You are on page 1of 11

Individual Choice in Voting and the Market

Author(s): James M. Buchanan


Source: Journal of Political Economy , Aug., 1954, Vol. 62, No. 4 (Aug., 1954), pp. 334-
343
Published by: The University of Chicago Press

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1827235

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Journal of Political Economy

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INDIVIDUAL CHOICE IN VOTING AND THE MARKET'

JAMES M. BUCHANAN

Florida State University

TTIIS paper will compare individual making. Collective choice implies cen-
choice in the political voting proc- tralized choice, whatever the process of
ess and in the market process, with choosing; hence the market has been
both considered as ideal types. A sub- compared with the whole subset of polit-
stantial portion of the analysis will be ical choice processes ranging from pure
intuitively familiar to all social scien- democracy to authoritarian dictator-
tists, since it serves as a basis for a large ship.
part of political theory, on the one hand, This paper will compare the individual
and economic theory, on the other. Per- choices involved in the price system and
haps as a result of disciplinary specializa- in a single form of centralized decision-
tion, however, the similarities and the making-pure democracy. The individu-
differences between these two methods al act of participation in the choice proc-
of individual decision-making in liberal ess will be the point of reference. The
society are often overlooked. The state comparison does not, of course, imply
of things is illustrated in the prosaic that these two processes will be presented
"one-dollar-one-vote" analogy, which is, as genuine alternatives to the individ-
at best, only partially appropriate and ual, even in their somewhat less pure
which tends to conceal extremely im- forms. A more complete understanding
portant differences. of individual behavior in each process
It is necessary to emphasize the lim- should, however, provide some basis for
itations of this analysis. No attempt will deciding between the two, if and when
be made to compare market choice and they do exist as alternatives.
voting choice in terms of the relative ef- The following distinctions between
ficiency in achieving specified social individual choice in voting and the mar-
goals or, in other words, as means of ket will be discussed: (1) the degree of
social decision-making. Many compari- certainty, (2) the degree of social par-
sons of this sort have been made. In the ticipation, (3) the degree of responsibil-
great debate over the possibility of ra- ity, (4) the nature of the alternatives pre-
tional socialist calculation, the discus- sented, (5) the degree of coercion, and,
sion has been concerned primarily with finally, (6) the power relations among
the workability of political decision- individuals. Quite obviously, these dis-
making processes when confronted with
tinctions are somewhat arbitrarily iso-
the social criterion of economic efficiency.
lated from one another, and, in a broad
The issue has been framed, appropriate-
sense, each implies others. After these
ly, in terms of the relative efficiency of
are discussed, some attention will be
centralized and decentralized decision-
given to their influence on the selection
' I am indebted to Marshall Colberg, Jerome Milli-
of voting or the market as a decision-
man, and Vincent Thursby for helpful comments and
suggestions. making process for the social group.

334

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INDIVIDUAL CHOICE 335

I logical impossibility if individual choice


is accepted as meaningful. This inherent
It will be assumed that the individual
uncertainty confronting the voter can
chooser possesses the same degree of
knowledge concerning the results of al- perhaps be classified as genuine uncer-
tainty in the Knightian sense; it is not
ternative decisions in the polling place
subject to the application of the proba-
that he does in the market place.2 It is
bility calculus.
essential that this assumption be made
at this stage, in order that the first im- This uncertainty must influence to
portant distinction, that of the degree of some degree the behavior of the individu-
certainty, between individual choice in al in choosing among the possible social
voting and individual choice in the mar- alternatives offered to him. Whereas the
ket may be made clear. chooser in the market,5 assumed to know

