent of the contemplated action harmful? (motives may appear that no obvious duties can be invoked or that du-
test) ties are in conflict. In other cases, the recognition of duties
5. Is it likely that any major damages to people or organizations is dependent on unknowable facts. In many business-related
will result from the contemplated action? (consequences test) contexts, duty-based theories produce conflicting obliga-
6. Is there a satisfactory alternative action that produces equal tions without any clear-cut method for resolving the con-
or greater benefits to the parties affected than the proposed flicts. Thus, a manager acting with a perceived ethical duty
action? (utilitarian test) to give appropriate consideration to the legitimate claims
7. Does tbe contemplated action infringe on property rights, and interests of stakeholders finds little guidance in resolv-
privacy rights, or the inalienable rights of the consumer? ing competing stakeholder claims. For example, animal
(rights test) rights advocates might demand that a cosmetics company
8. Does the proposed action leave another person or group less cease all testing on animals, whereas consumer activists de-
well off? Is this person or group already a member of a rel- mand that the firm use all known effective measures for
atively underprivileged class? (justice test) guaranteeing the safety of its products.
An affirmative answer to any of the tests is assumed to These and similar problems have led Robin and Reiden-
indicate that the marketer's decision is probably unethical bach (1993) to note that the "grand narratives" of moral phi-
and should be reconsidered. Pragmatic considerations con- losophy seem inadequate for the rich, complex context of
strain the value of this approach. If every type of ethical the marketing function. They despair of identifying any uni-
theory must be satisfied, few marketing decisions would be fying general ethical theory and instead argue for the devel-
likely to pass muster. Furthermore, the answering of certain opment of a workable, ethical approach specific to
questions as yes is likely to produce a no in another context. marketing.
For example, a duty of justice that contemplates some rea- Few of the frameworks reference social contract theory,
sonably equivalent distribution of benefits may consistent- despite its increasing prominence as a theory in business
ly conflict with shareholder property rights. Indeed, ethics (Dunfee and Donaldson 1995) and its use elsewhere
Laczniak and Murphy (1993) acknowledge that there may in marketing literature. We turn now to explore whether so-
be conflicting responses to their questions. Thus, though cial contract theory might be a useful addition to the frame-
use of this framework undoubtedly has merit in assisting works for decision making in marketing ethics, either as one
marketers to reflect on the ethics of their decisions, it is less of the alternatives in a pluralistic approach or as a primary
satisfactory in providing definitive ethical evaluations of theory in certain contexts. As a first step, we provide a brief
specific practices. introduction to social contract theory and its use in business
Approaches in business ethics based on classical theo- ethics.
ries, particularly those that rely on Kantian ethics and utili-
tarianism, have been criticized as too abstract and general to
provide adequate guidance for managers (Stark 1993). The Sociai Contract Theory
problems with utilitarianism are well known. In many cases, Social contract theory has its origins in the social upheavals
utilitarian analysis requires forecasting of unknowable fu- of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century Europe. The decline
ture events (e.g., the percentage of women who would de- of feudalism and the rejection of the divine right of kings as
velop medical problems from silicone breast implants). a basis for obedience to the state gave rise to a search for a
Also, comparing different types of utilities is notoriously political philosophy that legitimized state authority. Consent
difficult. How, for example, should the joy and excitement theories of political obligation developed, best articulated
of riding on a three-wheel, all-terrain vehicle be measured by the English philosopher John Locke (1632-1704). He ar-
against the associated physical dangers? Finally, the trade- gued that "a citizen's obligation to obey the law can be
offs required by the underlying principle of impartiality— grounded only in that citizen's personal consent to the au-
such that the utilitarian is indifferent to who is hurt and thority of the law" (Simmons 1992, p. 919). In Two Treatis-
how—strike many people as counterintuitive. es of Government (1690), Locke sought to identify a basis
Consider the marketing of harmful pesticides, banned in for the legitimacy of state authority. His resulting social con-
the United States, to less developed countries. A utilitarian tract justified the existence of the state and identified the
might be comfortable balancing the "costs" of possible reciprocal obligations of citizen and state. Subsequently,

16 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999


Locke's ideas informed the American Revolution, the U.S. a caveat. The inevitable trade-offs that must be made, espe-
Declaration of Independence, and the U.S. Constitution. cially between the interests of consumers and workers (low-
Locke was influenced by Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), er prices or higher wages?), require that the contract must
one of the earliest proponents of the social contract. not violate certain minimum standards of justice; though
Hobbes's Leviathan (1651) argues for the institution of an welfare trade-offs are permissible, organizational acts of in-
absolute sovereign as a way to further the peace of the com- justice are not. Thus, at the minimum, productive organiza-
munity and thereby promote the preservation and comforts tions must "avoid deception or fraud ... show respect for
of its citizens (Hampton 1992, p. 543). Hobbes identifies a their workers as human beings, and ... avoid any practice
"state of nature," a world without a state, wherein people act that systematically worsens the situation of a given group in
to satisfy their desires, principally self-preservation. He society" (Donaldson 1982, p. 53).
suggests (Hampton 1992, p. 544) this state of nature would Some moral philosophers are critical of social contract
be a "war of every one against every one" and that life theory, denying the existence of actual contracts while ar-
would be "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short." In these guing that hypothetical contracts cannot provide for mean-
conditions, Hobbes argues, people would accept the only ingful consent and agreement. Hume (1711-1776), for
logical solution and agree to recognize an absolute sover- example, used the analogy of the press-ganged seaman who
eign. Similarly, in The Social Contract {\162), Jean-Jacques is asked when at sea to "consent" to service. Anticipating
Rousseau (1712-1778) suggests that presocial discord may this criticism, Donaldson (1982, p. 40, his emphasis)
be solved by individuals placing themselves under the di- writes: "There may never have been a pen and ink contract,
rection of a "general will" (Reath 1992, p. 1114). Accord- but remarkably enough, thousands of people have acted as
ingly, three elements are common to most social contract i/there were." However, Kultgen's (1986, p. 30) critique of
theories: (I) consent of the individual, (2) agreement among Donaldson's social contract for business argues that it must
moral agents, and (3) a device or method by which an agree- be claimed either that the contract is "a mere heuristic de-
ment (actual or hypothetical) is obtained. vice" or that it exists or could be made to exist. Donaldson
(1989, pp. 56-61) disputes this assertion, though in his lat-
Social Contract Theory and Business Ethics er work with Dunfee (Donaldson and Dunfee 1994, 1995,
Questions about the legitimacy of business decisions are 1999), he has proposed ISCT as a framework that incorpo-
more common today than questions about the legitimacy of rates actual (micro)social contracts. In summary, Donald-
the state (Freeman and Gilbert 1988). Business ethicists are son (1982, 1989) has established the role of a social
interested in justifications for the exercise of corporate pow- contract for business and the likelihood that it would be
er and the appropriate forms and effects of business decision consented to by individuals.
making. Accordingly, the search for a basis for establishing Social contract theory is attracting considerable atten-
that the pricing of a life-saving drug is "fair" or that an ad- tion within the business ethics field. A special issue of Busi-
vertising campaign using fear appeals is "right" has much in ness Ethics Quarterly has been devoted to the topic (April
common with Locke's search for a basis for obedience to the 1995), and recent major books on business ethics have fea-
state. tured this approach (e.g., Donaldson 1982, 1989; Keeley
Donaldson (1982, 1989) has constructed a social con- 1988). Frederick (1995, p. 270), for example, refers to its
tract for business that provides for corporate legitimacy on "compelling theoretical significance" (also see Binmore
the basis of the consent of those affected by business; that is, 1994; Blau 1993; Hartman 1996; Macneil 1980; Medina
corporations exist only through the cooperation and com- 1993).
mitment of society. This suggests an implied agreement be-
tween the corporation and society: "If General Motors holds Social Contract Theory and Marketing
society responsible for providing the condition of its exis- The particular relevance of social contract theory for mar-
tence, then for what does society hold General Motors re- keting ethics lies in part in its shared focus on exchange. Es-
sponsible? What are the terms of the social contract?" sentially, according to Donaldson's (1982, 1989)
(Donaldson 1982, p. 42). Donaldson's (1982, p. 44) device hypothetical social contract, the firm offers advantages to
for such agreement (akin to Hobbes's "state of nature") is to society—its customers and employees—in exchange for the
imagine a society without the productive organizations be- right to exist and even prosper. At the same time, the ex-
ing analyzed—a "state of individual production"—and rec- change relationship between the firm and its customers is
ognize the problems solved by the introduction of considered fundamental to marketing by many theorists
productive organizations. As an alternative to a state of in- (e.g.. Hunt 1983; Kotler 1972). Clearly, the two are concep-
dividual production, ordinary people, economically interest- tually similar. Thus, there is an attractive conceptual con-
ed and rational, would consent to have productive gruity to using an exchange-based model of ethics to
organizations. understand the ethical issues associated with and to provide
In this way, Donaldson uses social contract theory to es- ethical guidance for a domain based on economic exchange.
tablish the moral foundation of the corporation. He argues As important, the shared focus on exchange grants social
(1982, p. 54) that "corporations considered as productive or- contract theory a unique advantage in offering prescriptive
ganizations exist to enhance the welfare of society through advice to marketers.
the satisfaction of consumer and worker interests, in a way The concept of social contracts has been used both
which relies on exploiting corporations' special advantages explicitly and implicitly in the general marketing litera-
and minimizing disadvantages." However, Donaldson adds ture. For example, Goolsby and Hunt (1992, p. 58) define

