You are on page 1of 11

Catenae in Morphology

Thomas Groß
Aichi University, Nagoya, Japan
tmgross@vega.aichi-u.ac.jp
takes the backseat with just 8 pages. Valency
Abstract theory is characterized by putting valency-
bearing lexical items at center stage. Assuming
This paper argues for a renewed attempt at morpholo- that non-lexical material is somehow subsumed
gy in dependency grammar. The proposal made here by lexical material seems on a logical trajectory.
is based on the concept of the “catena” proposed by But research in typology, foremost Bybee (1985),
Authors (in press). The predecessor to this notion was has confirmed that affixes as expressions of va-
the “chain” introduced by O‟Grady (1998), and em-
lency, voice, aspect, modality, tense, mood, and
ployed by Osborne (2005) and Groß and Osborne
(2009). In morphology and morphosyntax, a morph person obtain in a specific linear order (or hie-
catena is A MORPH OR A COMBINATION OF MORPHS rarchy), and developments in generative gram-
THAT IS CONTINUOUS WITH RESPECT TO DOMINANCE. mar during the 1980‟s emphasized the domin-
This concept allows for a parsimonious treatment of ance structure of the IP/TP, where such affixes
morphology on the surface. The fact that no additional are thought to be located. Similar statements also
terms and concepts are necessary for the analysis of concern NP structure: if case or plural is ex-
morphological data is highly desirable because it pressed by morphs, then these morphs appear in
makes a fluid transition from syntax to morphology peripheral position, an indication that they domi-
possible. This paper introduces the relevant depen- nate their nouns. In general, it is safe to say that
dency relationships seen operating in morphology,
dependency grammar has missed out on impor-
and shows how they can be used to explain compound
structure, bracketing paradoxes, and multiple periph- tant trends and insights, and this has severely
rasis. hampered any formulation of a dependency-
based morphology. The fact that Anderson went
1 Introduction on to establish “dependency phonology” (Ander-
son & Ewen 1987) instead of pursuing his initial
Hays (1964: 517f; see in particular the second program of dependency morphology, is a case in
example on page 518) may have been the first to point. Among the widely known dependency
recognize the merit of extending the notion of grammars, only Mel‟čuk‟s Meaning-Text-Theory
dependency into morphology. The motivation for (1988) and Hudson‟s Word Grammar (1984,
doing so is clear: the complexity of word struc- 1990, 2007) explicitly address morphology.
ture in languages differs, and if dependency While the notion of dependency can be consi-
grammar desires to say something enlightening dered as established in syntax and phonology,
about languages with different word structure, morphology is still underdeveloped. In recent
then it must have the means to do so. Heringer times, Harnisch (2003) and Maxwell (2003) have
(1970: 96f) provided perhaps the first dependen- argued again that dependency grammar must
cy trees that included separate nodes for morphs. achieve a better understanding of the morpholog-
Anderson (1980) was the first to use the label ical component.
“dependency morphology”, in his analysis of This paper outlines a proposal for a dependen-
Basque verbs. Both Heringer‟s and Anderson‟s cy morphology based on the notion of “chain”,
analyses are characterized by the assumption that which was introduced by O‟Grady (1998).
derivational and inflectional morphs depend on O‟Grady shows that many idioms do not qualify
the lexical morphs with which they form words. as constituents, rather they form incomplete de-
This assumption has carried on to the present pendency trees, which he called “chains”. Os-
(e.g. Eroms 2010: 38f). Speculating on the rea- borne (2005) recognized the versatility of this
sons for this assumption, the European tradition notion for dependency grammar. Groß and Os-
sees dependency grammar as the theoretical borne (2009) use the chain concept to address
background for valency theory. A brief look at discontinuous structure in syntax, and Groß
Ágel and Fischer (2010) confirms this evalua- (2010) endeavors, in a first attempt, to apply the
tion; valency theory is treated prominently and chain to word structure, arguing that bracketing
initially on 14 pages, while dependency grammar paradoxes and multiple auxiliary constructions

