You are on page 1of 9

Comments

quences of which would be preferable in terms of


his most valued ends (1955, 314).1
Why the Rational Paradigm Persists: Why should planners make decisions rationally? Faludi
Tales from the Field (1973, 49) argues, &dquo;rational planning results in growth as a
product, and...the rational planning process may itself be
A decade ago, Linda Dalton (1986) posed a puzzle: viewed as a vehicle for the very process of growth.&dquo; Regard-
Planning academics and practitioners have both recognized less of whether many would share the faith of that assertion,
that planning decisions do not follow the rational model, it justified rationality as a means to a societal end: whatever
and yet they continue to espouse it. Why? the goals of a society, they would be more likely reached if
Dalton (1986) offered several explanations. In seeking members analyzed problems rationally.
professional status, planners follow American norms for The model and this justification have been criticized on
professionalism by emphasizing specialized scientific many grounds (e.g., Alexander 1992; Arrow 1958; Banfield
knowledge-in their case, expertise in applying rationality 1955; Etzioni 1968; Faludi 1973; Forester 1989; Lindblom
to urban problems (see Baum 1983; Freidson 1970; Larson 1959; Simon 1976). Empirically, it does not describe how
1977). Planning academics, because they work in and are planners, administrators, or politicians make decisions.
evaluated in bureaucratic organizations, are forced to Attention and information are limited, and interests
emphasize quantitative productivity if they want to keep constrain feasible alternatives. Often goals are fuzzy, and
their jobs. The first condition leads planners to espouse the criteria for evaluating consequences conflict with one
rational model even if they do not practice or believe in it. another. Forecasting is difficult. Finally, all these difficulties
The second, Dalton suggested, leads academics who argue are compounded when, as is usually the case, many actors

against the rational paradigm, in fact, to model it in take part in making decisions. In practice, people are as
practice. concerned about protecting their safety and interests as they
Yet these explanations are puzzling. While each argument are about following a &dquo;higher&dquo; rationality.

stands plausibly on its own, the second challenges the first. Critics have formulated alternative models that give a
If rationality is impossible in planning practice, how is it nod to certain realities while seeking to preserve the virtues
possible in planning academics’ practice? Are they such of the rational model. Disjointed incrementalism
different worlds? Or do planners practice rationally in ways (Braybrooke and Lindblom 1963), mixed scanning (Etzioni
they do not recognize? 1968), contingency planning (Alexander in press;
This article addresses these questions, first, by defining Christensen 1985), and critical pragmatism (Forester 1989)
the rational model and, then, by using stories from planning are familiar examples. In different ways, they acknowledge

education and practice to suggest why the model persists. that contexts matter, in both defining and limiting choices.
Still, they aim to promote decisions that are informed and
link action to goals. Forester (1989), for example, argues for
. RATIONAL PLANNING AND THE RATIONAL PLANNER
progressive political aims, but he justifies his model as
Banfield’s (1955, 314) articulation of the principles of Faludi did, with the view that planning processes lead
rational decision-making offers a succinct summary of the toward desired societal ends.
rational planning model: Why should a method of making decisions affect a
society in certain ways? Overtly, the connection is sociologi-
1. the decision-maker considers all of the alterna- cal, involving intervention in the operations of social
tives (courses of action) open to him...; institutions. These planning approaches make it possible to
2. he identifies and evaluates all of the conse- identify courses of action likely to produce chosen societal
quences which would follow from the adoption of ends.
each alternative...; and Mannheim (1940) conceived the connection psychologi-
3. he selects that alternative the probable conse- cally. Facing fascism, he believed industrialism had severed

