You are on page 1of 11

International Studies Quarterly (2018) 0, 1–11

Why Is There No Reactionary International Theory?


THEORY NOTE

JOSEPH MACKAY
Australian National University

AND

C H R I S T O P H E R D AV I D L A R O C H E
University of Toronto
Why is there no reactionary international theory? International relations has long drawn on a range of traditions in political
thought. However, no current, or even recent, major school of international-relations theory embraces reactionary doctrine.
This is more surprising than some might assume. Reaction was once common in the field and is now increasingly common in
world politics. In this note, we define reaction and show that no active and influential school of international-relations theory
falls within its ideological domain. Nonetheless, reactionary ideas once deeply shaped the field. We identify two distinct kinds
of reactionary international politics and illustrate them empirically. We argue that the current lack of reactionary international
relations undermines the field’s ability to make sense both of its own history and of reactionary practice. Finally, we offer some
preliminary thoughts about why reactionary ideas hold little sway in contemporary international-relations theory.

Why is there no reactionary international theory?1 Contem- movements that, reacting to globalism, defend putatively
porary international-relations scholarship draws on multiple “purer” racially or culturally homogenous societies and call
intellectual traditions: liberal, status-quo realist, radical, and for closed borders. We find it in the Islamist radicalism
critical, to name only a few. However, the discipline lacks an that those nativists condemn, which itself recalls an ideal-
explicitly reactionary school—one that rejects the present in ized Pax Islamica of more than a millennium ago. These
favor of the past. The systematic and sometimes radical nos- ideas shape world politics and share a common attitude
talgia of reactionary politics is almost entirely absent from toward historical change—yet current international-
the contemporary field. This absence is striking because re- relations theory provides little systematic insight into,
action itself has a long history in political thought and prac- or understanding of, them.
tice. Indeed, as recent historiography of the field implies, By reactionary, we mean a specific political attitude toward
reaction played an important part in academic international long-run historical change. The word is more commonly
relations at its inception.2 We call on scholars to re-examine used as a term of abuse than one of self-attribution—a pe-
reactionary politics—both in the discipline and in history jorative description for those who “unthinkingly” reject the
more broadly—and thereby better understand and address fruits of progress. In contrast, we find a potentially system-
these persistent and consequential phenomena. atic, influential, and important tradition, predicated on a
We write not as reactionaries ourselves but as concerned distinctive attitude toward history. Liberal progressives and
members of the discipline. We do not claim understanding radicals alike view change, explicitly or tacitly, as both pos-
reactionary world politics requires expressly reactionary in- sible and often desirable. Realists emphasize fundamental
ternational theory. Instead, we contend that the absence of continuities in politics and tend to discount the significance
reactionary theory has likely shaped the field’s inattention of apparent changes in world politics. In contrast, reac-
to political reaction as such. While current international tionaries neither embrace historical change nor discount its
theory may overlook political reaction, it is all around importance. Instead, they understand deep historical trans-
us in contemporary politics. We see it in Western nativist formations as both real and catastrophic. For reactionaries,
the world was once better: a past political order, now lost,
Joseph MacKay is a research fellow in the Department of International Rela- shows us retrospectively how things should be but no longer
tions, Australian National University. are. Fixated on this prelapsarian world, reaction is a doc-
Christopher David LaRoche is a doctoral candidate in the Department of Po- trine of political nostalgia. It imagines a past it hopes to
litical Science and a fellow at the Trudeau Centre for Peace, Conflict and Justice recreate.3
at the Munk School of Global Affairs, University of Toronto.
We offer an exploratory account of reactionary interna-
Authors’ Note: The authors would like to thank Kiran Banerjee, Scott Dodds,
Alena Drieschova, Michael Millerman, and David Polansky, who (along with con-
tional politics. We proceed in four sections. First, we define
sidered disagreements) offered a range of helpful comments. We also thank the political reaction. Second, we show its nearly complete ab-
anonymous reviewers and editors of International Studies Quarterly. sence from contemporary international-relations theory. We
1
We allude to Wight (1966), whose own political orientation we review below. also explore the field’s reactionary early history and find
2
That research challenges international-relations theory’s once-canonical ori- scattered and incomplete reaction in more recent scholar-
gin story as a battle between liberal progressives and realist critics, pointing to ship. Third, for context, we offer a brief history of Western
heterodox and sometimes problematic beginnings (Schmidt 2012; Guilhot 2013;
Vitalis 2015). While some scholars assess expressly conservative international
3
thought (Hall and Rengger 2005; Hall 2015), few treat reaction rigorously and On how theories or philosophies of history shape international relations, see
specifically as an analytical category. MacKay and LaRoche (2017).

MacKay, Joseph, and Christopher David LaRoche. (2018) Why Is There No Reactionary International Theory? International Studies Quarterly, doi: 10.1093/isq/sqx083
© The Author(s) (2018). Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the International Studies Association.
All rights reserved. For permissions, please e-mail: journals.permissions@oup.com

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018
2 Why Is There No Reactionary International Theory?

reactionary political thought. Fourth, we illustrate its impor- Theodore Kaczynski or Anders Breivik, imagine technolog-
tance in world politics, identifying two reactionary strate- ically or racially different pasts, with dubious historical ac-
gies in world politics—revisionism and restructuring—with curacy. Islamic radicals likewise are sometimes silent on
respective historical examples: Nazi Germany and the Con- the violence, slavery, and eventual corruption of the early
cert of Europe’s counter-revolutionary “Metternich system.” Caliphates. However, reactionaries may internationally em-
A conclusion rethinks reaction’s place in the field. phasize these features, or argue they are the acceptable costs
of an overall better society. In some instances, reactionar-
ies may simply mythologize the past. What matters is that
What is Political Reaction?
the putative status quo ante represents a condition of greater
We understand reaction as the claim that a past political moral-political wellbeing than the present.
order is preferable to the present. It is often accompa- Second, reactionaries imagine an event or process that
nied by attempts to restore that past order.4 Like liberal destroyed that order. Reactionaries understand “progres-
progressivism or Marxian radicalism, reaction focuses on sive” political change as destructive, whether in the form
the processes, particularly with respect to modernity, of his- of cataclysm or of gradual decay. The signal event for
torical transformation. Its distinguishing feature is a belief nineteenth-century reactionaries was the French Revolu-
in the fundamentally destructive character of reformist or tion, which they saw as catalyzed by the Enlightenment’s
progressive change. However, where progressives imagine a disenchantment of traditionally religious authority (Maistre
better world that does not yet exist, reactionaries refer to 1994, for example, 41–48). Late twentieth-century American
one they understand as already behind us.5 Reactionary pol- reactionaries often blamed societal instability on “social en-
itics have historically appealed to wide and diverse groups gineers” disrupting traditional ways of life (Buckley 1955).
and may be as, or more, convincing to audiences as these To treat the past as prelapsarian, reactionaries must identify
other traditions. As Lilla (2016, xiv) notes, “Hope can be the Fall that destroyed it.
disappointed. Nostalgia is irrefutable.”6 Third, reactionaries generally blame some actor or group
Reactionaries believe in a lost prior order that is consti- for that destructive change. Islamic radicals have often
tutive of the good life or conditions for human flourish- blamed European imperialism, and Islamic modernization
ing, recognize a specific event or process that destroyed it, attempts, for the nineteenth and twentieth century moral
and blame some actor, group, or event for that destructive and political nadir of the Islamic world (Euben 1999, 93–
change. Reactionary international theory, in turn, imagines 94). The Nazis blamed the Jews for the decadence, moral
a past in which either a given national political order (now disorder, international capitalism, and destruction of na-
lost) was secure within the larger world order, or the world tional culture they claimed to see in modern Europe. As
order itself was both different and preferable.7 This under- these examples suggest, this component may have some
standing constitutes an ideal type—an analytically simplified basis in fact or none at all. Nor need the disruption be
account that, while precisely describing few cases, nonethe- intentional. Reactionaries need not claim that Enlighten-
less captures core features held in common across most in- ment philosophers meant to destroy medieval European
stances.8 We now explore it in greater detail. civilization—disillusionment was merely a by-product of
First, reactionaries imagine a past preferable to the their intellectual flourishing.
present or expected future. They posit a long-run histor- We stress the ideal-typical character of the preceding de-
ical trajectory, over which change is linear and systemati- scription. Actual cases of reactionary thought and practice
cally knowable. Thus, religious radicals, nativists, and other will fit imperfectly; many combine elements with other ide-
kinds of reactionaries begin by describing an idealized past. ologies and even represent “borderline” cases. Degrees of
This serves as a baseline against which to judge the present reaction vary, both in the remoteness of the past recalled
and future. This history need not be complete—or even ac- and the means mobilized to recapture it. Whereas Metter-
curate. Catholic reactionaries may excoriate the Reforma- nich wanted only a restored prerevolutionary monarchical
tion as dogmatic, blaming it for later events such as the Europe, Hitler aimed at an imagined premodern utopia.
French Revolution, but also deemphasize Medieval Chris- What matters is not our ability to neatly and unproblemati-
tendom’s less attractive doctrinal practices, such as the In- cally categorize theorists, movements, and regimes. Instead,
quisition.9 Violent reactionaries in the west today, such as we trace reaction, by degrees, across cases and contexts.
Moreover, while we focus on conservative reactionaries,
4
We draw here on Lilla’s (2016, ix–xxi) recent concise theoretical work. So reaction is not coextensive with the right (Lilla 2016, xii).10
defined, reaction is distinct from such related concepts as conservatism, nos- The British Luddites recalled a past before machines re-
talgia, romanticism, populism, nationalism, and others. We thus adopt a more placed their labor (Randall 1986, 8–9). Some deep ecol-
specific definition than Robin (2011, 34), who uses “the words conservative, ogists today imagine restoring a closer, preindustrial link
reactionary, and counterrevolutionary interchangeably”—treating conservative
“philosophers, statesmen, slaveholders, scribblers, Catholics, fascists, evangelicals,
between humanity and nature (Devall and Sessions 1985).
businessmen, racists, and hacks” as belonging to the same core political experi- Contemporary opponents of modern medicine (e.g., vac-
ence: “a meditation on—and theoretical rendition of—the felt experience of hav- cine sceptics) sometimes idealize, tacitly or explicitly, a more
ing power, seeing it threatened, and trying to win it back” (Robin 2011, 4, see also “natural” human past reliant on folk remedies instead of
28). Such elite impulses may animate reaction as we define it, but need not. Nor, modern pharmacology (for example, Kata 2010, 171–14).
we argue below, need reaction be strictly rightwing. Eliding distinctions between Inversely, many conservatives have scant reactionary beliefs.
these terms makes for less precise and useful analysis.
5
Bauman (2017, 5, 8) terms this imagined past “retrotopia.”
Burke (2014) grounded his impassioned criticism of the
6
The word was coined in 1688, by a Swiss medical student, from the Greek French Revolution in a defense of gradual and local change,
nostos (return or homecoming) and algos (pain). It originally described a psychi- not of wholesale return to the past (see Welsh 1995). More
atric diagnosis: a malignant and destructive homesickness and, more broadly, a
10
“refusal to consider any but a world lost to the past as the habitable world” (Roth Our account nonetheless resonates with Mannheim’s (1936, 207) concep-
1991, 15). It is linked to longing for one’s homeland and thus nationalism. tion of a conservative “counter-utopia which serves as a means of self-orientation
7
Thus, for example, the “fascist internationalism” of the interwar period and defence” against progressive and revolutionary ideologies. For Mannheim,
(Steffek 2015, 3–4). conservatives do not resist reform first in principle. Instead, they do so in practice
8
On ideal-types in international relations, see Jackson (2011, 37, 142–46). and acquire ideological frameworks only in response to insurrection. We distin-
9
See, for example, Kuehnelt-Leddihn (1952, 179–87); More recently, Gregory guish reaction as a systematic ideational appeal to the past, as against the status
(2012) locates modern disillusionment in the Reformation. quo.
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415
by guest
on 19 April 2018
JOSEPH MACKAY AND C H R I S T O P H E R D AV I D L A R O C H E 3