47
can be quite easily resolved. Below, however, the words. A dependency relationship between
term catena will be used instead of “chain” be- morphs inside the same word is called an intra-
cause “chain” is understood in an entirely differ- word dependency. Intra-word dependencies are
ent way in derivational theories of syntax. This determined by distribution:
decision is also motivated by the work of Os-
If the combination of two morphs M1
borne et al (in press), who show that the catena,
and M2 distributes more like M2 than
rather than the constituent, is implicated in idiom
like M1, then M1 is a dependent of M2.
formation, ellipsis, and predicate formation.
They define a catena (in syntax) as A WORD OR A This definition is similar to Mel‟čuk‟s definition
COMBINATION OF WORDS THAT IS CONTINUOUS of “surface syntactic dominance” (2003: 200f).
WITH RESPECT TO DOMINANCE. This definition The next example from Japanese illustrates intra-
identifies any dependency tree or subtree of a word dependencies:
tree as a catena. By replacing “word” with (1) -na
“morph”, the catena is also available for mor-
phology. mu-
This paper proceeds as follows: Section 2 in- kankei
forms on the central notions and shows how they
are used to explain morphological dependencies mu- kankei -na (Japanese)
within and across words and with clitics. It also NEG relation -ADN
illustrates briefly that non-concatenative mor- „unrelated‟
phology can be dealt with. Section 3 concerns The intra-word dependencies are represented by
compounds: gradient compound structure as well the dotted edges (as opposed to solid edges). The
as exocentric compounds are explained. Section lexical morph kankei receives a (vertical) projec-
4 addresses bracketing paradoxes. Section 5 de- tion edge. The hyphens represent phonological
monstrates that a catena-based approach can par- attachment (in the horizontal dimension). The
simoniously account for multiple periphrasis. A negation prefix mu- phonologically attaches to
final section concludes the paper. the next morph to its right, and the attributive
suffix phonologically -na attaches to the next
2 Catena-based morphology
morph to its left; in (1) this morph is kankei. The
Building on Osborne et.al. (in press), a morph prefix mu- must depend on the suffix -na because
catena is a MORPH OR A COMBINATION OF the morph combination mu-kankei distributes
MORPHS THAT IS CONTINUOUS WITH RESPECT TO like a member of the lexical class of nominal
DOMINANCE. The choice of “morph” instead of adjectives “keiyō meishi”. The morph catena
“morpheme” is motivated by the need to main- kankei-na is not possible because kankei is a
tain a surface-oriented level of analysis. A morph noun rather than a nominal adjective. Intra-word
is loosely defined as any meaning bearing unit dependencies are thus motivated on the basis of
that cannot be reduced any further, but that can distribution.
be separated from other meaning bearing units in
2.2 Across words
the horizontal AND/OR vertical dimension. 1 The
inclusion of the notion “vertical dimension” al- An inter-word dependency is a morphosyntactic
lows for the treatment of phenomena subsumed relationship between a morph and a word. If the
under non-concatenative morphology (trans- and morph licenses the appearance of the word, then
suprafixation, reduplication, etc.), as briefly the morph governs the word. The next example
demonstrated below. This section addresses illustrates that with an example from German:
morph dependencies within and across words,
(2) mit
clitics, and non-concatenative morphology.
-n
2.1 Within words
-er
Morph catenae obtain in morphology proper, i.e.
inside words, and in morphosyntax, i.e. across Kind
mit Kind -er -n (German)
1 with child -PL -DAT
While there are certainly difficulties with the notions
„with children‟
“morph” and “morpheme” (cf. Mel‟čuk 2006: 384ff),
the proposal here is sufficient in the present context.

48
Example (2) shows the two units mit and Kind- dent on a morph capable of constituting a pro-
er-n. The former qualifies as a word and a morph, sodic word, or it must depend on a morph that
while the latter only qualifies as a word. Again, depends on such a morph, and so on, recursively.
the dotted edges represent the intra-word depen- “Wackernagel” or “second position” clitics chal-
dencies inside the noun: the plural suffix -er is lenge many theories. In the approach here, these
seen as dominating the noun Kind because Kind- clitics can appear as quasi-words but must be
er distributes like a plural noun, rather than like prosodically dependent on – most often – the
the singular noun Kind. The dative case suffix is final morph of the first minimal prosodic unit.
seen as dominating the plural noun because the This is illustrated with a Serbo-Croat example
dative case should encompass the entire plural taken from Corbett (1987: 406). There the clitics
noun Kind-er rather than just singular Kind. The -mu and -ih depend on dati, but they are part of
noun Kind-er-n is dominated by the preposition the prosodic word formed by Želim. -ih prosodi-
mit. Since mit can be seen as a morph, Kind-er-n cally depends on -mu, which depends on Želim.
is a dependent of mit, mit licensing the appear-
(4) Želim
ance of the entire word Kind-er-n.
Note that the morphs in examples (1) and (2) dati
qualify as morph catenae. In (1) the following
-mu -ih
morph catenae obtain: mu-kankei, mu-…-na, the
individual morphs, and the entire expression. In Želim -mu -ih dati
(2) Kind-er, -er-n, Kind-er-n, mit...-n, mit...-er-n, wish.1sg.NPST 3sg.m.DAT 3pl.ACC give
the individual morphs and the entire expression „I wish to give them to him.‟
qualify as morph catenae.
2.4 Non-concatenative morphology
2.3 Clitics The morph catena can also accommodate phe-
Clitics are morphs on the borderline between free nomena from non-concatenative morphology.
and bound morphs (Klavans 1985, Kaisse 1985, The ability to accommodate transfixation is
Nevis 1986, Zwicky 1987, Anderson 1992, 2005 demonstrated next with Hebrew data, taken from
and others). Clitics express meanings usually Booij (2007: 37):
reserved for free morphs, but fail – for whatever (5) a a_ hi i_ i a
reasons – to appear as individual prosodic words.
g d l gd l gd l
In the current system, these properties are ex-
pressed by the following tree conventions: A clit- a. g a d a l b. hi gd i l c. gd i l a
ic appears without a projection edge but with a „grow‟ „enlarge‟ „growth‟
hyphen and a solid dependency edge. The lower consonant series in (5a-c) constitute
the lexical morph gdl, which expresses the vague
(3) smile
meaning of „grow‟. The transfixes _a_a_ „infini-
-s tive‟, hi__i_ „causative‟, and __i_a „nominalizer‟
are seen as dominating the lexical morphs be-
girl
cause their appearance affects the distribution of
the know the entire expression. The “root” morph and the
transfixes qualify as morphs because they can be
I
separated from one another in the vertical dimen-
the girl I know -s smile sion. The resulting horizontal units are the re-
spective morphs. The slots in the transfixes fulfill
The possessive -s depends on the following smile,
the role of the hyphen in concatenative morphol-
seemingly like a full word.2 It also governs the
ogy.3
noun girl like a full noun. However, the clitic
Ablaut can be analyzed in a similar fashion. In
appears without a projection edge in exactly the
some German nouns, the plural is formed solely
fashion bound morphs would. Like bound
by ablaut: Vater – Väter, Mutter – Mütter, Brud-
morphs, the clitic must be prosodically depen-