Marketing Ethics/17
social responsibility as relating "to the social contract be- Following the classic contractarians, Donaldson and
tween businesses and the society in which they operate." Dunfee (1994, 1995, 1999) envision rational humans seek-
Reidenbach and Robin (1990) include social contract ing to design a binding, though unwritten, agreement that
items in their multidimensional ethics scale. Moreover, establishes the parameters for ethics in economic relation-
various researchers have referred to "norms," an implicit ships. To justify consent on the part of the contractors, they
reference to generally understood standards or obliga- limit themselves to parsimonious assumptions and a mini-
tions derived from social contracts. Heide and John malist global social contract.
(1992, p. 34) define norms as "expectations about behav- The terms of the contract are based on the global con-
ior that are at least partially shared by a group of decision tractors' rational response to two assumptions. First, the
makers" and note that "specialized normative structures contractors are assumed to be aware of and concerned about
have been shown to govern individual exchange relation- bounded moral rationality. Bounded moral rationality repre-
ships between firms." However, though marketing litera- sents an extension of the well-grounded idea of bounded
ture makes use of social contracts or norms within economic rationality to the moral sphere. It is assumed that
exchange relationships, little attention has been given to individual moral agents lack the information, time, and
their potential use in a normative evaluation of marketing emotional strength to make perfect judgments consistent
practice. with their moral preferences. Thus, breast-implant salespeo-
Social contract theory has been used in marketing ple who know they are committed utilitarians may not be
ethics-related empirical studies. In the context of direct able to apply their preferred theory because they lack the
marketing, Culnan (1995) uses social contract theory to an- time and information to determine whether the risks associ-
alyze privacy issues associated with consumer awareness of ated with the product may exceed its positive cosmetic and
name removal procedures. Robertson and Anderson (1993) psychological value.
implicitly used social contract theory when they found that The bounded moral rationality assumption also ac-
sales managers and salespeople respond differently to the knowledges that global contractors may not be able to
same ethical dilemmas and attributed this to differences in identify and agree to an omnipotent comprehensive
roles, responsibilities, and cultures between the two groups. moral theory. Therefore, ISCT assumes (Donaldson and
We suggest that the two groups may operate under different Dunfee 1995, p. 93) that the individual contractors would
social contracts. Robertson and Ross (1995) make explicit wish to retain the right to select their own values to the
reference to social contracts when hypothesizing about dif- maximum extent possible and that they would "desire to
ferences between students and salespeople in responses to participate in economic communities that reflect their
ethically related scenarios. They find that salespeople, who personal and cultural values." In so doing, the contractors
better understand the norms operating in a selling situation, would be recognizing bounded moral rationality insofar
are less influenced by situational pressures than are stu- as it limits the ability of moral theorists to design a moral
dents. Thus, there is some tentative empirical validation of calculus applicable to all decision contexts for all of di-
the importance of social contract concepts in the thinking of verse humanity.
salespeople. Second, it is assumed that the global contractors would,
Given the connections to marketing theory, it remains in response to bounded moral rationality, recognize the
surprising that the normative marketing ethics frameworks need for a community-based moral fabric as a necessary
have not made greater use of the concept of social contracts. condition for both the generation of wealth and the main-
In considering how social contract-based approaches may tenance of an environment conducive to a good and pro-
be more directly relevant to marketing, we describe a spe- ductive life. Without this moral fabric, which is the
cific social contract-based approach to business ethics, purpose of the global convention, there is the threat of so-
ISCT. cial denigration into Hobbes's "war of every one against
every one."
In response to these core assumptions, Donaldson and
Integrative Social Contracts Theory Dunfee (1994, 1995, 1999) hypothesize that the global con-
Donaldson and Dunfee's (1994, 1995, 1999) ISCT relies on tractors would agree to the creation of a binding macrosocial
real, contextual, microsocial contract norms within an over- contract. Donaldson and Dunfee argue that this global
all framework based on a classical, hypothetical, macroso- macrosocial contract is the only rational solution to the need
cial contract similar to those envisioned by Hobbes and for a moral fabric in the face of bounded moral rationality.
Locke. The term "integrative" captures that ISCT encom- Because it is assumed to be logically compelling, all ratio-
passes two different types of social contracts: a hypotheti- nal humans are assumed to consent to its terms, which are
cal macrosocial contract used as a heuristic device and spelled out subsequently.
actual microsocial contracts based in living communities.
The use of the plural term "contracts" refers not only to the Moral Free Space and Protected Informed
two types of contracts, but also to the millions of Consent
community-based microsocial contracts whose norms are
important in rendering normative judgments in business The first two terms of the macrosocial contract are as follows:
ethics. Thus, ISCT is grounded in the familiar idea of social 1. Local economic communities may specify ethical norms for
norms that serve as the foundation for rules of behavior their members through microsocial contracts (i.e., the
within communities. "moral free space" term).

18 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999


2. Norm-generating microsocial contracts must be grounded in given subsequently) are obligatory for dissenting members
informed consent, buttressed by rights of exit and voice (i.e., of communities. The obligation stems from the consent giv-
the "protected informed consent" term).' en when a person acts as a member of a community, perhaps
Communities are the core focus of the macrosocial contract. by accepting the benefits of the community environment.
A community is defined in ISCT (Donaldson and Dunfee However, ISCT imposes some additional requirements on
1994, p. 262) as "a self-defined, self-circumscribed group of the operation of the community. The community must re-
people who interact in the context of shared tasks, values, or spect the right of members to exit from group membership.
goals and who are capable of establishing norms of ethical Thus, a dissenting member of a community who is dis-
behavior for themselves." Corporations, subsidiaries, and tressed about a particular authentic norm may elect to leave
even departments or informal units within an organization, the community. An employee may, and generally should,
along with partnerships, professional groups, trade associa- leave a corporation whose values are significantly at odds
tions, and nation states, may be ISCT communities in the with the employee's important personal values.
context of a given ethical decision. In focusing on commu- Similarly, we emphasize that an individual should have
nities, ISCT recognizes that norm-governed group activity is the opportunity to exercise voice within the community.
a critical component of economic life. This is consistent with much of the organizational justice lit-
The idea of moral free space is consistent with the con- erature that emphasizes procedural justice. Often, some
tractors' desire to keep their options open. It also recognizes form of voice (e.g., the right to a hearing to present one's
that communities are entitled to have differing norms. The side of the case) is critical in perceptions that a firm has act-
parameters of ethical behavior in advertising may vary ed justly (Lind and Tyler 1988). People desire the right to in-
among Japan, France, and the United States; for example, fluence the development and evolution of norms and,
comparison advertising is not considered acceptable in perhaps most important, to be able to infiuence changes in
Japan, whereas it is in the United States. Acting within its norms they find objectionable. In summary, as long as the
own moral free space, each of these communities may gen- requirements of community recognition of voice and exit
erate indigenous "authentic" ethical norms. A norm is de- are met and the attitudes and behaviors of a substantial ma-
fined as authentic when it is supported by the attitudes and jority of the members of a community support a given norm,
behaviors of a substantial majority of the members of a it qualifies as an authentic norm.
community.
Proxies such as professional codes and standards may be Hypernorms and Legitimacy
used to point toward potential authentic norms under ISCT.
Thus far, the only mechanism that would protect a dissent-
But when there is evidence that most members of the com-
ing individual from having an ethical obligation to comply
munity hold a different view, the proxy does not represent
with a distasteful norm is the right to leave the community
an authentic norm. For example, the ethics code of the Pro-
or try to change the norm. Beyond that, it appears as though
fessional Marketing Research Society (PMRS) of Canada
the "is" has become the "ought." To avoid excessive rela-
(1984) specifies that "good practice" requires that inter-
tivism and recognizing that communities develop authentic
viewers indicate to the respondent "a reasonably accurate
norms supporting racial and gender discrimination and oth-
estimate of the duration of the interview." Yet a survey of
er problematic practices, ISCT assumes that the original
Canadian marketing researchers, including PMRS members,
contractors would wish to recognize a thin set of universal
by Laroche, McGown, and Rainville (1986) suggests that
principles that would constrain the relativism of community
providing respondents with accurate estimates of the length
moral free space. Accordingly, the third term of the
of research interviews may not be an authentic norm.
macrosocial contract states:
Seventy-two percent of their sample agreed that misleading
respondents about the duration of an interview was a com- 3. To be obligatory, a microsocial contract norm must be com-
mon industry practice; 76% had confronted the practice, of patible with hypemorms (i.e., the "hypernorms" term).
which 86% had done it themselves. The ultimate, definitive
source of norms lies in the attitudes and behaviors of the According to ISCT, a hypemorm is a norm by which au-
members of the relevant communities. Thus, the authentic thentic norms are tested. The term "legitimate" is used to de-
norm of this sample of the Canadian marketing research scribe an authentic norm that has passed the hypernorm test.
community appears to be that misleading respondents about Hypernorms are defined (Donaldson and Dunfee 1994, p.
interview duration is acceptable. 265) as "principles so fundamental to human existence that
A major impact of ISCT is to establish that authentic ... we would expect them to be refiected in a convergence of
norms (which also satisfy the other requirements of ISCT religious, philosophical, and cultural beliefs." As expressed
by Walzer (1992, p. 9), they would be a "set of standards to
which all societies can be held—negative injunctions, most
'Note that we have added voice to the macrosocial contract likely, rules against murder, deceit, torture, oppression, and
terms initially envisioned by Donaldson and Dunfee (1994). Con- tyranny." This is a high standard for a set of universal prin-
sistent with Hirschman (1970), we believe that voice is parallel to ciples, and presumably, the number and scope of such stan-
exit as a fundamental alternative for economic agents and, there-
fore, that the option to exercise voice must be present to justify the dards would be, as Walzer suggests, rather small. This is
imposition of microsocial contract norms on economic agents. In appropriate when we consider the dominant role of hyper-
addition, we have made a minor amendment to the fourth term of norms and their effect of constraining choice within local
the macrosocial contract, which establishes priority rules. communities by overriding any and all inconsistent norms

Marketing Ethics/19
or standards. An overly thick set of hypernorms could con- itively correct as examples of hypernorms. The following
strain diversity across cultures by imposing a straightjacket are three candidates:
of suffocating morality. Advocates of diversity in morality
1. Firms should adopt adequate health and safety standards for
rightly are concerned about the threat of a professional or employees and grant employees the right to know about
educational elite defining and enforcing a large set of moral job-related health hazards (Frederick 1991, p. 166);
preferences on individuals on the basis of some stylized 2. People should not lie; they should speak and act truthfully
conception of the good. (Parliament of the World's Religions 1993, p. 11); and
An obvious question is, how do we ascertain the exis- 3. Businesses should be expected to honor their obligations in
tence of particular hypernorms? Donaldson and Dunfee a spirit of honesty and faimess (Caux Round Table Secre-
(1994) describe the efforts of anthropologists, political sci- tariat 1994, Section 2, Principle 1).
entists, and philosophers, among others, who are searching
for a convergence of beliefs and values at the global level. Hypernorms thus bound the moral free space of com-
Scholars from many cultures and academic disciplines are munities. If, for example, a hypernorm prohibiting bribery
asking similar questions regarding what humans commonly can be sustained, any authentic norm recognizing bribery
believe. An appropriate starting point would be an attempt to among, say, a community of corrupt government officials in
identify the extent of convergence among the convergence Russia is not legitimate ipso facto. However, hypernorms do
scholars.2 not provide a complete bounding of the moral free space of
In support of the claim for the existence of hypernorms, communities. The issue of conflict between two or more
we can point to studies that find similar methods of moral norms that are legitimate still might arise.
reasoning across cultures (Kohlberg 1968) and agreement
regarding certain core principles across large samples of Priority Rules for Conflicting Norms
managers (Kanter 1991). The evidence from the many stud- The final term of the macrosocial contract is as follows:
ies that seek to compare the attitudes and behaviors of man-
agers from two or three cultures is mixed but may be 4. In the case of conflicts among norms that satisfy Terms 1-3,
priority must be established through the application of rules
interpreted in a manner consistent with the concept of hy-
consistent with the spirit of the overall macrosocial contract
pernorms. Although these studies show a divergence of (i.e., the "priority rules" term).
views on certain issues, such as software copying, they tend
to show agreement regarding more fundamental concepts, Multiple legitimate norms applicable to the same ethical
such as the value of trust (Swinyard, Rinne, and Kau 1990). judgment may conflict. This may happen when a transaction
Furthermore, it is not critical to the existence of hypernorms crosses two distinctly different communities, often the case
to show substantial agreement on a single form of expres- in marketing and global business. For example, a European
sion. Walzer (1994, p. 18) argues that "minimalism" (his firm doing business in Beijing must decide whether it will
term for what Donaldson and Dunfee 1994 call hypernorms) follow the local practice of Guanxi, in which Chinese offi-
"is not foundational: it is not the case that different groups cials want their children hired for a job at a U.S. plant. The
of people discover that they are all committed to the same action, acceptable in China, violates norms of fairness in the
set of ultimate values." Instead, minimalism "consists in United States. Here, both norms are recognized as authentic,
principles and rules that are reiterated in different times and and both may be considered legitimate because neither vio-
places, and that are seen to be similar even though they are lates a hypernorm. To resolve such problems, ISCT speci-
expressed in different idioms and reflect different histories fies (Donaldson and Dunfee 1995, pp. 105-106) a loose set
and different versions of the world" (Walzer 1994, p. 17). of six priority rules derived from the basic assumptions and
Can examples be provided? Frederick (1991) studied six terms of the macrosocial contract and influenced by con-
intergovernmental compacts (including the Organization for cepts that underlie principles of international conflicts of
Economic Cooperation and Development [OECD] Guide- law and dispute resolution. They are as follows:
lines for Multinational Enterprises, the Helsinki Final Act,
1. Transactions solely within a single community, which do not
and the International Labour Organisation Tripartite Decla- have significant adverse effects on other humans or commu-
ration of Principles Concerning Multinational Enterprises) nities, should be governed by the host community's norms;
to identify principles common to the set. Similarly, we could 2. Community norms for resolving priority should be applied,
study the statements of global organizations as potential as long as they do not have significant adverse effects on
sources of hypernorms. The principles for business devel- other humans or communities;
oped by the Caux Round Table (1994) (which meets annu- 3. The more extensive the community that is the source of the
ally in Caux, Switzerland) are a prime example, as is the norm, the greater the priority that should be given to the
"Declaration Toward a Global Ethic," produced by the norm;
Council for a Parliament of the World's Religions (1993). 4. Norms essential to the maintenance of the economic envi-
From these, we can pull some samples that seem to be intu- ronment in which the transaction occurs should have priori-
ty over norms potentially damaging to that environment;
5. When multiple conflicting norms are involved, patterns of
consistency among the altemative norms provide a basis for
2For an elaboration of this and other issues about how decision prioritization; and
makers might apply ISCT, see Donaldson and Dunfee (1999), par- 6. Well-defined norms ordinarily should have priority over
ticularly Chapter 7. more general, less precise norms.