recent free-market conservatives or right-libertarians need While many classical realists had reactionary sentiments,
not be explicitly nostalgic at all (Friedman 1962, 7–21).11 these did not amount to wholly reactionary theory. Morgen-
Finally, we focus on reaction primarily as a modern thau, Kennan, and Kissinger all expressed nostalgia for a
and Western phenomenon. Accelerated change linked to nineteenth-century diplomatic order that predated democ-
intellectual, political, and industrial modernity—perhaps ratized foreign policy.17 But Morgenthau, like Niebuhr, em-
first and most acutely experienced in the West—provide phasized unchanging, “perennial” political problems that
conditions in which reactionary thinking became com- impede progress and cannot be permanently solved.18
monplace. Non-European peoples often first experienced Kennan’s views on social hierarchy and race led him to si-
modernity as colonial domination. Responses to it were multaneously condemn South African apartheid and dis-
consequently different and varied widely across contexts.12 courage America from attempting to end it.19 Indeed, re-
In principle, some political reaction may have no connec- cent scholarship finds that many classical realists had criti-
tion with modernity—Confucius and Homer both recalled cal, liberal, or progressive elements, including Morgenthau,
golden ages prior to their own. Nor is all criticism of moder- Niebuhr, Carr, Wolfers, and Herz (Williams 2005a, 82–127;
nity reactionary. Those who link declining attention spans to Neacsu 2010; Scheuerman 2011; Levine 2012, 120–35).20
social media or question the uneven effects of globalization Raymond Aron’s defense of liberalism is well known.21
on traditional ways of life are not necessarily reactionary. Re- Kissinger has cautiously embraced elements of progressive
actionaries go beyond criticism, instead idealizing a past so- liberal internationalism over time.22 Whatever their differ-
cial order and endorsing it over the present. Criticism aims ences, classical and neorealists alike do not view historical
to understand modernity; reaction sets out to replace it.13 transformation as destructive. Instead, they view it as im-
Nonetheless, modernity presents distinctive conditions of possible or misguided, at least on liberal terms.23 So under-
persistent transformation that have permitted antimodern stood, realist values are not strictly reactionary.
nostalgia to proliferate (Lilla 2016, xiv).14 The English School is sometimes identified as conserva-
tive (Buzan 2014, 89 passim) and thus might be thought
of as reactionary. Most English School conservatism is ei-
Reactionary International Relations
ther broadly Burkean or gradualist, or is the status-quo con-
On this definition, no major contemporary school in inter- servatism of realism. However, as Hall (2011, 48–55) has
national relations theory is meaningfully reactionary. This shown, many first generation English School scholars, in-
should be obvious in the cases of classical and neoliberal cluding Butterfield and Wight, expressed a strident nostal-
progressivism and historical materialist radicalism.15 In their gia for empire and imperial-era international society. Early
canonical forms, all of these schools imagined better fu- English School theorists claimed this period was more so-
tures that differ from the past, whether achieved through cially “thick” and pacific. They linked colonial notions of civ-
gradual evolution or revolutionary struggle.16 However, ilizational superiority to a stable and peaceful international
those schools sometimes called conservative are not usually order. Hedley Bull was relatively isolated among them in ac-
reactionary, at least in their more recent formulations. Real- cepting decolonization.24 However, second generation En-
ism, the school most commonly linked to conservatism, de- glish School accounts locate conservative tendencies within
scribes no corrosive historical change. Instead, realists ques- the school’s larger pluralism (Little 2000; Buzan 2004).
tion whether fundamental international change is possible Third generation English School work can be more or less
at all. Waltz (1979, 66) is perhaps clearest: “The texture of explicitly anticolonial (Suzuki 2009).
international politics remains highly constant, patterns re- Other exceptions are rare and mostly partial, proving the
cur, and events repeat themselves endlessly. The relations rule. While power transition theories claim rising powers
that prevail internationally seldom shift rapidly in type or in are more risk acceptant than declining ones (Gilpin 1983),
quality. They are marked instead by dismaying persistence.” some versions argue declining states too are risk acceptant
Mearsheimer (2003, 2) concurs: “international politics has (Levy 1987). Here though, states in decline aim to prevent
always been a ruthless and dangerous business, and it is later, more destructive wars—not recover lost power and
likely to remain that way.” This vision has little transforma- standing. Elsewhere, Schweller (2014) describes an entropic
tion of any kind—good or ill. process whereby the modern world’s increasing complexity
11
Nor is reaction equivalent to populism, which may be a doctrine of the
17
left or right and says nothing systematic about the past (Müller 2016, 21–22; see See the review in Bessner and Guilhot (2015, 85–98); for Morgenthau
also Marchlewska, Cichocka, Panayiotou, Castellanos, and Batayneh 2017). Nor is specifically, see Neacsu (2010, chaps. 4 and 5).
18
reaction inherently populist—it may be a doctrine of return to traditional social See Morgenthau (1948, 13; 2004, 15–16) and Niebuhr (2008, chap. 7).
hierarchy. While they differ from Waltzian structuralism, both see violence as persistent and
12
Anticolonial reaction contrasts with more common progressive or radical international progress tenuous at best.
19
anticolonialism (for example, Fanon 1965). Elsewhere, quasi-modernities may See Gaddis (2011, 603–5), who notes Kennan “long believed that race
have emerged independently of the West (Woodside 2009, 1, 10). shaped culture.” Kennan’s (2014, 46–47) diaries suggest a generalized nostalgia:
13
Similarly, not all theoretical critics of modernity, such as Leo Strauss and “I cannot help but regret I did not live fifty or a hundred years sooner. . . . I should
others, propose a reactionary political program (Zuckert 2011). Some may even have lived in those days when . . . foreign countries were still foreign, when a vast
aim to ameliorate modern politics (Arendt 1998; 2006) or defend some ele- part of the world always bore the glamour of the great unknown, when there were
ments of modernity while criticizing others (Manent 2006; Elshtain 1993, 2008; still wars worth fighting and gods worth worshipping.”
20
Thompson 2008; Delsol 2010). Other schools, such as postmodernism, are hos- The later Morgenthau, for example, endorsed world federalism
tile to modernity without nostalgia of any kind. See note 42 for two liminal cases, (Scheuerman 2011, 117–58).
21
Martin Heidegger and Carl Schmitt. For an overview, see Anderson (1997).
14 22
Reaction as we define it may presuppose modernity, insofar as reactionary See Kissinger (1994, 804–12, 832–36; 2014, 371–74, 372): “A world order
political beliefs require a historicist conception of political life. Such understand- of states affirming individual dignity and participatory governance, and coop-
ings became available only through Rousseau, Hegel, and other modern Euro- erating internationally in accordance with agreed-upon rules, can be our hope
pean theorists. and should be our inspiration. But progress toward it will need to be sustained
15
International relations scholars tend to have left-liberal political views through intermediary stages.” In his first book Kissinger (2013) expressed admi-
(Maliniak, Peterson, and Tierney 2012). ration for Metternich’s post-Napoleonic restoration (see below).
16 23
Early liberal internationalists were progressive, and sometimes anti- Carr (2001, 113) had an exceptional, quasi-Hegelian view of progress, see-
imperialist, as was Angell, but also paternalistic and Eurocentric—and thus at least ing it as possible but aimed toward goals revealed only as they were realized
potentially reactionary (Hobson 2012, 40–45). On Angell generally, see Ceadel (MacKay and LaRoche 2017, 226).
24
(2009). See, for example, Bull (1959); discussion in Hall (2011, 51–52).
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415
by guest
on 19 April 2018
4 Why Is There No Reactionary International Theory?