In market choice the individual is the what he wants, will always take the at-

acting or choosing entity, as well as the tainable combination of goods and serv-
ices standing highest on his preference
entity for which choices are made. In
voting, the individual is an acting or scale, the voter will riot necessarily, or
choosing entity, but the collectivity is perhaps even probably, choose the alter-
the entity for which decisions are made. native most desirable to him. The actual
The individual in the market can pre- behavior of the voter must be examined
dict with absolute certainty the direct within the framework of a theory of
or immediate result of his action. The choice under uncertainty. As is well
act of choosing and the consequences of known, there is no fully acceptable theo-
choosing stand in a one-to-one corres- ry of behavior here, and there are some
pondence.3 On the other hand, the voter, students of the problem who deny the
even if he is fully omniscient in his fore- possibility of rational behavior in un-
sight of the consequences of each pos- certain conditions.6
sible collective decision, can never pre- II
dict with certainty which of the alter-
The second fundamental difference in
natives presented will be chosen. He can
the two choice processes is found in the
never predict the behavior of other vot-
sense or degree of participation in social
ers in the polling place. Reciprocal be-
decision-making. In the market the in-
havior prediction of this sort becomes a
dividual is confronted with a range of
2 This is a simplifying assumption; there is reasoncommodities and services, each of which
for believing that the individual possesses a greater
knowledge of alternatives in the market. This is due,is offered at a given price. Individually,
first, to the greater continuity of market choice an(l,the buyer or seller considers both the
second, to the difference in the degree of knowledge
range of alternatives and the set of prices
required to compare alternatives in each case. The
latter difference has been stressed by Professor Hayek
4Cf. Frank H. Knight, "Economic Theory and
(see F. A. Hayek, "Individualism: True and False,"
Nationalism," in his The Ethics of Competition (Lon-
Individualism and Economic Order [Chicago: Uni-
don: Allen & Unwin, 1935), p. 340.
versity of Chicago Press, 1948]; see also Robert A.
Dahl and Charles E. Lindblom, Politics, Economics, 6 The device of considering productive services as
and Welfare [New York: Harper & Bros., 1953], negatively desired and hence carrying negative prices
p. 63). enables both the buying and the selling activity of the
individual to be encompassed in "market choice."
3Cf. Kenneth J. Arrow, "Alternative Approaches
to the Theory of Choice in Risk-taking Situations," 6 See Arrow, op. cit., for an excellent summary of
Econometrica, XIX (1951), 405. the various theories of choice under uncertainty.

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
336 JAMES M. BUCHANAN

to be beyond his power to alter.7 He is The sense of participation in social


able, therefore, to assume himself apart choice may exert important effects on the
from, or external to, the social organiza- behavior of the individual. It seems prob-
tion which does influence the alternatives able that the representative individual
made available. IHle is unconscious of the will act in accordance with a different
secondary repercussions of his act of preference scale when he realizes that he
choice which serve to alter the allocation is choosing for the group rather than
of economic resources.8 The individual merely for himself. There are two reasons
tends to act as if all the social variables for this. First, his identification will tend
are determined outside his own behavior, to be broadened," and his "values" will
which, in this subjective sense, is non- be more likely to influence his ordering of
participating and therefore nonsocial.9 alternatives, whereas in market choice
The influence of the individual's actual his "tastes" may determine his deci-
behavior on the ultimate social decision sion.12 As an example, the individual mlay
made has no impact upon such behav- cast a ballot-box vote for the enforce-
ior."0 ment of prohibition at the same time
The individual in the polling place, by that he visits his bootlegger, without
contrast, recognizes that his vote is in- feeling that he is acting inconsistently.
fluential in determining the final collec- Even if the individual's welfare horizon
tive choice; he is fully conscious of his is not modified in a shift from market to
participation in social decision-making. voting choice, or vice versa, there is a
The individual act of choosing is, there- second, and perhaps equally important,
fore, social, even in a purely subjective reason for a rearrangement of his pref-
sense. erence scale and hence for some differ-
7 Cf. Ludwluig von Mlises, Human Action: A Treatiseence in behavior. The individual's rank-
on Economics (New Haven: Yale University Press, ing of alternatives in market choice as-
1949), p. 312.
sumes no action on the part of other in-
8The fact that individual behavior in the market
dividuals in specific correspondence to
sets off reactions which are not recognized or intended
by the actor, but which do control society's utilization his own. In voting, the choice is deter-
of resources, is stressed in a somewhat different con- mined from a ranking of alternative situ-
text by Dahl and Lindblom (op. cit., pp. 99-102).
They are concerned with the "spontaneous field con-
ations in each of which the position of
trol" exerted over the individual in this manner. the individual is collectively determined
"Control" in this sense, however, is no different from for him and for all other individuals in
that imposed by the natural environment or any other
the group.' As an example of this dif-
set of forces external to the individual (see Sec. V).
9 For a definition of social action see Max Weber, ference, businessmen in a perfectly com-
The Theory of Social and Economic Organization, trans. petitive industry marketing a product
A. M. Henderson and Talcott Parsons (New York: with an inelastic demand may vote to
Oxford University Press, 1947), p. 88.
approve governmentally imposed pro-
15 It has been advanced as a merit of the price
system that it does place the individual in a position "Dahl and Lindblom, op. cit., p. 422.
of adapting his behavior to the anonymous forces of
12Cf. Kenneth J. Arrow, Social Choice and Indi-
the market without at the same time feeling that he
vidual Values (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1951),
can participate in changing these forces. On this point
p.82.
see Hayek, op. cit., p. 24.
Market behavior can, of course, become "social" 13 Cf. William J. Baumol, Welfare Economics and
if the individual is made to realize the secondary re- Theory of the State (Cambridge: Harvard University
percussions of his action. Exceptional cases of such Press, 1952), p. 15; Trygve Haavelmo, "The Notion
realization may be present even in the perfectly com- of Involuntary Economic Decisions," Econometrica,
petitive economy, e.g.,"buyers'strikes." XVIII (1950), 3, 8.