20 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999


Some of the more challenging issues of marketing ethics a transaction crossing two (or more) communities or in the
involve conflicting legitimate norms. The marketing re- case of a marketer f^acing a decision relevant to two (or
search community, for example, may believe that some more) communities with mutually exclusive norms in which
"soft" deception of respondents is acceptable to obtain re- he or she is simultaneously a member.
sults that further the goals of marketing research and con- In the next section, we examine the issue of commercial
tribute to the general economic welfare. The broader social bribery using ISCT. We summarize conventional arguments
community may have an opposite norm and believe that full regarding its moral status and demonstrate how ISCT often
disclosure of who is behind research or its purposes is nec- provides important insights in judging marketing decisions
essary to justify the respondent's participation. Thus, the re- that could involve bribery.
search community accepts a utilitarian justification, whereas
the broader social community is concerned about dignity
and a right to consent. Both norms may pass the hypernorm ISCT and Commercial Bribery
and exit/voice tests so that both are legitimate. According to Marketing Ethics and the Issue of Bribery
ISCT, the priority rules are to be applied as a set, not in iso-
lation. For a given dilemma, several rules might be involved. Noonan's (1984) chronological account of bribery as a
The rules are not given priority themselves in the writings moral concept traces its origins back to 3000 B.C. Despite its
about ISCT to date; they presumably are to be weighed condemnation, bribery has persisted as a corrupt practice in
human affairs. Nonetheless, Noonan foresees a time when
loosely and applied without a strict calculus of relative val-
bribery, similar to slavery, will become obsolete, at least in
ue. In this case, the fourth rule (norms essential to the trans-
its central form of the exchange of payment for official ac-
action environment) would support the soft deception. But
tion. This would be good news for business and, especially,
the third, fifth, and (possibly) the second rule might appear for marketers. Bribery typically tops the list of practices that
to support the norms of the broader social community, re- U.S. business executives would most like to have eliminat-
quiring disclosure to the participant. ed from their industry (Baumhart 1961; Brenner and Molan-
The process by which ISCT may be applied ex ante by der 1977); accordingly, it is featured prominently in most
marketing practitioners to ethical dilemmas produced by corporate codes of conduct. Chonko and Hunt's (1985) sur-
conflicting norms is demonstrated in Figure 1. In Figure 1, vey of American Marketing Association members found
we show how the priority rules would operate in the case of that marketing managers identified bribery as the most dif-

FIGURE 1
The ISCT Decision Process: Multiple Communities and Multiple Competing Norms

Multiple Remaining Ethical


All norms
Ethical Appropriate community legitimate Judgment
screened
relevant norms norms screened based on
evaluation for legitimacy
communities identified and for dominance dominant
required under
identified tested for under legitimate
hypemorm test
authenticity priority rules norm

If no clearly dominant
norm, may base decision Ethical judgment
on any legitimate norm based on a
legitimate norm
in moral free space

Priority Rules

1. Adverse effects on others.


2. Priority rules adopted as norms within communities.
3. Relative size of communities.
4. Indispensable to transaction environment.
5. Patterns of consistency across communities.
6. Whether norm is well defined.

Marketing Ethics/21
ficult ethical issue they faced. Trevino and Nelson (1995, p. not sitting here damning Young & Rubicam as a horrible,
273) observe that it is the "most frequent source of anxiety corrupt organization. Throughout, there were a lot of very
for American business persons operating abroad." With the honest people connected with this."
increasing importance of global marketing, the U.S. gov-
ernment, lobbied by business, has stepped up efforts to se- Bribery Defined
cure the prohibition of transnational bribery (Nichols 1997). Bribery must be defined carefully to avoid ambiguity, both
The prototypical problem areas with global bribery involve in determining its moral status and in identifying whether a
the marketing function: promotional expenses such as trav- given action constitutes a bribe. Bribery occurs when one
el and entertainment for purchasing agents, hiring of self- person (the briber) provides an inducement to another per-
described marketing agents, customs payments in a channel son (the bribee) that is intended to be in exchange for the
of distribution, exchanges of gifts and entertainment during bribee doing, or not doing, something that would favor the
the negotiation process, and so on. Clearly, commercial briber and be contrary to the bribee's positional duty. One
bribery is one of the most important ethical issues in indication that bribery is a moral concept is evident from its
marketing. definition as a violation of duty. Bribery has been defined
Bribery has been studied empirically in marketing, but more rigorously, as follows (Philips 1984, pp. 625-26):
little attention has been given to a normative evaluation Pis bribed by R if and only if (1) P accepts payment from
(notable exceptions are Fritzsche 1985; Laczniak and Mur- R to act on R's behalf, (2) P's act on R's behalf consists in
phy 1993). In contrast, the ethics of bribery have been ex- violating some rule or understanding constitutive of a
amined thoroughly in the broader fields of business and practice in which P is engaged, and (3) either P's violation
applied ethics. We rely on these analyses to define the con- is a violation of some official duty P has by virtue of his
cept of bribery and provide the conventional moral argu- participation in that practice or P's violation significantly
affects the interests of persons or organizations whose
ments against bribery, as well as justifications advanced in
interests are typically connected to that practice.
its favor. We then show how ISCT can be applied to bribery.
Bribery is a particularly appropriate issue for exploring the Much analysis of bribery focuses on violations of duty
implications of social contract-based analysis, especially by public officials, including activities outside the commer-
bribery in a global context. Our discussion of bribery will cial sphere, such as payments to sway judges in criminal
involve the following two cases: cases. Yet it is apparent from the preceding definitions that
Honda (Jenkins 1996; Miller 1994; Robinson 1997; The bribery may occur within private-sector commercial trans-
Wall Street Journal 1998). During the 1980s and early actions, as in the Honda example. Private-sector commercial
1990s, Honda dealers paid more than $15 million directly to bribery, as generally defined in U.S. legal statutes, consists
Honda executives to get extra allotments of popular Honda of "conferring a benefit on an employee, agent, or fiduciary
and Acura models that typically sold at a premium to the with intent to influence the recipient's conduct in his princi-
pal's affairs" (Noonan 1984, p. 578). In a principal-agent
manufacturer's sticker price. Gifts included shopping sprees
analysis, the bribee violates the trust of his or her principal
in Hong Kong, cash, and checks for children's college tu-
and becomes the agent of another in exchange for payment.
ition. Two dozen Honda dealers and executives were indict-
Accordingly, D'Andrade (1985, p. 239) has referred to
ed, including senior vice presidents and regional managers. bribery as the "alienation of agency."
Two were convicted in court trials, and twenty pled guilty.
At the trial of the two convicted officials, the defense The Moral Status of Bribery: Deontological and
claimed that bribery was an accepted practice at American Consequentiaiist Approaches
Honda and was a way to keep salaries below the industry
norm. Stanley Cardiges, the senior vice president in charge Normative evaluation of bribery could draw on multiple the-
of sales, was the main benefactor of the bribery, receiving ories of moral philosophy. Fritzsche (1985) and Shaw
more than $5 million during a ten-year period when his (1988) use theories of justice. However, the major works on
salary was $125,000. Prosecutors called the case the largest bribery in applied ethics are largely deontological or conse-
commercial bribery case in U.S. history. Subsequently, 1800 quentiaiist. This is not surprising; because of their impor-
dealers sued in a class action, alleging that they were pun- tance, extant frameworks in marketing ethics also rely
ished if they failed to pay exorbitant bribes. Honda ulti- heavily on these theories (Hunt and Vitell 1993).
mately settled the case for $330 million. ^ A deontological approach. From a deontological per-
Young & Rubicam (Hall 1989; Lipman 1990). In 1990, spective, bribery is wrong when it involves an intentional vi-
Young & Rubicam (Y&R) pled guilty to conspiring to vio- olation of a binding moral duty. In such a case, both the
late the Foreign Corrupt Practices Act (FCPA) and paid a briber and the bribee may have engaged in an unethical act.
fine of $500,000. The charges resulted from claims that The action of offering a bribe may be immoral because a
Y&R had made payments to Arnold Foote, a Jamaican busi- person should not entice others to do what is morally wrong
ness executive, who used the money to bribe the Jamaican (Carson 1985), among other reasons. The bribee's moral du-
Minister of Tourism, Eric Abrahams, to win an advertising ty stems from a special obligation that comes with the posi-
account for Jamaican tourism. The resulting contract pro- tion he or she holds; acceptance of a bribe conflicts with the
duced the award-winning advertising campaign "Make it Ja- bribee's binding obligations to a principal and thus would be
maica, Again," featuring the song "Come Back to Jamaica." a violation of a contract or a breach of promise (Carson
In bringing the indictment, the U.S. attorney stated: "I'm 1985; Philips 1984). When the agent is a public official, a