drives disorder and chaos. However, he does not describe advocated a geopolitical worldview and American naval mili-
a specific Fall from a clearly delineated better past. Nor tarism (Tuathail 1996, chaps. 1, 3; Black 2016, 126–41). Both
does he hold anyone responsible—the effect is structural. addressed the “closing of the world”: the increasing proxim-
Elsewhere still, neoconservatives have deep ties to some ity of once isolated societies to the United States, especially
forms of liberalism.25 an encroaching “Asiatic” world (Hobson 2012, 123–30). Re-
An exception in recent decades is Huntington’s (1997) acting to Germany’s post-1919 crises, German geographers
overtly reactionary Clash of Civilizations. Huntington lo- also attempted to revive German expansion with geopoliti-
cates group identity and fellow feeling in large, historically cal theory. After World War 2, classical geopolitics fell out
rooted silos—prone, he believed, to conflict with one an- of academic favor because of its associations with Nazism
other. Huntington’s subsequent account of American na- (Tuathail 1996, chap. 4; Black 2016, chap. 7; cf. Hobson
tional identity, Who We Are (2004), argued that America 2012, 158–65). When Kissinger and others revived the term
should return to the cultural homogeneity of its “found- “geopolitics” during the Cold War, they used it and related
ing” white Anglo-Saxon protestant values to renew its na- terms as “casual synonyms for realist views of international
tional strength. Taken together, Clash and Who We Are pro- strategic rivalry and interaction” (Deudney 2000, 79), elid-
pose a narrative of decline in which Western nationalism ing their reactionary linkages.30
is under attack by both expanding liberal multiculturalism Apart from geopolitics, early international-relations, in-
and undifferentiated foreign civilizations; America can be cluding early liberalism, was deeply tied up with the linked
rescued by ethnonational homogeneity at home and antag- tasks of administering empires and maintaining white
onism abroad. Hassner (1996, 65, 69) usefully summarizes: supremacy.31 As European imperialism declined, post-war
Huntington’s civilizational emphasis on “tradition and reli- British liberal imperialists in international studies became
gion cannot be understood except as a reaction to modern- tacitly reactionary: nostalgic adherents of an older order
ization and its discontents.” The rise of civilizational interna- (Hall 2011, 44–47). The narrative of “great debates” be-
tional politics makes sense only if construed as reactionary. tween liberals and realists, from which the discipline pu-
As Welch (2013) notes, the account was neither predictive tatively emerged, concealed this history. Imperial nostalgia
nor explanatory—instead, “it was a wish.” Although Hunt- was erased from international relations’ origin story.32
ington’s work is often discussed in nonacademic settings, in- No contemporary international relations scholar is sys-
ternational relations scholars remain consistently critical of tematically reactionary. However, disciplinary international
it, suggesting he led no larger trend in the field.26 relations elides a significant portion of its own history. In-
Absent a reactionary school, we might look for schol- deed, reaction has deeply shaped both modern political
ars who take reaction as an object of study. Constructivism, theory (in its many antimodern forms) and the modern
which focuses on ideas (Finnemore and Sikkink 2001, 393), practice of world politics. We address these in the next two
could in principle take reaction seriously. However, con- sections.
structivists have not in practice documented the social con-
struction of international reaction. While some emphasize
the divisive, realist, power-politics of ideas (Mitzen 2006; A Brief History of Political Reaction
Barkin 2010), they do not pay much attention to narra- Modern political reaction initially responded to the French
tives of historical decline.27 Psychological accounts of iden- Revolution, in which the term réaction referred to anyone
tity emphasize in-group/out-group dynamics (Mercer 1995) who opposed the Jacobins (Lilla 2016, xi). Some early mod-
but not over time.28 Postcolonial international-relations the- ern thinkers opposed large-scale change—Thomas More’s
ory finds imperial nostalgia in contemporary world politics campaign against the Reformation is exemplary. However,
(for example, Seth 2013, 152–53) but does not offer a sys- reactionary thought in the sense we mean emerged from the
tematic treatment of reaction as such. Revolutionary period. Its canonical statement was and re-
Strikingly, however, this absence itself elides early interna- mains Joseph de Maistre’s (1994) Considérations sur la France.
tional relations’ history of reactionary and quasi-reactionary
tendencies.29 The field’s early history includes many forms 30
Recent geopolitics revivals acknowledge critical geography’s critique while
of imperial, geopolitical, or racialized nostalgia. As Hobson disagreeing with its poststructuralism (for example, Deudney 2000; Kelly 2016,
(2012, chaps. 5 and 7) has pointed out, early twentieth- 45–69; Black 2016, 202–4, 229–39).
century classical geopolitics had pronounced reactionary 31
For example, Foreign Affairs was founded as the Journal of Race Development
strains, including geographic ethnonationalism and im- (Vitalis 2015, ix–x). The elision of such episodes from standard histories of the
perial nostalgia. Halford Mackinder hoped much of his field is a double injustice, obscuring both the field’s imperial origins and the
work, including his now-famous “geographical pivot” theory, early scholars who resisted it. Henderson (2017) documents the contributions
of the “Howard School” (the term is Vitalis’s) to international relations theory.
would renew British seafaring imperialism against competi- Some early American political scientists, such as Paul Reinsch, advocated a more
tion from land empires. In the United States, Alfred Mahan “benign” imperialism (Schmidt 2008; Hobson 2012, 121–23). This broader racial-
ized history of the early field overlaps only partially with political reaction as we
25
Neoconservatism lacks standard formulations in international relations define it. Rather than being reactionary or nostalgic at the time, racism was all
theory—the field usually relies on outside analytical reconstructions (for exam- too normal. Thus, for example, Vucetic (2011) traces the emergence of the “An-
ple, Williams 2005b; Drolet 2011). glosphere” to racializing processes distinguishing the English-speaking peoples
26
Huntington’s thesis has been repeatedly disproven empirically (Chiozza from others. See also Thakur, Davis, and Vale (2017) on the South African origins
2002; Fox 2002; survey in Musgrave 2017). His account is distinct from con- of the field. On empire and liberalism in international relations, see Jahn (2005a;
structivist accounts of grand cultural or civilizational difference (for example, 2005b; 2013, 17–19); on empire and political theory more broadly, see Pitts (2005;
Katzenstein 2009; Acharya 2014). 2010).
27 32
See Adamson (2005, 547) on the “liberal bias” of constructivism, exempli- Indeed, tropes now thought of as typifying the period had roots in geopo-
fied by its blindness to political Islam. litical forerunners. For example, Mackinder’s (1919, 10–16) reference to “demo-
28
Exceptionally, Freedman (2016) emphasizes lost perceived status and at- cratic idealism” and “reality” prefigures Carr’s utopian vs. realist formulation. For
tempts to regain it. Mackinder, however, reality and idealism can be synthetized in modernist effi-
29
Although reflexive international relations scholars such as Hobson have ciency, the excesses of which may be destructive—his diagnostic case is the French
recently (re-)connected classical geopolitics to early international relations, this Revolution’s Terror. The modern realist critique of idealism goes back at least to
critique was first made by critical geographers vis-à-vis their own discipline: see Machiavelli (Pangle and Ahrensdorf 1999, chaps. 4 and 5; Zuckert 2017) but is
Tuathail (1996); Tuathail, Dalby, and Routledge (2006). distinct from reactionary politics as defined here.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018
JOSEPH MACKAY AND C H R I S T O P H E R D AV I D L A R O C H E 5