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INDIVIDUAL CHOICE 337

duction limitations, while, if left to op- does not suggest, however, that the
erate independently, they would have no greater precision in the consideration of
incentive to restrict production. A fur- alternatives by individuals in the market
ther example may be used to illustrate implies that the costs and benefits taken
the case in which both these effects on into account are necessarily the proper
individual choice may be operative. A ones from the social point of view.15
man who in the unregulated market It seems quite possible that in many
economy would construct a billboard instances the apparent placing of "the
advertising his product might vote for public interest" above mere individual
the abolition of billboards because he or group interest in political decisions
considers such action preferable in terms represents nothing more than a failure
of group welfare and/or because his ownof the voters to consider fully the real
interests will be better served by such costs of the activity to be undertaken.
collectively imposed action. It is extremely difficult to determine
whether the affirmative vote of a non-
III
beneficiary individual for a public wel-
The difference in the individual's fare project implies that he is either act-
sense of social participation has its ob- ing socially in accordance with a "no-
verse, however, which may be intro- bler" ordering of alternatives or is esti-
duced as a third distinction between the mating his own self-interest in accordance
voting and market processes. Since vot- with a "collective-action" preference
ing implies collective choice, the respon- scale, or whether it suggests that he has
sibility for making any particular social failed to weigh adequately the oppor-
or collective decision is necessarily di- tunity costs of the project.
vicle(l. This seems clearly to affect the The difference in responsibility pro-
individual's interest in the choosing vides a basis for Professor Aises' argu-
process. Since a decision is to be made ment that an individual is "less corrup-
in any case, the single individual need tible" in the market.16 This right plau-
not act at all; he may abstain from vot- sibly be advanced without necessarily
ing while other individuals act. contradicting the claim that ballot-box
The responsibility for market deci- choice, if uncorrupted, is made in ac-
sions is uniquely concentrated on the cordance with a more inclusive and mnodi-
chooser; there can be no abstention.
fied value scale. A somewhat related
There is a tangible benefit as well as a
point has been made by Professor Speng-
cost involved in each market chooser's
ler when he says that there is, in voting
decision, while there is neither an im-
as compared with the market, "the tend-
mediately realizable and certain benefit
ency of the individual (especially when
nor an imputable cost normally involved
in the voter's choice.i4 This difference he is a part of a large and disciplined or-
tends to guarantee that a more precise '51n cases where spill-over effects are significant,
and objective consideration of alterna- the costs taken into account by the individual in the
market will clearly exclude some i-t-mportant elements
tive costs takes place in the minds of in-
of social costs (positive or negative) w hich should be
dividuals choosing in the market. This considered in the making of a social decision (see
Dahl and Lindblom, op. cit., p. 419).
14 On this point see Alfred C. Neal, "The 'Planning
Approach' in Public Economy," Quarterly Journal of 16 Ludwig von Mises, Socialism (new ed.; New
Economics, LIV (1940), 251. Haven: Yale University Press, 1951), p. 21.