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015


128

social ties and given rise to a mass society in which individu- the irrational forces of life, among them politics
als were no longer constrained from acting irrationally. and religion, with only the instruments of reason:
Planning was for him &dquo;the rational mastery of the irrational&dquo; the passions had to be controlled. It is interesting
(ibid., 265). He sought a society where behavior was to note how, in their less observed moments,
controlled in ways that allowed individual intellectual and aggressive rationalists often express a quite
emotional expression but preserved freedom and democracy. irrational fear of what they are evidently unable to
His society would be governed by the &dquo;substantial control (ibid., 100).
rationality [of] intelligent insight into the inter-relations of
events in a given situation,&dquo; but he faced the challenge of Consistently, &dquo;Weber argued passionately for an intellectual
the &dquo;substantially irrational&dquo;: &dquo;everything else which either is asceticism in which factual statements would be held rigidly
false or not an act of thought at all (as for example drives, apart from statements of value&dquo; (ibid., 99). This method-
impulses, wishes, and feelings, both conscious and uncon- ological commitment split science and politics and led, as
scious)&dquo; (ibid., 53). The &dquo;irrational,&dquo; he wrote, Friedmann argues, to the formulation of the rational
decision model.
is not always harmful but...on the contrary, it is In other words, the rational model has two references.
among the most valuable powers in man’s posses- One is a process where information is collected and analyzed
sion when it acts as a driving force towards rational in certain ways. The other is a practitioner (or member of
and objective ends or when it creates cultural society) who can, and wants to, collect and analyze informa-
values through sublimation, or when, as pure elan, tion only in those ways. Most simply, such a planner,
itheightens the joy of living without breaking up following a rigid logic, would analyze issues intellectually,
the social order by lack of planning (ibid., 62-63). disinterestedly, and unemotionally. Intuition is reckless,
because it leads to undisciplined mental leaps. Emotions
Ideally, society would begin with &dquo;self-rationalization,&dquo; &dquo;the inappropriately contaminate the reasoning process because
individual’s systematic control of his impulses&dquo; (ibid., 55). they attach individuals to others and create loyalties that
Practically, social order would depend on supporting self- pull away from rational analysis. Free of emotions, one can
rationalization, as well as compensating for its absence, observe and judge the world without being affected by
through societal controls. people in it. As a result, one is especially likely to discover an
Mannheim held out different social aims from some unambiguously optimal solution for a well-defined problem.
other advocates of rationality, but he made explicit an Some revisions of the rational planning model both
assumption others held tacitly: rational decision-making recognize political interests and espouse advocacy. However,
would change society by requiring individual members to the revisions share the model’s premise about feelings: they
act in rational ways. &dquo;The rational society,&dquo; Etzioni (1968, confuse professional judgment, and they should (and can)
255) observed, &dquo;is then viewed as the society that produces a be ignored or suppressed. The following stories show how
relatively high proportion of detached men, and its family practitioners and students, even if they might criticize the
and educational systems are studied to establish the ways in rational analytic model, adhere to the rational practitioner
which this is achieved.&dquo; He went on to note, &dquo;Modern model, with this premise, for psychological reasons.
structures, are said to provide a segregated unit for each
sector of social activities [based on] the conception that the
more a society is differentiated the more it is rational...&dquo;
. SOME STORIES OF RATIONALITY
(1968, 256).
Friedmann (1987), tracing what might be called the The Clockwork and the Snakepit
psychological history of rationality in planning, links Howard Schwartz (1990) tells a story about teaching
Mannheim with Weber and emphasizes that both saw organizational behavior in a business school. Once he asked
rationality as oppositional, in tension with irrational forces his students to picture the organization they knew best.
to be controlled by regulation or, better yet, repression. Of Then he described two types of organizations. He calls the
Weber he writes, first the clockwork

The principle of rationality, then, is closely related In it, the organization is like a clock; everybody
to the notion of objectivity in scientific work. For knows what the organization is all about and is
Weber, science was a means for mastering the concerned solely with carrying out its mission;
irrational, and the irrational, to which he felt people are basically happy at their work; the level
himself irresistibly drawn, could be contained of anxiety is low; people interact with each other in
within its own sphere only through the most severe frictionless, mutually supportive cooperation; and
of personal struggles. He was determined to grasp if there are any managerial problems at all, these

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015


129

are basically technical problems, easily solved by past waves of immigration to American cities, where
someone who has the proper skills and knows the newcomers consistently chose to assimilate and problems of

correct techniques of management (ibid., 7). ethnic differences evaporated.


Members of the first panel, however, told different
The second, opposite, organization is the snakepit. stories, focused on race-black-white relations particularly.
A white woman who works with community groups on
Here, everything is always falling apart, and education issues explained that, no matter how clear
common interests in children seem before discussions begin,
people’s main activity is to see that it doesn’t fall
on them; nobody really knows what is going on, people must first talk about and try to work through race-
though everyone cares about what is going on related concerns. They need to air grievances, express anger,
because there is danger in not knowing; anxiety and evaluate guilt before they can agree they care about
and stress are constant companions; and people children and talk about improving education.
take little pleasure in dealing with each other, The second panelist, an African-American man, began by
doing so primarily to use others for their own saying that people differ in a lot of ways, that race is only
one difference of many. However, he and the third panelist
purposes or because they cannot avoid being so
used themselves. Managerial problems here are (another African-American man) went on to describe
experienced as intractable, and managers feel that painful indignities they had suffered simply trying to do
they have done well if they are able to make it their jobs.
through the day (ibid., 8). At comment time, I observed that the optimistic account
of European ethnics’ assimilation into America contrasted
Nearly all his students said the organization they knew with the panelists’ accounts of race. Although people differ
best resembled the snakepit-but they wanted him to say in many ways, the panelists seemed to say they found race to
nothing further about it and devote the semester, instead, to be the most important difference, a persistent difference,
explaining how to manage a clockwork. Schwartz’ convinc- and a difference that often led to problems. They sounded
ing explanation is that the reality these students knew was pessimistic, I said. However, all protested in response that,
too frightening to think about, and they preferred the while race was a problem, they struggled to work with it and
fantasy that they could replace it with a rational clockwork despite it, and they were hopeful about addressing issues in
they could control. their fields of housing, transportation, and education.
These students (who managed or expected to manage As I thought about what they said, and as I listened to
organizations) wanted to talk about a view of human the second panel, I noticed how messy their presentations
were. They weren’t
behavior that portrayed it as rational in the following rambling or thoughtless-quite the
respects: people could be assumed to act dispassionately, contrary. These planners, in describing their practice,
disinterestedly, atomistically, and, as a result, predictably. acknowledged that racial differences, among others,
They liked the behavioral assumptions that could make complicated their work, but they did not see the world in
Weber’s (1967) ideal-typical bureaucracy a reality. Manag- clearly delineated shapes of black and white. Sometimes race
ing such an organization would be easy because it would not mattered in one way, sometimes in another, sometimes it
require serious involvement with workers: staff would follow did not matter much at all. Even when they were offended
written rules and rational protocols. What motivates this by something they encountered, they tried to understand
rational organizational ideal, which most students agreed why people acted as they did and to find ways of working
they had never seen, is a wish to command and control with them, to serve what they insisted on seeing as shared
without coming into contact with a messy, dangerous, interests.
debilitating reality. Students who wanted to escape a world The stories revealed practitioners who, unlike the
where their relationships made them feel bad imagined a management students, accepted the world of interests,
world where they had no relationships at all. relationships, and feelings and struggled in the middle of it
all to design workable programs. In doing so, they presented
A Colloquium on Diversity contrasts to two other groups and shed light on them. One

