You are on page 1of 13

A Possible Explanation of Rousseau's General Will

Author(s): Patrick Riley


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 64, No. 1 (Mar., 1970), pp. 86-97
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1955615 .
Accessed: 12/11/2014 15:48

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Political Science Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
A POSSIBLE EXPLANATION OF ROUSSEAU'S GENERAL WILL
PATRICK RILEY
Harvard University

A "general will" is a philosophical and psy- glossed over by attempting to reduce the general
chological contradiction in terms; will is a con- will-as did T. H. Green-to a "common ego,"
ception understandable, if at all, only in terms or to an analogical forerunner of Kant's pure
of individual actions. The problem cannot be practical reason.2 Why, then, did Rousseau
make so unviable an idea the center of his polit-
N. B.: For the convenience of American readers, ical theory,3 and why has that idea continued
to
reference has been made whenever possible to a receive serious attention?
standardEnglish translation of Rousseau. All trans- The general will has continued to be taken
lations from French editions are my own. seriously because it is an attempted (though not
'This title was adopted not out of modesty, but explicit) amalgam of two extremely
important
simply because this article makes certain assump- traditions of political thought, which
Most may be
tions which are not universally agreed on. called, roughly, ancient "cohesiveness" and mod-
importantly, it holds that Rousseau understood ern "voluntarism." Political thought since
the
"will" not only as a psychological attribute but 17th century has been characterized,
among
also as a moral faculty; that there is an implicit other things, by voluntarism,
by an emphasis on
metaphysical dimension in Rousseau without which the assent of individuals as the
standard of po-
a concept such as "willing" would be incomplete. litical legitimacy.4 One certainly
finds this in
By treating the concept of volition in psychological many of the most important
thinkers between
rather than in metaphysical terms, however, Mrs. Hobbes and
Kant; and even Hegel, while
J. N. Shklar, in her persuasive Men and Citizens: scarcely an "atomistic
individualist" or a con-
A Study of Rousseau's Social Theory (Cambridge
tractarian, explicitly argued that while "in the
University Press, 1969) is able to make the general states of antiquity the
subjective end simply
will both internally consistent and closely related coincided with the state's
will," in modern times
to Rousseau's individual psychology. That is, by "we make claims for
private judgment, private
treating individual will as a defense-mechanism, willing, and
private conscience." When a politi-
and the general will as a collective defense-mechan- cal decision is to
be made, Hegel continued, "an
ism (used largely as a weapon against inequality,
'I will' must be pronounced by man himself."
whose effects for Shklar are mainly psychologically This "I will,"
he thought, must have an "ap-
destructive), she is able to make the general will propriate objective
existence" in the person of a
conceptuallyplausible. This reading,however, seems monarch; "in a
few) well-organized monarchy, the ob-
to involve a weakening of those (admittedly
jective aspect belongs to law alone, and the mon-
passages in which Rousseau speaks, in a traditional arch's part is
merely to set to the law the sub-
way, of volition as a moral faculty whose endorse-
jective 'I will'."5 If even Hegel allows this volun-
ment is the source of all moral legitimacy, e.g., "to tarist turn in his own
non-contractarian theory,
deprive your will of all freedom is to deprive your it goes without saying that all
of social contract
actions of all morality" ( Contrat Social, chapter theory can be seen
as the supreme example
IV). This idea is clearly the foundation of Rous-
seau's attack on paternalism and on the equation of 2 Green, T. H., Lectures on the Principles of

right and force. It is certainly possible to conceive Political Obligation. (Longmans, Green and Co.,
the "general will one has as a citizen" in a psycho- London, 1941), pp. 82 ff.
logical and metaphorical sense, if one imagines this 'Barth, Hans, "Volonte Generale et Volonte
"generality" in terms of factors wholly congruent Particuliere chez J.-J. Rousseau," in Rousseau et la
with psychology: education, public spectacles and Philosophie Politique, Annales de Philosophie Poli-
games, the authority of the legislator. But this can tique No. 5, (Presses Universitaires de France, Par-
never show how a will in anything but a psycholog- is, 1965), pp. 44 ff.
ical sense can be general, simply because the edu- 'Chapman, John, "Political Theory: Logical.
cation and authority congruent with psychology Structure and Enduring Types," in L'Idee de Philo-
are not congruent with a concept of free will and sophie Politique, Annales de Philosophie Politique
of moral choice. A psychological treatment of voli- No. 6, (Presses Universitaires de France, Paris,
tion does in fact hold out the best prospect of a 1965), pp. 65-69.
consistent treatment of Rousseau; but it also in- 'Hegel, G. W. F., Philosophy of Right, translated
volves a weakening of the voluntarist and contrac- T. M. Knox, Oxford University Press, London,
tarian elements of his philosophy. 1942, pp. 280, 288-289.
86

