You are on page 1of 8

Poverty, Inequality and Unemployment

Some Conceptual Issues in Measurement


Amartya Sen
The Indian poor may not be accustomed to receiving much help, but they are beginning to get used
to being counted. The poor in this country have lately been lined up in all kinds of different ways and have
been subjected to several sophisticated head-counts.l Measurements of two related phenomena, viz, inequa-
lity and unemployment, have also received much attention recently.3 This note is concerned with tackling
some conceptual issues thrown up by these measurement exercises. In particular, the object is :
(i) to discuss briefly the relation between the concepts of poverty, inequality and unemployment;
(ii) to review some recent analytical results on the welfare aspects of inequality measurement;
(in) to present an axiomatic framework for inequality measurement aiming to throw some light on
measures like the Gini co-efficient;
and (iv) to propose, in the light of (iii), an alternative measure of poverty, which is, in some im-
portant ways, superior to the measure used in the poverty debate.
with inequality, though illegitimate, is
field of poverty as such remains an
not as easily dismissable as it may open question, which I have tried to
Poverty, Unemployment and the appear at first sight. However, even discuss elsewhere (Sen 1973), even
Income Criteria if the minimal level is determined en- though it should be observed that Dan-
POVERTY as a concept is closely re- tirely by the actual distribution of
dekar and Rath's own use of their esti-
lated to inequality. Given the average income (e g, equated to some fraction mates is hardly affected by whether
income level, a higher level of inequa- of the mean, or the mode), the num- they call these people "poor*' or ''un-
lity (reflected by the usual measures) ber of the poor w i l l still be a very employed".
will tend to be associated with a gross measure of inequality, concen- In this context I would like to make
higher level of poverty. Furthermore, trating as it does only on one thing. one remark on Raj Krishna's illuminat-
the so-called "poverty line" may some- As it happens it is, in fact, also a ing classification of the concepts of
times be drawn in the light of the gross measure of poverty. In Section 6 unemployment and in particular on his
socially accepted "minimal" standard of there will be an occasion to discuss definition of "the Income Criterion".
living, and the latter can be influenced this measure further. Suppose we reject the Dandekar-Rath
by the average income level, so that Poverty has been identified not view. We shall then be left with Raj
poverty measures, thus defined, may merely with inequality but also with Krishna's other trade categories, viz
catch an aspect of relative inequality unemployment. This has occurred re- "the Time Criterion", "the Willing-
as well. cently in many studies across ness Criterion" and "the Productivity
the
The famous study group (set up by globe, e g, i n the I L O 4'country re-
Criterion". Can wo do without an
the Planning Commission) that sancti- ports1', especially in the Kenya report.
income concept in the study of un-
fied in 1962 the magic figure of Rs 20 In India a somewhat similar view has employment even if we reject the defi-
per month at 1960-61 prices as the been taken by Dandekar and Rath nition of an unemployed as a person
poverty level had considered nutrition, (1971), who have defined "an adequate who "earns an income per year less
but did not specify any particular level of employment . . . in terms of than some desirable minimum"? I
nutritional norm nor any set of prices its capacity to provide minimum liv- would argue that we cannot since a
as a justification for its choice of Rs 20. ing to the population". In his four- relevant distinction is concerned with
That number has been widely used, fold classification whether the work in question produces
of unemployment,
along with other rides of thumb, c g, Raj Krishna (1973) identifies an income for the person concerned,
this
Bardhan's Rs 15 for rural and Rs 18 approach to unemployment as i e, whether the emoluments received by
"the
for urban areas, and Dandekar and Income Criterion". He observes that a person is conditional on his work.
Rath's Rs 15 for rural and Rs 22.50 Dandekar and Rath "abandon the The distinction is quite crucial in the
for urban areas. While other estimates context of pre-capitalist economic for-
time criterion altogether for measuring
were also done by Ojha, Dandekar and unemployment and, in effect, mations.
reject
Rath, and Bardhan, using specific the distinction between poverty, consi- Contrast two cases, In both the cases
nutritional standards,3 many of the dered as consumption below a certain a person receives his economic sup-
poverty estimates are based on mini- minimum, and unemployment, consi-
port from the joint family and also
mal levels that directly or indirectly dered as an involuntary failure to get works on the family farm. In case
take note of the prevailing social ideas income-yielding work for the normal A he would cease to receive the sup-
on the subject of "poverty". The num- number of working days in a year" port if he would stop working, while
ber of the poor in such a context is (p 475). A person may be working for in case B he would receive the support
also partly a reflection of relative ine- long hours and be paid for his efforts,
anyway, even if he did not work. "The
quality, and the same authors would but if his remuneration rate is low, he
Time Criterion" cannot discriminate
have presumably used different norms may still end up being classified as between the two cases since he work3
if they were ' to estimate poverty in, "unemployed". the same amount in both cases. Nor
say, the United States. Whether it makes sense to stretch can "the Willingness Criterion", since
Thus the identification of poverty the concept of unemployment into the he may be equally willing or unwilling