2 3
A reviewer suggests the possibility of a DP analysis A reviewer comments on whether tmesis such as
such that the clitic dominates both girl and smile abso-bloody-lutely can be accommodated. In view of
which would result in a D-projection of the entire the analysis in (5), one can assume that such an analy-
expression. Evidence for DP is, however, ambiguous sis is possible in the current system, even though I
at best, and as a result the current account rejects DP. refrain from providing one due to space reasons.

49
er – Brüder etc. Since the appearance of the ab- (8) tire
laut changes the distribution of the whole expres-
tire truck-
sion, it is seen as the root:
truck- military-
(6) ¨ ¨ ¨
Vater Mutter Bruder a. truck- tire b. military- truck- tire
a. Väter b. Mütter c. Brüder Example (8a) is a compound, but unlike (7b).
„fathers‟ „mothers‟ „brothers‟ Here truck-, can still be modified, as (8b) illu-
strates. The truck is a military type of truck, ra-
The ablaut, represented by ¨, now constitutes an
ther than the tire being a military type of tire.
individual node that can be accessed. The dotted
This kind of compound is less syntactic than (7a),
dependency edge is now completely vertical, a
but more syntactic than (7b); this fact is
feature also present in infixation, transfixation,
represented by the solid dependency edge be-
and suprafixation. Reduplication, suprafixation,
tween the compound parts.
and infixation can be accommodated in a similar
German seems to dislike (8a)-type compounds.
vein.
Modifying adjectives must appear without their
3 Compounds attributive suffixes, an indication that the mod-
ified noun has lost the ability to license the ap-
Compounds are words containing at least two pearance of attributives:
lexical morphs. Because lexical morphs have the
(9) Sport sport
ability to constitute prosodic words, the appear-
ance of two lexical morphs in one prosodic word -er Extrem-
requires one of these morphs to be integrated into
extrem
the prosodic word structure of the other.
a. extrem -er Sport b. Extrem- sport
3.1 Compound gradience „extreme sports‟
Compounds are of particular interest for depen- In (9a) the adjective is a regular attributive adjec-
dency morphology because the semanto- tive, and it can be modified by sehr „very‟. In
syntactic connection between compound parts (9b) however, the adjective is integrated into the
exhibits gradience. Consider the next English prosodic word structure of sport, and it cannot be
examples: marked with the attributive suffix -er (or any
(7) room room other inflectional suffix), thus indicating com-
pounding.
dark dark- But German can build compounds by using
a. dark room b. dark- room the Fugen -s-:
Example (7a) shows a purely syntactic depen- (10) haus
dency relationship. The attributive adjective can -s-
still be modified by e.g. very. In (7b), that is im-
possible, hence this expression is a compound. Wirt
Because dark-room denotes a kind of room, not a Wirt -s- haus
kind of dark(ness), room is seen as the root do- „tavern‟
minating the adjective. The adjective is inte-
grated into the prosodic word structure of the Example (10) is very simple, and much more
morph room, which is represented by the hyphen complex examples exist (e.g. Einzugsermächti-
on dark-. Morphs must either be marked by a gung „collection authorization‟). The important
hyphen or receive a projection edge (but never issue here is that -s- combines two units, each of
both). which requires one of its morphs to be marked
The words in (7a-b) represent the endpoints of with a projection edge (here: Wirt and haus). The
a compound continuum. English allows com- hyphens on either side of -s- signal this important
pounds to reside between these two end points, function; technically, -s- functions as an infix.
as the next examples demonstrate:

50
3.2 “Exocentric” compounds tion with closer association of its parts should be
4 preceded by a construction with freer association
Exocentric compounds come in different types:
at an earlier time. When and how the association
in bahuvrihi compounds, the meaning of the en-
changes is a matter for specialists. The assump-
tire expression cannot be deduced from its parts,
tion of such a continuum is, however, compatible
or only with great difficulty, e.g. skinhead, old-
with much research in grammaticalization theory,
money, bluecollar, etc. Other types of exocentric
see Bybee‟s (2010:136-50) analysis of Engl. in
compounds defy morphological categorization.
spite of. The important issue here is that in order
The words musthave and kickback are nouns (ra-
to undergo this process, the individual parts of
ther than verbs), auxiliaries, or prepositions. Fur-
the complex expression must form catenae.
thermore, there are dvandva compounds: copula-
Since the bahuvrihi compound classes are
tive dvandva have two (or more) semantic heads
very extensive, the discussion concentrates on
such as bitter-sweet or sleep-walk, and in apposi-
four classes that contain verbal morphs:
tional dvandva the compound parts contribute to
a similar degree to the meaning of the entire ex- (12) a. VERB + NOUN
pression, such as in maid-servant. b. VERB + PARTICLE
At first blush, bahuvrihi and dvandva com- c. PARTICIPLE + PARTICLE
pounds are removed from productive compounds d. AUXILIARY + VERB
to a significant degree. Bahuvrihi such as skin-
Examples for type (12a) are dodgeball, kickball,
head, which means a certain type of person, ra-
jumprope etc. For type (12b), one finds kickback,
ther than a body part, are in the process of idiom
breakdown, havenot etc, and examples for type
formation or have already completed this process.
(12c) are rundown, letdown, shutout, etc. Type
Applying O‟Grady‟s (1998) lesson of syntactic
(12d) includes musthave and hasbeen.
idioms to compounding leads to the straightfor-
Even though the noun ball depends on the
ward assumption that the units involved in these
verbs dodge and kick in the VPs dodge (a) ball
types of compound must qualify as catenae if
and kick (a) ball, the noun dominates the verb in
they are to be retained in the lexicon. But the
the compounds because these compounds denote
lexicon, as understood in construction grammar,
specific objects or activities using these objects,
also contains constructions, which is why Gold-
and these objects are represented by ball and
berg (1995) calls it “constructicon” rather than
rope. Type (12a) exhibits the following morph
lexicon. Concerning compound constructions,
dependencies:
English requires the root of the compound to be a
nominal, i.e. a noun, adjective, or some other (13) ball ball rope
nominal form. In other words, the English com-
dodge- kick- jump-
pound construction continuum could look like
this (with the horizontal order being free): a. dodge- ball b. kick- ball c. jump- rope
(11) Y Y Y Examples (13a-c) show that the initial compound
part depending on the final compound part.
X X- X-
Type (12b) compounds differ from type (12a)
a. X Y b. X- Y c. X- Y insofar as the initial compound part is seen as the
root. Expressions such as kickback, breakdown,
Construction (11a) is purely syntactic, like (7a).
havenot etc. are clearly nominals, because they
In the next step (11b), X loses its ability to con-
can be pluralized: kickbacks, breakdowns, have-
stitute a prosodic word, but still retains the abili-
nots. It is, however, the initial compound parts
ty to govern modifiers. At stage (11c), the ability
that undergo plural formation, i.e. kicks, breaks,
to govern modifiers is relinquished. Beyond that
haves, rather than *backs, *downs, *nots. Mul-
stage, a new morph obtains. The example truck-
tiple jumpropes are still multiple ropes, while
tire in (8a) is at stage (11b), while (11c) is accu-
multiple kickbacks are not multiple backs, but
rate for dark-room in (7b). In general, a construc-
multiple instances of kicking back. Hence the
assumption that the initial parts form the roots,
4
The literature on this topic is quite extensive. Com- and that the plural morph vertically attaches to
pounding and their types are treated in Fabb (1998), the initial parts is also justified when seen from
Olsen (2000), Ten Hacken (2000), Bauer (2001, semantics. The structure of type (12b) com-
2009), etc. Dvandva are addressed in Bauer (2008). pounds is shown next:
See Scalise and Bisetto (2009) and Arcodia (2010) for
an overview.