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1970 A POSSIBlLE EXPLANATION OF ROUSSEAU)S GENERAL WILL 87

of voluntaristic ideas. No theory, then, es- he wanted voluntarism to legitimize what he


caped the enthronement of will-quite liter- conceived to be the unity and cohesiveness-the
ally, in Hegel's case-at some point in the politi- generality-of ancient polity, particularly of
cal scheme. Why voluntarism, political legiti- Sparta and Rome. Indeed his political ideal was
macy through authorization by individual wills, the ancient polity, now willed by moderns who
came to hold such an important place in West- were as concerned with reasons for obligation as
ern thought, requires a book to itself, a history with perfect forms of government. Against the al-
of political will.6 What is probable is that an- leged atomism of earlier contract theory, Rous-
cient quasi-aesthetic theories of the best regime seau wanted the generality-the non-individual-
and the proper end of man gave way, with the ism, or rather the pre-individualism-of antiq-
introduction of Christianity, to thinking about uity to be legitimized by consent. Here of course
politics after the model of "good acts": just as he got himself into the paradox of insisting on
good acts required both knowledge of the good the willing of the essentially non-voluntaristic
and the will to do good, politics now required politics characteristic of antiquity. He got him-
moral assent, the implication of the individual in self, that is, into a philosophical paradox of
politics through his own volition. The freedom willed non-voluntarism; but if this paradoxical
to conform voluntarily to absolute standards concept, the general will, a will which is the
had always been important in Christian doc- corporate "will" of a whole society, a will to
trine; the Reformation doubtless strengthened stop being willful, cannot be philosophically de-
the element of individual choice in moral think- fended, it can at least be unravelled with inter-
ing, while downplaying the role of moral author- esting implications for all voluntaristic and per-
ity. And it was natural enough that the Protes- fectionist theories-not to mention democratic
tant view of individual moral autonomy and theories, which are always hard-pressed to fuse
responsibility should spill over from metaphysics what is wanted with what is intrinsically good.
into politics, forming the intellectual basis of And this treatment helps to clear up some of the
contract theory. The mere excellence of a social usually insoluble paradoxes in Rousseau, and to
institution would no longer be enough; it would make his thought clearer, if not less problemati-
now require rational assent. However voluntar- cal.
ism and contract theory arose, what is certain is
that ideas of the "good" state increasingly gave
way to ideas of the merely "legitimate" state. Jean-Jacques Rousseau was a severe critic of
And this legitimacy, after the 17th century, was modern political life-of its lack of a common
often taken to rest on will. morality and virtue, of its lack of patriotism
But while voluntarism took care of legiti- and civic religion, of its indulgence in "base"
macy, it could say nothing about the intrinsic philosophy and morally uninstructive arts.9 At
goodness of what is willed. It is, of course, possi- the same time, he was a great admirer of the
ble to assert that whatever is willed is right sim- more highly unified political systems of antiq-
ply because it is willed.8 But this was not uity, in which, as he thought, morality, civic
enough for Rousseau; and it was precisely here religion, patriotism, and a simple way of life had
that he made a stand for a particular kind of made men "one," wholly socialized and truly
will. He wanted will to take a particular form; political.'0 And he thought that modern political
'Plamenatz, John, "Equality of Opportunity," 'See particularly Rousseau, J.-J., Discourse on
in Aspects of Human Equality, edited L. Bryson, the Arts and Sciences, translated G. D. H. Cole,
(Harper and Bros., New York, 1957), pp. 79-107. (E. P. Dutton and Co., New York, 1950), pp. 172-
7Jouvenel, Bertrand de, Sovereignty, translated 174; Rousseau, J.-J., Gouvernement de Pologne
by J. Huntington, (University of Chicago Press, in Political Writings, edited C. E. Vaughan, (Basil
Chicago, 1957), various passages. Blackwell, Oxford, 1962), Vol. II, pp. 430, 437-438;
8Leibniz accused Hobbes and Pufendorf of ad- Rousseau, J.-J., Disease on Inequality, translated
hering to this view. "To say stat pro ratione volun- G. D. H. Cole, (E. P. Dutton and Co., New York,
tas, my will takes the place of reason," Leibniz 1950), pp. 247 ff., 266 ff.; Rousseau, J.-J., Lgttre a
observed, "is properly the motto of a tyrant." He M. d'Alembert, critical edition of M. Fuchs, (Li-
traced this line of thought back to Thrasymachus brairie Droz, Geneva, 1948) (entire).
' See particularly
in the Republic, and urged that Hobbes, "who is Rousseau, Gouvernement de
noted for his paradoxes, wanted to maintain nearly Pologne, op. cit., chapters II and III; Rousseau,
the same thing as Thrasymachus." See Leibniz, Discourse on the Arts and Sciences, op. cit., pp.
G. W., Meditation sur la Notion Commune de la 153-158; Rousseau, J.-J., Economie Politique in
Justice, edited G. Mollat, Verlag J. H. Robolsky, Political Writings, edited Vaughan, op. cit., Vol. I,
Leipzig, 1885, pp. 56 ff. pp. 253-254; Rousseau, J.-J., Rome et Sparte, in