Two years ago, my program sponsored a colloquium on is academics who write unambiguous portrayals of race,
diversity in planning. The panelists, who presented a class, and gender. In those treatments, the meanings of these
contrast to Schwartz’ students, illustrated an alternative differences are clear and uniform, and oppression is
approach to the snakepit and shed light on attractions to the straightforward, even where some may not feel like victims.
clockwork. Those treatments of race, class, and gender can be
Panelists were asked to talk about their experiences in considered rational in that they deal with these attributes as
working with communities that were different from them. abstractions. Neat theoretical accounts rarely refer to specific
The introductory speaker, an academic, gave an account of persons who are male or female, grew up in a particular

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015


130

family, participate in a certain culture, and work in a An


specific job.2To be sure, any description abstracts from Internship Seminar
reality, and theoretical formulations are meant to abstract The diversity colloquium called to mind experiences of a
considerably. However, much of this work is so abstract, it few years ago. When conducting a seminar for students in
is difficult to locate real persons in theoretical generaliza- internships, I was surprised to hear many rail against politics
tions. in terms that could have come from any 1950’s planners.
In this respect, these models of society resemble the Citizen involvement messed up planning because citizens
rational clockwork organizational model. Not only are could not see things rationally and took up too much time
people linked to each other in only the most abstract ways, with irrelevant concerns. And elected officials kept injecting
but the observer is so detached from them that highly interests into what should be rational decisions.
abstract generalizations seem to suffice for accurate ac- I was surprised, because I had assumed that student
counts. These formulations lack the messy detail of the thinking had moved along with what many planning
world the presenters portrayed, the detail that comes from academics had come to say: politics, whether or not one
direct encounter. It is unclear whether these theoretical enjoys it, is part of democracy and inevitably enters into
models could guide the presenters’ practice. planning. Planners must accept this reality and try to act
One explanation for such neat abstraction would parallel effectively in the political context. I shared my reactions
interest in the clockwork: it is a defense against unruly with other faculty members, and one outgrowth of intermit-
reality. Judging whether particular authors, in fact, theorize tent discussions was to require students to take a planning
with this motivation would depend on knowing them well. theory and history course that, among other things, more
At the same time, there is a possibly simpler explanation for directly appraises politics. Still, the connection between a
the rational purity of some academic theorizing: that is what planning theory course and students’ practice is uncertain.
academics are expected to do. Their practice does not Strikingly, many students in a later seminar spoke as their
involve land uses or housing conditions, but the formulation predecessors.
and communication of ideas. The analogue to a comprehen- In the seminar, I ask students to describe episodes from
sive zoning ordinance in the university is a theoretical their placements. I try to help students discover that
framework in which all ideas are distinct and in their place. mundane events are significant, can be talked about, and are
Interestingly, a Chinese-American woman panelist at the worth analyzing. I call attention to what events reveal about
colloquium passionately recounted how land use planners relationships with coworkers and supervisors, authority,
destroyed San Diego’s Chinatown by rezoning the area to responsibility, organizational decision-making, and reactions
single use, making it impossible for Chinese families to live to these things. I do that, I explain, because I think reflec-

and work in the same building. These planners, the second tion on issues like these enables students tounderstand
group that contrasted with the panelists, could not compre- more deeply what they are doing and how their actions
hend diversity-either that Chinese families lived differently contribute to success or difficulties.
than the planners did or that different land uses could Students in this later seminar turned aside most of my
coexist without danger. invitations to talk about what they were doing. Some said
Two complementary rational assumptions encouraged their work would only bore the group-these explanations
that rezoning. First, planners believed they could (intellectu- warned others not to bore the group by talking about their
ally) analyze and decide on land use without becoming own activities. Several explained they had worked before