1457
Special Number August 1973
ECONOMIC AND POLITICAL WEEKLY
in both eases. Nor can "the Producti-
II surement. These and other related
vity Criterion", since he may be equal-
questions I have tried to go into else-
ly productive in both cases; his remo- Standard Inequality Measures where (Sen 1973a).
val may or may not affect the output
in either case. But is there not a re- In the empirical literature many
levant distinction in the fact that in measures of inequality have been Ill
used, and they do not often rank
case A the person's income will cease
alternative income distributions in the Lorenz Curve Comparisons
if his work ceases, while in case B it
same way. The variance, the co-effi-
will not? The Lorenz Curve shows the per-
cient of variation, the standard devia-
The distinction is important for eco- centage of income received by the
tion of logarithms, the Lorenz curves,
nomies like India, and is of relevance bottom x per cent of the population
the Gini co-efficient, the income share
to many different problems. First, it is with x varying from 0 to 100. See
of the bottom x (say, 10) per cent of
Diagram 1, curve OB A. The great
important in developing a conceptual the population, and other examples
advantage of Lorenz curve compari-
framework for the coverage of the work- abound in the empirical literature.
sons is that we can say something
force. The right of an ablebodied man What underlying view of social wel-
about comparative levels of social wel-
to receive economic support without fare, or planning objectives, do they
fare without specifying anything very
working typically differs from that of respectively imply?
particular about the exact welfare
a woman or a child depending on As is well known, the mean-variance function. If distribution .x has a uni-
social traditions. Second, it is also re- analysis used in a system in which formly higher Lorenz curve (higher at
levant in calculating the supply price social welfare is taken to be the sum some places and lower nowhere)
of a labourer from a joint family mov- of individual welfares would make than distribution y involving the same
ing to the town for employment there sense only if individual welfare is a total income, then social welfare W
rather than continuing to work in the quadratic function of individual from x must be larger than social wel-
joint farm, since the emigrant's calcu- income, and this is quite a restrictive fare from y, no matter which W(.)
lations of his own gains would depend assumption. For variance as a mea- function we choose as long as W(.) is
on whether and to what extent his sure of relative inequality there is the a symmetric and strictly quasiconcave
farm income is conditional on his be- further difficulty that it is not arean- function of the vector of individual
ing on the farm and working there. independent, i e, x may be a relatively incomes. (In fact, even quasi-conca-
Third, a substantial short-run influx of more equal distribution in a uniform vity is not necessary, on which I shall
migrant labourers from their town way than y, but x can still have a comment presently.) Suppose we know
jobs to their family farms at peak higher variance if the mean income is that social welfare W depends on indi-
periods of harvesting and sowing, higher for x than for y. This prob- vidual incomes :
which has been frequently interpreted lem can be avoided by using instead
to mean the absence of unemployment the co-efficient of variation, but the W - W (y„....,y n )
in terms of "the Productivity Crite- limited nature of the underlying wel-
rion", need not necessarily imply any fare function remains. Further, no special importance is
such thing. It is possible that the farm attached to who has which income,
The standard deviation of loga- i e, a permutation of the incomes
output would still be the same (with
rithms is, in some ways, even more of
others working harder), but the right between the persons leaves W
a special cose in terms of its welfare
of the migrant labourer to a part of the unchanged (symmetry), and the social
interpretation, even though it has the
fruits of the joint farm would be com- welfare level from any weighted
attractive characteristic, in contrast
promised by his inability to participate average of two income distribution
with the co-efficient of variation, that
in the work a I. crucial moments. In vectors is larger than the minimum of
the sensitivity of the measure to a
this case the person would be unem- the social welfare levels of the two
small transfer of income from a per-
ployed in the farm in terms of "the (strict quasi-concavity), which implies
son with income y to one with income
Productivity Criterion-\ but employed — roughly — that the ratio of the
(y + d) diminishes sharply as we con-
in terms of an "Income Criterion", weight on person is income vis-a-vis
sider higher and higher y. But it can
which has nothing to do with the Dan- that on i's income will go down as i
be shown that even a perverse result
dekar-Rath "Income Criterion" which gets relatively richer vis-a-vis j.
is possible in the sense that a transfer
Raj Krishna discuses. Then, even without knowing anything
from a poorer person to a richer man
more about the nature of the social
I shall not go further into the ques- can, under certain circumstances,
welfare function W(.), we can tell that
tion here; ! have tried to spell out reduce the standard deviation of
a higher Lorenz curve implies more
elsewhere (Sen 1973) the relevance of logarithms for relatively high incomes.4
social welfare for the same total of
this conceptual category for unemploy- A social welfare function that permits
income. The argument can be easily
ment studies in pre-capitalist formations this is obviously open to some serious
extended to variable population sizes
varying with rules relating ownership, objection.
as well under a relatively innocuous
work, economic support, and income. The rest of the paper will be con- assumption, and a higher Lorenz curve
Poverty may be an odd measure of cerned with the Lorenz curve, the implies a larger mean social welfare
unemployment, but to catch one im- Ginico-efficient, and some poverty for the same mean level of income.6
portant dimension of the problem of measures, I shall not discuss any fur- Thus the practical importance of a
unemployment, we do need some ther the welfare aspects of other ine- higher Lorenz curve is indeed substan-
income criterion, in addition to the quality measures. Nor the problem of tial, even without specifying a great
criteria based on time, willingness and output heterogeneity and relative pri- deal about the objectives of planning.
productivity. ces in the context of inequality mea- Such statements as "the distribution

