You are on page 1of 8

American Economic Association

Absolute versus Relative Poverty


Author(s): James E. Foster
Source: The American Economic Review, Vol. 88, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of the
Hundred and Tenth Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association (May, 1998), pp.
335-341
Published by: American Economic Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/116944 .
Accessed: 24/12/2013 13:24

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
American Economic Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 128.59.62.83 on Tue, 24 Dec 2013 13:24:08 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
WHATIS POVERTYAND WHOARE THEPOOR?
REDEFINITION
FOR THEUNITEDSTATESIN THE1990'St

Absolute versus Relative Poverty

By JAMES E. FOSTER*

Should poverty be measured using an "ab- choosing poverty lines and in aggregating the
solute" or a "relative" approach?This age- data into an overall index of poverty. A gen-
old question in poverty measurement is once eral taxonomy is presented, and the question
again on the agenda, due to the ambitiouspro- of robust comparisons is addressedwithin this
posals of PatriciaRuggles (1990) and the Na- general framework.Special attentionis paid to
tional Research Council of the National distinguishing between (i) the general concept
Academy of Sciences (Constance Citro and underlying the poverty line and (ii) the partic-
Robert Michael, 1995) to alter the way U.S. ular cutoff chosen. The paper concludes with
poverty is measured. Their wide-ranging sug- a discussion of "hybrid" poverty lines and the
gestions include a new "hybrid" approachto associated parameterthatis likely to play a key
setting the poverty threshold that, unlike the role in futurediscussions: the income elasticity
current absolute method, is sensitive to of the poverty line.
changes in the general living standard,but less
sensitive than a purely relative approach.The I. Elements
proposals also recommend using aggregate in-
dexes of poverty beyond the usual "head- Poverty measurement is based on a com-
counts," such as well-known "gap" measures parison of resources to needs. A person or
and indicators of the distributionof resources family is identified as poor if its resources fall
among the poor. Importantrelative notions of short of the poverty threshold. The data on
poverty enter at this "aggregation" step as families are then aggregatedto obtain an over-
well. The effects of the various recommenda- all view of poverty.
tions on the trend and cross-sectional profiles There are many ways of defining resources,
of poverty are actively being explored (see constructing thresholds, and aggregating the
e.g., David Betson and JenniferWarlick, 1997; resulting data (see e.g., Ruggles, 1990; Martin
Thesia Gamer et al., 1997; David Johnson et Ravallion, 1994; Citro and Michael, 1995).
al., 1997). At the same time it may prove use- Virtually all partition the population into
ful to consider some of the conceptual mea- groups of families (or resource-sharingunits)
surement issues arising from the proposals. with similar characteristics, and I follow this
This is the direction taken in the present study. approachhere. Let 0 denote the raw data, con-
This paper evaluates the multiple notions of taining information on resources received by
relative and absolute poverty that arise in families, their demographic and other charac-
teristics, and perhaps other data (e.g., con-
sumption distributions) needed to construct
t Discussants: David S. Johnson, U.S. Bureau of Labor poverty thresholds. Let m be the number of
Statistics; Patricia Ruggles, U.S. Department of Health distinct groups, with nk nfk()- being the
and Human Services; BarbaraWolfe, University of Wis- number of families in group k. Once a specific
consin; ChristopherJencks, HarvardUniversity. definition of family resources has been fixed,
* Department of Economics, Vanderbilt University,
this yields a distribution of resources among
Nashville, TN 37235. I thank the discussant, David S. the families in group k, denoted by the nk_
Johnson, for his insightful commentary.Financial support
from the John D. and CatherineT. MacArthurFoundation dimensional vector x k = Xk ( ) . The poverty
throughthe Network on Inequalityand Poverty in Broader threshold for families in group k is denoted by
Perspective is gratefully acknowledged. the number Zk = zk(0); a family is identified
335