Maistre advanced a providential, theocratic understanding Donoso Cortés. For example, the French romantic writer
of politics, blamed the revolution on Enlightenment phi- Chateaubriand was a staunch royalist decades after the
losophy, and advocated a Bourbon restoration.33 As Pierre revolution and a defender of Catholicism against secu-
Manent writes in his introduction to Maistre (2006, vii), “in- larizing Enlightenment critique.39 Later, Nietzsche’s radi-
stead of critiquing the Revolution for this or that measure, cal critique of Western philosophy often implied extreme
or for its excesses in general, [Considérations] rejects it en- antimodernism—although he never expressly advocated a
tirely, in its essence, as contrary to the very nature of social premodern politics.40
and moral man.” By defending hierarchical political tradi- In twentieth-century America, reaction referred to those
tion against abstract and destructive Enlightenment ratio- who would, in William F. Buckley’s (1955) phrase, “stand
nalism, Maistre helped establish and spread an intellectual athwart history, yelling Stop”—in opposition to “Social En-
tradition dedicated to restoring and defending an idealized gineers” who would undermine “the organic moral order.”
past.34 Across the Atlantic, the influence of Maistre and Cortés
The revolution also implicated two figures who, though was most visible in the decisionism of Carl Schmitt. Schmitt
not reactionaries themselves, shaped later reaction. The (2003) expressed nostalgia for the pre-Wilsonian Jus Pub-
first was Jean-Jacques Rousseau, whose arguments inspired licum Europaeum era of international public law, condemned
both the revolution itself and later forms of political an- the corroding effects of liberal “Atlanticist” commercial-
timodernism. For Rousseau (1997, Note IX, 197), human- ism, and advocated supranational “Großraüme” that could
ity was originally “naturally good,” and human ills were so- counter-balance Atlantist imperialism.41 Schmitt’s antiliber-
cial creations—epitomized in eighteenth-century Europe’s alism has had a wide impact: apart from his revival on the
corrupt, “bourgeois” society. Revolutionaries (both left and critical left, Schmitt influenced Morgenthau’s realism, “new
right) drew radical conclusions from this: if all problems right” writers in Europe such as Alain de Benoist (Hooker
were social, then society itself could and should be trans- 2009, 204–13), and the international thought of Russian
formed and the human condition perfected. In the reac- Alexander Dugin.42 By degrees, all of these accounts partic-
tionary version, this meant recreating an earlier, purer soci- ipate in political reaction: they view social change or reform
ety not yet corrupted by bourgeois culture.35 The second was itself as destructive, with some aiming to recreate a tradi-
Edmund Burke, who founded modern conservatism. Like tional social and political order in response.
Maistre, Burke saw the Revolution as imposing a radically In the twentieth century, a second strain of reaction
abstract, inhuman modernity on the tradition-dependent, emerged, often linked to mass ideological movements. In-
complex reality of human life.36 fluenced by Nietzsche and more distantly by Rousseau, writ-
However, neither Rousseau nor Burke was strictly reac- ers such as Julius Evola lent it intellectual ammunition. This
tionary. Burke represented a “progressive” conservative as- mass reactionary politics sought a more radicalized and un-
pect of the Enlightenment, intended to temper change and compromising reversion to an original, mythical past, one
curtail universalism.37 Rousseau questioned the Enlighten- since degraded by modernity, capitalism, or bourgeois soci-
ment’s transformative premises but aimed to reform them ety. It was most visible in National Socialism and other fascist
in his later work.38 movements, peaking in the 1930s and 1940s. While defeated
Modern political reaction is descended from these events in WWII, this more radical reaction persists today. Current
and theorists, in more and less radical forms. Later writ- European far-right intellectual movements and parties—for
ers expanded, modified, and transformed its core ideas— example, “Golden Dawn”—also intend to recover a puta-
appeal to tradition and religion against revolutionary mod- tively purer past (Charalambous 2015). They deploy mod-
ernism. They influenced many of the statesmen respon- ernizing means, including advanced communications and
sible for the 1815 post-Napoleonic restoration, as well weapons technologies, to antimodern ends: the aggressive
as later reactionaries, including Louis de Bonald and or radical transformation of the world around them. Global
33
See Maistre (1994, 62–76, 84–85; emphases original): “It will be in the name
of the VERY GOOD AND VERY GREAT GOD . . . that you will return to your old
39
constitution and that a king will give you the only thing that you ought wisely to Not all reactionaries of the period agreed unproblematically with one an-
desire—liberty through the monarchy.” other in practice. Chateaubriand, for example, advocated unilateral French re-
34
For the historical reception of Maistre, see Armenteros and Lebrun (2011). vision of the Vienna settlement status quo maintained by Metternich’s congress
35
Rousseau did not describe, or necessarily intend, a program of reaction. system (Schroeder 1962, 210, 229–36).
40
Many of his intellectual descendants were leftist radicals, including Robespierre Likewise, Spengler (1991) elaborated a nostalgic philosophy of history in
and Marx. On Rousseau and the French Revolution, see Furet (1997); on his which the West was in decline—but did not advocate any return to the past; see
practical politics, see Kelly’s introduction to Rousseau (2005, xiii–xxiii). Dannhauser (1995).
36 41
For example, Burke (2014, 17–36). Both excoriate modern theory or what Despite his Nazism, Schmitt more closely resembled the moderate (if theo-
Burke (see 2014, 8, 22, 59–62, 185–88, 224–27) labels “metaphysical” abstractions cratic) reaction of Maistre (Garrard 2001; cf. Meier 2011; Mouffe 1999; 2007).
and Maistre (1994, 41, 45, 47, 57) “philosophy” and “philosophism.” Burke advo- His core intellectual commitments did not include reversion to an antimodern
cated armed intervention against the French Revolution, but also the progressive social order and, thus, were not wholly consistent with Nazism. On this basis many
gradualism of British constitutionalism, defending the 1688 and 1776 revolutions contemporary theorists on the left (for example Mouffe 1993; 2005), have used
(Welsh 1995). Maistre (1994, 60–61, 104–21) disliked all three but was nonethe- Schmittian concepts to critique modern democratic practice from a critical stand-
less a “liberal” or (we prefer) moderate reactionary: he admired Britain’s consti- point. In contrast, Heidegger (the other academic theorist most closely linked to
tutional monarchy and although he wanted “a restoration of the old order . . . he Nazism) had vague but extreme political views. While thinly articulated, his reac-
ha[d] a fairly liberal understanding of what defined the old order” (Beiner 2011, tion was likely more radical. Schmitt’s international thought has attracted atten-
350; cf. Garrard 2001, 162–63). For Maistre’s relationship with Burke, see Lebrun tion from critical international-relations scholars and others (Odysseos and Petito
(2001). 2007; Hooker 2009).
37 42
For example: “A state without the means of some change is a state without Dugin’s published works in English are mostly concerned with domestic
the means of its conservation”; “by preserving the method of nature in the con- politics. His account of international relations advocates an expressly reactionary
duct of the state, in what we improve we are never wholly new; in what we retain formulation of Russia’s place in the world (Astrov and Morozova 2012, 209–15;
we are never wholly obsolete” (Burke 2014, 23, 35). Schouten 2014). His theory of multipolarity focuses on regional-civilizational
38
Although considered an Enlightenment thinker, Rousseau challenged pre- poles he claims can collectively counter the United States–backed Atlanticist
vailing narratives of scientific and social progress. He argued that they under- hegemony—an account indebted to Schmitt and classical geopolitics. Despite his
mined political and social life. See Garrard (2003) and Pangle and Ahrensdorf public profile however, Dugin is influential neither in mainstream Western inter-
(1999, 185–90). national theory nor in Russian foreign policy practice (Laruelle 2015).

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018
6 Why Is There No Reactionary International Theory?

jihadist movements, too, combine reactionary politics with (Kissinger 2013).46 Below, these two examples illustrate the
the techniques of modern politics.43 role of reaction in world politics.47
Moderate and radical political reactionaries alike accept
the premises of modern thought and politics but do so
Revisionism and the Third Reich, 1933–45
in opposed ways. Moderate reaction aims to slow or pause
modernity’s progressive march by defending traditional in- Nazi Germany was perhaps the most extreme reactionary
stitutions against progressive undermining or attack. Radi- state on record. While Nazi ideology was often vague and
cal reaction takes the modern premise that human society inconsistent (Mann 2004, 140–43), it aimed consistently “to
is malleable as an opportunity to reconstruct or approxi- restore to the German people an ethnic purity that was
mate a pre-modern society. It leverages modern ideologies imagined to have existed in the past” (Turner 1972, 551).
and technologies to antimodern ends. Nonetheless, the two It recalled the “First Reich” of Charlemagne, a loosely Ger-
lie on a continuum, and actual instances may fall between manic medieval empire. This provided “a powerful sym-
them. The most radical extreme may take on the histori- bolic link to the imagined greatness of the past” (Evans
cal unreality of, for example, core Nazi ideology. Moderate 2005, 460), tied to the idea of a premodern Volk. Impe-
reaction may shade into gradual acceptance of modernity rial Germany echoed this ancestral Germanic utopia af-
itself. ter 1870 as the “Second Reich,” but it was destroyed by
World War I, the punitive Versailles peace treaty, and
Weimar-era economic disaster. Consistent with the view
Reactionary World Politics that “Fascists need a demonized enemy against which to
If reaction is an important feature of modern political mobilize followers” (Paxton 2007, 37), the Nazis blamed
thought, it has also recurred as a central feature of mod- the Jews for these circumstances. German Jews were a
ern international political practice. We distinguish two largely assimilated minority and made up less than one
ideal-type varieties of reactionary action—revisionism and percent of the interwar German population. The Nazis
restructuring—and show briefly how each plays out histor- nonetheless cast them as an inassimilable other—a state-
ically. The two correspond to the radical and moderate less, landless, internationalized people—and linked them
modes of reaction above. to the vicissitudes of international finance, which the
Revision, the most direct approach, corresponds to radi- Nazis also blamed for German hardship (Snyder 2015,
cal or militant reactionary antimodernism. Faced with the 42–44).48
perceived loss of a morally superior past, revisionist reac- The Nazis were not merely reactionary; they were revision-
tionaries aim to restore the status quo ante, often in direct ist. Their goals conflicted acutely with the existing world
and uncompromising ways. The diagnostic case is Nazi Ger- order.49 A rapidly rearmed Germany set out to expand its
many.44 Believing in a premodern better world and armed borders and turn Europe into a premodern, racially strati-
with the military capacity of a modern great power, Nazi fied world: “they sought to transcend existing reality at one
elites set out to reconfigure Europe on the model of an blow and substitute for it a radically different social order”
imagined past by sheer force of arms. (Turner 1972, 552). To do this the Nazis used modern tech-
More moderate reactionaries may aim to restructure, nologies and institutions to antimodern ends. Nazi revision-
restoring past political order by building institutions and co- ism proceeded by war, structural reconfiguration, and geno-
ordinating international order. Restructuring requires less cide.50 Germany conquered most European states west of
coercion and instead emphasizes cooperation and multilat- the rapidly receding Soviet frontier or turned them into
eralism. New international institutional frameworks become satellite regimes. The Nazis aimed to transform the Euro-
the vessels for restored past political orders.45 The diagnos- pean state system into a hierarchy, with the Third Reich at its
tic case is the nineteenth-century Concert of Europe and apex. They then set out to erase the Jews, whom they blamed
specifically its “Metternich system” of counterrevolutionary for pre-war Germany’s ruin, from the face of the earth.51
management. Here, a coalition of European great powers Did reactionary Nazi ideology drive German actions?
partially restored and maintained the monarchical order Even structuralist accounts of WWII suggest a linkage.
that preceded the French Revolution and Napoleonic Wars Schweller (1998, 5) allows that “Hitler’s ideas distinguished
him from prior German leaders.” While ideology did not
cause the war, German reactionary revisionism helped create
43
As Ahmad (2017, 16) writes, a key aspect of today’s “reactionary yet hyper-
46
modern” Islamist groups lies in their promise to recreate “a romanticized golden Reactionary states with neither coercive capacity nor multilateral linkages
age that predates the miseries of the colonial era and draws on an imagined con- may adopt a third strategy: withdrawal. Franco’s Spain, for example, lacked both
ception of an Islamic nation that transcends all other loyalties.” Some, such as great power status and ideological allies after 1945. Instead of seeking to overturn
Daesh and the Islamic Courts Union, also employ modern state-building tech- other parts of Europe, it isolated itself from the post-war international order.
47
niques, co-opt and tax local businesspeople, and recruit new followers using mod- Our cases are illustrations, not empirical tests. We select diagnostic cases,
ern communications technology. A key early intellectual here is Qutb (2006), not ambiguous ones. This approach is akin to a “plausibility probe” (George and
whose antimodernism is expressly reactionary—as distinct from progressive an- Bennett 2005, 75).
48
ticolonialisms. On parallels between Qutb and Maistre, see Euben (1999, 199, On the “Nazi conscience” generally, see Koonz (2003).
49
n181). On Islamist politics generally, see Ismail (2003), Shapiro and Fair (2010), Reactionary revisionist states differ from other revisionists in their goals—
Raqib and Barreto (2014), and Ahmad (2015; 2016). On Islamism and political vi- the early Soviet Union aimed at world transformation but was in no sense reac-
olence, see Greenberg (2005), Toft (2007), Farrall (2011), and Hamid and Farrall tionary.
50
(2015). The relationship between the Holocaust and modernity is contested. For
44
An alternate example, the Khmer Rouge, blended left and right. They Bauman (2001), the Holocaust is part of modernity itself, bound up with modern
sought to recreate the Khmer empire and “restored” Cambodian society to a pu- nationalism, technologically implemented mass murder, and the depersonalizing
tative “year zero.” They did this by emptying urban centers, murdering educated effects of modernity itself. We emphasize additionally the Nazis’ expressed anti-
and foreign-influenced elites, and instituting a closed agrarian society (Kiernan modernism. Herf (1986, 1–4) terms Nazism a form of “reactionary modernism,”
2008, chapter 15). a term since taken up by Mirowski (2013, 212–17) to describe early international
45
This “reactionary institutionalism” differs in goals, if not means, from the relations theory.
51
institutionalism of neoliberals (Keohane and Martin 1995) or neofunctionalists While the Nazis targeted and murdered multiple groups, they focused on
(Haas 1964). The contrast suggests little about institutionalism is inherently lib- Europe’s Jews as those primarily responsible for putative German civilizational
eral or progressive (Steffek 2015). decline.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018
JOSEPH MACKAY AND C H R I S T O P H E R D AV I D L A R O C H E 7