1458
ECONOMIC AND POLITICAL WEEKLY Special Number August 1973 -

T A B L E 1 : PERCENTAGE SHARE OF CON- income varies, we can say that the site order to the ranking of the values
SUMPTION ENJOYED BY T H E B O T T O M X change from the first to the second of the Gini co-efficients. Additivity is,
PER C E N T OF THE I N D I A N RURAL POPU-
LATION: 1964-65
involves an inequality-increasing shift of course, a restriction and is possibly
in the distribution of income combined quite objectionable, as noted in Sen
x% NSS(%) NCAER(%) with a change in total income. But (1972), (1973a), and Sheshinski (1972),
sometimes two distributions do not but it can be easily demonstrated that
have this property and the Lorenz a relaxation of additivity alone will
curves may cross. Typically, the Lorenz not eliminate this problem of the Cini
ranking is a partial ordering. co-efficient in a framework of indivi-
A good example is given by two dualistic social welfare. In fact, as
alternative estimates of the distribution slated in the last section, the nega-
of rural consumption in 1964-65 based tive of the Gini co-efficient is not
respectively on the National Sample strictly quasi-concave, which would
Survey data and the data of the National of course rule out non-additive welfare
Council of Applied Economic Research.1^ functions as well if they are strictly
Table 1 presents the percentage shares quasi-concave (see Dasgupta, Sen and
of income is worse from the welfare
of the bottom x per cent of the rural Starrett 1973 and Sen 1973a).
point of v i e w " can be made in these
population taken in cumulative decile This seems a bit sad since the Cini
cases without the need to specify any
groups. I t is clear that the NCAER co-efficient is so widely used. What
particular social welfare function.
Lorenz curve starts above the NSS does the Gini co-efficient stand for ex-
In fact, Lorenz curve comparisons
curve but falls below it later. The actly? In the next section an axiomatic
can be shown to have another rather
7 theorems stated in the last section on framework is presented yielding axioms
extraordinary property. If x has a
Lorenz comparisons will not now yield that are necessary and sufficient for the
higher Lorenz curve than y but the
anything whatsoever. We must take: a planner to wish to minimise the Gini
same total income, then we can move
more specific view of the welfare co-efficient of distributions of a given
from y to x through a finite sequence
objectives. total income.
of single transfers from richer to poor-
Consider two of the widely used
er persons. Thus a higher Lorenz
measures in India: (i) the share of the
curve implies a more equal distribu- V
bottom 10 per cent: NCAER with 3.77
tion in this strictly descriptive (rather
per cent as opposed to 3.48 per cent is
than normative) sense. It is also the An Axiomatic Framework
a better distribution; (ii) the Gini co-
case that with a symmetric and strict-
efficient (or the Lorenz Ratio as it is Consider the welfare value of an
ly quasi-concave welfare function
frequently called): NSS is a better dis- income vector y given by:
W(.), such a sequence of rich-to-poor
tribution having a value of 0.29 as
transfers must necessarily increase