22 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999


broader obligation to the public may be involved. Abra- fact-finding. We also must consider the possibility that some
hams's actions in the Y&R case violated his duties as a gov- justifications for bribery may carry moral weight.
ernment minister, as well as broader obligations of public From the deontological perspective, bribery is only pri-
trust to the citizens of Jamaica. ma facie wrong. This means that there may be considera-
In private-sector bribery, such as the Honda case, though tions that override the duties violated by bribery; it is not a
bribees typically are in violation of duties to their employ- categorical rule (Pastin and Hooker 1988). Consider the
ers, it is less clear that any broader duty exists. The Honda manager who, in violation of company policy, made a pay-
executives had obligations that derived from their employ- ment (some years ago) to a South African official not to en-
ment contracts and basic job requirements to allocate new force the rules of apartheid. Moreover, a briber may have
cars in a certain manner. They accepted personal induce- overriding duties, such as to protect the welfare of other em-
ments to act inconsistently with that duty. D'Andrade (1985) ployees, when deciding whether to pay a bribe. Or, the
extends this analysis to suggest that many employees of pri- briber may have duties to him- or herself or family when co-
vate businesses have a quasi-official status, similar to that of erced, physically or economically, into making a payment.
public officials. In addition, there may be problems associated with how
duty-based approaches are applied. For example, it may be
A consequentialist approach. Bribery may be judged un- difficult to identify the duties that an agent owes to his or her
ethical from a consequentialist perspective when it produces principal. It is often suggested that customs agents do not vi-
overall bad consequences. Direct or microenvironmental ef- olate a duty when they take small payments to perform their
fects may include the following: Bribery may lead to a sub- duties because these payments are regarded as an expected
optimal purchase decision by the organization on whose part of their compensation (though the right to accept pay-
behalf the bribee ostensibly acts. The bribing organization ments generally is not specified expressly, and there are of-
may need to falsify its accounts to hide the payment, there- ten questions as to whether the right indeed exists and the
by defrauding stockholders. In its purpose of obtaining an scope of permissible payments). A similar argument was ad-
unfair advantage for one supplier, bribery harms that suppli- vanced to justify bribery in the Honda case, with executives'
er's competitors. In the Y&R case, it may be presumed that low salaries offered in justification. The payments were
competing agencies were disadvantaged unfairly if they did claimed to be part of the intended compensation scheme.
not engage in bribery. Bribery may contribute to the corrup- Moreover, there may be conflicting duties. Although some
tion of the moral character of the bribee, which may lead to argue there is a duty not to bribe a public official, others ar-
future harmful actions. In contrast, direct good conse- gue for a counter-duty to shareholders that requires bribery
quences of bribery also may be identified, particularly by of public officials when that appears to be the most prof-
marketing decision makers, including saving jobs, enhanc- itable long-run business decision (Pastin and Hooker 1988).
ing shareholder wealth, and maintaining an ability to pay
creditors. Applying consequentialist theories to specific cases of
Indirect or macroenvironmental effects of bribery can bribery also can be difficult. The forecasting required to as-
include economic inefficiencies. Public-sector bribery is a sess probable consequences may be beyond the capacity of
form of rent-seeking by business that can lead to inefficient both marketing managers and business ethicists. How, for
allocations of resources, including the diversion of time and example, should Y&R executives have weighed the negative
resources away from the production of useful goods and ser- effects of their bribery on competitors as compared with its
vices or the implementation of monopolistic pricing prac- positive effects on their own firm and even, perhaps, on the
tices (Becker 1994; Nichols 1997). One effect of corrupt nation of Jamaica, if we assume that they believed they
senior government officials is their tendency to favor could develop the best advertising campaign? Business ethi-
public-sector spending that provides more opportunity for cists have suggested similar arguments. Green (1991) has
bribery, such as infrastructure and defense projects, rather developed an explicitly consequentialist framework that
than education or health care. Both public- and private- would allow payments of bribes by smaller firms that other-
sector bribery distort the market mechanism; the secrecy of wise might incur large harms if the inducement were not
bribery means that price information is less meaningful, provided. Pastin and Hooker (1988) employ a consequen-
again leading to allocation inefficiencies. More broadly, tialist analysis as part of their attack on the FCPA (but also
there may be diminished trust in the economic system. Oth- see Alpern's 1988 reply).
er indirect consequences include the wider social harm of Perceived positive effects of bribery, at least from the
corruption. Nichols (1997) refers to its corrosive effect on vantage point of the briber, may lead to its attempted justifi-
the social structure, including the diminished happiness of cation. For example, it may be argued that payment of a
the citizenry, reduced credibility and viability of the govern- bribe may retain jobs, save a substantial capital investment,
ment, increased lawlessness, and even the potential for pub- or open an important market. Thus, it could be claimed that
lic disgust supportive of revolution. paying the bribe would generate significant positive returns
to shareholders. Moreover, consider the direct negative ef-
Problems with these approaches. In the abstract at least, fects of bribery listed previously and how a potential briber
bribery appears to be generally unethical when analyzed might discount them. The bribee may have long ago passed
from deontological and consequentialist perspectives. How- the point at which the briber is causing him or her any fur-
ever, the application of these approaches to specific cases of ther moral harm. Falsifying accounts may be fraud against
bribery often requires complex judgments and extensive shareholders, but if offset by a significant increase in share-

Marketing Ethics / 23
holder wealth, this could be perceived as no more than a mi- cepting the bribes may have believed that the system was
nor reporting peccadillo. The bribe may serve to guarantee not rewarding them adequately, especially given Honda's
that the bribee chooses the "best" supplier for the organiza- marketing success, and that they were entitled to adopt a
tion for which he or she acts. Finally, doing harm to com- mutually beneficial system that provided extra compensa-
petitors may be regarded as business as usual or, at most, as tion. However, not all dealers shared this perspective. In a
one negative consequence in an otherwise entirely positive suit filed against Honda, a former Acura dealer in New
set of consequences. Although we are unlikely to ever know, Hampshire claimed that because he did not cooperate, he
Y&R executives may have engaged in some of this reason- could not obtain the cars he needed and was forced to sell
ing in deciding to allow Foote to bribe Abrahams. In sum- his dealership (Robinson 1997). In the class action, 1800
mary, in a consequentialist analysis, the ethical evaluation dealers sued, charging that the bribery racket was under the
amounts to balancing many potential costs and benefits direction of top company executives. If these protesting
from the perspective of their impact on those affected by the dealers represent a majority of dealers, the acceptability of
payment. Such judgments are plagued by the seemingly in- bribery was not an authentic norm among the entire com-
tractable problems of forecasting and incommensurability. munity of Honda dealers. Therefore, bribery in the Honda
We examine the role of ISCT in responding to these and case is not morally permissible under the first condition. If
other concerns. First, however, we provide a social con- they are not a majority or if the dealers are treated as multi-
tract-based analysis of bribery. ple communities, then nonbribing dealers at least must be
treated as a relevant community in the analysis.
The Moral Status of Bribery in Social Contract In seeking to identify authentic ethical norms, it is es-
Approaches sential to consider all potentially relevant communities.
Therefore, when communities with probribery authentic
As our preceding review of social contract theory indicates,
norms are identified, it is important to take into account oth-
an evaluation of bribery from a basic social contract per-
er relevant communities that might have antibribery norms.
spective would judge it unethical when it is shown to con-
In the Y&R case, there is solid evidence that the broader po-
stitute a fundamental violation of the social contract
litical community in Jamaica condemned the practice of
between business and society. Philips (1984, p. 627) lends
bribery. That the payment was kept secret would appear to
support to this analysis and suggests that the moral obliga-
tions of the bribee stem from a social contract model of or- indicate that the participants were aware of a contrary norm
ganizations: "By accepting a position in an organization ... in the broader community. The strong negative reactions in
one tacitly agrees to abide by the rules of that organization. both the United States and Jamaica when the payments were
To be bribed is to violate that agreement... and is, therefore, disclosed constitute further support for the existence of an
prima facie wrong." Hence, a basic social contract analysis antibribery norm in those communities. Furthermore, the
suggests that bribery is often unethical, at least in the ab- broader communities are the ones that bear the negative
stract. As a particular formulation of social contract theory, costs of the practice and rationally would be expected to
ISCT allows that claim to be made much more strongly in have an antibribery norm.
relation to specific cases of bribery. When all relevant communities and authentic norms
have been identified, it becomes necessary to determine that
Consider how consequentialist and deontological theo-
ries might be applied to the Honda example. Some Honda the norms do not violate a hypernorm and are therefore le-
dealers might have concluded that bribery was a competitive gitimate. We believe that the practice in the Y&R case,
necessity and that, if it was practiced by all dealers, it would which involved a coarse selling of public assets for private
not result in bad (direct) consequences; conceivably, they gain, violates a hypernorm. Bribery is condemned in some
might argue that there would be only good consequences. form throughout the world, as Nichols (1997, p. 324) makes
Furthermore, they might have had difficulty identifying a vi- clear:
olation of duty by the bribees, if the practice was widespread Corruption and bribery cannot be claimed as accepted phe-
and seemingly condoned by Honda. However, ISCT sug- nomena in any culture. These acts are condemned by each
gests a different and potentially more compelling analysis. of the major moral and religious codes. They are criminal-
ized by every country. And they are universally despised,
Bribery would be morally permissible under ISCT if all particularly by those who endure corrupt governments.
of the following conditions hold: First, the acceptability of
bribery is an authentic norm of the communities involved, This claim supports the idea of a convergence of opinion
that is, a norm held by a majority of community members. and wisdom to the effect that coarse public-sector bribery is
Second, the norms of all relevant communities have been condemned by a hypernorm. The concept of a hypernorm is
considered. Third, the acceptability of bribery is a legitimate central to the application of ISCT. It serves as a constraint
norm; that is, it does not violate a hypernorm. Fourth and fi- on the moral free space of communities while providing a
nally, any conflict among communities' norms is resolved source of guidance for ethicists and business decision mak-
by the priority rules in favor of the communities sustaining ers. The small set of hypernorms believed to exist as part of
the acceptability of bribery. We analyze the Honda and Y&R the assumptions of the macrosocial contract is universally
cases following this procedure. applicable to all cultures and business functions. In that
In the Honda case, it is possible that the acceptability of sense, there are not marketing hypernorms or U.S. hyper-
bribery as a means of allocating new cars was an authentic norms, per se. But there may be hypernorms that are espe-
norm of the Honda marketing managers and a subset of the cially relevant to a particular business function, such as
dealers. The bribing dealers and the marketing managers ac- marketing.