This content downloaded from 128.59.62.83 on Tue, 24 Dec 2013 13:24:08 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
336 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MAY 1998

as poor if its resource level falls below Zk. Ex- A. Threshold


actly how Zk is to be set (i.e., the "identifica-
tion step" of Amartya Sen, 1976) is a key part The first and perhaps most important sense
of the present discussion. in which poverty measurement is absolute or
As for the "aggregation step," most U.S. relative concerns the setting of the poverty
studies report poverty levels for the demo- standard. An absolute poverty line is a fixed
graphic groups and then aggregate to obtain (group-specific) cutoff level Za that is applied
an overall level of poverty. Thus, they implic- across all potential resource distributions. In
itly take the poverty index to be "decompos- comparisons over time, for example, the stan-
able" across the groups (on which more will dard is unchanged even in the face of eco-
be said presently). With overall poverty a nomic growth (although provisions are made
weighted sum of group poverties, the aggre- for changes in price levels);1 similarly, in
gation question reduces to a choice of the pov- comparisons across countries, fixed-threshold
erty index P(x; z) to apply to a typical group comparisons require an appropriateexchange
distribution x and poverty line z. The most rate. If the absolute standardis truly indepen-
common index is the head-count ratio H(x; z) dent of the current data, though, how can one
= qln where q is the number of poor families be sure that the standard chosen is an appro-
in x given z, and n is the number of families priate one? The poverty line is typically cal-
in x. This index provides importantinforma- ibrated in some initial period using, say,
tion on poverty (namely, the frequency of pov- food-budget studies, and it is then carried
erty among the population) but ignores other forth from year to year, irrespective of
relevant information on the depth and distri- whether the same procedure applied to cur-
bution of poverty. Another importantkind of rent data would yield the same result. In a
"partial index" is based on the sum of the growing economy, the gap between the hy-
income gaps (z - xi) of poor families. These pothetical recalibratedlevel and the historical
"gap indexes" add a second dimension of standardmay well be quite large. Such is the
"depth" to poverty evaluations. A third di- case with the current U.S. poverty standard,
mension is provided by indexes of inequality and this is one of the criticisms that have been
among the poor. leveled against it (see Citro and Michael,
While each partial index conveys useful in- 1995 pp. 2-3).
formation about some aspect of poverty (as- In contrast, a relative approachuses current
suming, of course, that the poverty threshold data to generate the currentpoverty threshold.
itself is meaningful), one must be careful in A relative poverty line begins with some no-
using its unidimensional prescriptions as a tion of a standard of living r(x) for the distri-
guide to policy. For this and other reasons, it bution x, such as the mean, median, or some
has been argued (see e.g., Foster and Sen, other quantile, and defines the cutoff as some
1997) that an index combining all three di- percentage a of this standard.The result is a
mensions is more coherent in this role. Such poverty threshold Zr = ar(x) that varies one-
"distribution-sensitive" indexes have been for-one with the standardof living, in that a 1-
used to great advantage in internationalcom- percent increase in r is matched by a 1-percent
parisons and development studies (see e.g., increase in Zr, Examples include the "50 per-
Ravallion, 1994). cent of the median" relative poverty line pro-
posed by Victor Fuchs (1969) and the "50
II. Absolutesand Relativities percent of the mean" threshold employed by

There are several ways in which relative and


absolute considerations enter into poverty
measurement. I offer a simple taxonomy in-
' There is a significant issue of whetherresource should
cluding the threshold and equivalence-scale
be expressed in real terms and, if so, which cost of living
choices in the identification step, and the treat- index to use. This issue is ignored here for simplicity, but
ment of population, scale, and individual dep- it is clearly another potentially importantsource of "rel-
rivation in the aggregation step. ativity" in the measurementof poverty.

This content downloaded from 128.59.62.83 on Tue, 24 Dec 2013 13:24:08 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL. 88 NO. 2 WHATIS POVERTYAND WHOARE THE POOR? 337