its conditions of possibility.52 The ideological idiosyncrasies Conclusion


of Nazism may not have been necessary, but a will to over-
Reaction, we have argued, is almost completely absent from
throw the status quo and recreate a mythical past was.53
contemporary international-relations theory. However, we
can find fragmentary traces of reaction in the field’s history
Restructuring and the Metternich System, 1815–1848 and an extensive presence in the history of political thought.
Reactionary beliefs and dispositions play a significant role
A prominent example of reactionary restructuring occurred in modern international political practice. This raises the
during the great power management of post-Napoleonic Eu- question: why is there now no reactionary international the-
rope, sometimes labelled the “Congress system” or Concert ory? Here, we can only offer some conjectures. We suspect
of Europe.54 Recent international-relations analyses have fo- that its absence is linked to the field’s putatively ameliorative
cused either on the Concert’s progressive institutionalism orientation—that is, the way the field often locates its roots
or its material balance of power (Finnemore 2004, 108– in liberal idealism and the decidedly nonreactionary chal-
124; Mitzen 2013, 2015; Kagan 1997; Slantchev 2005; cf. lenge posed by realists. Such a narrative, and particularly
Weber 1995, 40–60). Both understate the Concert’s central the part played by liberalism, suggests notions of “the good”
repressive apparatus, sometimes called the “Metternich Sys- in world politics incompatible with reactionary ideas.58
tem” after Austrian foreign minister Prince Klemenz von This narrative renders past international-relations reac-
Metternich.55 Although Metternich represented the weak- tionaries invisible by obscuring connections between canon-
est of Europe’s five great powers, along with the Burkean ical international-relations schools and reactionary ideas.
Lord Castlereagh, he played a central role in managing the Early realists are read as emphasizing the permanent limits
post-Napoleonic restoration, such that Kissinger (2013, 11) of political change. Early geopolitical reactionaries have, un-
termed him “Prime Minister of Europe.” til recently, been read out of the discipline entirely. Liberal
The Metternich system grew out of treaties signed by linkages to empire were elided as embarrassing. Later criti-
Europe’s powers, particularly the four allied powers that cal theorists rejected liberals and realists alike as unreflexive
contributed most to defeating Napoleon—Prussia, Russia, and presentist—as too focused on the status quo and blind
Britain, and Austria. Gathering in Vienna in 1814–15, to the possibilities of emancipatory politics. However, they
the allies redrew the European map and restored many did so in the name of “a critique of domination” that would
pre-Revolutionary monarchies. The “Vienna settlement” explore means of resistance available to “those systemati-
created a territorial balance of power that hemmed in cally or casually subjected to sustained forms of suffering,
France and satisfied Europe’s other powers (Kissinger 2013, denigration, and/or exclusion” (Weber 2014, 532).59 Such
41–190; Jarrett 2013, 43–205; Slantchev 2005). Worried rev- criticisms may reject reaction generally but do little to distin-
olution could spread throughout Europe and upset the Vi- guish it from the joint liberal-realist project of international-
enna settlement, Metternich spent three decades coordi- relations theory as such.
nating the allies—and, after 1818, France—to repress Ja- Why then does reaction matter? The practice of reac-
cobinism, uphold monarchical legitimacy, and strengthen tionary international politics appears more widespread at
Great Power cooperation. Concerns about international sta- present than at any time in the post-war period. At the time
bility and regime type were thus deeply intertwined. For of writing, far-right parties are active—though not quite
Metternich, constitutionalist and liberal regimes threatened ascendant—across Europe; the politics of reaction appears
the hard-won Vienna equilibrium.56 Agreements at Trop- increasingly normalized (Cole 2005; Fligstein, Polyakova,
pau (1820) and Münchengrätz (1833) secured Prussian and and Sandholtz 2012). British voters, led by activists chiefly
Russian cooperation in Metternich’s antirevolutionary in- from the right, narrowly chose to leave the European Union.
terventions, which suppressed revolts in Italy and Poland. This “Brexit” was partially motivated by “cultural backlash”
Aided by French disorganization and the Burkean tenor of (Inglehart and Norris 2016, 29–31) or racially tinged (Rajan-
British politics, Metternich also largely succeeded in pre- Rankin 2017, 2) nostalgia. The stated positions of the new
venting Western cabinets from upsetting the Vienna restora- American president, who campaigned on a promise to
tion. As Alan Sked (2008, 105) summarizes, “fear of revolu- “Make America Great Again,” often upend the traditional
tion” was the “bottom line in international affairs” for Eu- party system and deride liberal international order (Patrick
rope’s powers. In short, reactionary institution building was, 2017). The so-called Islamic State has declared a Caliphate,
for decades, the basis of European order.57 putatively modeled on a premodern Islamic world order
(Ahmad 2017, 12). Elsewhere in the West, individual reac-
52
Moreover, as Goddard (2015) shows, Nazi claims of legitimacy for German tionary radicals like Kaczynski and Breivik no longer seem
revanchism helped secure British and Allied appeasement, prior to Munich. isolated, as evidenced by the rise of the alt-right and its self-
53
The memory of fascism and antifascism in Europe remains contested be- styled ideologues, such as Richard Spencer (Wood 2017).
tween the political center and left (see for example Grunenberg 1997; Mammone Once-solid bulwarks between the mainstream right and ex-
2006; Prezioso 2008; García, Yusta, Tabet, and Clímaco 2016).
54 tremists no longer seem secure.60 Reactionary politics are
Labels for the post-Napoleonic order vary widely; see Schroeder (1962, 4–
5); Jarrett (2013, 347–69). We focus on what has been labelled the “Metternich on the march and are reshaping the world political future.
system,” the part of the order committed to repressing constitutionalist rebellions
58
and which ended in 1848. When, for example, Angell (1972, 59) insisted war “belongs to a stage of
55
While realists downplay ideas (Kagan 1997; Slantchev 2005), constructivists development out of which we have passed,” he implied progress was both possible
acknowledge its illiberalism without focusing on it (Mitzen 2013). Earlier interna- and desirable.
59
tional relations analyses sometimes feature the repressive apparatus (for example, See similarly feminist IR scholars, who assert the power of critical schol-
Morgenthau 1948, 481–90); see also Vick (2014) for a criticism. arship to produce desirable change in the world (Tickner 2006 386–87; Sjoberg
56
Finnemore (2004, 108–24). Like Maistre, Metternich respected British con- 2006, 233–34; Eschle and Maiguashca 2007; Ackerly and True 2008; Wibben 2011,
stitutionalism but did not think it was transferable to the continent. As the top 111–12). For a similar ethos in postcolonial critique, see chapters in Chowdhry
minister in the multinational Austrian Empire, he had a material interest in and Nair (2004), Jabri (2005), and Agathangelou and Ling (2009).
60
maintaining monarchical absolutism and suppressing nationalist revolt. See Sked Kaczynski’s ideological predilections have been linked to his upbringing
(2008, esp. 1–25, 64–106, 244–46). and education (Chase 2003), and Breivik’s racist terrorism radicalized ideas nor-
57
See Jarrett (2013, esp. 72–84, 231–77); Schroeder (1962, 235–66; 1994, 583– mal on the European far right (Berntzen and Sandberg 2014). These beliefs were
804); and Sked (2008). likely never truly marginal.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018
8 Why Is There No Reactionary International Theory?