24 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999


Accordingly, one possible hypernorm is that the bribery legal act under the FCPA. However, less than half of the sur-
of officials who exchange significant public-sector assets for vey respondents condemned the payment, perhaps because
substantial personal gain is wrong. An antibribery hyper- they believed that the payment could be justified. We now
norm is supported by the condemnation of bribery in explic- examine some of the popular justifications for making such
it terms by texts of Buddhism, Christianity, Confucianism, payments.
Hinduism, Islam, Judaism, and Sikhism; Adam Smith and It is often claimed that "certain payments should not be
MaoTse-tung also have condemned bribery (Nichols 1997). counted as bribes, or that, even though they are bribes, they
Coarse public-sector bribery is legally prohibited in every are still acceptable, generally as the lesser of two evils"
country, even those considered the most corrupt (Nichols (D'Andrade 1997, p. 47). Some payoffs may be defended as
1997; Noonan 1984). Indeed, a multicultural team explicitly coerced by physical or severe economic extortion. Pay-
applying ISCT has identified such a hypernorm (Fritzsche et ments also may be justified as mere "grease payments," le-
al. 1995). A case also might be made that the coarser forms gitimate third party commissions, or gifts. Justifications for
of private-sector bribery violate a hypernorm, even though bribery also may be based on arguments about cultural dif-
this does not involve the violation of public trust that occurs ferences in transnational bribery or on claims of greater
when the bribee is a public official. There is, after all, a harm resulting from failure to pay the bribe. Through an
growing consensus across many world communities that emphasis on understanding community norms, ISCT helps
bribery is wrong and that significant efforts should be taken clarify these justifications.
to limit its practice, prompting new initiatives by multilater-
al organizations such as the OECD (Mason and de Jon- Extortion as justiftcation. Extortion payments are made
quieres 1997). under duress. Payment is demanded by the bribee, with the
threat of serious harm for nonpayment. Nichols (1997, p.
The implications for the two examples are as follows: 317) defines extortion as "using the power of an official's
The coarse public-sector bribery found in the Y&R case vi- office to extract payments." Corporate agents, as well as
olates a hypernorm and thus could be evaluated on this ba- government officials, may practice extortion. In the United
sis alone as unethical under ISCT. The application of an States, a buyer for the retailer JCPenney Co. was prosecut-
antibribery hypernorm is more problematic in the Honda ed for taking up to $1.5 million from vendors. One vendor
case because public-sector officials were not involved. claimed that the buyer was engaging in extortion and sued
However, putting aside the possibility of a private-sector JCPenney, charging that payment was a matter of survival:
antibribery hypernorm, this case still may be problematic "If I had not paid him and he pulled the line as he had threat-
because it is not necessary to rely solely on hypernorms to ened, I'd have gone out of business" (Gerlin 1995, p. A16).
determine whether the payments were ethical. We turn to the This vendor explained that he could not report the buyer to
priority rules to resolve the confiict between the possible au- the company because he was the Buyer of the Year and high-
thentic norms that supported the payments and other norms ly regarded by JCPenney.
that opposed the practice. Acting as an extortionist is always morally problematic.
The priority rules are used to resolve confiicts in norms Giving in to genuine extortion also may be problematic.
between communities. The third and fourth priority rules Philips (1984) observes that it is morally wrong to pay off
might be used to show that bribery in Honda would not be extortionists in some cases. Under U.S. law, evidence of
permissible under ISCT. The third priority rule determines duress is admissible to establish the nature of the intent in-
priority on the basis of the relative size of the communities. volved in the payment. D'Andrade (1985, p. 245) also sug-
It would favor the nonbribing dealers if they represent a larg- gests that extortion payments are excusable in some
er group, because greater priority is given to the norms of circumstances, noting that "we just do not expect moral
more extensive communities. The fourth priority rule deter- heroism." Turow (1985, p. 251) concludes that "bribery can
mines priority on the basis of whether a norm is indispens- be justified only if the bribe-giver is truly without
able to the transaction environment. It also would appear to alternatives."
favor the nonbribing dealers, because an antibribery norm is An ISCT-based analysis of bribery focuses on commu-
arguably essential to their economic environment and thus nity norms to determine when extortion demands should be
would have priority over a norm that favored bribery, which, resisted or, contrariwise, when they may be accepted. Al-
if widely adopted, could harm that environment. though we may not expect moral heroism of marketers,
there may be a legitimate expectation on the part of society
ISCT and Justifications Advanced for Bribery of a certain amount of "moral courage" (Mahoney 1998), a
willingness to face down evil and accept some self-sacrifice.
In a survey of more than 2000 U.S. business executives,
However, the extent to which we might expect moral hero-
Longenecker, McKinney, and Moore (1988, p. 343) asked
ism by marketers will vary across communities, refiecting
respondents whether they considered the following scenario
differing norms about how to face extortion. For example, in
"personally acceptable": a situation in which corruption is negligible, strongly prose-
A company paid a $350,000 "consulting" fee to an oftlcial cuted, and rarely associated with threats of physical harm,
of a foreign country. In return, the official promised assis- there may be an increased expectation that marketers will
tance in obtaining a contract, which should produce a $10 not bow to extortion. Accordingly, acceding to extortion in
million profit for the contracting company. many markets in the United States may be less morally jus-
Assuming that the official would act in violation of a posi- tifiable than in circumstances often found in, say, Nigeria or
tional duty, we have a clear illustration of bribery and an il- Russia.

Marketing Ethics / 25
Grease payments and legitimate commissions. A firm corporate boxes at sports stadiums, special golf outings, and
may make small payments to induce public officials to car- meals at fancy restaurants. Yet, in spite of what appears to
ry out their official and nondiscretionary duties, often re- be a strongly entrenched practice, there is some evicience of
ferred to as a "facilitating" or "grease" payment. Although a countertrend. American businesses seem increasingly to
the action may have been carried out more expeditiously, it be questioning the role of gifts and entertainment in con-
does not confer a substantial advantage on the party making ducting business (Priest 1998). From an ISCT perspective,
the payment. Similarly, a firm may provide bona fide com- the norms of gift giving and entertainment in U.S. business
pensation to a middleman to promote or demonstrate its are changing. General Motors, for example, recently intro-
products and services. Both types of payment may be legal duced a policy that forbids its employees from accepting
under the FCPA. The FCPA expressly recognizes that there free meals, hockey tickets, golf outings, or most other gifts
may be small payments made to obtain permits or licenses from vendors (Sedgwick 1996). Vendors complained that
to do business, get mail or telephone service, process visas, the new policy restricted the scope for building the social re-
or get cargo loaded (particularly for perishable products). lationships necessary for good business relationships. Gen-
But judgment is required. What types of payments can be eral Motor's concern, however, is that their gifts and
justified as facilitating payments? Or, what happens when entertainment were tantamount to bribery.
the marketing intermediary (or joint venture partner) uses Those who provide such largess are on the horns of a
part of the "commission" to pay a large bribe to a public of- dilemma. If they believe that hosting buyers in corporate
ficial, as in the Y&R case? Sometimes, it is difficult to know boxes makes no difference in the buyer's behavior, as some-
where the payment is actually going and, thus, whether it is times is claimed, then how can they justify the expenditures
legitimate (Kaikati and Label 1980). The law seeks to deter- to their shareholders? If they are spending the money and
mine whether there is an awareness of a high probability of getting nothing in return, the shareholders would appear to
the existence of a prohibited circumstance. Principles such have a legitimate complaint that corporate assets are being
as "willful blindness" and "conscious disregard" are used to squandered. If, conversely, gifts and entertainment are in ex-
prohibit a firm from purposely establishing opaque informa- change for preferential treatment, then providing them may
tion channels and thereby being able to deny knowledge of be considered an act of bribery. Priest's (1998, p. 6) advice
wrongdoing. Although in some circumstances it may be dif- is to "build strong business relationships but don't be cor-
ficult to account for the size or recipients of such payments, rupted by them."
purposeful ignorance is not a permissible justification for If the practice is consistent with background norms that
bribery. provide the ground rules, as it were, for proper gift giving in
The ethical issue of when a payment may be proper runs business transactions, it may be acceptable under ISCT. The
norms specify the boundaries for acceptable social lubrica-
parallel to this legal approach. The critical distinction is the
tion while also providing markers of what is excessive and
nature of the official function purchased and whether it in-
out of bounds. The norms vary in their details over time and
volves a violation of duty by the official (Nichols 1997;
among industries. Perhaps in recognition of this phenome-
Philips 1984). However, companies often overlook this non, many companies have policies on accepting gifts that
rather fine distinction. For example, when Gulf Oil Corpo- appear vague, because they ask employees simply to "exer-
ration was attempting to expand its distribution in Italy, it cise good judgment." This may be interpreted as instructing
made off-the-book payments to government officials to se- employees to rely on their knowledge of industry norms and
cure the permits it needed to open new service stations. Gulf practices. Other companies have strict, often monetary, lim-
officials characterized these payments as "tipping" (Noonan its on what may be received. Although such policies may re-
1984, p. 639). duce the appearance of bribery, they also may be at odds
Thus, an ISCT-based analysis recognizes that the social with well-understood norms of acceptable behavior. When
contract in some communities defines these payments as ac- this occurs, the overly restrictive norms are not likely to be
ceptable bribery or, perhaps, not even as bribery at all. The well received by either vendors or companies' own
firm is responsible f^or knowing the relevant norms in the employees.
specific community in question and, more important, in tbe Gift giving and entertainment, particularly in the context
broader communities influenced by the decision. Such of business-to-business exchanges, may be analyzed for-
knowledge would enable firms to respond appropriately and mally using ISCT. Consider the trend whereby companies
avoid mistakes such as Gulf's. increasingly are sending out "no presents" letters during the
Gift giving and entertainment. Relationships constitute December holidays. Absent evidence of close personal
an important foundation for business. This fundamental fact friendship, gifts (and entertainment) in excess of industry
is recognized explicitly in the marketing function through norms are indicative of bribery. These letters specify com-
relationship marketing and selling. In many cultures, norms pany policy regarding what its employees may receive as
pertaining to proper behavior among people in all walks of gifts and ask that suppliers observe these rules. This can re-
life often specify the giving of gifts and providing of enter- sult in a classic conflicts-of-norms situation. One firm, an
tainment in appropriate circumstances. However, bribes al- aggressive marketer, uses gifts and entertainment to build
so can take the form of gifts and entertainment. relationships. The firm sending the letter, however, seeks to
The United States has a long tradition of gifts and enter- limit the pernicious effect gifts may have on its purchasing
tainment in business relationships. A large industry exists agents. Although duties might otherwise be unclear and con-
that encompasses well-known practices such as parties in sequences difficult to parse out, ISCT approaches the con-