opposed to NCAER's 0.32. The for- w
0')=35ys v. 0 ) , (2)
social welfare W . But quasi-concavity
mer criterion is a perfectly obvious i
is not necessary for this purpose. What
one. Its merits are clear and so are where y is the income of the 1-th 1-1th
then is the necessary and sufficient
its defects. But the Gini co-efficient is
condition to be satisfied by the wel- person (i e, the 1-th 1.-th component of y)
more opaque since it measures the
fare function W(.) to have the property
distance between the diagonal "line ol and v. ( y ) a weight on yjyi Note that
of yielding a higher W wherever the
equal division'' and the Lorenz Curve, this functional form as such is not very
Lorenz curve shifts upwards? The type
e g, the shaded area OB A in Diagram 1. restrictive, since v. can vary with any
of concavity required is strict S-con-
Unlike in Lorenz comparisons, the component of Y, T/, and whatever the
cavity. 8 This can be satisfied by some
Gini co-efficient comparisons are always shape of any general general W(.) function,
welfare functions which arc not strict-
conclusive since one real number must we can represent it in the form of (2)
ly quasi-concave, e g, the negative of
be greater than, equal to, or less than, by choosing an appropriate set of
the Cini co-efficient. Essentially any
another. But what does it stand for?
welfare function that responds positi- I shall now propose four axioms. I
vely to the type of rich-to-poor trans- A number of papers written recent-
ly have queried the welfare implications should explain at the outset that I do
fers that is involved in moving to a not intend to lay down my life fighting fighting
higher Lorenz curve will do. The con- of the Cini co-efficient, it has been
asked: What class of welfare func- for the acceptance of these axioms,
dition to be imposed on the welfare
function is perfectly transparent and is, tions will be maximised if the Gini but they are somewhat appealing
co-efficient is minimised for distributions within a specific framework, and what
in fact, much easier to follow than is more important, they correspond
the rather technical concepts of con- of a given total income? It has ap-
peared that the class of welfare func- exactly to the Gini co-efficient, helping
cavity, quasi-concavity and S-concavity,9 us to understand it. Let us define (y,i) (yj)
tions corresponding to the Gini co-
asas the state of being in individual is
IV efficient is highly restrictive. Atkinson
shoes with the distribution yt 1 %
(1970) raised his additively separable
Lorenz Comparison Indeterminacy eyebrows at the Gini co-efficient's lack having yi income while the distribu_
distribu-
and the Gini Co-efficient tion is f/.y.
of strict concavity, and Newbery (1970)
If we compare two distributions formally proved a theorem showing Axiom E (Weighting Equity): IIff every_ every-
and the Lorenz curve of one is uni- that no additive social welfare function one prefers (y,
( y , i) to (y.j), then:
formly above that of another, we are based on strictly concave individual
in luck as far as inequality measure- utility functions can order distributions vj ( 0 > vs ( 0 .
ment is concerned. Even if the total of a given total in precisely the oppo- Axiom O (Ordinal Information): If
If