However concerning this may be, though, the account above ARMENTEROS, CAROLINA, AND RICHARD LEBRUN. 2011. Joseph de Maistre and His
reminds us these circumstances are not new: reaction is a re- European Readers: From Friedrich Von Gentz to Isaiah Berlin. BRILL.
curring feature of international politics.61 ASTROV, ALEXANDER, AND NATALIA MOROZOVA. 2012. “Russia: Geopolitics from
If we are correct, then the contemporary discipline, the Heartland.” In The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms
and Foreign Policy Identity Crises, edited by Stefano Guzzini, 192–216.
scrupulously forgetful of its reactionary past, is shorn of in-
124. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
tellectual history that might clarify present circumstances. BARKIN, J. SAMUEL. 2010. Realist Constructivism: Rethinking International Rela-
A field that ignores reaction as such may be blind to re- tions Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
actionary political practice. This blindness in turn weakens BAUMAN, ZYGMUNT. 2001. Modernity and the Holocaust. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Uni-
the responses scholars can offer. Indeed, contemporary re- versity Press.
action might have been anticipated. A quarter century ago, ———. 2017. Retrotopia. Cambridge: Polity.
in framing his otherwise ultra-liberal “end of history” thesis, BEINER, RONALD. 2011. Civil Religion: A Dialogue in the History of Political Philos-
Francis Fukuyama noted a powerful nostalgia for the time ophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
when history existed: BERNTZEN, LARS ERIK, AND SVEINUNG SANDBERG. 2014. “The Collective Na-
ture of Lone Wolf Terrorism: Anders Behring Breivik and the Anti-
Such nostalgia, in fact, will continue to fuel compe- Islamic Social Movement.” Terrorism and Political Violence 26 (5):
tition and conflict even in the post-historical world 759–79.
for some time to come. Even though I recognize its BESSNER, DANIEL, AND NICOLAS GUILHOT. 2015. “How Realism Waltzed Off: Lib-
inevitability, I have the most ambivalent feelings for eralism and Decisionmaking in Kenneth Waltz’s Neorealism.” Interna-
tional Security 40 (2): 87–118.
the civilization that has been created in Europe since
BLACK, JEREMY. 2016. Geopolitics and the Quest for Dominance. Bloomington, IN:
1945, with its north Atlantic and Asian offshoots. Per- Indiana University Press.
haps this very prospect of centuries of boredom at the BUCKLEY, WILLIAM F. 1955. “Our Mission Statement.” National Review. http://
end of history will serve to get history started once www.nationalreview.com/article/223549/our-mission-statement-
again. (Fukuyama 1989, 18) william-f-buckley-jr. Accessed 7 November 2017.
BULL, HEDLEY. 1959. “What Is the Commonwealth?” World Politics 11 (4): 577–
That nostalgia now appears present in force in world pol-
87.
itics.62 In the years ahead, a central task for international- BURKE, EDMUND. 2014. Revolutionary Writings: Reflections on the Revolution in
relations theory will be to take reaction seriously, as both an France and the First Letter on a Regicide Peace. Edited by Iain Hampsher-
intellectual tradition and a form of practical politics. Schol- Monk. Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought. New York:
ars whose political preferences are liberal or radical, or who Cambridge University Press.
embrace a realist skepticism of both projects, may find little BUZAN, BARRY. 2004. From International to World Society? Cambridge: Cam-
to dislike in their field’s implicit antireactionary moral ori- bridge University Press.
entation. We do not advocate a reactionary alternative. We ———. 2014. An Introduction to the English School of International Relations: The
aim instead to consider the analytical and political implica- Societal Approach. Cambridge: Polity Press.
CARR, EDWARD HALLETT. 2001. What Is History? London: Palgrave Macmillan
tions of having neglected reaction as such. A field that does
Limited.
not understand it in theory is ill equipped to understand CEADEL, MARTIN. 2009. Living the Great Illusion: Sir Norman Angell, 1872–1967.
and confront it in practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
CHARALAMBOUS, GIORGOS, ed. 2015. The European Far Right: Historical and Con-
temporary Perspectives. 2. Oslo, NO: PRIO Cyprus Centre and Friedrich-
References Ebert-Stiftung.
CHASE, ALSTON. 2003. Harvard and the Unabomber: The Education of an American
ACHARYA, AMITAV. 2014. “Global International Relations (IR) and Regional
Terrorist. New York: Norton.
Worlds.” International Studies Quarterly 58 (4): 647–59.
CHOWDHRY, GEETA, AND SHEILA NAIR, eds. 2004. Power, Postcolonialism and Inter-
ACKERLY, BROOKE, AND JACQUI TRUE. 2008. “Reflexivity in Practice: Power and
national Relations: Reading Race, Gender and Class. London: Routledge.
Ethics in Feminist Research on International Relations.” International
CHIOZZA, GIACOMO. 2002. “Is There a Clash of Civilizations? Evidence from
Studies Review 10 (4): 693–707.
Patterns of International Conflict Involvement, 1946–97.” Journal of
ADAMSON, FIONA B. 2005. “Global Liberalism Versus Political Islam: Com-
Peace Research 39 (6): 711–34.
peting Ideological Frameworks in International Politics.” International
COLE, ALEXANDRA. 2005. “Old Right or New Right? The Ideological Position-
Studies Review 7 (4): 547–69.
ing of Parties of the Far Right.” European Journal of Political Research 44
AHMAD, AISHA. 2015. “The Security Bazaar: Business Interests and Islamist
(2): 203–30.
Power in Civil War Somalia.” International Security 39 (3): 89–117.
DANNHAUSER, WERNER J. 1995. “Nietzsche and Spengler on Progress and De-
———. 2016. “Going Global: Islamist Competition in Contemporary Civil
cline.” In History and the Idea of Progress, edited by Arthur M. Melzer,
Wars.” Security Studies 25 (2): 353–84.
Jerry Weinberger and M. Richard Zinman, 117–33. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
———. 2017. Jihad & Co.: Black Markets and Islamist Power. New York: Oxford
University Press.
University Press.
DELSOL, CHANTAL. 2010. Icarus Fallen: The Search for Meaning in an Uncertain
AGATHANGELOU, ANNA M., AND L. H. M. LING. 2009. Transforming World Politics:
World. Translated by Robin Dick. Wilmington, DE: ISI Books.
From Empire to Multiple Worlds. London: Routledge.
DEUDNEY, DANIEL. 2000. “Geopolitics as Theory: Historical Security Material-
ANDERSON, BRIAN C. 1997. Raymond Aron: The Recovery of the Political. Lanham,
ism.” European Journal of International Relations 6 (1): 77–107.
MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
DEVALL, BILL, AND GEORGE SESSIONS. 1985. Deep Ecology: Living as If Nature Mat-
ANGELL, NORMAN. 1972. The Great Illusion, 1933. New York: Arno Press.
tered. Salt Lake City, UT: Gibbs Smith.
ARENDT, HANNAH. 1998. The Human Condition. Second edition. Chicago: The
DROLET, JEAN-FRANÇOIS. 2011. American Neoconservatism: The Politics and Culture
University of Chicago Press.
of a Reactionary Idealism. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
———. 2006. Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. Pen-
ELSHTAIN, JEAN BETHKE. Democracy on Trial. The Massey Lectures Series. Con-
guin Classics. New York: Penguin Books.
cord, ON: Anansi, 1993.
———. 2008. Sovereignty: God, State, and Self. New York: Basic Books.
61
Outside of the West, the Chinese philosopher Zhao Tingyang (2009) advo- ESCHLE, CATHERINE, AND BICE MAIGUASHCA. 2007. “Rethinking Globalised Resis-
cates reviving an idealized tianxia world order, modeled on the Zhou Dynasty of tance: Feminist Activism and Critical Theorising in International Re-
more than two millennia ago. Historical Chinese hegemony was more complex lations.” The British Journal of Politics and International Relations 9 (2):
than this account implies—see for example Lee (2016); Park (2017). 284–301.
62 EUBEN, ROXANNE L. 1999. Enemy in the Mirror: Islamic Fundamentalism and the
On Trumpism specifically, see Williamson (2016); Lieberman, Mettler,
Pepinsky, Roberts, and Valelly (2017); and Slaughter (2017). On recent shifts in Limits of Modern Rationalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
American conservatism, see Skocpol and Williamson (2012); Skocpol (2013). EVANS, RICHARD J. 2005. The Coming of the Third Reich. New York: Penguin.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018
JOSEPH MACKAY AND C H R I S T O P H E R D AV I D L A R O C H E 9