26 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999


flict by directing the corporate policymaker to identify or- man (1986, p. 136) refers to Coca-Cola in Egypt, noting that
ganizational, industry, and national norms pertaining to gift "to sell cola. Coke did not bribe ministers, it planted trees."
giving (these norms often will be well known or easy to But why not bribe if, apparently, it is culturally accept-
identify). Under ISCT, if the firm sending the "no presents" able? Various writers agree that bribery is not unethical if it
letters is acting in a manner consistent with industry and na- is an accepted practice in the culture in which it takes place
tional norms (and thus the letter refers to a legitimate, au- (D'Andrade 1985; Danley 1983; Philips 1984). Longeneck-
thentic norm), it should dominate the norms of the selling er, McKinney, and Moore (1988, p. 341), after noting that
firm. According to the priority rules, the "no presents" nonn for some people "the international setting modifies the ethi-
is essential to the transaction environment, is consistent with cal character of bribery," report that many of their respon-
other community norms, and represents that organization's dents justified bribery with the adage: "When in Rome, do
preference regarding confiicts of norms. as the Romans do." At issue, then, is the acceptability of
bribery in different cultures.
Acceptability of bribery in some cultures. Many cultures
A justification often offered for bribery in foreign mar-
accept and encourage the presence of certain forms of gift
kets is that standards are different and, implicitly, lower.
giving in business and personal relationships. However, so-
However, this claim is made notwithstanding the prevalence
cieties always face the concern that their economic systems
of bribery in the United States and other Western countries
be able to generate wealth and allocate resources efficiently,
(in the 1997 rankings of the prevalence of corruption by
a goal that may be compromised by corrupt behavior. A
Transparency International, a highly regarded nongovern-
plausible community response is to develop norms that
mental organization, the United States ranked 16, France 20,
specify the boundaries of acceptable behavior. This may
and Italy 30, where lower numbers mean less corruption).
help account for highly ritual gift-giving practices in many
Moreover, while noting that in some societies there is not
cultures. Background norms provide guidance as to the tim-
necessarily a violation of duties when an official shows fa-
ing and amount of gifts and the context in which they may
voritism to friends and kinsmen. Philips (1984, p. 636)
be given and accepted. Those who act outside of these
warns of the risk of "bribery in ethnic dress." It has also
norms do so at their peril.
been suggested that Western businesspeople too readily pre-
Fadiman (1986) offers a rich description of how tradition sume a requirement for bribery, especially when frustrated
plays an important role in business in non-Western cultures. by red tape and inefficient government practices (Pitman
He describes how he misunderstood requests for Chai and and Sanford 1994). As noted in The Economist {19SS), per-
Zawadi—which can be Swahili terms for "bribe"—when haps it is LDCs (less developed countries) that are brought
conducting business in East Africa. He turned down his down by MNCs (multinational corporations), not the other
prospective business partner's request for cash and a radio, way round.
only later to discover that they were intended for a feast in In response, ISCT provides a framework specifically set
his honor that, in keeping with tradition, would have been an up to resolve the ethical issues arising between communi-
introduction to his partner's social and business contacts. ties. According to our previous analysis, bribery in a foreign
Building on this anecdote, Fadiman explains how, in more country would be morally permissible under ISCT if its ef-
communal societies, there are often obligations of protection fects were limited largely to the community in which it was
and assistance that extend beyond the nuclear family to an acceptable (assuming bribery does not violate a hypernorm).
inner circle of "comrades and kin." In these societies, there Thus, arguments in favor of bribery in certain culturally de-
is a preference for business relationships with people in the fined contexts may be interpreted in a manner consistent
inner circle who are known and trusted. Accordingly, there with ISCT. But it would be rare that such a situation would
are various traditional ways by which such relationships are hold. In practice, there typically would be some affected
developed, including future favors and gift giving. Fadiman communities for which the acceptance of bribery is not an
(1986, p. 126) explains, "any individual under obligation to authentic norm. In any specific situation, however, this may
another has entered a relationship in which the first favor be subject to empirical verification. What ISCT does in this
must be repaid in the future." This ongoing process builds case is prompt the marketer to identify all relevant commu-
trust and is different from Western approaches: "Western in- nities. At least when managers have good knowledge of the
terest lies in doing business; non-Western, in forming bonds countries and cultures in which they operate, empirical re-
so that business can begin. Westerners seek to discharge search should not be necessary. If, as D'Andrade (1985)
obligations; non-Westerners, to create them" (Fadiman suggests, there is always a third party to bribery, we might
1986, p. 126). Gift giving is one way of creating future argue that it is never sufficient to consider only the norms of
obligation. the immediate participants in bribery. As in our analysis of
In some cultures, Fadiman (1986) suggests, gifts that the Y&R case, we must instead observe the broader com-
would be viewed as unacceptable bribes in other cultures are munities within which bribery occurs. The insistence of
still regarded as merely gifts. Accordingly, he advises West- ISCT on attention to the relevant communities and their
ern businesspeople to understand the local context first and norms and its priority rules that favor larger or more exten-
then look for legal, ethical, and culturally appropriate ways sive communities generally can be expected to lead to the
to meet the local partner's expectations. For example, non- identification of overriding antibribery norms.
monetary responses or public donations might be possible Competitive disadvantage as a justification for bribery.
that meet the business partner's desire for local recognition, Bribery has been justified as an unfortunate necessity, be-
as well as consolidate the relationship. As an example, Fadi- cause a likely outcome is the loss of business to a bribe-

Marketing Ethics / 27
paying competitor. The justification often is tied to a conse- noir of moral philosophy. In the field of business ethics, it is
quentialist analysis, with the briber arguing that payment attacked as illogical and self-defeating; relativism "repre-
preserves jobs, increases profits, and produces future busi- sents an admission that our human reason can no longer be
ness opportunities. It also may be akin to the extortion argu- useful ... that we must engage in ... deception, physical co-
ment, because the bribee's threat of lost business may be ercion, even war, rather than try to do the admittedly diffi-
regarded as a form of economic coercion. In that context, cult job of resolving conflicting moral viewpoints"
the justification offered by a deontological analysis would (Freeman and Gilbert 1988, p. 39). In spite of this, some the-
ije that the briber lacked intent because of the overcoming of orists of marketing ethics have explicitly (Robin and Rei-
free will by the economic threat. The consequentialist argu- denbach 1993) or implicitly (Thompson 1995) advocated a
form of relativism as an effective approach to problems of
ment has been recognized implicitly in the broad claim that
U.S. companies are at a competitive disadvantage because marketing ethics. Fear of being branded a relativist may re-
of their inability to make payments due to the FCPA. How- sult in the downplaying of the role of community, organiza-
ever, evidence for this is mixed (The Economist 1988; tional, and professional norms. Yet, as recognized in most of
Kaikati and Label 1980; Nichols 1997; Pastin and Hooker the descriptive approaches to marketing ethics (e.g.. Hunt
1988). and Vitell 1986, 1993), background norms are important in
- The moral justification for a payment due to competitive making normative judgments about marketing practices.
disadvantage must depend in part on the extent of the harm Appropriately, ISCT invokes the use of a traditional, accept-
threatened. Competitive disadvantage is likely to be less sig- ed philosophical methodology (social contracts) to legiti-
nificant when it pertains to a threat to future business mate giving significant weight to authentic norms of
prospects, in contrast with a direct threat to existing and sub- marketing ethics. The ultimate impact of ISCT is to provide
stantial capital investment. Whether competitors are likely a middle ground in which marketing norms may be given
to make payments to obtain the business also should be a weight, yet are checked by hypernorms and the occasional
factor. In the JCPenney case discussed previously, prosecu- priority of other communities.
tors discovered that other vendors had rejected requests for ISCT provides a formal definition for authentic norms
payment and not suffered, contrary to the extortion claim. In and relevant communities that are often important compo-
the Honda case, there is evidence of harm resulting to deal- nents in marketing ethics frameworks. Many of the extant
ers who chose not to make payoffs. marketing ethics f^rameworks are designed to explain indi-
Competitive disadvantage is less likely to justify bribery vidual decision making (see Table 1). They are thus subject
under ISCT. Only if authentic ethical norms support such to the individuals' own preferences regarding the choice of
payments and, even then, no hypernorms are violated can moral reasoning and the recognition of others' interests.
ISCT be used to support such a payment. Furthermore, there This would seem to allow for an egoist to make successful
may be contrary norms in other communities, which also use of the model. One response to a concern about potential
would not allow the briber to use competitive disadvantage egoism is to recognize a leavening role for social norms.
as an argument in support of payments. Thompson (1995) recognizes them as a source of cultural
meanings, Mascarenhas (1995) as the source of standards
for fault or accountability, and Hunt and Vitell (1986) as a
Implications of ISCT for Marketing source of duties. Sparks and Hunt (1998) identify awareness
Ethics of norms as an influence on ethical sensitivity. In ISCT,
recognition of the role of norms is extended by specifying
A social contract perspective on marketing ethics, especial-
the sources of norms and the processes by which norms are
ly within the framework provided by ISCT, would appear to
to be identified for normative analysis.
offer considerable insight on the issue of bribery, going be-
yond that provided by extant approaches. In this section, we ISCT encourages decision makers to consider the norms
illustrate ISCT's broader potential and consider its implica- of all relevant communities and thus ensures a broad con-
tions for managers and researchers by examining it in rela- sideration of stakeholder interests. In addition to the eight
tion to other normative frameworks and noting its particular tests in their framework for ethical reasoning, Laczniak and
applicability to marketing. We then conclude this section by Murphy (1993, p. 51) add stakeholders, recognizing that
Identifying opportunities that ISCT provides to researchers "weighing the concerns of multiple stakeholder groups ...
in marketing ethics and by showing how marketing research becomes the essence of appropriate ethical decision-making
techniques may facilitate application of ISCT. ... [and] the root of the complexity of such decision-
making." In its emphasis on the norms of relevant commu-
I$CT Compared with Extant Normative nities, ISCT provides a systematic method to encourage
frameworks decision makers to make sure they have considered all pos-
sible communities that may have a significant interest in a
We first study how ISCT supplements, complements, or oth- decision. Sparks and Hunt (1998) find that ethical sensitivi-
irwise informs the existing models of marketing ethics. ty, which involves the ability to recognize and ascribe im-
What are the general merits of an ISCT-based analysis, rel- portance to an ethical issue, is learned. Their results indicate
ative to extant approaches? that ethical sensitivity of marketing researchers may be in-
ISCT provides normative legitimizationfor the relevance fluenced more by organizational than by professional
of community and professional norms. Relativism is the bete norms. They suggest that this may be due in part to the

28 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999


youth of the marketing research profession and its less sys- often a community (sometimes nested within more general
tematic structures and activities, compared with professions communities) that has developed norms that may signifi-
such as law, medicine, and accounting. The emphasis of cantly affect the exchange process (consider, for example,
ISCT on searching for relevant norms in broader communi- the global diamond business). Simply put, the exchange
ties may enhance ethical sensitivity on the part of marketing transaction cannot be understood fully without reference to
researchers. the communities and norms in which it is embedded.
ISCT acknowledges the role of a small set of universal The potentialfor ISCT to integrate the normative and de-
standards that can serve to limit the excessive relativism of
scriptive streams of research in marketing ethics literature.
some frameworks. The concept of a hypernorm is central to
To date, in marketing as in many other domains, the norma-
the application of ISCT. It serves as a constraint on the
tive and descriptive research streams have followed separate
moral free space of communities while providing a source
courses with little or no overlap. In ISCT, the conflict be-
of guidance for ethicists and business decision makers.
tween the "is" of descriptive research and the "ought" of
ISCT provides a means for dealing with cross-cultural normative research may be bridged. Theoretieally, ISCT re-
issues. With the possible exception of Thompson (1995), the quires both the normative and the descriptive to function ad-
marketing ethics frameworks do not deal explicitly with the equately; thus, it defines a significant role for each.
problem of cross-cultural application, including their use by Practically, ISCT's willingness to consider any authentic, le-
someone more familiar with Eastern philosophies who may gitimate norm as binding on the community and its insis-
not be inclined to apply Western deontological or teleologi- tence on the existence of various microsocial contracts that
cal thinking. The moral free space recognized in ISCT is are community-based offer considerable scope for the "is"
open to cultural and philosophical diversity. In many of the of descriptive research. Yet its insistence on the existence of
marketing ethics frameworks, divergent answers may be ob-
hypernorms and priority rules for dealing with conflicting
tained when the framework is invoked by, on the one hand,
authentic, legitimate norms offers a true normative founda-
a manager in the United States and, on the other, a manager
tion with considerable scope for continuing conceptual de-
in Japan. These frameworks and models are generally silent
regarding how such divergence is to be handled. velopment. (We discuss the implications of ISCT for
empirical research in more detail subsequently.)
ISCT's Particular Applicability to Marketing Social contract theory is all the more relevant given the
The advantages of ISCT relative to extant approaches are development of relationship marketing (Dwyer, Schurr, and
applicable to its use throughout business ethics. However, Oh 1987; Morgan and Hunt 1994). Relationship marketing,
we suggest that ISCT is especially applicable when the mar- with its emphasis on fostering ongoing, tightly linked rela-
keter's activity spans multiple communities with conflicting tionships between buyers and sellers, implicitly acknowl-
norms, particularly, for example, in international marketing, edges the role of shared values. Clear recognition of buyer
relationship marketing, and personal selling and sales man- and seller expectations pertaining to the other's behavior
agement. This leads to the reasons ISCT is particularly ap- will influence successful interactions and become reflected
plicable to marketing. in norms that essentially frame their relationship. Perhaps
more important, tightly linked marketing relationships
The role of the marketing manager as a boundary span-
themselves may become communities with their own
ner (Singh 1993), operating at the interface between the
norms. A foundational principle of relational marketing is
corporation and its customers, competitors, and channel
trust. Norms based in informal social contracts are critical to
members. As a boundary spanner, the marketer is subject to
the norms of many communities, including the marketer's the development of trust in exchange relationships (Gund-
firm, the marketer's department, the industry or market- lach and Murphy 1993). Social norms provide a more flex-
place, the individual customers, and the channel. Thus, ible and enduring fabric for relationships than do other
ISCT's explicit recognition of many microsocial contracts alternative fibers, such as litigation or government regula-
and the communities that spawn them provides a framework tion. In ISCT, there is a framework for understanding and
for understanding the ethical pressures on the marketer and potentially resolving the ethical issues that arise in this
providing guidance to marketing managers. context.