(emotionally) involved with the Chinese community- and did not need to talk about what they were doing; they
whatever they might learn about the community culture knew what to do.
should have no bearing on zoning recommendations. At the fourth weekly session, one student had to leave
Second, they accepted &dquo;the conception that the more a early to attend an agency meeting. I asked what her role at
society is differentiated the more it is rational&dquo; (Etzioni the meeting was. She would be sitting in the corner, she
1968, 256). Optimally, a zoning ordinance would tidily said; she was &dquo;just a little peon.&dquo; I picked up that phrase, to
see if it might lead students to discuss their positions in their
segregate residential and commercial land uses.
When academics distill formal theories so they are departments, their perceptions of authority in the hierar-
perfectly consistent, often they do what the land use chies, and their reactions to it. The students humored my
planners did. They separate themselves from the messiness efforts, but no one got seriously involved in the discussion.
of everyday life and risk misunderstanding it. This is a way Later on, students cited that discussion as an example of
academics model the rational paradigm, regardless of the where I drew topics out too long, past the time when they
overt content of their ideas. It adds to what Dalton (1986) had said what they had to say.
described as the institutional incentives of universities. And When I asked students to evaluate the seminar at the end,
it encourages students, who will become planners, to expect many said they did not think it could be useful to talk about
to see the world unambiguously. events at work. Many also said they wished the discussion

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015


131

had been more theoretical, though they agreed about neither professional judgments and political pressures. Agency
what they meant by theoretical or which issues they had in higher-ups, elected officials, and community leaders tried to
mind. As one positive example, several cited a session when influence analyses and decisions. One student called a
students debated the merits of historic preservation. situation criminal negligence. Another mentioned a
Other comments more specifically disagreed with the conversation in which a senior coworker privately said he
approach of talking from experience about roles and disagreed with agency policy but feared saying so in
organizational settings. A couple of students rejected what meetings. Another said the walls at his office had a number
they called my interest in politics as irrelevant to their work. of cartoons of people with zippers over their mouths.
One or two reacted strongly to my attention to interper- &dquo;Maybe,&dquo; one student suggested, &dquo;only people without
sonal relations. These students were not concerned about power can be idealistic.&dquo;
them. And, if students were supposed to learn about Some of these comments are the reactions of beginning

interpersonal relations, one declared, there should be a workers who are new to their organizations. Much is
specific course on them, with a textbook. One student said strange, and they have little power to affect anything. And
that I should not have asked them about their feelings; it yet they report on their seniors’ reactions, as well. The
made them uncomfortable. students’ ethical and intellectual impulses are often right.
There is no simple interpretation for all this. Indeed, the These are discouraging situations, certainly some frightening
students made it clear that I did not seem as sensitive or ones. They call into question one’s choice of profession.

sympathetic a listener as I thought I was. However, among It would be safer to avoid thinking about feelings about
the things apparent here is a wish that planning follow a such situations, to think more theoretically about them, and
rational model. to cherish the wish that getting work done could come

Explicitly, some students disdained a concern for either down to conscientious analysis.
interpersonal relations or the relations of politics. A A Class on the Politics of Planning
textbook encounter with the subject of interpersonal
relations would be abstract and safe, neither messy nor A few weeks after the diversity seminar, I was surprised to
personal. The student who rejected my inquiries about consider how typical academic practices may have taught
feelings apparently distinguished them from thoughts. these students to think and react as they did. I was teaching
Thoughts can be considered abstract, autonomous, not a class on the politics of planning, using John Forester’s

implicated in emotion. A thought stands by itself, for others (1989) Planning in the Face of Power. I heard myself
to look at and next to which they might put their own speaking increasingly apologetically of the classical rational
thoughts. In contrast, feelings are relational; they connect model as a context for the book. I wondered out loud
one person to another, and they arise from such connec- whether this model meant much to my students. I explained
tions. To ask students about their feelings is to insist that why I mentioned it. First, it was part of the intellectual
they recognize how they are attached to others. Theoretical history of planning, including my own education, and it was
concerns, as students specifically defined them, would have a reference point for subsequent analysis of planners’

nothing to do with what they personally did in the presence actions. Second, I told my students, if I were still using
of, with, or against others. Many would like planning to be Altshuler’s (1965) case studies of Minneapolis and St. Paul,
largely an independent cognitive act. they could have seen planners who, indeed, believed they
Some explanations for their preference would focus on were enacting the classical model. Third, I suggested they