Michael O'Higgins and Stephen Jenkins adjusted across demographic groups. One ap-
(1990).2 proach is to apply repeatedly the procedurefor
Using a relative line does not amount to setting poverty lines to each group separately
measuring inequality (although theorem 6 in and thereby arrive at m independent thresh-
Foster and Anthony F. Shorrocks [1988a] pro- olds. However, as noted by Ruggles ( 1990 Ch.
vides one important link) nor does it imply 4), this can lead to odd (rnonmonotonic)be-
that poverty is by definition "always with us" havior of the poverty line as famiily size
(see Anthony Atkinson, 1975 p. 189). And changes. An alternativeapproach sets the line
while many studies regardabsolute lines as be- in one reference group and then derives the
ing especially low and relative lines as being remaining thresholds using an "equivalence
high, this is not necessarily the case. If living scale" to account for the differing needs of
standardsare rising and thresholds are pegged different-sized families. The typical scale pro-
at Za = Zr in some initial period, then Za < Zr vides the rate at which a dollar for one group
for all subsequent periods, but Za > Zr for all translatesinto dollars for another. So if group
previous periods, as emphasized by Citro and 1 is the reference, and Sk is the conversion rate
Michael (1995 p. 132). In any isolated period, from group 1 to group k, then Zk = 5k l be-
it is not possible to tell whether a given thresh- comes the poverty line for group k.
old z is relative or absolute, nor is the distinc- This sort of equivalence scale is relative in
tion particularly important, since the same that the transformationfrom group to group is
numerical cutoff, however originally derived, multiplicative, and consequently group pov-
must lead to the same level of poverty. erty lines are proportionateto each other. An-
The key distinction between absolute and other possibility raised by Charles Blackorby
relative thresholds is not seen in the specific and David Donaldson ('1994) is for variations
values obtained at a given date, but in how the in family configurationto have an constantab-
values change as the distribution changes. solute effect so that, for example, adding an-
Thus, there is an important distinction to be other child is seen as an additionalfixed (real)
made between the general concept underlying cost to the family, independent of the size of
the poverty threshold, and the specific cutoff the base threshold.Relative equivalence scales
selected. For comparisons involving extended preserve the ratios of group poverty lines as
periods of time, or very different standardsof the base threshold changes; an absolute equiv-
living, the former is likely to be the more im- alence scale preserves the absolute differ-
portant issue (see also Ruggles, 1990 Ch. 3), ences. The two forms are indistinguishablefor
while the latter choice (of cutoff) is largely a single observation or if the reference thresh-
arbitrary(see Fuchs, 1969; Atkinson, 1975, old remains unchanged (as with an absolute
1987; Foster and Shorrocks, 1988b). This in- poverty line).
evitable arbitrarinesscasts doubt on the mean-
ing of the cardinal poverty levels obtained at C. Population
specific cutoffs and leads to a considerationof
the robustness of results to changes in the cut- The aggregation stage uses three notions of
off, a topic I will returnto below. absolute and relative poverty in constructing
poverty indexes. First, a relative or per capita
B. Equivalence Scale poverty index is independentof the population
size in the sense that "replicating" the popu-
A second entry point for relativities in pov- lation leaves the poverty value unaffected: for
erty measurement is where poverty lines are example, P(x, x; z) = P(x; z). Such a mea-
sure is based purely on the relative frequencies
of incomes in the income distribution.In con-
2 There are importantmeasurement issues in selecting trast, an absolute index is one whose value
the standardof living. Should it be the mean, the median, rises in proportion to the number of replica-
or some other representative income? Should it be from
the entire population or some reference group? Should it tions: for example, P(x, x; z) = 2P(x; z).
be for all expenditures or a significant subset? (For ref- The head-count ratio qln is relative in this
erences, see Citro and Michael [1995].) sense while the head-count q is absolute. An

This content downloaded from 128.59.62.83 on Tue, 24 Dec 2013 13:24:08 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
338 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MAY 1998