FANON, FRANTZ. 1965. The Wretched on the Earth. Translated by Constance Far- HOOKER, WILLIAM. 2009. Carl Schmitt’s International Thought: Order and Orienta-
rington. New York: Grove Press. tion. New York: Cambridge University Press.
FARRALL, LEAH. 2011. “How Al Qaeda Works: What the Organization’s Sub- HUNTINGTON, SAMUEL P. 1997. The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of
sidiaries Say about Its Strength.” Foreign Affairs 90: 128–39. World Order. New York: Simon and Schuster.
FINNEMORE, MARTHA. 2004. The Purpose of Intervention: Changing Beliefs about the ——— 2004. Who Are We?: The Challenges to America’s National Identity. New
Use of Force. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. York: Simon and Schuster.
FINNEMORE, MARTHA, AND KATHRYN SIKKINK. 2001. “Taking Stock: The Construc- INGLEHART, RONALD, AND PIPPA NORRIS. 2016. “Trump, Brexit, and the Rise of
tivist Research Program in International Relations and Comparative Populism: Economic Have-Nots and Cultural Backlash.” HKS Working
Politics.” Annual Review of Political Science 4 (1): 391–416. Paper No. RWP16-026. Rochester, NY.
FLIGSTEIN, NEIL, ALINA POLYAKOVA, AND WAYNE SANDHOLTZ. 2012. “European Inte- ISMAIL, SALWA. 2003. Rethinking Islamist Politics: Culture, the State and Islamism.
gration, Nationalism and European Identity.” JCMS: Journal of Common New York: I.B. Tauris.
Market Studies 50 (s1): 106–22. JABRI, VIVIENNE. 2005. “Critical Thought and Political Agency in Time of War.”
FOX, JONATHAN. 2002. “Ethnic Minorities and the Clash of Civilizations: A International Relations 19 (1): 70–78.
Quantitative Analysis of Huntington’s Thesis.” British Journal of Political JACKSON, PATRICK THADDEUS. 2011. The Conduct of Inquiry in International Rela-
Science 32 (3): 415–34. tions: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of World Politics.
FREEDMAN, JOSHUA. 2016. “Status Insecurity and Temporality in World Poli- 1st ed. London: Routledge.
tics.” European Journal of International Relations 22 (4): 797–822. JAHN, BEATE. 2005a. “Barbarian Thoughts: Imperialism in the Philoso-
FRIEDMAN, MILTON. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University Of phy of John Stuart Mill.” Review of International Studies 32 (3): 599–
Chicago Press. 618.
FUKUYAMA, FRANCIS. 1989. “The End of History?” The National Interest. 16: 3–18. ———. 2005b. “Kant, Mill, and Illiberal Legacies in International Affairs.”
FURET, FRANÇOIS. 1997. “Rousseau and the French Revolution.” In Rousseau International Organization 59 (1): 177–207.
and the French Revolution, edited by Clifford Orwin and Nathan Tarcov, ———. 2013. Liberal Internationalism: Theory, History, Practice. New York: Pal-
168–82. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. grave Macmillan.
GADDIS, JOHN LEWIS. 2011. George F. Kennan: An American Life. New York: Pen- JARRETT, MARK. 2013. The Congress of Vienna and Its Legacy: War and Great Power
guin Press. Diplomacy after Napoleon. ILHS 80. London: I.B. Tauris.
GARCÍA, HUGO, MERCEDES YUSTA, XAVIER TABET, AND CRISTINA CLÍMACO, eds. 2016. KAGAN, KORINA. 1997. “The Myth of the European Concert: The Realist-
Rethinking Antifascism: History, Memory and Politics, 1922 to the Present. Institutionalist Debate and Great Power Behavior in the Eastern Ques-
New York: Berghahn Books. tion, 1821–41.” Security Studies 7 (2): 1–57.
GARRARD, GRAEME. 2001. “Joseph de Maistre and Edmund Burke: A Compar- KATA, ANNA. 2010. “A Postmodern Pandora’s Box: Anti-Vaccination Mis-
ison.” In Joseph de Maistre’s Life, Thought and Influence: Selected Studies, information on the Internet.” Vaccine; Kidlington 28 (7): 1709–
edited by Richard Lebrun, 220–38. Montreal, CA: McGill-Queen’s Uni- 16.
versity Press. KATZENSTEIN, PETER J., ed. 2009. Civilizations in World Politics: Plural and Plural-
———. 2003. Rousseau’s Counter-Enlightenment: A Republican Critique of the ist Perspectives. London: Routledge.
Philosophes. SUNY Series in Social and Political Thought. Albany, NY: KELLY, PHILIP. 2016. Classical Geopolitics: A New Analytical Model. Stanford, CA:
State University of New York Press. Stanford University Press.
GEORGE, ALEXANDER L., AND ANDREW BENNETT. 2005. Case Studies and Theory KENNAN, GEORGE F. 2014. The Kennan Diaries. Edited by Frank Costigliola. New
Development in the Social Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. York: W. W. Norton and Company.
GILPIN, ROBERT. 1983. War and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Cam- KEOHANE, ROBERT O., AND LISA L. MARTIN. 1995. “The Promise of Institutional-
bridge University Press. ist Theory.” International Security 20 (1): 39–51.
GODDARD, STACIE E. 2015. “The Rhetoric of Appeasement: Hitler’s Legitima- KIERNAN, BEN. 2008. The Pol Pot Regime: Race, Power, and Genocide in Cambodia
tion and British Foreign Policy, 1938–39.” Security Studies 24 (1): 95– Under the Khmer Rouge, 1975–79. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
130. KISSINGER, HENRY. 1994. Diplomacy. New York: Simon and Schuster.
GREENBERG, KAREN J., ed. 2005. Al Qaeda Now: Understanding Todays Terrorists. ———. 2013. A World Restored: Metternich, Castlereagh and the Problems of Peace,
New York: Cambridge University Press. 1812–22. Brattleboro, VT: Echo Point.
GREGORY, BRAD S. 2012. The Unintended Reformation: How a Religious Revolution ———. 2014. World Order. New York: Penguin Press.
Secularized Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. KOONZ, CLAUDIA. 2003. The Nazi Conscience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
GRUNENBERG, ANTONIA. 1997. “Antitolitarianism Versus Antifascism—Two sity Press.
Legacies of the Past in Germany.” German Politics & Society 15 (2): 76– KUEHNELT-LEDDIHN, ERIK VON. 1952. Liberty or Equality; the Challenge of Our Time.
90. London: Hollis and Carter.
GUILHOT, NICOLAS, ed. 2013. The Invention of International Relations Theory: Re- LARUELLE, MARLENE. 2015. “Scared of Putin’s Shadow.” Foreign Affairs, March
alism, the Rockefeller Foundation, and the 1954 Conference on Theory. New 25. https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/russian-federation/2015-
York: Columbia University Press. 03-25/scared-putins-shadow. Accessed 7 November 2017.
HAAS, ERNST B. 1964. Beyond the Nation State: Functionalism and International LEE, JI-YOUNG. 2016. China’s Hegemony: Four Hundred Years of East Asian Domi-
Organization. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. nation. New York: Columbia University Press.
HALL, IAN. 2011. “The Revolt against the West: Decolonisation and Its Reper- LEVINE, DANIEL J. 2012. Recovering International Relations: The Promise of Sustain-
cussions in British International Thought, 1945–75.” The International able Critique. New York: Oxford University Press.
History Review 33 (1): 43–64. LEVY, JACK S. 1987. “Declining Power and the Preventive Motivation for War.”
HALL, IAN, ed. 2015. Radicals and Reactionaries in Twentieth-Century Inter- World Politics 40 (1): 82–107.
national Thought. The Palgrave Macmillan History of International LIEBERMAN, ROBERT C., SUZANNE METTLER, THOMAS B. PEPINSKY, KENNETH M.
Thought. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. ROBERTS, AND RICHARD VALELLY. “Trumpism and American Democ-
HALL, IAN, AND NICHOLAS RENGGER. 2005. “The Right That Failed? The Am- racy: History, Comparison, and the Predicament of Liberal Democ-
biguities of Conservative Thought and the Dilemmas of Conservative racy in the United States.” SSRN Scholarly Paper. Rochester, NY: So-
Practice in International Affairs.” International Affairs 81 (1): 69–82. cial Science Research Network, August 29, 2017. https://papers.
HAMID, MUSTAFA, AND LEAH FARRALL. 2015. The Arabs at War in Afghanistan. ssrn.com/abstract=3028990.
London: Hurst. LILLA, MARK. 2016. The Shipwrecked Mind: On Political Reaction. New York: New
HASSNER, PIERRE. 1996. “Morally Objectionable, Politically Dangerous.” The York Review Books.
National Interest 46: 63–69. LITTLE, RICHARD. 2000. “The English School’s Contribution to the Study of In-
HENDERSON, ERROL A. 2017. “The Revolution Will Not Be Theorised: Du Bois, ternational Relations.” European Journal of International Relations 6 (3):
Locke, and the Howard School’s Challenge to White Supremacist IR 395–422.
Theory.” Millennium. MACKAY, JOSEPH, AND CHRISTOPHER DAVID LAROCHE. 2017. “The Conduct of His-
HERF, JEFFREY. 1986. Reactionary Modernism: Technology, Culture, and Politics in tory in International Relations: Rethinking Philosophy of History in IR
Weimar and the Third Reich. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Theory.” International Theory 9 (2): 203–36.
HOBSON, JOHN M. 2012. The Eurocentric Conception of World Politics: Western In- MACKINDER, SIR HALFORD JOHN. 1919. Democratic Ideals and Reality: A Study in
ternational Theory, 1760–2010. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. the Politics of Reconstruction. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018
10 Why Is There No Reactionary International Theory?