what they are taught. Either we do not teach them as well as might work with planners who adhered to the rational
we should and perhaps can, or else some of us effectively model.
teach them to act as we do. Another explanation would I turned back to Forester’s (1989) framework in which he
focus on students’ personalities. Perhaps they chose plan- characterizes four conditions of boundedness that contrast
ning because their image of it, which corresponded to what with the classical rational model. Significantly, my students
we or their coworkers model, suited them both intellectually had trouble with the concept of boundedness. I put it into
and emotionally (see Baum 1983, 1986). intellectual context, summarizing March and Simon (1958;
Still another explanation, consistent with Schwartz’ story, March 1982).
would look at the conditions of their practice. When I reviewed Forester’s four conditions of boundedness.
students did talk about their jobs, they often described the When only cognitive limits bound the possibilities of
work as hazardous-like the snakepit. In the first session, a planning or acting rationally (Bounded I), a single, though
student railed against hostile community members: they fallible, actor works in a single room, but one open to the
make so much trouble, they could cost a planner his or her environment, working on an ambiguous problem with
job. Another student described a commissioner who abused imperfect information in a limited time. The practical
his authority to intimidate applicants at hearings. Several strategy is satisficing. When social differentiation enters
students told recurrent stories of conflicts between their (Bounded II), the situation is further bounded: there are

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015


132

several actors and several rooms, though connected by health, education without the economy, and so forth.
phones; problems are subject to interpretation; information Planning faculty members differ in their academic
varies in quality, accessibility, and location; and actors have practices. Some work with public agencies or community
different amounts of time. Networking is an important groups. Still, much of what they do as salaried professionals
strategy. tacitly teaches the rational view that it is possible to under-
In a pluralistic world (Bounded III), actors are part of stand and make decisions about the social world without
competing interest groups, operating in many rooms with direct involvement.
multiple definitions of problems, manipulating information, This view fosters the assumption that one can control the
and treating time as a source of power. Practical strategies world from a distance-recall the Minneapolis and St. Paul
are negotiating, mediating, and acting incrementally. When planners. We and our students might collude in maintain-
great inequalities in power create structural distortions in ing this illusion because it offers reassurance that one can
society (Bounded IV), actors differ in power, work in rooms plan without being vulnerable to the dangers of the world,
of different value, define problems ideologically, deliberately including others’ power. We might hold onto this belief, as
misinform others, and have unequal control over time. The well, because it allows us to avoid responsibility for social
practical strategy for the less powerful is to organize. events. These are premises of the clockwork.

In that context, I turned to our curriculum. It offered


students a great deal of advice about how to act in Bounded
I situations and some for Bounded II. We said little to our . THE RATIONAL PARADIGM AS A PSYCHOLOGICAL
ASSUMPTION
students about how to act as planners when they worked in
situations of many competing actors. We occasionally told
our students that negotiating, lobbying, organizing, working Interpreting the Stories
with groups, and the like were important, but we did not As a guide for collecting and analyzing information, the
teach these skills. We seemed tacitly to be teaching our rational model has virtues. Generally interpreted, it encour-
students that planning is similar to doing research. ages planners to collect a great deal of information to
Planning programs vary. Some give careful attention to understand an issue. It tells them to set goals in terms of
skills for Bounded III and even Bounded IV situations. But identified problems. It calls on planners to justify recom-
in many programs, faculty members who do mainly mendations in terms of the ends they are expected to serve
research, and who have chosen to teach rather than practice and to choose among alternatives on the basis of explicit
planning, are the tacit models of practice given students. criteria.
They have selected academic life for various reasons. One is Problems with the rational model arise from accompany-
pleasure in manipulating ideas. Another is a taste for ing assumptions concerning the practitioner that are part of
working autonomously. Still another, consistent with these, the model’s cultural
origins and history. The model
is wanting to avoid involvement in the kinds of messy encourages planners to think of themselves as living in a
situations planning practice includes. world of information without human beings, where the task
In the end, most academics model a practice that, is to organize information logically, but not to organize
enacted in planning, would incorporate several of the people (who have information, ideas, and interests) politi-
classical rational assumptions. As researchers, particularly cally. A model rational planner who follows rational
when using secondary and quantitative data, they offer guidelines for analyzing problems will see situations
understandings of the world without much direct contact abstractly, narrowly, and superficially and will likely fail to
with it. To say this is not to denigrate the value of such understand what social conditions mean to the people who
research. However, simply to teach and illustrate research live them. As a result, the planner may recommend inter-
methods without showing how to use research in planning ventions that do not fit these conditions and harm people
practice suggests that information utilization is mysterious, who might be helped. Urban renewal is the prototypical
spontaneous, magical, or someone else’s concern. By and example.
large, academics imply that intellectual analysis, without Hence, one might argue, planning teachers should
emotionally implicated social interaction, suffices for admonish students to take the virtues of the analytic model
influence (see Baum in press). without the constraints of the practitioner model. Such a
In addition, in working independently-one person view assumes rationality is simply a set of abstract ideas or
concerned with housing, another with economic develop- intellectual premises that people can freely choose to hold or
ment, another with urban design, and so forth-academics leave aside. However, talk of a rational paradigm reflects our
model the sectoral segregation and social differentiation that learning from Kuhn (1962) that we participate in cultures
Etzioni (1968) identifies with rationality. Following the that lead us to take a particular way of thinking as the
practice of academic specialization, faculty suggest that one normal approach to understanding and acting. We do so
can understand the environment without thinking about not only because the paradigm makes sense of the matters