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
88 THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEW VOL. 64

life divided man against himself, leaving him, Above all, the imperfect socialization of mod-
with all his merely private and anti-social inter- em man, in Rousseau's view, allowed private
ests, half in and half out of political society, en- persons and corporate interests to control other
joying neither the amoral independence of na- private persons, leading to extreme inequality
ture nor the moral elevation afforded by true and personal dependence; only generality of
socialization." laws based on an idea of common good, he
Why Rousseau thought the unified ancient thought, could abolish all private dependence,
political systems preferable to modern ones is which was for him, perhaps, the supreme social
not too hard to understand. He conceived the evil. What he wanted was that socialized men
difference between natural man and political might be "perfectly independent of all the rest,
man in very sharp terms; while for most con- and extremely dependent on the city,"15 for only
tract theory political life was merely non-na- the power of the state, and the generality of its
tural (and this largely to do away with argu- laws, "constitutes the liberty of its
ments for natural political authority), for members."16
Rousseau it was positively unnatural, or anti-nat- Ancient polities such as Sparta, Rousseau
ural, a complete transformation of the natural thought, with their simplicity, morality (or poli-
man. The political man must be deprived of his tics) of the common good, civic religion, moral
natural powers and given others, "which are for- use of fine and military arts, and lack of ex-
eign to him and which he cannot use without treme individualism and private interest, had
the help of others"; politics reaches a peak of been political societies in the proper sense: in
perfection when natural powers are completely them man was "part of a larger whole" from
dead and extinguished, and man is given a "par- which he "in a sense receives his life and
tial and corporate existence."12 The defect of being."1 Modern "prejudices," "base philoso-
modern politics, in Rousseau's view, was that it phy," and "passions of petty self-interest," on
was insufficiently political; it compromised be- the other hand, assure that "we moderns can no
tween the utter artificiality and commonality of longer find in ourselves anything of that spiri-
political life and the naturalness and indepen- tual vigor which was inspired in the ancients by
dence of pre-political life, and in so doing caused everything they did" (Gouvernement de
the greatest misfortunes of modern man: self-di- Pologne).18 And this spiritual vigor may be
vision, conflict between private will and the taken to mean the avoidance (through identity
common good, a sense of being neither in one with a "greater whole") of "that dangerous dis-
condition nor another. "What makes human position which gives rise to all our vices,"'9
misery," Rousseau said in Le Bonheur Public, self-love. Political education in an extremely
"is the contradiction which exists between our unified state will "lead us out of ourselves" be-
situation and our desires, between our duties fore the human ego "has acquired that con-
and our inclinations, between nature and social temptible activity which absorbs all virtue and
institutions, between man and citizen."'13 To constitutes the life and being of little minds"
make man one, to make him as happy as he can (J.conomie Politique).20 It follows that the best
be, "give him entirely to the state, or leave him social institutions "are those best able to dena-
entirely to himself . . . but if you divide his ture man, to take away his absolute existence
heart, you will rip him apart; and do not imag- and to give him a relative one, and to carry
ine that the state can be happy, when all its the moi into the common unity" (I?mile).21
members suffer."'4 These social institutions, in ideal ancient poli-
ties, were always for Rousseau the creation of a
great legislator, a Numa or a Moses: they did
not develop and perfect themselves in political
Political Writings, edited Vaughan, op. cit., Vol. I
pp. 314-318; Shklar, J. N., "Rousseau's Two Mod- 15Rousseau, CS, op. cit., p. 58.
els: Sparta and the Age of Gold," Political Science 16Ibid.
Quarterly, Vol. LXXXI (March 1966), 25-51. "Ibid., p. 42.
11Rousseau, J.-J., Le Bonheur Public, in Political Rousseau, J.-J., Gouvernement de Pologne,
Writings, edited Vaughan, op. pit., vol. I pp. 325- translated F. Watkins, in Political Writings, op.
326. cit., pp. 166-167 (hereafter cited as Pologne).
' Rousseau, J.-J., Le Contrat Social, translated 19 Rousseau, J.-J., Jconomie Politique, translated