1459
Special Number August 1973 ECONOMIC AND POLITICAL WEEKLY

1460
ECONOMIC AND POLITICAL WEEKLY Special Number August 1973

DIAGRAM 1

Axiom L (Limit Equality): All distri_


butions y of a constant total income
Y over a constant population must
have the same maximal v. (y).
and the same minimal vi (y) for
variations in i.
Axiom M (Independent Monotonicity):
For all all individuals regard (y, i)
to be at least as good as (y, j) if and
only if yi > yj.
Axiom E requires that a person
whose position is regarded by all to
be worse than that of another should
enjoy a higher weight on his own
income. 11 Axiom O suggests that in
constructing the weights only ordering
information can be used with no in_
formation on intensity of preference
other than how many positions lie in
between the two alternatives in the per_
son's preference scale, which is part of
in either order in the case of a tie), The weights depend on rank orders
the ranking data. So that if everyone pre-
then: and weight difference between two
ievs (y, i) to (y, j) with no interme_
persons with given incomes will change
diate alternative, and (y m) to (y, n)
if the number of people with incomes
again with no intermediate alternative,
in between changes. The difficulty arises
then the weight on j's income should
from trying to get a set of cardinal
exceed that of i by precisely as much where A and B are constants for weights from ordinal information only
as the weight on n's income over that a given total income and given popu- and that too confined to the ranking
of m. Axiom L wants all income dis_ lation, w i t h B > 0 , It is, of course, of the different persons' positions only
tributions to have weights lying within easily demonstrated that the Gini co- in the distribution in question.
the same range as long as they are efficient can be written as:
distributions of the same total income
over the same population. Axiom M VI
makes each person decide his prefer_
ence on the basis of his income alone Measurement of Poverty
and it is assumed that he prefers more Finally, some remarks on poverty
to less. where z = mean income, and n measures. Let y be the minimal ac-
Theorem: A welfare function W(.) population size. I t is obvious that given ceptable level of income. I n the frame-
satisfying Axioms E, O, L z. and n, minimising G is equivalent work of (2), consider the following sys-
and M must rank all alter_ to maximising W . tem of weighting ;
native distributions of a Perhaps the most controversial axiom
given total income over a is Ordinal Information. In trying to get
given population, with distinct a weighting system based on ranking
income for each individual, information only without arbitrary dis-
in exactly the same way tinctions, we come close to a rank-
as the negative of the Gini order weighted sum of individual in-
co-efficient. comes. The Gini co-efficient amounts to
The proof is easily provided but is this also since the Lorenz. curve is con- where N ( Y > y ) is the number of
omitted here, 12 but the strategy of it structed taking the poorest person's people with income no lower than the
lies in showing that Axioms E, O, L income at every point, the next poorest poverty line. Maximising (6) for a given
and M imply that W(y) must be a person's income at all points but one, population w i l l amount to minimising
positive linear (strictly, affine) trans_ and so on until the richest man comes poverty as defined in the Minhas-
formation of the rank-order weighted in by the skin of his teeth at the last Brdhan - Ojha- Dandekar-Rath - Vaidyana -
sum of individual incomes. More point. Hence the correspondence with than debate. The extreme nature of (5)
specifically, if 1 stands for the i-th poor_ rank order weighting. is apparent. While rule (i) satisfies the
est man (with the poorest being 1, Axiom O also brings out one of the Axiom of Weighting Equity, rule (ii)
next poorest 2, etc, taking individuals main limitations of the Gini measure. violates it robustly.