absolute index can be converted to a relative III. RobustComparisons


index by dividing by n.
The above taxonomy presents several ave-
D. Scale nues for relative and absolute concepts to enter
into poverty evaluations, and many combina-
A second notion concerns the behavior of tions are possible. For example, the current
an index when the poverty line and incomes method for evaluating U.S. poverty employs
are simultaneously altered. A relative or an absolute threshold for each group and a rel-
scale-invariant index is one that is un- ative or absolute equivalence scale (indeter-
changed when the poverty line and all minate since poverty lines are unchanging) to
incomes are multiplied by the same factor. identify the poor; for the aggregation step it
An absolute or translation-invariant index typically uses the head-count ratio, a popula-
is independent of additions of the same tion relative index that is both absolute and
constant to the poverty line and all in- relative with respect to scale, and which is
comes (Blackorby and Donaldson, 1980). based purely on absolute deprivation. The ag-
Thus, for example, the aggregate poverty gregate gap, which is absolute in all three di-
gap 1% I (z - xi) is an absolute index of mensions, is often used as an alternativeindex.
this sort, while the normalized poverty gap Each combination of absolutes and relative
l(z-xi )/z (which measures the poverty concepts has many possible implementations
gap in poverty line units) is relative. The (i.e., specific cutoffs, scales, and indexes)
head-count ratio is both absolute and relative from which to choose. Inevitably, this entails
in this sense (and is essentially unique in this making choices for which there is little guid-
respect [see Buhong Zheng, 1994]). ance (why 50 percent of the median instead of
49 percent?). It is importantto note, however,
E. Deprivation that the decision need not be based on nor-
mative or subjective considerations. The
Finally, the basic notion of deprivation selection from the arrayof possible implemen-
that underlies a given index may be relative tations could be purely arbitrary-made in the
or absolute. If a family's poverty level de- interest of getting on with the analysis (on this
pends purely upon its own characteristics, its distinction, see Sen [1980]).
resource level, and its threshold, then the in- Given the inherent arbitrarinessin selecting
dex is based on a notion of absolute depri- a specification, it is importantto evaluate the
vation. Foster and Shorrocks (1991) relate robustness of any conclusions obtained. In
this to decomposability of the index across cases where the numerical poverty levels are
population subgroups (overall poverty is a important, this may be as simple as testing
weighted sum of subgroup poverties for any other reasonable specifications and reporting
partition) and also to a more fundamental how the poverty level changes. Betson and
notion of subgroup consistency (overall Warlick (1997), for example, use 20-percent
poverty is increasing in subgroup poverty changes in z to illustrate the cardinal sensitiv-
levels for any partition). The head-count ra- ity of head-counts to the threshold. Alterna-
tio and the gap indexes are absolute in this tively, when rankings of poverty levels are all
sense, as is the index of Foster et al. (1984) that matter, one has available a rather large
which takes [(z - xi)/zI as the ith poor collection of tools to evaluate ordinal robust-
family's deprivation level. In contrast, Sen's ness (analogous to the well-known Lorenz cri-
( 1976) index is founded on the notion of rel- terion for inequality analysis), which cover
ative deprivation, since a family's depriva- variable thresholds, equivalence scales, and
tion level depends crucially on its relative indexes (see e.g., Foster, 1984; Foster and
position among poor families and thus in- Shorrocks, 1988b; Atkinson, 1987, 1992).
corporates information beyond its own data. Virtually all approaches trace back to notions
A discussion of the two approaches can be of stochastic dominance from risk theory (see
found in section A6 of Foster and Sen the general discussion in Foster and Sen
(1997). [1997]).

This content downloaded from 128.59.62.83 on Tue, 24 Dec 2013 13:24:08 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL. 88 NO. 2 WHATIS POVERTYAND WHOARE THE POOR? 339