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015


133

about which we are concerned, but also because following fantasy, it also takes revenge on political actors by eliminat-
the paradigm gives us meaningful relations with others who ing them.
do so.
Dalton (1986) described how social institutions reflect Research on Planners
and reinforce culturally normal rational principles. Planners Research on planning practitioners supports this interpre-
claim to act rationally even if they do not believe they do, tation. Hoch’s (1988) survey of American planners found
because the prevailing model of a professional emphasizes that many considered politics dangerous. Fifty-six percent
disinterested scientific knowledge. Planning academics focus reported a seriously threatening political conflict during
on producing many publications and, perhaps incidentally, their career, with 40% of conflicts pitting politics against
give their students little personal attention, because bureau- planning, 17% involving political loyalty, 14% raising
cratic university administrators evaluate subordinates ethical disputes, and 14% involving political &dquo;squeezes.&dquo;
quantitatively. Eighty-three percent considered their antagonist stronger
Both examples express the common principles that actors than they were.
should have no personal involvement with those around Sixty percent said they tried to prevent conflict, but only
them. A good planner is one who has no personal interests a third were successful. When conflict broke out, planners

and who follows strict scientific norms whenever interven- believed they won only 37% of the time, with their antago-
ing in the social world. A good university administrator does nists winning 40% of the time. Significantly, when planners
not allow feelings about or general impressions of faculty won, they credited their professional work, but when they
members to affect judgments about tenure or promotion lost, they felt no responsibility and, instead, blamed
and, either by intention or just as a result of demanding so opponents for political strategizing. In other words, they
much of faculty members, discourages them from getting to wanted to succeed as rational practitioners, and they saw
know their students personally. politics as a dangerous violation of the rational model.
In Dalton’s (1986) analysis these are unfortunate Vasu (1979), also surveying a national sample, found
examples of how planners and academics are forced to act many planners who, after recognizing the social and political
inauthentically. If only they were free, practitioners would realities of practice, chose technical rational roles. On the
make intuitive, subjective, personal judgments with a clear one hand, 78% saw the
planning process as value oriented,
conscience and publicly confess these deeds. Academics rather than technical. As the 88% who said no plan is
would spend more time with their students and in their neutral emphasized, planning requires judging among
work would embrace the messiness of society and planning competing interests. And 88% argued that public planning
practice. should be concerned with physical, economic, and social
The stories I have recounted shadow something more planning-in contrast with the segregated, differentiated
complicated. Not only do institutions incorporate social rational ideal.
pressures to follow the rational model, but many people Yet at the same time 53%, many of them among the
choose to follow it for psychological reasons unrelated to its large majorities in the first groups, asserted that comprehen-
ostensive focus on solving substantive problems. They try to sive rational planning by government is possible; that,
enact it because its tacit model of social relations-rather, despite plural values and interests, planners can identify
nonrelations-offers safety from risky reality. courses of action which most or all support. And 48%

The diversity colloquium participants are practitioners argued that planners should take technical roles defined by
who accept the messiness of the world where they work. In neutral judgment of the public interest and apolitical
contrast, the business school students openly retreat from a professionalism-in short, the rational model.3 Where
world that is frightening, and the planning students appear values are at stake, where neutrality is impossible, and where
to do the same. A psychological reading of these stories conflict is likely, it seems safer to claim to be a rational
would suggest that the culturally normal rational paradigm technician.
offers a ready, unconscious defense against the anxieties this Schon (1983) found a planner working with a zoning
messiness arouses. board of appeals taking just this approach. In moving
If community groups are hostile, if bosses put agency between board and developers, he tried to find designs that
politics above rigorous analysis, if coworkers duplicitously satisfied both parties, along with his own standards.
do not share information, taking the rational view that However, to maximize his autonomy and control, he told
planning is simply abstract analysis eliminates these each that he was only interpreting rules, that he had no
concerns and the feelings they evoke. This approach helps to discretion to negotiate. Engaged in covert politics, he
reconcile one’s responsibilities with one’s limited authority. presented himself as a technician. He was practicing what
In fantasy, it extricates a planner from an uncontrollable, Argyris and Schon (1974; Argyris 1982) call a Model I
perhaps upsetting, situation. It may help to avoid getting theory-in-use, that emphasizes unilaterally setting and
angry, as well as making new problems by acting angrily. In pursuing goals, conceptualizing situations in terms of

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015


134

winning and losing, discouraging negative feelings, and more securely to struggle with the messiness of societal
being rational (objective, intellectual, and unemotional). problems?
Argyris and Schon (1974) have found Model I among Recently, most of our faculty became involved in research
many planners. They consider it defensive in the ordinary and planning with local communities, and students work
political sense this planner had in mind. In addition, they with Thus part of the time we are in the messy world of
us.