51
(14) kick break ize more readily than expressions that contain
such morphs.
-back -down
Finally, type (12d) compounds like musthave
a. kick -back b. break -down seem to be very rare. Nevertheless, their struc-
-s ture must be like (15):
have have (17) has
-not -not must -en
c. have -not c'. have -not -s -have -be
(14a-c) show the structure of kickback, break- a. must -have b. has -be -en
down, and havenot. Example (14c') shows the
Compare the structure (17b) with periphrasis in
plural form of (14c).
Section 5 below.
Type (12c) is a variation of type (12b). The
Once an expression has reached the stage
difference lies with the form of the verb morph,
(11c), it can be converted into a verb: babysit,
which appears as a stem in (12b) but as a parti-
benchpress, bodycheck, bullrush, carpetbomb,
ciple form in (12c). As long as the participle
crashdive, fieldtest, housebreak, housesit, proof-
forms do not contain overt participle morphs,
fread, slamdunk, tapdance, etc. 5 Many of these
type (12c) compounds are seen as structured
examples are considered to have undergone
along the lines of (14):
backformation; for instance, baby-sit is derived
(15) run let shut from babysitter, carpetbomb from carpetbomb-
ing, etc. Other examples such as benchpress or
-down -down -out
crashdive are seen as zero-conversion. One real-
a. run -down b. let -down c. shut -out life example shows the conversion of the com-
pound noun cake-walk into a verb:
Type (12c) compounds such as (15a-c) appear as
nominal compounds because the participle is a (18) …as Joseph Addai really cakewalked
nominal form. In the examples (13a-c), (14a-d), into the endzone…
and (15a-c), dotted dependency edges obtain be-
This example appeared in the commentary of the
cause no material can intervene between the
Colts-Raiders game (season 2010/11, week 17),
compound parts.
and it illustrates the productivity of the reconver-
When a participle morph is present, a solid
sion of apparent compounds to lexical morphs.
dependency edge between the verb morph and
the adverb must obtain because the participle 3.3 Clausal compounds
morph must intervene in the horizontal dimen-
sion: A further phenomenon of interest is compounds
containing whole clauses. Well known examples
(16) -en -ing include the fully lexicalized English forget-me-
brok mak not and its German version Vergissmeinnicht.
Both are based on imperative clauses: evidence
-down -out for this assumption is the ablaut of vergiss, the
a. brok -en -down b. mak -ing -out stem of which is vergess. In German verbs with
an /e→i/ ablaut, the ablaut version serves as the
In (16a-b), the participle morphs -en and -ing imperative form. Since the verb is the clausal
mark the expressions as nominals, but they ap- root, it retains this role in compounding within
pear in medial position. The adverbs must there- its compound part. The structure of forget-me-
fore be connected by solid dependency edges. not and Vergissmeinnicht are given next:
This indicates that, in the compound continuum,
the expressions in (15a-c) are located closer to (19) forget Vergiss
the lexical endpoint of the continuum than the -me -not -mein -nicht
expressions (16a-b). More precisely, the expres-
sions (15a-c) are at stage (11c), while the expres- a. forget -me -not b. Vergiss -mein -nicht
sions (16a-b) reside at stage (11b). Since highly
irregular verbs such as run, let, shut, etc. do not 5
Contrary to spelling conventions, none of these ex-
appear with a participle morph, they can lexical- pressions is written with a hyphen here, because these
words are fully lexicalized.

52
The structure of the verbal morphs is left unana- compound root, nor between the units of the
lyzed. A diachronic analysis of the German noun clausal compound. Unlike the English forget-me-
would be much more complex. The German not and German Vergissmeinnicht, which must
Vergissmeinnicht can undergo further com- be considered to be at stage (11c), this construc-
pounding because one of its meanings is the tion is at stage (11b).
flower in question, while an idiomatic meaning is
„black eye‟. In this meaning, Vergissmeinnicht 4 Bracketing paradoxes
can undergo compounding with German Auge
Bracketing paradoxes (Williams 1981, Pesetsky
„eye‟:
1985, Sproat 1988, Spencer 1988, Beard 1991,
(20) auge Stump 1991/2001, Becker 1993, Müller 2003)
pose significant problem for many theories. On
Vergiss-
adoption of catena-based dependency morpholo-
mein- nicht- gy, however, bracketing paradoxes dissolve.
Consider the next well-known example, intro-
Vergiss- mein- nicht- auge
duced by Williams (1981) and dubbed “personal
„black eye‟
noun” by Spencer (1988):
Note the hyphen convention in (20): because
(24) moral philosopher
Vergissmeinnicht is prosodically dependent on
auge, the hyphens are employed to express this The expression in (24) is usually understood as
property. Vergiss- attaches to mein- in the hori- referring to a philosopher concerned with moral
zontal dimension, mein- attaches to nicht-, and issues, i.e. ethics. Under normal circumstances,
nicht- to Auge. This example thus nicely illu- people do not view the philosopher as necessari-
strates the logical transitivity of attachment in the ly moral, rather the type of philosophy this per-
horizontal dimension, or prosodic dependency. son practices is concerned with moral issues. The
Interestingly, the meaning of „not forgetting‟ problem with this reading is that it conflicts to a
is also used in Japanese: a Japanese forget-me- certain degree with intuitions on word formation.
not is a wasure-na-gusa. Its structure is illu- Consider the next two bracketing structures:
strated as follows:
(25) a. [moral [philosoph-er]]
(21) gusa b. [[moral philosoph]-er]
na- While (25a) means that the person is moral,
(25b) correctly sees the philosophy as such, but it
wasure- na- gusa
does so at the expense of cutting into the second
forget NEG grass
word. In dependency grammars that do not reach
„forget-me-not‟
into words, the structure of (24) should be (26):
The expression in (21) must be a compound be-
(26) philosopher
cause the initial consonant of the compound root
is voiced; on its own it is kusa „grass‟. moral
English retains a rather productive construc-
moral philosopher
tion, where a clause forms a compound together
with a noun such as face. Such a clausal com- (26) suggests an understanding along the lines of
pound is shown in the next example: (25a). Employing the morph catena however, an
insightful analysis becomes possible:
(22) face
(27) -er
don‟t-
philosoph
mess-
-al
with-
mor
me-
mor -al philosoph -er
She gave me her don‟t- mess- with- me- face.
A catena-based analysis can provide all and ex-
The high productivity of this construction does
actly those units required. (27) contains the cate-
not merit the dotted dependency edge between
na philosoph-er, which is missing in (25b), and it
the root of the clausal compound part and the
shows the catena mor-al philosoph, which is re-