1461
ECONOMIC AND POLITICAL WEEKLY Special Number August 197-3

DIAGRAM 2
P = (2/n2z)£ (y*-yd (q-i+i)
i=)
(9)
I t is easily checked that putting
and we get the Gini co-efficient
as a special case of this poverty mea_
sure.
I n Diagram 2, the poverty measure
is roughly represented by the shaded
area OBC, where the slope of OE re_
presents the poverty level normalised
in percentage units. It differs from the
Gini co-efficient (area OBA), which is
a measure of relative inequality, in two
ways, viz., (a) in being concerned only
with the people who lie below the
poverty line (leaving out area DBA),
and (b) in calculating the income
differences from the poverty level and
not from the average income of the
distribution itself (leaving out area
ODC). On the other hand, it differs
from the standard poverty measure q,
represented in Diagram 2 by OQ, in
being sensitive to the size of the income
100 gaps of the poor, and in putting more
weight on the relatively poorer both (a)
by noting their larger income gaps as
well as (b) by putting in greater weights
It also emphasises the sharp break per unit of that shortfall in the poverty
per unit on their income gaps.
at y which makes it worthwhile for measure.
public policy makers, seeking credit for The following additional notation will I would ar
achievements in "garibi hatao", to con_ be used : poverty, P is superior both to the usual
centrate on people just below the level q = t h e number of people at or below head-count as well as to the standard
of y*. Pushing them a little higher up the poverty line, i c t ya ~ y*; measures of relative inequality. Fur_
brings in rich dividends in terms of this r=the weight on the poverty gap thermore, the data requirement to esti_
of
poverty measure, while the credit for person i; mate P is less than what is needed to
pushing up even poorer people is likely draw the Lorenz curve or to calculate
A ( Y , n ) = a parameter dependent on
to be zero in this measure unless they the Gini co-efficient, both of which are
total income Y and population size n.
are pushed up quite a bit. The con- frequently performed.
Satisfying (i) and (ii), we can consider
centratfon on the "potentially viable"
the following general form for the
small farmers in the recent schemes of
poverty measure P : Notes
rural development reflects an approach
1 See, especially, Minhas (1970),
that is closely aligned to the concep_ (1971), Bardhan (1970), (1971).
tion of poverty given by (6). While there (1973), Ojha (1970), Dandekar and
is no doubt that the poverty debate Rath (1971), and Vaidyanathan
that took place recently has contribut_ (1971).
ed much to our understanding of cer_ 2 The literature on income distribu_
In the light of the justification of tion is vast, and includes, among
tain important aspects of the Indian others. Lydall (I960), Ojha and
economy, the nature of the measure_ the system of rank order weighting in
Bhatt (1964), (1964a), Randive
ment used provides scope for public the Gini co-efficient, a case for using (1965), Ahmed (1965), Iyengar and
policy being concerned with the rela_ rank order weights in the poverty mea_ Bhattacharya (1965), Swamy (1967),
sure can also be constructed. A simple f 1967a), Mukherjee (1969), (1972),
tively richer among the poor, ignoring Bardhan and Srinivasan (1971),
greater suffering. measure, closely aligned to the Gini
Srinivasan and Vaidyanathan
measure of inequality, will be : (1971), Vaidyanathan (1971), Ahm_
How should we modify the poverty ed and Bhattacharya (1972), and
measure to take note of these prob_ Bardhan (1973). For an excellent
critical evaluation of the literature
lems? At least two changes would seem
on unemployment, sec Raj Krishna
to be needed : (i) we should be con_ (1973).
cerned not merely with the number In fact a slight variation helps to make 3 See also Panikar (1972).
of people below the poverty line but the poverty measure independent of the 4 See Atkinson (1970), and Dasgup-
also with the amounts by which the absolute size of the population, i e, ta, Sen and Starrett (1973).
incomes of the poor fall short of the making the value of P unaffected by 5 See Dasgupta, Sen and Starrett
specified poverty level, and (ii) the multiplying the population in each in_ (197-3). This is an extension of an
bigger the shortfall from the poverty come group by the same positive num_ important earlier result by Atkin_
son (1970). The assumptions of
level, greater should be the weight ber : additive separability and strict