find people choose it for psychological reasons-to defend practice, and students see and interact with us in new ways.
themselves against seeming wrong, imperfect, or uncertain. We have not changed our formal curriculum, though this
Even though this rational way of acting succeeds fairly as a new practice might encourage us to do so. What we are

psychological defense, it defeats efforts to plan. The planner doing is new for us and not unique, but, as in other
with the zoning board so convinced a developer not to try to programs that do similarly, it holds out one possible answer
negotiate with a technician, the planner failed to discover a to the question. When faculty members and students
engage
compromise that would have satisfied the developer and in planning, if they can examine what they do, both may
himself, and the developer withdrew his proposal. Both lost. learn more about mastering the difficulties of practice.
By keeping planners from the social and political
conditions affecting decisions, the rational practitioner Howell S. Baum
model provides psychological reassurance, but at the risk of
ineffectiveness. Howell S. Baum as Professor of Urban Studies and Planmng at Unwerstty of
Maryland, College Park, Maryland 20742 USA.
N CONCLUSION
. NOTES
The speakers on diversity illustrate an alternative to the
1. Alexander (1992), Etzioni (1968), Faludi (1973), and Friedmann
rational model of planning. While they reason carefully
(1987) offer similar summaries.
about issues, they do not shy away from either messy 2. Two rich exceptions are Hoch (1995) and Rubin (1994).
problems or messy situations. They trust their intuition. 3. Other research methods have led to different findings. Baum (1983)
found 60% of a sample of Maryland planners to describe their
They recognize others’ feelings and their own-both that planning as primarily an intellectual process. Howe and Kaufman
they influence thinking and action and that they can express (1979), asking planners about their beliefs, found 27% of a national
reasonable responses to situations. They try to work sample to be technicians and 51% hybrids, combining technical and
collaboratively even when others resist, but they are also political role conceptions. It is less fruitful to try to reconcile these
findings, because the methods vary, than it is to make sense of
willing to organize against those who oppose them. differences between what the same planners told Vasu (1979) they
They are unusual,4 but not unique. They are not always believed in general but wanted for themselves in particular. See
Baum (1986, 1988) for analysis of the empirical literature.
successful, and anyone might disagree with some of their 4. It is impossible to make firm generalizations about how common
decisions. But they embrace the social and political world in such behavior is, but evidence that these practitioners are atypical
the rational spirit of trying to understand carefully, and they comes from Krumholz and Forester’s (1990) observations on
succeed often enough. They are examples Dalton would practitioners and Baum’s (1986) review of research on planners.

approve. And yet-this was her puzzle-why do so many


others follow the rational paradigm? . REFERENCES
We can suggest one more answer to Dalton’s (1986)
Alexander, . Second edition. Langhorne,
E. R. 1992. Approaches to Planning
question about &dquo;the persistence of the rational paradigm&dquo; by Pennsylvania: Gordon and Breach.
clarifying the question. Planners continue to endorse at least Alexander, E. R. In press. After rationality: Towards a contingency theory
of planning. In Explorations in Planning Theory, eds. S. J. Mandelbaum,
the spirit of the rational analytic model, not only because it
L. Mazza, and R. W. Burchell. New Brunswick, New Jersey: Center for
supports claims of professional status, but also because it Urban Policy Research.
emphasizes the fundamental principle of guiding action by Altshuler, A. A. 1965. The City Planning Process. Ithaca, New York: Cornell
knowledge. There is no puzzle here. University Press.
Argyris, C. 1982. Reasoning, Learning, .
and Action San Francisco: Jossey-
Many planners, further, try to convince themselves they Bass.
strictly follow the letter of the rational analytic model by Argyris, C., and Schon, D. A. 1974. Theory in Practice: Increasing
being model rational practitioners. Dalton (1986) asks why . San Francisco, California: Jossey-Bass.
Professional Effectiveness
Arrow, K. 1958. Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: Wiley.
planners not only espouse, but also embrace, a discredited Banfield, E. C. 1955. Note on conceptual scheme. In Politics, Planning,
model of analysis and decision making. Some, she explains, and the Public Interest, eds. M. Meyerson and E. C. Banfield. New
do so under institutional duress. But others-this is the York: Free Press.
Baum, H. S. 1983. Planners and Public Expectations
. Cambridge,
import of the stories, consistent with research on planners- Massachusetts: Schenkman.
do so because of the psychological benefits of being-really, Baum, H. S. 1986. Politics in planners’ practice. In Strategic Approaches to
trying to be-a model rational practitioner. Planning Practice, ed. B. Checkoway. Lexington, Massachusetts:
That rational model offers psychological safety. Hence we Lexington Books.
Baum, H. S. 1988. The problems of governance and the professions of
should recast Dalton’s question: how can we enable planners planners. In Two Centuries of American Planning
, ed. D. Schaffer.