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
338 JAMES M. BUCHANAN

ganization) more easily to lose ... politi- natives, which are regularly of the "all-
cal than economic autonomy."17 or-none"y variety.
For the individual, market choice
IV
amounts to the allocation of an unspe-
A fourth distinction, and perhaps one cialized and highly divisible resource
of the most important, between individ- (income-yielding capacity) among a
ual choice in voting and the market lies range of alternatives. On the other hand,
in the nature of the alternatives offered few voting schemes include means which
to the individual in each case. Choice enable an individual to break his total
implies that alternatives are mutually voting strength down into fractional
conflicting; otherwise, all would be parts. The attribute of scarcity has never
chosen, which is equivalent to saying been applied to voting strength; an ad-
that none would be chosen. It is in the ditional vote is granted to each individ-
precise way in which the alternatives ual when each new collective decision is
mutually conflict that the voting proc- made. In order for market choice to be
ess must be sharply distinguished from made similar to voting in this respect,
the market mechanism. each individual would be required to
Alternatives of market choice normal- devote his whole capacity in each mar-
ly conflict only in the sense that the law ket period to one commodity or service.
of diminishing returns is operative. This If only the buying side is taken into ac-
is true at the level both of the individual count, this means that the consumer's
chooser and of the social group. If an whole expenditure should be on one com-
individual desires more of a particular modity. It seems clear that this feature
commodity or service, the market nor- of the choice process can itself affect the
mally requires only that he take less of nature of the alternatives presented. If
another commodity or service. If all in- the individual were required to spend the
dividuals, through their market choices, whole of his income on one commodity,
indicate that more resources should be market alternatives would tend to be-
devoted to the production of a particular come mutually exclusive and to become
commodity, this requires only that less severely limited in number and variety.
resources be devoted to the production Most of the normally available goods and
of other commodities. services would disappear from the mar-
Alternatives of voting choice are more ket places.
normally mutually exclusive, that is, the The major share of the difference in
selection of one precludes the selection the nature of the alternatives presented
of another. This, too, is true at the level in the two choice processes must, how-
both of the individual chooser and of the ever, be attributed to fundamental dif-
whole system. The individual voter nor- ferences in the objects of choice them-
mally faces mutually exclusive choices selves. In a very real sense many voting
because of the indivisibility of his vote. choices can never be made in the market
Group choices tend to be mutually ex- because they are inherently more dif-
clusive by the very nature of the alter- ficult, involving, as they do, considera-
tions which cannot be taken into account
17J J. Spengler, "Generalists versus Specialists in
Social Science: An Economist's View," American
effectively by the individual choosing
Political Science Review, XLIV (1950), 378. only for himself. The choice to be made