53
quired for the correct semantic interpretation of
the entire expression (and which is missing in (30) … (has -en) (be -ing) (be -ed) (discuss)
(25a)).
This ”hopping” guaranteed that there was one
A phenomenon related to bracketing paradox-
level at which the respective units were conti-
es appears in compounding. Fabb (1998: 72f)
guous, a prerequisite to establishing a semantic
calls this phenomenon “subconstituency”. He
relationship.
uses the example American history teacher:
In Distributed Morphology (DM) (Halle &
(28) -er Marantz 1993, Harley & Noyer 2003, Embick
and Noyer 2001/2007, Embick 2003), affix hop-
teach
ping is now seen as the predecessor of “lower-
history- ing” and “local dislocation”.6 Whatever one calls
the mechanism, the core assumption is that if
American-
some unit is displaced on the surface, this unit
a. American- history- teach -er must have moved to its surface position from a
position at which it was contiguous with other
-er
units with which it forms a greater semantic unit.
American teach Based on the concepts introduced in the pre-
vious sections, example (29) can now be reex-
history-
amined. The structure of the individual words
b. American- history- teach been, being, and discussed is given below:
(31) -en -ing -ed
In (28a) American history is traditionally seen as
a subconstituent of the whole expression, which be be discuss
refers to a teacher of American history, the
a. be -en b. be -ing c. discuss -ed
teacher not necessarily being an American. In
(28b), history teacher is seen as a subconstituent In (31), the suffixes invariably dominate their
of the entire NP, which now refers to an Ameri- lexical verbs: in (31a), -en dominates be because
can teacher of history, the history not necessarily be-en distributes like a participle rather than as
being that of America. the infinitive. The same is true for (31c). In (31b),
be-ing distributes like a progressive marked verb
5 Multiple periphrases form rather than like the infinitive. The complete
morph dependency structure of example (29) is
That multiple auxiliary constructions, i.e. mul-
now shown:
tiple periphrases, are a problem was acknowl-
edged early on by Chomsky (1957: 39). He po- (32) perfective
sits “affix hopping” in order to explain why the
has
morphemes expressing aspect and voice do not
appear together on the surface. Consider the next problem -en progressive
sentence:
The be
(29) The problem has be-en be-ing discuss-ed.
-ing passive
The units has and -en express perfective aspect,
be
the first be and -ing express progressive aspect,
and the second be and -ed express passive voice. -ed
The problem is that these units of functional
discuss
meaning are not contiguous, because parts of
other functional units intervene on the surface. The problem has be -en be -ing discuss -ed.
For instance, be of the progressive unit inter-
The dependency structure in (32) must first be
venes between has and -en forming the perfec-
compared to the affix hopping/lowering analysis
tive aspectual unit. Chomsky (1957: 39) pro-
in (30): the units expressing the respective func-
posed that the respective units are contiguous at a
tional meanings are present as units on the sur-
deeper level, and the affix of the unit “hops” over
face. has and -en (=perfective aspect), be and -
the verb of the next unit. The next example,
ing (=progressive aspect), and be and -ed
based on Anderson (1992: 16), shows how this
proposal plays out:
6
See Sternefeld (2009: 481-88) for an overview.