The theoretical congruence of ISCT as a framework for Managerial attractiveness—that ISCT will be found in-
examining exchange relationships. We noted previously that tellectually comfortable for many educated, reflective mar-
the exchange concept is fundamental to marketing and so- keting practitioners. The limitations of a strict use of
cial contract theory and, thus, that contractarian approaches utilitarianism or any one of the other basic models probably
appear particularly appropriate for ethical reasoning in mar- have led to the focus by marketing ethics researchers on
keting. By bringing clearer focus to the ethical ambiguities composite models as they have sought realistic, pragmatic
associated with exchange, ISCT sharpens these advantages. approaches. The basic notions of ISCT—community-
• Exchange occurs between parties who are each simultane- specific, authentic norms that are acceptable if they fit with
ously members of multiple communities. Each party draws a small set of hypernorms and do not conflict with norms of
the norms that guide his or her beliefs, attitudes, and behav- other significant communities—would seem to provide lati-
1 iors from a relevant set of communities. Moreover, the ex- tude for professionalism, coupled with realistic checks and
change transaction itself occurs in an environment that is balances that should be appealing to marketing managers.

Marketing Ethics/29
Implications for Researchers Research to advance ISCT. Research on the more diffi-
cult ethical issues in marketing, possibly augmented by the
Given the foregoing implications, we believe that ISCT pro-
application of marketing research techniques, represents
vides marketing researchers with greater scope for making
one set of directions for further research. In addition, there
normative contributions to marketing ethics literature by
is scope to develop ISCT further. In relation to hypernorms,
evaluating some of the more troubling ethical issues in mar-
the application of ISCT would benefit from a more defini-
keting, such as privacy obligations in the cross-marketing of
tive set. This is no small task. A starting point might be to
financial services, conflicting goals in the marketing of for-
identify hypernorms that are especially relevant to particu-
profit health care, intersegment differences in the acceptable
lar business functions, such as marketing. We suggest pos-
level of product safety (especially across different country
sible marketing-relevant hypernorms in the hope that others
markets), conflicts of interest in personal selling, the ac-
will extend and, where necessary, modify our list. We base
ceptability of puffery in advertising, and fairness in pricing.
our suggestions on the assumption that they reflect a suffi-
We show how empirical research may be critical to an ISCT-
cient convergence of thought and opinion to satisfy the def-
based analysis of some of these issues. We then conclude
inition of hypernorm used in ISCT.
this section by identifying directions for further research
that may advance ISCT. •People should be treated with dignity and respect in all mar-
keting transactions.
Marketing research techniques may facilitate the appli-
•Promises should be kept.
cation of ISCT. In ISCT, reliance is placed on actual com-
munity norms. This attribute imposes a prerequisite for the •Deception of any sort in marketing transactions or marketing
research is wrong unless a substantial justification convinc-
successful application of ISCT: accurate information re-
ing to the membership of all relevant communities is possi-
garding community norms or adequate proxies from which
ble.
to infer those norms. Several marketing research techniques,
•Property rights, including intellectual property, consistent
particularly those associated with ascertaining a person's witii widespread views of the nature of property should be re-
brand or store loyalty, can be applied to this problem. Broad- spected.
ly, these divide into three classes of techniques: (1) direct in- •Bribery of officials who exchange substantial public sector
quiry, for example, techniques based on Fishbein and assets for personal gain is wrong.
Ajzen's (1975) work; (2) indirect inquiry, for example, con-
joint analysis-based techniques (Green and Wind 1975); or Norms represent another area of research that could ad-
(3) measurement of behavior. The first type is subject to vance ISCT. More specifically, what are the antecedents of
self-presentation issues, making the latter two classes more authentic and legitimate norms in a community? How trans-
attractive (though both are more complicated to administer). ferable are norms? How easy is it for firms or professional
In particular, some conjoint analysis-based techniques have associations to impose norms on new members?
the distinct advantage of being derived from preferences for
complete scenarios rather than directly elicited. As such,
they are less susceptible to biases of both self-presentation
Conclusion
and self-deception. And for deeper probing of community In this article, we have explored the real potential that social
norms and the basis for those norms, other techniques, such contract theory in general and ISCT in particular has for the
as focus groups, might make a real contribution. Thus, well- field of marketing ethics. We view them as complementing
established marketing research techniques are available to and strengthening the existing frameworks and constructs
assist with the identification of authentic norms in defined for marketing ethics. To recapitulate, ISCT has several sig-
communities. nificant theoretical advantages. First, it provides a core set
This suggests a different approach to marketing ethics of principles—hypernorms—that may be used to specify the
research, one that would be norm-focused rather than issue- line of the moral minimum that no marketing practitioner
focused. Studies could be conducted on the authenticity and should ever cross. Second, it explicitly recognizes differ-
legitimacy of norms espoused by marketing communities. ences across communities and the conflict that differing
For example, is there substantial agreement among sales- community-based norms engender and develops a process
people in particular industries that denigration of a competi- for resolving that conflict. Third, it offers a process for de-
tor's product is acceptable conduct? termining the appropriateness, that is, the authenticity and
Yet one of the challenging issues in applying ISCT is legitimacy, of a community-based nonn. Fourth, ISCT pro-
defining the boundaries of a community. Market segmenta- vides a legitimating theoretical foundation for much of the
tion techniques, such as cluster or discriminant analysis, and emphasis on norms, attitudes, beliefs, and cultural meanings
dimensional reduction techniques can be used to ascertain in the field of marketing ethics.
community membership and the parameters that actually de- We have suggested a symbiotic relationship between
fine membership. More qualitative methodologies, such as ISCT and marketing, such that ISCT complements frame-
those associated with subcultural and reference group deter- works for ethical decision making in marketing and pro-
mination, also could prove useful. Thus, in a sense, there is vides greater clarity regarding judgments about some of the
a symbiotic connection between ISCT and marketing. difficult issues in marketing ethics, such as bribery. At the
Whereas ISCT provides a useful ethical framework for mar- same time, marketing research, perhaps more than any oth-
keting, marketing provides the empirical techniques neces- er field, offers techniques that can enable ISCT to be effec-
sary to use ISCT at its best. tively and efficiently applied.

30 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999


REFERENCES
Akaah, Ishmael P. and Edward A. Riordan (1989), "Judgments of ical Theory and Business, Tom L. Beauchamp and Norman E.
Marketing Professionals About Ethical Issues in Marketing Re- Bowie, eds. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 97-106.
search: A Replication and Extension," Journal of Marketing Re- Fadiman, Jeffrey A. (1986), "A Traveler's Guide to Gifts and
search, 26 (February), 112-20. Bribes," Harvard Business Review, 64 (July/August), 122-36.
Alpern, Kenneth D. (1988), "Moral Dimensions of the Foreign Ferrell, O.C. and Larry G. Gresham (1985), "A Contingency
Corrupt Practices Act: Comments on Pastin and Hooker," in Framework for Understanding Ethical Decision Making in Mar-
Ethical Issues in Business, Thomas Donaldson and Patricia H. keting," Journal of Marketing, 49 (Summer), 87-96.
Werhane, eds. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 54-59. Fishbein, Martin and Icek Ajzen (1975), Belief, Attitude, Intention:
Baumhart, Raymond C. (1961), "How Ethical Are Businessmen?" An Introduction to Theory and Research. Reading, PA: Addison
Harvard Business Review, 39 (July/August), 6-19, 156-76. Wesley.
Becker, Gary S. (1994), 'To Root Out Corruption, Boot Out Big Frederick, William C. (1991), 'The Moral Authority of Transna-
Government," BusinessWeek, (January 31), 18. tional Corporate Codes," Journal of Business Ethics, 10
Bellizzi, Joseph A. and Robert E. Hite (1989), "Supervising Uneth- (March), 165-77.
ical Salesforce Behavior," Journal of Marketing, 53 (April), (1995), Values, Nature, and Culture in the American Cor-
36-47. poration. New York: Oxford University Press.
Binmore, Kenneth (1994), Game Theory and the Social Contract, Freeman, R. Edward and Daniel R. Gilbert Jr. (1988), Corporate
Vol. I: Playing Fair. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Strategy and the Search for Ethics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Pren-
Blau, Judith R. (1993), Social Contracts and Economic Markets. tice Hall.
New York: Plenum Press. Fritzsche, David J. (1985), "Ethical Issues in Marketing Manage-
Brenner, Steven N. and Earl A. Molander (1977), "Is the Ethics of ment," in Marketing Ethics: Guidelines for Managers, Gene R.
Business Changing?" Harvard Business Review, 55 Laczniak and Patrick E. Murphy, eds. Lexington, MA: Lexing-
(January/February), 57-71. ton Books, 85-96.
Bowie, Norman E. and Ronald F. Duska (1990), Business Ethics.
, Y. Paul Huo, Sakae Sugai, and Stephen Dun-Hou Tsai
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
(1995), "Exploring the Ethical Behavior of Managers: A Com-
Buchanan, Allen (1988), Ethics, Efficiency, and the Market. To-
parative Study of Four Countries," Asia Pacific Journal of Man-
towa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.
agement, 12 (October), 37-61.
Business Ethics Quarterly (1995), "Special Issue on Social Con-
Gerlin, Andrea, (1995) "How a Penney Buyer Made Up to $1.5 Mil-
tracts and Business Ethics," 5 (April).
lion on Vendor's Kickbacks," The Wall Street Journal, (February
Carson, Thomas L. (1985), "Bribery, Extortion, and 'The Foreign
7),A1.
Corrupt Practices Act'," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14
(Winter), 66-90. Goolsby, Jerry R. and Shelby D. Hunt (1992), "Cognitive Moral
Development and Marketing," Journal of Marketing, 56 (Janu-
Caux Round Table Secretariat (1994), Caux Round Table Principles
ary), 55-68.
for Business. Washington, DC: Caux Round Table.
Chonko, Lawrence B. and Shelby D. Hunt (1985), "Ethics and Mar- Green, Paul E. and Yoram Wind (1975), "New Way to Measure
keting Management: An Empirical Investigation," Journal of Consumers' Judgments," Harvard Business Review, 53
Business Research, 13 (August), 339-59. (July/August), 107-17.
Culnan, Mary J. (1995), "Consumer Awareness of Name Removal Green, Ronald M. (1991) "When Is 'Everyone's Doing It' a Moral
Procedures: Implications for Direct Marketing," Journal of Di- Justification?" Business Ethics Quarterly, 1 (January), 75-94.
rect Marketing, 9 (Spring), 10-19. Gundlach, Gregory T. and Patrick E. Murphy (1993), "Ethical and
D'Andrade, Kendall (1985), "Bribery," Journal of Business Ethics, Legal Foundations of Relational Marketing Exchanges," Jour-
4 (August), 239-48. nal of Marketing, 57 (October), 35-46.
(1997), "Bribery," in Encyclopedic Dictionary of Business Hall, Carol (1989), "Life's a Beach, and Then You're Indicted; How
Ethics, Patricia H. Werhane and R. Edward Freeman, eds. Cam- a Dream Ad Account Became Y&R's Nightmare," Newsday,
bridge, MA: Blackwell, 46-48. (November 6), 1.
Danley, John R. (1983), 'Toward a Theory of Bribery," Business Hampton, Jean (1992), 'Thomas Hobbes," in Encyclopedia of
and Professional Ethics Journal, 2 (Spring), 19-39. Ethics, Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, eds. New
Donaldson, Thomas (1982), Corporations and Morality. Engle- York: Garland Publishing, 543-49.
wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Hartman, Edwin M. (1996), Organizational Ethics and the Good
(1989), The Ethics of International Business. New York: Life. New York: Oxford University Press.
Oxford tJniversity Press. Heide, Jan B. and George John (1992), "Do Norms Matter in Mar-
• and Thomas W. Dunfee (1994), 'Towards a Unified Con- keting Relationships?" Journal of Marketing, 56 (April), 32-44.
ception of Business Ethics: Integrative Social Contracts The- .Hirschman, Albert O. (1970), Exit, Voice, and Loyalty. Cambridge,
ory," Academy of Management Review, 19 (April), 252-84. MA: Harvard University Press.
and (1995), "Integrative Social Contracts Theory: Hosmer, LaRue T. (1994), "Strategic Planning as if Ethics Mat-
A Communitarian Conception of Economic Ethics," Economics tered," Strategic Management Journal, 15 (Summer), 17-34.
and Philosophy, II (April), 85-112. Hunt, Shelby D. (1983), Marketing Theory: The Philosophy of Mar-
and (1999), Ties that Bind: A Social Contracts Ap- keting Science. Homewood, IL: Richard D. Irwin.
proach to Business Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business and Scott J. Vitell (1986), "A General Theory of Marketing
School Press. Ethics," Journal of Macromarketing, 6 (Spring), 5-16.
Dunfee, Thomas W. and Thomas Donaldson (1995), "Contractarian and (1993), "A General Theory of Marketing
Business Ethics: Current Status and Next Steps," Business Ethics: A Retrospective and Revision," in Ethics in Marketing,
Ethics Quarterly, 5 (April), 173-86. N. Craig Smith and John A. Quelch, eds. Homewood, IL:
Dwyer, F Robert, Paul H. Schurr, and Sejo Oh (1987), "Develop- Richard D. Irwin, 775-84.
ing Buyer-Seller Relationships," Journal of Marketing, 51 Jenkins, Holman W. (1996), '"Tis the Season of Sin at Honda," The
(April), 11-27. Wall Street Journal, (December 17), A23.
The Economist (1988), "On the Take," (November 19), 21. Kaikati, Jack G. and Wayne A. Label (1980), "American Bribery
Evan, William M. and R. Edward Freeman (1988), "A Stakeholder Legislation: An Obstacle to International Marketing," Journal of
Theory of the Modem Corporation: Kantian Capitalism," in Eth- Marketing, 44 (Fall), 3 8 ^ 3 .