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INDIVIDUAL CHOICE 339

is normally among two or more alterna- or service is exchanged in the market,


tives, only one of which may be chosen, the individual chooses from among ex-
with its very selection precluding the isting alternatives; at the secondary stage,
selection of the others. Even if the re- of which he is unconscious, his behavior
sults of the voting were to be based upon tends to direct economic resources in a
the proportionate number of votes cast specific manner.
for each alternative, combinations or In voting, the individual does not
composite solutions of the market type choose among existing but rather among
would not be possible in most cases. In- potential alternatives, and, as mentioned
herent in the market solution, by con- earlier, he is never secure in his belief
trast, is choice among an almost infinite that his vote will count positively. He
number of combinations of goods and may lose his vote and be placed in the
services, in each of which some of almost position of having cast his vote in op-
every conceivable good and service will position to the alternative finally chosen
be included.18 As a result of this differ- by the social group. He may be com-
ence, individual choice in the market can pelled to accept a result contrary to his ex-
be more articulate than in the voting pressed preference. A similar sort of coer-
booth. cion is never present in market choice. It
has been argued that pressure toward
V
social conformity "compels those out-
There follows directly from the dif- voted to make an expenditure against
ference in the nature of alternatives an their will."21 While it is no doubt true
extremely important fifth distinction that both the individual's earning and
between the voting process and the mar- expenditure patterns are conditioned to
ket process as faced by the individual a large degree by the average patterns of
choice-maker. If production indivisi- his social group, the distinction between
bilities may be disregarded (they would this indirectly coercive effect involved
not be present in the ideally competitive in the social urge to conform and the
world), each dollar vote in the market direct and unavoidable coercion involved
becomes positively effective"9 to the in- in collective decision seems an extremely
dividual, not only in providing him with important one.
a unit of the chosen commodity or serv- If the assumption of production divisi-
ice, but also in generating changes in the bility is relaxed, some modifications of
economic environment. In either of this conclusion must be made. Given the
these senses a dollar vote is never over- presence of indivisibility, the individual's
ruled; the individual is never placed in dollar vote may be overruled at the sec-
the position of being a member of a dis- ondary stage of the market choice proc-
senting minority.20 When a commodity ess. On the buying side, if the consumer's
dollar vote is not accompanied by enough
18 The market is thus the only system of propor-
tional representation which will likely work at fall 20 For an excellent summary discussion of this point
(cf. Clarence Philbrook, "Capitalism and the Rule of see Von Mises, Illtman Action: A Treatise on Eco-
Love," Southern Economzic Journal, XIX [1953], 466). nomics, p. 271.
19 A decision to sell productive services may be con- 21 Dahl and Lindblom, op. cit., p. 424. A similar
position is taken by Professor Howard Bowen (see
sidered as a vote for generalized purchasing power (i.e.,
dollars), and thus may be considered positively effec- his Toward Social Economy [New York: Rinehart &
tive if the sale is consummated. Co., 1948], p. 44).

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
340 JAMES M. BUCHANAN

other votes to maintain the production vote. It is true that there may be com-
of the particular good or service, it may modities and services not offered for sale
be "lost," and, at this stage, the buyer which the individual would be willing to
may be in a position apparently equiva- purchase, but there may also be many
lent to that of the ballot-box supporter potential alternatives never presented
of the losing side of an issue. On the sell- for a vote which an individual might de-
ing side, if there are not enough final de- sire to support.
mand dollar votes to warrant production
VI
of those commodities or services embody-
ing the individual's productive contribu- Each of the five preceding distinctions
tion, then the attempt to convert produc- in the individual participation in voting
tive services into generalized purchasing and market choice is present even when
power on former terms may be thwarted. the relative power positions of individ-
But in each case, at the initial or primary uals are made equivalent in the two proc-
stage of the market process, the individ- esses, that is, when there is absolute
ual's expressed choice is never overruled. equality in the distribution of income-
The buyer would never have possessed earning capacity among market choosers.
the opportunity to choose, had not the All these distinctions tend, therefore, to
commodity or service been existent in be neglected in the simple "one-dollar-
the market; and the seller of productive one-vote" analogy, which concentrates
services would have never been able to attention only upon the difference in the
develop particular skills, had not a de- relative power of individuals. Market
rived demand for those skills been pres- choice is normally conducted under con-
ent. And since the one-to-one correspond- ditions of inequality among individuals,
ence between the act of choice and its while voting tends, at least ideally, to be
result is the only condition directly in- conducted under conditions of equality.
fluencing the individual's behavior, there The essential point to be emphasized
can never be present the sense of directly in this connection is that the inequalities
losing one's market vote. There may, of present in market choice are inequalities
course, arise a sense of regret when the in individual power and not in individual
consumer returns to the market place freedom, if care is taken to define free-
and finds a desired commodity no longer dom and power in such a way as to mnaxi-
available and when the individual no mize the usefulness of these two concepts
longer is able to market productive serv- in discussion. As Knight has suggested,
ices previously adapted to particular it seems desirable for this reason to de-
uses. The consumer may also regret that fine freedom somewhat narrowly as the
certain desired goods have never been absence of coercion and unfreedom as the
placed in the market in the first place, state of being prevented from utilizing
and the individual seller may be con- the normally available capacities for
cerned that there has never existed a action.22
ready market for his peculiar talents.
22See Frank H. Knight, "The Meaning of Free-
This sort of regret does not, however, dom," in The Philosophy of American Democracy, ed.
apply uniquely to market choice. It ap- Charles M. Perry (Chicago: University of Chicago
plies equally to political voting, and it Press, 1943), p. 64; "Conflict of Values: Freedom and
Justice," in Goals of Economic Life, ed. Dudley Ward
does not, therefore, constitute the mar- (New York: Harper & Bros., 1953), pp. 207, 226. For
ket's equivalent of the "lost" ballot-box supporting views see Michael Polanyi, Tie Logic of