54
(=passive voice) qualify as morph catenae. The lows for a fluid transition between syntax, mor-
assumption of movement is unnecessary, since phosyntax, and morphology, and thus simplifies
the respective morph combinations are discerni- the theoretical apparatus.
ble in the vertical dimension (rather than the ho-
rizontal dimension). References
Two issues are of importance here: 1. The Ágel, V. and K. Fischer. 2010. 50 Jahre Valenztheorie
analysis in (32) obeys the Bybee hierarchy und Dependenzgrammatik. Zeitschrift für germa-
(1985: 196-7), because the perfective morph ca- nistische Linguistik 16. 249-290
tena dominates the progressive morph catena,
which in turn dominates the voice catena. 2. The Anderson, J. 1980. Towards dependency morphology:
the structure of the Basque verb. Anderson, J. and
respective functional meanings are expressed by
C. Ewen eds., Studies in Dependency Phonology,
units that qualify neither as constituents nor as 221-271. Ludwigsburg.
words. As a corollary, the morph catena is – like
its syntactic equivalent – a unit of meaning, Anderson, J. M. and C. J. Ewen. 1987. Principles of
available on the surface. dependency phonology. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
6 Conclusion Anderson, S. R. 1992. A-Morphous Morphology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
This paper has argued that morphological struc-
ture can be captured in dependency grammar by Anderson, S.R. 2005. Aspects of the Theory of Clitics.
extending the notion of the catena from syntax Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.
into morphology. The fact that no additional Arcodia, G.F. 2010. Coordinating compounds. Lan-
concepts are necessary – and thus that morphol- guage and Linguistics Compass 4/9, 863-873.
ogy plays out as syntax inside words is desirable. Bauer, L. 2001. Compounding. Haspelmath, M., E.
Section 2 introduced the morph catena as A König, W. Oesterreicher and W. Raible eds., Lan-
MORPH OR COMBINATION OF MORPHS THAT IS guage typology and language universals: an inter-
CONTINUOUS WITH RESPECT TO DOMINANCE. national handbook, 695–707. Berlin/New York:
The two relevant dependency relationships be- Mouton de Gruyter.
tween morphs were then established: intra-word Bauer, L. 2008. Dvandva. Word Structure 1. 1–20.
dependencies obtain between morphs contained
in the same word; they are based on distribution. Bauer, L. 2009. Typology of compounds. Lieber, R.
Inter-word dependency, or government, plays out and P. Štekauer eds., The Oxford handbook of
compounding, 343–56. Oxford: Oxford University
between a morph and a word, so that the morph
Press.
licenses the appearance of the word. Using these
two concepts, morphs can be connected into ca- Becker, T. 1993. Back-formation, cross-formation,
tenae regardless of the complexity of the struc- and „bracketing paradoxes‟ in Paradigmatic Mor-
ture. It has also been demonstrated that this ac- phology. In Booij, G. & van Marle, J. (eds.), Year-
book of Morphology (vol. 6). Dordrecht: Foris Pub-
count can accommodate non-concatenative mor-
lications. 1–25.
phology (although these phenomena were not in
focus). Booij, G. 2007. The Grammar of Words. Second Edi-
The main message of this paper is that depen- tion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
dency grammar should and can make more of Bybee, J.L. 1985. Morphology: A study of the relation
morphology. At present, dependency grammar between meaning and form. Amsterdam/Philadel-
operates in syntax. However, the same meaning phia: John Benjamins Publishing
can be encoded at different levels in different Bybee, J. 2010. Language, Usage and Cognition.
languages. For instance, causative constructions Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
are periphrastic in English and German, but mor-
phological in Japanese. In order to compare lan- Embick, D. and R. Noyer. 2001. Movement opera-
tions after syntax. Linguistic Inquiry Vol 32, No. 4,
guages, the concentration on syntax alone is in-
555–595
sufficient; rather it is necessary to provide a sys-
tem that enables a fluid transition of description Embick, D. and R. Noyer. 2007. Distributed Mor-
from syntax to morphology and back. This is phology and the Syntax/ Morphology Interface.
possible if dependency relationships are seen as Ramchand, G. and C. Reiss eds. The Oxford Hand-
book of Linguistic Interfaces. 289-324. Oxford
operating not only in syntax, but also in morpho-
University Press.
syntax and morphology. The catena concept al-