146.3
Special Number August 1973 ECONOMIC AND POLITICAL WEEKLY

concavity used there are dropped Ahmed, M, and Bhattacharya, N (1972), nomics and Statistics, Vol 27.
in Dasgupta, Sen and Starrett "Size Distribution of Per Capita Rothschild, M, and Stiglitz, J E (1973),
(1973). See also Rothschild and Personal Income in India", Economic "Some Further Results on the Mea-
Stiglitz (1973). See Bardhan (1973a) and Political Weekly, Special Num- surement of Inequality", Journal of
for empirical uses with Indian ber, Vol VII. Economic Theory, Vol 6.
data. Atkinson, A B (1970), "On the Mea- Sen, A K (1972), "Utilitarianism and
surement of Inequality", Journal of Inequality", Economic and Political
See Dasgupta, Sen and Starrett Weekly, Annual Number, Vol VII.
(1973), Theorem 2. Economic Theory, Vol 2.
— (1973), "Employment Policy and
See Kolm (1969), Atkinson (1970), Bardhan, P K (1970), "On the Mini- Technological Choice", in press.
and Dasgupta, Sen and Stiglitz mum Level of Living and the Rural — (1973a), "On Economic Inequality",
(1973). Poor", Indian Economic Review, RadclifTe Lectures, 1972, Clarendon
See Berge (1963). Vol 5. Press, Oxford, Norton, New York,
— (1971), "On the Minimum Level of and OUP, Bombay.
There is a minor error in the Living and the Rural Poor : A Fur-
presentation of our results in Das- Srinivasan, T N, and Vaidyanathan, A
ther Note", Indian Economic Review, (1971), "Data on Distribution of
gupta, Sen and Starrett (1973). We Vol 6.
defined strict S-concavity thus: "If — (1973), "On the Incidence of Poverty Consumption Expenditure in India:
for all bistochastic matrix Q, which An Evaluation", paper presented at
in Rural India", Economic and the IS1 Seminar on Income Distribu-
is not a permutation matrix of Political Weekly, Annual Number, tion.
order n, F(Qx) > F(.r), then F Vol V I I I . Swamy, S (1967), "Distribution of In-
is strictly S-concave" (p 183). In — (1973a), "The Pattern of Income come in India", Economic and Politi-
fact, Q can permute some x with- Distribution in India: A Review", cal Weekly, Annual Number, Vol IL
out Q being a permutation matrix. Bardhan, mimeographed. (1967a), "Structural Changes and
P K, and Srinivasan, T N the Distribution of Income by Size",
Consider, for example : (1971), "Income Distribution Pat- Review of Income and Wealth, June.
terns, Trends and Policies", Econo- Vaidyanathan, A (1971), "Some Aspects
mic and Political Weekly, April 24, of Inequalities in Living Standards
Vol VI. in Rural India", paper presented at
Berge, G (1963), "Topological Spaces", the ISI Seminar on Income Distribu-
The correct definition should be: Oliver and Boyd, Edinburgh. tion.
f " I f for all bistochastic matrix Q, Dandekar, V M, and Rath, N (1971),
F ( 0 x) > F(x) whenever Qx is "Poverty in India", Indian School of
not x nor a permutation of it, Political Economy.
then F is strictly S-concave". A Dasgupta, P, Sen, A K, and Starrett, D Superior Electronic Systems
corresponding correction is need- (1973), "Notes on the Measurement
ed in statement (i) of Lemma 2 of Inequality", Journal of Economic SUPERIOR ELECTRONIC SYSTEMS
and in Theorems 1 and 2 (p 182). Theory, Vol 6.
has introduced its model of electronic
I am most grateful to Penelope Iyengar, N S, and Bhattacharya, N
Rowlatt for raising a perceptive (1965), "On the Effect of Differen- digital calculators in the market. Called
query concerning Lemma "2. tials in Consumer Price Index on Superior 14M, the calculator is the first
Measures of Inequality", Sankhya. in India to vise Gallium Arsenide Phos-
10 See Bardhan (1973a), Table 6. Kolm, S Ch (1969), "The Optimal Pro-
Note that the NSS data refer duction of Social Justice", in J Mar- phide (GaAsP) Light Emitting Diodes