Most results of this type are presented in a malized equivalent incomes can be compared
one-group framework with absolute thresh- using first-degree stochastic dominance over
olds; but in fact, the tools have far greaterap- the range (0, c ), while the tests for the nor-
plicability. As an illustration, suppose that the malized gap index and the Foster et al. (1984)
base threshold z1 and equivalence scale sk are index use second- and third-degree stochastic
relative, the index P is based on a notion of dominance, respectively. Atkinson's (1987)
absolute deprivation (hence decomposable) results go beyond these results to consider
but otherwise relative, and the only question variations in poverty indexes and indicate, for
is the specific cutoff a to be used in setting the example, that if there is an unambiguouscom-
relative poverty line. Suppose that for a spe- parison for H (and hence first-degree stochas-
cific value of a, say, a - 50 percent, the re- tic dominance), then virtually any acceptable
source distribution (x, ... , xm) has greater index P will agree with this conclusion. This
poverty than (y', ... , yi). When can one be illustrates the power of the head-count ratio in
sure that this will remain true for an entire this context.
range of a values, say (0, ii ) where ii > 50
percent? Let r be the standardof living under- IV. HybridMeasurement
lying the relative poverty line, and let rx and
ry denote the respective standardsin the dis- Many of the categories in my taxonomy al-
tributions. Constructa new "equivalent" dis- low for an intermediateposition to be chosen
tribution xik for demographic group k by in place of a pure relative or absolute ap-
dividing family resources by the equivalence proach. One particularlyinterestingexample is
scale sk, and then replicating by family size in the "hybrid" poverty threshold that is central
k, so that xk has one equivalent resource level to the proposal in Citro and Michael (1995),
for each person in group k. It is not difficult which is based on what lnight be termed a
to show that for P satisfying the above prop- "partial" standardof living: rpis the median
erties, the poverty level of the original distri- expenditure on certain basic goods. The
bution (x1 ..., xm) at the group-specific threshold z = arp has the same structureas a
thresholds z = s kz is simply purely relative cutoff (and in fact the robust-
ness result applies equally well to it). How-
Px 1
Pi,..., m; .
,mz) ever, median expenditures on basic goods do
not rise as fast as, say, median total expendi-
or the poverty in the equivalent distribution tures, and it is this empirical fact that gives z
given group l's poverty line. If one further its hybrid nature.
normalizes incomes by the standardof living, One could also imagine thresholds that are
then the poverty level is given by hybrid by construction, in that they depend di-
rectly on an absolute and a relative standard.
P(xI rx, ... , ?m/rx; a) . For example, consider a weighted geometric
averageof a relativethresholdZr = ar and an
Consequently, the judgment that (x', ..., xm) absolute threshold Za, namely, z =. zzI -p
has greaterpovertythan(y', ..., ym) is in fact where 0 < p < 1. This form of hybrid line has
robust in a if the property that a 1-percent increase in the
living standard r always leads to a p-percent
P(x/rx, ..,xmlr,,; a) increase in the poverty line. In other words, p
is the elasticity of the poverty line with respect
>P(y1Ir , a)
ym/ry; to the living standard,or what Gordon Fisher
( 1995 ) has termed the income elasticity of the
foralla E (0, ). poverty line. In general, p = (dzldr)(r/z) has
This last condition is in a form that allows a naturalinterpretationas a measure of the ex-
the application of results in Foster and tent to which a given threshold z is relative,
Shorrocks (1988b) and Atkinson (1987). So, with p = 0 correspondingto an absolute pov-
for example, the test for the head-count ratio erty line and p = 1 a fully relative one. The
H checks whether the two distributionsof nor- possibility of using a hybrid standardchanges

This content downloaded from 128.59.62.83 on Tue, 24 Dec 2013 13:24:08 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
340 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MAY 1998

the question "absolute or relative?" to "ex- _ . "Measuring the Cost of Children: A


actly how relative?" with p as the relevant de- Theoretical Framework," in Richard
cision variable. Blundell, Ian Preston, and Ian Walker, eds.,
In his defense of the relative approach, The measurement of household welfare.
Fuchs (1969 p. 201) posited that the cutoff Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
"would be recognized as a national value 1994, pp. 51-69.
judgment and would be arrivedat through the Citro,ConstanceF. and Michael,RobertT. Mea-
normal political process." One theme of the suring poverty: A new approach. Washing-
present paper is the primacy of general con- ton, DC: National Academy Press, 1995.
cept over specific cutoff; if this is accepted, Fisher,GordonM. "Is There Such a Thing as
then the subject of public discourse would an Absolute Poverty Line Over Time?"
more properly be p, the income elasticity of Mimeo, U.S. Department of Health and
the poverty line. The choice of p would then Human Services, Washington, DC, August
answer the normative question: "To what ex- 1995.
tent should the poor share in economic Foster,James E. "On Economic Poverty," in
growth?" An elasticity of 1 appears to be too Robert Basmann and George Rhodes, eds.,
high to command much political supportin the Advances in econometrics, Vol. 3. Green-
United States. An elasticity of 0 is implicit in wich, CT: JAI Press, 1984, pp. 215-51.
the current standard, but given the historical Foster, James E.; Greer, Joel and Thorbecke,
tendency for absolute standardsto be period- Erik. "A Class of Decomposable Poverty
ically revised (Fisher, 1995) and the long- Measures." Econometrica, May 1984,
standing explanations why, when the general 52(3), pp. 761-66.
standardof living rises, resources may need to Foster, James E. and Sen, Amartya. "On Eco-
be higher to achieve the same ends (e.g., nomicInequalityafter a QuarterCentury,"9
Atkinson, 1975; Sen, 1983), this answer may in Amartya Sen, ed., On economic inequal-
not be tenable in the long run. However, it ity. Oxford: Clarendon, 1997, pp. 107-219.
remains to be seen whether the particularhy- Foster,JamesE. and Shorrocks,AnthonyF. "In-
brid standardproposed by National Research equality and Poverty Orderings." European
Council of the National Academy of Sciences, Economic Review, March 1988a, 32(2-3),
which has a historical income elasticity of p = pp. 654-61.
0.65 (Citro and Michael, 1995 p. 143), will _ "Poverty Orderings and Welfare
*