Marketing Ethics / 31
Kanter, Rosabeth Moss (1991), 'Transcending Business Bound- Reath, Andrews (1992), "Jean-Jacques Rousseau," in Encyclopedia
aries: 12,000 World Managers View Change," Harvard Business of Ethics, Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, eds.
Review, 69 (May/June), 151-66. New York: Garland Publishing, 1112-16.
Keeley, Michael (1988), A Social Contract Theory of Organiza- Reidenbach, R. Eric and Donald P. Robin (1990), 'Toward the De-
tions. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. velopment of a Multidimensional Scale for Improving Evalua-
Kohlberg, Lawrence (1968), 'The Child as a Moral Philosopher," tions of Business Ethics," Journal of Business Ethics, 9
Psychology Today, 2 (September), 25-30. (August), 639-53.
Kotler, Philip (1972), "A Generic Concept of Marketing," Journal Robertson, Diana C. and Erin Anderson (1993), "Control System
of Marketing, 36 (April), 46-54. and Task Environment Effects on Ethical Judgment: An Ex-
Kultgen, John (1986), "Comments on Donaldson's Corporations ploratory Study of Industrial Salespeople," Organization Sci-
and Morality," Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 5 ( 1 ) , ence, 4 (November), 617-44.
28-39. and William T. Ross Jr. (1995), "Decision-Making Process-
Laczniak, Gene R. (1983), "Framework for Analyzing Marketing es on Ethical Issues: The Impact of a Social Contract Perspec-
Elhics," Journal of Macromarketing, 1 (Spring), 7-18. tive," Business Ethics Quarterly, 5 (April), 213-40.
and Patrick E. Murphy (1993), Ethical Marketing Decisions: Robin, Donald P and R. Eric Reidenbach (1987), "Social Respon-
The Higher Road. Needham Heights, MA: AUyn and Bacon. sibility, Ethics, and Marketing Strategy: Closing the Gap Be-
Laroche, Michel, K.L. McGown, and Joyce Rainville (1986), "How tween Concept and Application," Journal of Marketing, 51
Ethical Are Professional Marketing Researchers?" Business Fo- (January), 44-58.
rum, II (Winter), 21-25. and (1993), "Searching for a Place to Stand: To-
LeClair, Debbie Thome, O.C. Ferrell, and Linda Ferrell (1997), ward a Workable Ethical Philosophy for Marketing," Journal of
"Federal Sentencing Guidelines for Organizations: Legal, Eth- Public Policy & Marketing, 12 (Spring), 97-105.
ical, and Public Policy Issues for International Marketing," Robinson, Edward A. (1997), "Fall of a Megadealer," Fortune,
Journal of Public Policy & Marketing, 16 (Spring), 26-37.
(April 28), 34.
Lind, E.A. and T.R. Tyler (1988), The Social Psychology of Proce-
dural Justice. New York: Plenum Press. Sedgwick, David (1996), "GM's New No-No Freebies Code Rais-
Lipman, Joanne (1990), "Young and Rubicam Settles Jamaica es Anxiety Level for Staff and Suppliers," Automotive News,
Case," The Wall Street Journal, (February 12), B4. (July 22), 1.
Longenecker, Justin G., Joseph A. McKinney, and Carlos W. Moore Shaw, Bill (1988), "Foreign Corrupt Practices Act: A Legal and
(1988), 'The Ethical Issue of International Bribery: A Study of Moral Analysis," Journal of Business Ethics, 1 (October),
Attitudes Among U.S. Business Professionals," Journal of Busi- 789-95.
ness Ethics, 7 (May), 341^6. Simmons, A. John (1992), "Obedience to Law," in Encyclopedia of
Macneil, Ian R. (1980), The New Social Contract. New Haven, CT: Ethics, Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, eds. New
Yale University Press. York: Garland Publishing, 918-21.
Mahoney, Jack (1998), "Ethical Attitudes to Bribery and Extortion," Singh, Jagdip (1993), "Boundary Role Ambiguity: Facets, Deter-
in Marketing Ethics: An International Perspective, Bodo minants, Impacts," Journal of Marketing, 57 (April), 11-31.
Schlegelmilch, ed. London: Intemational Thomson Business Smith, N. Craig (1995), "Marketing Strategies for the Ethics Era,"
Press, 283-301. Sloan Management Review, 36 (Summer), 85-97.
Mascarenhas, Oswald A.J. (1995), "Exonerating Unethical Market- Solomon, Robert (1993), Ethics and Excellence. New York: Oxford
ing Executive Behaviors: A Diagnostic Framework," Journal of University Press.
Marketing, 59 (April), 43-57. Sparks, John R. and Shelby D. Hunt (1998), "Marketing Researcher
Mason, John and Guy de Jonquieres (1997), "Goodbye Mr. 10%," Ethical Sensitivity: Conceptualization, Measurement, and Ex-
Financial Times, (July 22), 15. ploratory Investigation," Journal of Marketing, 62 (April),
Medina, Vicente (1993), Social Contract Theories: Political Oblig- 92-109.
ation or Anarchy? Savage, MD: Rowman and Littletield Pub- Stark, Andrew (1993), "What Is the Matter with Business Ethics?"
lishers. Harvard Business Review, 71 (May/June), 38-48.
Miller, Krystal (1994), "Former Honda Executives Plead Guilty to Swinyard, William R., Heikki Rinne, and Ah Keng Kau (1990),
Charges Tied to Bribes from Dealers," The Wall Street Journal, "The Morality of Software Piracy: A Cross-Cultural Analysis,"
(March 15), A4.
Journal of Business Ethics, 9 (August), 655-64.
Morgan, Robert M. and Shelby D. Hunt (1994), "The Commit-
ment-Trust Theory of Relationship Marketing," Journal of Thompson, Craig J. (1995), "A Contextualist Proposal for the Con-
Marketing, 58 (July), 20-38. ceptualization and Study of Marketing Ethics," Journal of Pub-
Nichols, Philip M. (1997), "Outlawing Transnational Bribery lic Policy & Marketing, 14 (Fall), 177-91.
Through the World Trade Organization," Law and Policy in In- Trevino, Linda K. and Katherine A. Nelson (1995), Managing Busi-
ternational Business, 28 (Winter), 305-81. ness Ethics: Straight Talk About How To Do tt Right. New York:
Noonan, John T. (1984), Bribes. New York: Macmillan Publishing John Wiley & Sons.
Tsalikis, John and David J. Fritzsche (1989), "Business Ethics: A
Company.
Parliament of the World's Religions (1993), Declaration Toward a Literature Review with a Focus on Marketing Ethics," Journal
Global Ethic. Chicago: Parliament of the World's Religions. of Business Ethics, 8 (September), 6 9 5 ^ 3 .
Pastin, Mark and Michael Hooker (1988), "Ethics and the Foreign Turow, Scott (1985), "What's Wrong with Bribery," Journal of
Corrupt Practices Act," in Ethical Issues in Business, Thomas Business Ethics, 4 (August), 249-51.
Donaldson and Patricia H. Werhane, eds. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: The Wall Street Journal (1998), "American Honda, Dealers' Accord
Prentice Hall, 48-53. Approved by Judge," (November 2), BI6.
Philips, Michael (1984), "Bribery," Ethics, 94 (July), 621-36. Walzer, Michael (1992), "Moral Minimalism," in The Twilight of
Pitman, Glenn A. and James P Sanford (1994), "The Foreign Cor- Probability: Ethics and Politics, W.R. Shea and G.A. Spadafo-
rupt Practices Act Revisited: Attempting to Regulate 'Ethical ra, eds. Canton, MA: Science History Publications, 3-14.
Bribes' in Global Business," International Journal of Purchas- (1994), Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and
ing and Materials Management, 30 (Summer), 15-24. Abroad. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Priest, Steve (1998), "Companies Seek Middle Ground on Gift Poli- Werhane, Patricia (1984), "Individual Rights in Business," in Just
cies," Federal Ethics Report, 5 (February), 1-6. Business: New Introductory Essays in Business Ethics, Tom Re-
Professional Marketing Research Society of Canada (1984), Rules gan, ed. New York: Random House, 100-128.
of Conduct and Good Practice of the Professional Marketing Williams, Oliver and Patrick E. Murphy (1990), "The Ethics of
Research Society of Canada. Toronto: Professional Marketing Virtue: A Moral Theory for Marketing," Journal of Macromar-
Research Society. keting, 10 (Spring), 19-29.

32 / Journal of Marketing, July 1999

You might also like