55
Embick, D. 2003. Linearization and local dislocation: valency: An international handbook of contempo-
Derivational mechanics and interactions. Linguistic rary research, vol. 1, 678-684. Berlin: Walter de
Analysis 33/3-4. 303-336. Gruyter.
Eroms, Hans-Werner. 2010. Valenz und Inkorpora- Mel‟čuk, I. 1988. Dependency syntax: Theory and
tion. Kolehmainen Leena, Hartmut E. Lenk and practice. Albany: State University of New York
Annikki Liimatainen eds. Infinite Kontrastive Hy- Press.
pothesen. 27-40. Frankfurt: Peter Lang
Mel‟čuk, I. 2003. Mel‟čuk, I. 2003. Levels of depen-
Fabb, N. 1998. Compounding. Spencer A. and A. M. dency in linguistic description: concepts and prob-
Zwicky eds., Handbook of morphology, 66–83. lems. In Ágel, V. et.al (eds.), Dependency and va-
Oxford: Blackwell lency: an international handbook of contemporary
research, vol. 1, 188-229. Berlin: Walter de Gruy-
Goldberg, Adele. 1995. Constructions: A Construc-
ter.
tion Grammar approach to argument structure.
Chicago: The University Press of Chicago. Mel‟čuk, I. 2006. Aspects of the Theory of Morpholo-
gy. Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Groß, T. 2010. Chains in syntax and morphology. In
Proceedings of the 24th Pacific Asia Conference Müller, S. 2003. Solving the bracketing paradox: an
on Language, Information and Computation at To- analysis of the morphology of German particle
hoku University, eds. O. Ryo, K. Ishikawa, H. verbs. Journal of Linguistics 39. 275–325.
Uemoto, K. Yoshimoto & Y. Harada, 143-152.
Nevis, J. A. 1986. Finnish Particle Clitics and Gen-
Tokyo: Waseda University.
eral Clitic Theory. Working Papers in Linguistics
Groß, T. and T. Osborne 2009. Toward a practical DG 33. Columbus, Ohio: Dept. of Linguistics, Ohio
theory of discontinuities. Sky Journal of Linguistics State University.
22. 43-90.
O‟Grady, W. 1998. The syntax of idioms. Natural
Halle, M. and A. Marantz. 1993. Distributed Mor- Language and Linguistic Theory 16. 79-312.
phology and the Pieces of Inflection. Hale, K. and
Olsen, S. 2000. Composition. Geert B., C. Lehmann
S. J.Keyser eds., The View from Building 20, 111-
and J. Mugdan eds. Morphologie-morphology,
176, Cambridge: MIT Press.
897–916. Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter
Harley, H. and R. Noyer. 2003. Distributed Morphol-
Osborne, T. 2005. Beyond the constituent: a depen-
ogy. In The Second GLOT International State-of-
dency grammar analysis of chains. Folia Linguis-
the-Article Book. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. 463-
tica 39/3-4: 251-297.
496.
Osborne, T., M. Putnam and T. Groß (in press). Cate-
Harnisch, R. 2003. Verbabhängige Morphologie und
nae: Introducing a novel unit of syntactic analysis.
Valenzmorphologie der Subjekt-Verb-Kongruenz.
Syntax.
Ágel, V. et al. (eds.), Dependency and valency: An
international handbook of contemporary research, Pesetsky, D. 1985. Morphology and logical form.
vol. 1, 411-421. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Linguistic Inquiry 16:193-246.
Hays, D. 1964. Dependency theory: A formalism and Scalise, S. and A. Bisetto. 2009. The classification of
some observations. Language 40. 511-525. compounds. Lieber, R. and P. Štekauer eds., The
Oxford handbook of compounding, 34–53. Oxford:
Heringer, H-J. 1970. Einige Ergebnisse und Probleme
Oxford University Press.
der Dependenzgrammatik. Der Deutschunterricht 4.
42-98. Spencer, A. 1988. "Bracketing paradoxes and the
English lexicon." Language 64:663-682.
Hudson, R. 1984. Word Grammar. New York: Basil
Blackwell. Sproat, R. 1988. Bracketing paradoxes, cliticization,
and other topics: The mapping between syntactic
Hudson, R. 1990. An English Word Grammar. Ox-
and phonological structure. In Everaert et al. (eds),
ford: Basil Blackwell.
Morphology and Modularity. Amsterdam: North-
Hudson, R. 2007. Language networks: the new Word Holland. 339-360.
Grammar. Oxford University Press.
Stump, G. T. 1991. A paradigm-based theory of mor-
Kaisse, E. M. 19985. Connected Speech. New York: phosemantic mismatches. Language 67/4. 675-725.
Academic Press.
Stump, G. T. 2001. Inflectional Morphology: A
Klavans, J. L. 1985. The Independence of syntax and Theory of Paradigm Structure. Cambridge:
phonology in cliticization. Language 61, 95-120. Cambridge University Press.
Maxwell, D. 2003. The concept of dependency in Sternefeld, W. 2009. Syntax: Eine morphologisch
morphology. Ágel, V. et al. (eds.), Dependency and motivierte generative Beschreibung des Deutschen.

56
Band 2. Third Edition. Tübingen: Stauffenberg.
Ten Hacken, P. 2000. Derivation and compounding.
Geert B., C. Lehmann and J. Mugdan eds. Morpho-
logie-morphology, 349–60. Berlin/New York:
Mouton de Gruyter.
Williams, E. 1981. On the notions „lexically related‟
and „head of a word‟. Linguistic Inquiry 12. 245-
274.
Zwicky, A. M. 1987. Suppressing the Zs. Journal of
Linguistics 23, 133-148.

57

You might also like