to July 1964 - June 1965 while golis and H Guitton, eds, "Public for its 14-di^it solid state display; other
the NCAER data are concerned Economics", Macmillan, London. makes of digital calculators available
with May 1964-April 1965. Lydall, H F (1960), "The Inequality of today use tubes or filaments which have
11 The rationale of this axiom has Indian Incomes", Economic Weekly,
some similarity with the Weak Special Number. •a limited life. Another feature claimed
Symmetry Axiom proposed in Sen Minhas, B S (1970), "Rural Poverty, for the calculator is its exchange func-
(1973a).' Land Redistribution and Develop- tion. On other electronic calculators,
ment", Indian Economic Review, only certain types of calculations in-
12 Proofs of this and some other Vol 5.
related theorems are given in my — (1971), "Rural Poverty and the volving reciprocals are possible — that
"Aggregation and Income Distri- Minimum Level of Living" Indian too, by partly doing the calculations on
bution". paper to be presented in Economic Review,, Vol 6.
the International Seminar on Mukherjee, M (1969), "National Income paper. The exchange function in the
Public Economics to be held in Superior 14M enables all such calcula-
of India: Trends and Structure",
Siena in September, 1973. The Calcutta. tions to be performed entirely on the
theorem presented here holds for — (1972), "Price Information Associa- machine, thereby eliminating a lot of
distributions with a distinct income ted with Principal Distributions of needless paper-work and speeding up
for each person, i e, for distribu- National Income", Economic and
tions such that no two persons computations. The Superior 14M also
Political Weekly, Vol VII.
have the .same income. To extend Ojha, P D (1970), " A Configuration of has a built-in 14-digit Memory Bank
the result to cover all distributions. Indian Poverty", Reserve Bank of for instant retention and repetitive re-
Axiom O 0 is used to supplement India Bulletin, January. call. The Superior 14M Electronic Digi-
Axiom O in my Siena paper, re- Ojha. P D, and Bhatt, V V (1964), tal Calculator has six 'instant response*
quiring that if all individuals rank "Some Aspects of Income Distribu-
a set of positions as indifferent, tion in India", Bulletin of the Oxford functions. Besides, it has facilities for
they should be put in any arbitrary University Institute of Economics performing multiplication and division
chain of unanimous strict prefe- and Statistics, Vol 26. using a constant, for reciprocal and in-
rence. All possible chains yield the — (1964a), "Pattern of Income Distri- version of operation, and for automatic
0
same result, and Axioms E, O, O , L bution in an Underdeveloped Eco-
and M make the theorem hold for nomy", American Economic Review, credit balancing. The Superior 14M
all distributions of a given income. Vol 54. utilises 70 per cent indigenously pro-
Panikar, P G K (1972), "Economics of duced components. Superior Electronics
Nutrition", Economic and Political Systems has a licensed capacity to pro-
References Weekly, Annual Number, Vol VII
Raj Krishna (1973), "Unemployment in duce 3,000 electronic digital calcula-
Ahmed, M (1965), "Size Distribution India", Economic and Political tors per year. Its calculators are distri-
of Personal Income and SavinR in Weekly, March 3, Vol VIII. buted by Blue Star which has expe-
India 1956-57", in N S R Sastry et al Randive. K R (1965), "The 'Equality' rience of handling vi wide range of busi-
eds, "Papers on National Income and of Incomes in India", Bulletin of the
Oxford University Institute of Eco- ness machines.
Allied Topics", Vol III.

1464

You might also like