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INDIVIDUAL CHOICE 341

VII dom is considered in isolation. The ab-


sence of negative results of individual
There remains the task of evaluating
choices and, therefore, of the direct coer-
the foregoing differences in the position
cion which requires that the individual
of the individual chooser in voting and
accept unchosen alternatives makes for
in the market, with a view toward deter-
a greater degree of freedom in market
mining the relative appropriateness of
choice.
the two choice processes for the social
On the other hand, voting should per-
group when they are, in fact, possible
haps be preferred to the market when
alternatives. If rationality in individual
individual motivation in choice is the
behavior is considered a desirable feature
attribute examined. Voting choice does
of a choice process,23 there would appear
provide individuals with a greater sense
to be several reasons for claiming that
of participation in social decision-mak-
market choice should be preferred. The
ing, and, in this way, it may bring forth
greater degree of certainty seems clearly
the "best" in man and tend to make in-
to produce more rational behavior; the
dividuals take somewhat more account
uniquely centered responsibility tends to
work in the same direction. Even if vot- of the "public interest." This attribute
ing and the market are genuinely alter- of the voting process has probably been
native means of making choices in a par- somewhat neglected by liberal students
and somewhat overemphasized in impor-
ticular situation (thereby eliminating
the inherent difficulties in voting choice tance by socialists. It should be noted,
when this is the only alternative), the however, that, even if this proves to be
difference in the divisibility of voting an important difference, voting will pro-
duce consistent or "rational" social
tends to make market choices finer and
more articulate. The fact that market choice only if men are able to agree on
choice tends to embody greater ration- the ultimate social goals.25 If men are not
ality in individual behavior than does able to agree on what is genuine moral-
voting choice does not suggest that mar- ity, the adoption of a choice process in
ket choice tends to produce greater social which they act more morally cannot be
rationality.24 justified on this ground.26
The market should also be preferred It is in the power structure among
as a choice process when individual free- individuals antecedent to choice that the
market may, and most often does, prove
Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), unacceptable. Political voting is charac-
p. 159; I". F. Carritt, Morals and Politics (London: terized by an alternative power structure
Oxford University Press, 1953), pp. 195 f.
which may be deemed preferable to that
23 Rationality in individual behavior is defined in
the normal manner, that is, the individual is able to
of the market. And the selection of the
rank alternatives, and such ranking is transitive. one-for-one power relation among in-
24 Itis on this basis that Dahl and Lindblom appear dividuals appears to carry with it the
to reject the argument that market choice is more selection of voting over market choice.
rational (op. cit., chap. xv). They do so because they
are concerned with rationality in the social sense, (le- 26 Cf. Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values.
fined as that action which maximizes the achievement 261If they cannot agree, the possible irrationality
of certain postulated social goals. If rationality is (le- of collective choice may be a desirable rather than an
fined purely in terms of individual behavior, their undesirable feature, since rationality could be imposed
argument appears to support that of this paper, only at the cost of minority coercion (see my "Social
although they seem explicitly to deny this at one Choice, Democracy, and Free Markets," Journal of
point (ibid., p. 422). Political Economy, LXII [19541, 114-23).