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015


135
London: Mansell Publishing Company, and Baltimore, Maryland:
Johns Hopkins University Press.
Baum, H. S. In press. Practicing planning theory in a political world. In
Towards Supranational Spatial
a
Explorations Planning Theory, eds. S. J. Mandelbaum, L. Mazza, and
in
R. W. Burchell. New Brunswick, New Jersey: Center for Urban Policy
Research.
Development Perspective:
Braybrooke, D., and C. E. Lindblom. 1963. A Strategy .
Glencoe, Illinois: Free Press.
of Decision Experience in Europe
Christensen, K. S. 1985. Coping with uncertainty in planning. Journal of
the American Planning Association 51:63-73. TheEuropean Union (EU) is increasingly shaping spatial
Dalton, L. C. 1986. Why the rational paradigm persists—the resistance of policy its member states by developing and implement-
in
professional education and practice to alternative forms of planning. ing a substantial body of legislation and policy with spatial
Journal of Planning Education and Research 5:147-153.
Etzioni, A. 1968. The Active Society
. New York: Free Press. objectives or effects (Williams 1993). The EU-a quasi-
Faludi, A. 1973. Planning Theory. Oxford: Pergamon. federal association of fifteen independent nations-is a
Forester, J. 1989. Planning in the Face of Power. Berkeley: University of
California Press. unique institution capable of initiating legislation that is
Freidson, E. 1970. Profession of Medicine New York: Dodd and Mead. binding on all its citizens and member states. This
Friedmann, J. 1987. Planning in the Public Domain
. Princeton: Princeton supranational organization (known from 1957 as the
University Press. European Economic Community, from 1967 as the
Hoch, C. 1988. Conflict at large: a national survey of planners and political
conflict. Journal of Planning Education and Research 8:25-34. European Community, and from 1993 as the European
Hoch, C. 1995. What Planners Do. Chicago, Illinois: Planners Press. Union) has a population of over 363 million and a land area
Howe, E., and J. L. Kaufman. 1979. The ethics of contemporary American of over 3.2 million square kilometers.2 The EU has about
planners. Journal of the American Planning Association 47(3):266-278. half as many people as the U.S. living in just over a third of
Krumholz, N., and J. Forester. 1990. Making Equity Planning Work.
Philadelphia, Pennsylvania: Temple University Press. the space. Needless to say the European territory is also
Kuhn, T. S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions
. Chicago, Illinois:
University of Chicago Press.
exceptional in its physical and cultural complexity. It follows
Larson, M. S. 1977. The Rise .
that the EU faces a large number of challenges relating to
of Professionalism Berkeley: University of
California Press. the spatial development of its territory and that many of
Lindblom, C. E. 1959. The science of muddling through. Public these cut across national boundaries. Examples of common
Administration Review 19:78-88.
concerns among the European nations include meeting the
Mannheim, K. 1940. Man and Society in an Age . of Reconstruction New
York: Harcourt, Brace & World. challenge of global economic competition while promoting
March, J. 1982. Theories of choice and making decisions. Society 20:29- sustainable patterns of growth and protecting the built and
39.
March, J., and H. A. Simon. 1958. Organizations natural heritage; ameliorating social problems and unem-
. New York: John Wiley
and Sons. ployment which have a clear spatial dimension, especially in
Rubin, L. B. 1994. Families on the Faultline
. New York: Harper Collins. the polarization of areas of opportunity across regions and in
Schön, D. A. 1983. The Reflective Practitioner
. New York: Basic Books.
Schwartz, H. S. 1990. Narcissistic Process and Corporate Decay. New York: the older cities; and revitalizing and diversifying the
New York University Press. economy of rural areas in decline.
Simon, H. A. 1976. Administrative Behavior
. Third Edition. New York: The spatial impacts of actions to meet the primary
Free Press.
Vasu, M. 1979. Politics and Planning
. Chapel Hill: University of North objectives of the EU-to establish and maintain a common
Carolina Press. market; to promote harmonious and balanced economic
Weber, M. 1967. From Max Weber, ed. and trans. H. H. Gerth and C. W.
Mills. New York: Oxford University Press. growth; and to allow the free movements of goods, people,
services and capital-were rarely given due attention until
the second half of the 1980s. Since then the EU has adopted
the explicit objective to reduce regional disparities, and over
the last 10 years, understanding of the spatial dimension of
economic and political change in Europe has steadily
increased.
Each country in the EU has responded to the problems of
spatial development in its own way, creating a bewildering
variety of planning procedures, policies, and instruments
across different countries and even regions. But increasingly,

the need for supranational coordination of these actions is


being argued. This is particularly so for the European
Commission (the executive body of the EU), whose actions
are already having great influence, directly and indirectly, on

the planning and environmental protection policies of


member states, a process which will inevitably increase in
future years (Davies and Gosling 1994).

Downloaded from jpe.sagepub.com at University of Birmingham on March 20, 2015

You might also like