garner enough support to displace the current Dominance." Social Choice and Welfare,
standard. 1988b, 5(2/3), pp. 179-98.
s . 'Subgroup Consistent Poverty Mea-
REFERENCES sures." Econometrica, May 1991, 59(3),
pp. 687-709.
Atkinson, Anthony B. The economics of in- Fuchs, Victor. "Comment on Measuring the
equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Size of the Low-Income Population," in
1975. Lee Soltow, ed., Six papers on the size dis-
"On the Measurement of Poverty."
.0 tribution of wealth and income. New York:
Econometrica, July 1987, 55(4), pp. 749- National Bureau of Economic Research,
64. 1969, pp. 198-202.
._ "Measuring Poverty and Differences Garner, Thesia I.; Paulin, Geoffrey; Shipp,
in Family Composition." Economica, Feb- Stephanie; Short, Kathleenand Nelson,Chuck.
ruary 1992, 59(233), pp. 1-16. "Experimental Poverty Measurement for
Betson,DavidM. and Warlick,JenniferL. "Al- the 1990's." Mimeo, Bureau of Labor Sta-
ternative Historical Trends in Poverty." tistics, Washington, DC, 1997.
Mimeo, University of Notre Dame, 1997. Johnson, David; Shipp, Stephanieand Garner,
Blackorby, Charles and Donaldson, David. "Eth- Thesia. "Developing Poverty Thresholds
ical Indices for the Measurement of Pov- Using Expenditure Data." Unpublished
erty." Econometrica, May 1980, 48(4), manuscriptpresented at the Joint Statistical
pp. 1053-60. Meetings, Anaheim, CA, August 1997.

This content downloaded from 128.59.62.83 on Tue, 24 Dec 2013 13:24:08 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL. 88 NO. 2 WHATIS POVERTYAND WHO ARE THE POOR? 341

O'Higgins, Michael and Jenkins, Stephen. "Pov- Sen, Amartya K. "Poverty: An Ordinal Ap-
erty in the EC: Estimates for 1975, 1980, proach to Measurement." Econometrica,
and 1985," in Rudolph Teekens and March 1976, 44(2), pp. 219-31.
Bernard M. S. van Praag, eds., Analysing _-. "Description as Choice." Oxford
poverty in the European Community:Policy Economic Papers, November 1980, 32 (3),
issues, research options, and data sources. pp. 353-69.
Luxembourg: Office of Official Publi- _-. "Poor, Relatively Speaking." Oxford
cations of the European Communities, Economic Papers, July 1983, 35(2), pp.
1990, pp. 187-212. 153-69.
Ravallion,Martin.Poverty comparisons. Chur, Zheng, Buhong. "Can a Poverty Index Be
Switzerland:Harwood, 1994. Both Relative and Absolute?" Econo-
Ruggles,Patricia.Drawing the line. Washing- metrica, November 1994, 62(6), pp.
ton, DC: Urban Institute Press, 1990. 1453-58.

This content downloaded from 128.59.62.83 on Tue, 24 Dec 2013 13:24:08 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like