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
342 JAMES M. BUCHANAN

If, however, the market power structure consider their own self-interest to be bet-
can be effectively modified independently ter served individualistically or collect-
of the choice process, this apparent ad- ively. If the "collective-action" pref-
vantage of political voting need not be erence scale allows the required majority
present. of individuals to attain a more esteemed
It should be noted that the fundamen- position than does the "individual-ac-
tal decision to modify the power struc- tion" preference scale, voting choice will
ture, as well as the extent of such modi- be selected regardless of the ranking of
fication, clearly must be made by the social goals. In this case it might be ir-
ballot box. And in this type of decision rational for an individual to choose the
especially it is essential that individuals market process, even though his behavior
act in accordance with a value-ordering in the market, once this process was se-
which is somewhat different from that lected by the group, would be more ra-
motivating individual market choice. tional than his behavior in the voting
After a redistributive decision for the booth. The electorate should select the
group is made, it must be further de- ballot box over the market place in those
cided whether a particular choice shall areas where individually determined
be made by the market or by political market acts tend to produce results
voting. This decision on process must which are in conflict either with those
also be made by means of the ballot box. which a large group of voters estimate
In this decision the market should be to be their own or the "social welfare"
rejected only if individual market choices and where the conflict is significant
are considered by voters to produce a enough to warrant the sacrifice both of
social state less desirable than that which the individual freedom and the individ-
is produced by individual voting choices. ual rationality involved.
The selection of the choice process, if In so far as market choice must be
the redistributive decision can be made made under imperfectly competitive
separately, will depend to a large degree conditions27 and voting choice under
upon the relative positions of the various conditions of less than "pure" democ-
social goals in the value scales of individ- racy, the analysis of individual behavior
uals comprising the voting group. If con- in each process must be appropriately
sistency in individual behavior and in- modified and the conclusions reached
dividual freedom are highly regarded earlier changed accordingly. No attempt
relative to other values, the market will will be made here to extend the analysis
tend to be favored. If, on the other hand, in this direction.
the somewhat vague, even though mean-
ingful, concept of "social welfare" is the VIII
overriding consideration, voting choice A major source of confusion in the
may be preferred. But even here, if the discussion of economic policy stems from
individual's expressed interest is judged the failure to distinguish carefully be-
to be the best index of social welfare, thetween the selection of the power struc-
market may still be acceptable as a ture among individual choosers and the
choice process (this was essentially the selection of the choice mechanism. This
position of the utilitarians).
27 Imperfections include, of course, the presence of
The selection of the choice process will such monetary and structural factors as may lead to
also depend on whether or not the voters unemployment.

This content downloaded from


82.63.77.45 on Fri, 19 Mar 2021 14:28:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INDIVIDUAL CHOICE 343

arises from the more fundamental fail- "resource" aspects of economic policy.
ure to define freedom in such a way that The problem of selecting the desirable
market freedom and market power may structure of power relations among in-
be differentiated conceptually.28 In many dividuals in the market is, of course,
real world situations the market power equivalent to the income problem broad-
structure cannot be effectively modified ly considered. The "resource" side of the
independently, that is, a redistributive "income-resource" dichotomy introduces
decision cannot be made in isolation. It is an evaluation of policy in terms of the
nevertheless essential for analytical clari- social criteria of economic efficiency, and
ty that this ideational distinction be these aspects of the market mechanism
made. tend to be emphasized. The "choice"
The separation of the power structure side of the "power-choice" dichotomy
and the decision-making process is less which has been developed here tends to
inclusive and less complex than the simi- concentrate attention upon individual
lar and more commonly encountered dis- behavior in making choices, and it tends
tinction between the "income" and the to emphasize the greater range of free-
dom allowed the individual, as well as
28 This constitutes one of the major weaknesses in
the greater degree of individual ration-
Dahl and Lindblom's otherwise excellent comparison
of voting and the market (op. cit., pp. 414-27). ality in market choice.

This content downloaded from


f:ffff:ffff:ffff:ffff:ffff:ffff:ffff on Thu, 01 Jan 1976 12:34:56 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like