MAISTRE, JOSEPH DE. 1994. Considerations on France. Edited by Richard Lebrun. PATRICK, STEWART M. 2017. “Trump and World Order.” Foreign Affairs 96 (2):
New York: Cambridge University Press. 52–57.
———. 2006. Considérations sur la France. Edited by Pierre Manent. Brussels: PAXTON, ROBERT O. 2007. The Anatomy of Fascism. New York: Knopf Doubleday.
Editions Complexe. PITTS, JENNIFER. 2005. A Turn to Empire: The Rise of Imperial Liberalism in Britain
MALINIAK, DANIEL, SUSAN PETERSON, AND MICHAEL J. TIERNEY. 2012. “TRIP and France. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Around the World: Teaching, Research, and Policy Views of In- ———. 2010. “Political Theory of Empire and Imperialism.” Annual Review
ternational Relations Faculty in 20 Countries.” Williamsburg, VA: of Political Science 13: 211–35.
Teaching, Research, and International Policy (TRIP) Project, The PREZIOSO, STÉFANIE. 2008. “Antifascism and Anti-Totalitarianism: The Italian
Institute for the Theory and Practice of International Relations, Debate.” Journal of Contemporary History 43 (4): 555–72.
College of William and Mary. https://www.wm.edu/offices/itpir/_ QUTB, SAYED. 2006. Milestones. New Delhi, IN: Islamic Book Service.
documents/trip/trip_around_the_world_2011.pdf. Accessed 7 RAJAN-RANKIN, SWETA. 2017. “Brexit Logics: Myth and Fact—A Black Feminist
November 2017. Accessed 7 November 2017. Analysis.” Feminists@law 7 (2): 1–2.
MAMMONE, ANDREA. 2006. “A Daily Revision of the Past: Fascism, Anti-Fascism, RANDALL, ADRIAN J. 1986. “The Philosophy of Luddism: The Case of the West
and Memory in Contemporary Italy.” Modern Italy 11 (2): 211–26. of England Woolen Workers, Ca. 1790–1809.” Technology and Culture 27
MANENT, PIERRE. 2006. A World beyond Politics?: A Defense of the Nation-State. (1): 1–17.
Translated by Marc LePain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. RAQIB, MARIAM, AND AMILCAR ANTONIO BARRETO. 2014. “The Taliban, Religious
MANN, MICHAEL. 2004. Fascists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Revival and Innovation in Afghan Nationalism.” National Identities 16
MANNHEIM, KARL. 1936. Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of (1): 15–30.
Knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. ROBIN, COREY. 2011. The Reactionary Mind: Conservatism from Edmund Burke to
MARCHLEWSKA, MARTA, ALEKSANDRA CICHOCKA, ORESTIS PANAYIOTOU, KEVIN CASTEL- Sarah Palin. New York: Oxford University Press.
LANOS, AND JUDE BATAYNEH. “Populism as Identity Politics: Perceived ROTH, MICHAEL S. 1991. “Dying of the Past: Medical Studies of Nos-
In-Group Disadvantage, Collective Narcissism, and Support for Pop- talgia in Nineteenth-Century France.” History and Memory 3 (1):
ulism.” Social Psychological and Personality Science, October 4, 2017, 5–29.
1–12. ROUSSEAU, JEAN-JACQUES. 1997. The Discourses and Other Political Writings. Edited
MEARSHEIMER, JOHN J. 2003. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York: W. W. by Victor Gourevitch. Cambridge Texts in the History of Political
Norton and Company. Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.
MEIER, HEINRICH. 2011. The Lesson of Carl Schmitt: Four Chapters on the Distinction ———. 2005. The Plan for Perpetual Peace, On the Government of Poland, and
between Political Theology and Political Philosophy. Chicago: The University Other Writings on History and Politics. Edited by Christopher Kelly. The
of Chicago Press. Collected Writings of Rousseau, v. 11. Hanover, NH: Dartmouth Col-
MERCER, JONATHAN. 1995. “Anarchy and Identity.” International Organization 49 lege Press.
(2): 229–52. SCHEUERMAN, WILLIAM E. 2011. The Realist Case for Global Reform. Cambridge:
MIROWSKI, PHILIP. 2013. “Realism Conservatism and Neoliberalism: From Re- Polity Press.
actionary Modernism to Postwar Conservatism.” In The Invention of In- SCHMIDT, BRIAN C. 2008. “Political Science and the American Em-
ternational Relations Theory: Realism, the Rockefeller Foundation, and the pire: A Disciplinary History of the ‘Politics’ Section and the Dis-
1954 Conference on Theory, edited by Nicolas Guilhot, 210–38. New York: course of Imperialism and Colonialism.” International Politics 45 (6):
Columbia University Press. 675–87.
MITZEN, JENNIFER. 2006. “Ontological Security in World Politics: State Identity ——— 2012. International Relations and the First Great Debate. New York: Rout-
and the Security Dilemma.” European Journal of International Relations ledge.
12 (3): 341. SCHMITT, CARL. 2003. The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus
———. 2013. Power in Concert: The Nineteenth-Century Origins of Global Gover- Publicum Europaeum. Edited by G. L. Ulmen. New York: Telos Press.
nance. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. SCHOUTEN, PEER. 2014. “Theory Talk #66: Alexander Dugin.” Theory Talks. De-
———. 2015. “Illusion or Intention? Talking Grand Strategy into existence.” cember 7. http://www.theory-talks.org/2014/12/theory-talk-66.html.
Security Studies 24 (1): 61–94. Accessed 7 November 2017.
MORGENTHAU, HANS J. 1948. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and SCHROEDER, PAUL W. 1962. Metternich’s Diplomacy at Its Zenith, 1820–1823.
Peace. New York: Knopf. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press.
———. 2004. Political Theory and International Affairs: Hans J. Morgenthau on ——— 1994. The Transformation of European Politics, 1763–1848. Oxford His-
Aristotle’s The Politics. Edited by Anthony F. Lang, Jr. Greenwood Pub- tory of Modern Europe. Oxford: Clarendon and Oxford University
lishing Group. Press.
MOUFFE, CHANTAL. 1993. The Return of the Political. New York: Verso. SCHWELLER, RANDALL L. 1998. Deadly Imbalances: Tripolarity and Hitler’s Strategy
MOUFFE, CHANTAL, ed. 1999. The Challenge of Carl Schmitt. New York: Verso. of World Conquest. New York: Columbia University Press.
MOUFFE, CHANTAL. 2005. The Democratic Paradox. New York: Verso. ——— 2014. Maxwell’s Demon and the Golden Apple. Baltimore, MD: Johns
———. 2007. “Carl Schmitt’s Warning on the Dangers of a Unipolar World.” Hopkins University Press.
In The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt. Edited by Louiza SETH, SANJAY. 2013. Postcolonial Theory and International Relations: A Critical In-
Odysseos and Fabio Petito, 147–53. London: Routledge. troduction. London: Routledge.
MÜLLER, JAN-WERNER. 2016. What Is Populism? Philadelphia, PA: University of SHAPIRO, JACOB N., AND C. CHRISTINE FAIR. 2010. “Understanding Sup-
Pennsylvania Press. port for Islamist Militancy in Pakistan.” International Security 34 (3):
MUSGRAVE, PAUL. 2017. “The Grim Fantasia of a Civilizational War.” Cato Un- 79–118.
bound. February 8. https://www.cato-unbound.org/2017/02/08/paul- SJOBERG, LAURA. 2006. Gender, Justice, and the Wars in Iraq: A Feminist Reformu-
musgrave/grim-fantasia-civilizational-war. Accessed 7 November 2017. lation of Just War Theory. Lanham, MD: Lexington.
NEACSU, MIHAELA. 2010. Hans J. Morgenthau’s Theory of International Relations: SKED, ALAN. 2008. Metternich and Austria: An Evaluation. New York: Palgrave
Disenchantment and Re-Enchantment. International Political Theory Se- Macmillan.
ries. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. SKOCPOL, THEDA. 2013. Diminished Democracy: From Membership to Management
NIEBUHR, REINHOLD. 2008. The Irony of American History. Chicago: The Univer- in American Civic Life. University of Oklahoma Press.
sity of Chicago Press. SKOCPOL, THEDA, AND VANESSA WILLIAMSON. 2012. The Tea Party and the Remaking
ODYSSEOS, LOUIZA, AND FABIO PETITO, eds. 2007. The International Political of Republican Conservatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal War and the Crisis of Global Order. SLANTCHEV, BRANISLAV L. 2005. “Territory and Commitment: The Concert
Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge. of Europe as Self-Enforcing Equilibrium.” Security Studies 14 (4):
PANGLE, THOMAS L., AND PETER J. AHRENSDORF. 1999. Justice among Nations: On 565–606.
the Moral Basis of Power and Peace. Lawrence, KS: University Press of SLAUGHTER, ANNE-MARIE. “Putting ‘America First’ Isn’t the Problem.
Kansas. Trump’s Version of It Is.” Washington Post, February 10, 2017, sec.
PARK, SAEYOUNG. 2017. “Long Live the Tributary System! The Future of Study- PostEverything. https://www.washingtonpost.com/posteverything/
ing East Asian Foreign Relations.” Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies 77 wp/2017/02/10/putting-america-first-isnt-the-problem-trumps-
(1): 1–20. version-of-it-is/.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018
JOSEPH MACKAY AND C H R I S T O P H E R D AV I D L A R O C H E 11

SNYDER, TIMOTHY. 2015. Black Earth: The Holocaust as History and Warning. New WEBER, MARTIN. 2014. “Between ‘isses’ and ‘oughts’: IR Constructivism, Criti-
York: Tim Duggan Books. cal Theory, and the Challenge of Political Philosophy.” European Journal
SPENGLER, OSWALD. 1991. The Decline of the West. Oxford: Oxford University of International Relations 20 (2): 516–43.
Press. WELCH, DAVID A. 2013. “Enemy Wanted: Apply Without.” E-International Rela-
STEFFEK, JENS. 2015. “Fascist Internationalism.” Millennium 44 (1): 3–22. tions. May 28. http://www.e-ir.info/2013/05/28/enemy-wanted-apply-
SUZUKI, SHOGO. 2009. Civilization and Empire: China and Japan’s Encounter with without/. Accessed 7 November 2017.
European International Society. London: Routledge. WELSH, JENNIFER M. 1995. Edmund Burke and International Relations: The Com-
THAKUR, VINEET, ALEXANDER E. DAVIS, AND PETER VALE. 2017. “Imperial Mission, monwealth of Europe and the Crusade against the French Revolution. St.
‘Scientific’ Method: An Alternative Account of the Origins of IR.” Mil- Antony’s/Macmillan Series. London: Macmillan Press.
lennium 46(1): 3–23. WIBBEN, ANNICK T. R. Feminist Security Studies: A Narrative Approach. London:
THOMPSON, NORMA. 2008. The Ship of the State: Statecraft and Politics from Ancient Routledge, 2011.
Greece to Democratic America. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. WIGHT, MARTIN. 1966. “Why Is There No International Theory?” In Diplomatic
TICKNER, J. ANN. 2006. “On the Frontlines or Sidelines of Knowledge and Investigations: Essays in the Theory of International Politics, edited by Her-
Power? Feminist Practices of Responsible Scholarship.” International bert Butterfield and Martin Wight, 17–34. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Studies Review 8 (3): 383–95. University Press.
TOFT, MONICA DUFFY. 2007. “Getting Religion? The Puzzling Case of Islam WILLIAMS, MICHAEL C. 2005a. The Realist Tradition and the Limits of International
and Civil War.” International Security 31 (4): 97–131. Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
TUATHAIL, GEARÓID Ó. 1996. Critical Geopolitics: The Politics of Writing Global ——— 2005b. “What Is the National Interest? The Neoconservative Chal-
Space. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. lenge in IR Theory.” European Journal of International Relations 11 (3):
TUATHAIL, GEARÓID Ó., SIMON DALBY, AND PAUL ROUTLEDGE, eds. 2006. The 307–37.
Geopolitics Reader. Second edition. New York: Routledge. WILLIAMSON, VANESSA. 2016. “What the Tea Party Tells Us about the Trump
TURNER, HENRY ASHBY. 1972. “Fascism and Modernization.” World Politics 24 Presidency.” Brookings (blog), November 9, https://www.brookings.
(4): 547–64. edu/blog/fixgov/2016/11/09/tea-party-and-trump-presidency/.
VICK, BRIAN E. 2014. The Congress of Vienna: Power and Politics after Napoleon. WOOD, GRAEME. 2017. “His Kampf.” The Atlantic, June. https://www.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2017/06/his-kampf/524505/.
VITALIS, ROBERT. 2015. White World Order, Black Power Politics: The Birth of Amer- Accessed 7 November 2017.
ican International Relations. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. WOODSIDE, ALEXANDER. 2009. Lost Modernities: China, Vietnam, Korea, and the
VUCETIC, SRDJAN. 2011. The Anglosphere: A Genealogy of a Racialized Iden- Hazards of World History. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
tity in International Relations. Stanford, CA: Stanford University ZHAO, TINGYANG. 2009. “A Political World Philosophy in Terms of All-under-
Press. Heaven (Tian-Xia).” Diogenes 56 (1): 5–18.
WALTZ, KENNETH N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. New York: McGraw- ZUCKERT, CATHERINE H., ed. 2011. Political Philosophy in the Twentieth Century:
Hill. Authors and Arguments. New York: Cambridge University Press.
WEBER, CYNTHIA. 1995. Simulating sovereignty: intervention, the state and Symbolic ZUCKERT, CATHERINE H. 2017. Machiavelli’s Politics. Chicago: The University of
Exchange. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Chicago Press.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/isq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/isq/sqx083/4951415


by guest
on 19 April 2018

You might also like