F. Watkins, in Political Writings, (Thomas Nelson G. D. H. Cole, (E. P. Dutton and Co., New York,
and Sons, Edinburgh, 1953), p. 42 (hereafter cited 1950), p. 308 (hereafter cited as 1c. Pol.).
as CS). 20Ibid.
Rousseau,
R Le Bonheur Public, op. cit., p. 326. Rousseau, J.-J., mile (excerpt), in Political
141bid. Writings, edited Vaughan, vol. II p. 145.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1970 A POSSIBLE EXPLANATION OF ROUSSEAU S GENERAL WILL 89

experience, but were "handed down" by the politically right. While for Hobbes and Locke
law-giver.22 the theory of obligation by consent is of central
But if Rousseau thought highly unified an- importance, for Rousseau it is not a complete
cient polity, and its political morality of com- political theory. Any political system "which
mon good, superior to modern fragmented poli- confines itself to mere obedience will find diffi-
tics, and its political morality of self-interest, at culty in getting itself obeyed. If it is good to
the same time he shared with modern individ- know how to deal with men as they are, it is
ualist thought the conviction that all political much better to make them what there is need
life was conventional and could be made obliga- that they should be" (Economie Politique).27
tory only through individual consent. He very That, in a word, was Rousseau's criticism of all
definitely thought that he had based political contract theory: it dealt too much with the
obligation and rightful political authority on form of obligation, with will as it is, and not
convention: "civil association is the most volun- enough with what one ought to be obligated to,
tary act in the world; since every individual is and with will as it might be.
born free and his own master, no one is able, on His criticism of Hobbes is based on this
any pretext whatsoever, to subject him without point. Hobbes had, indeed, established rightful
his consent."23 Indeed, the first four chapters of political authority on consent, rejecting paternal
the Contrat Social are devoted to refutations of authority and obligation based on either natural
erroneous theories of obligation and right (pa- or divine law; he had made law (and therefore
ternal authority, the "right of the strongest," morality) the command of an artificial "repre-
and obligation derived from slavery). "Since no sentative person" to whom subjects were "for-
man," Rousseau concluded, "has natural author- merly obliged" through transfer of natural
ity over his fellow men, and since might in no rights ( save self-defense) by consent.28 But
sense makes right, convention remains as the Hobbes had done nothing to cure the essential
basis of all legitimate authority among men."24 wrongness (in Rousseau's view) of modern poli-
And yet Rousseau was also clear that con- tics; private interest was rampant, and indeed
tract theory provides, in itself, little more than a paramount, in Hobbes' system (could one not
mere theory of political obligation. In the Lettres decide whether or not to risk one's life for the
de la Montagne (VI), speaking of contract and Hobbesian state?). The essential error of
consent, he said that a state is made one by the Hobbes, Rousseau thought, was to have read
union of its members; that this union is the back into the state of nature all the human
consequence of obligation; and that obligation vices which half-socialization had created, and
can follow only from convention. He admitted thus to see culturally-produced depravities as
that the foundation of obligation had divided "natural" and Hobbesian absolutism, rather
political theorists: "according to some, it is than the creation of a feeling of a common good,
force; according to others, paternal authority; as the remedy for these depravities. "The error
according to others, the will of God."25All theo- of Hobbes and of the philosophers," Rousseau
rists, he said, establish their own principle of ob- declared, "is to confound natural man with the
ligation and attack that of others. "I myself men they have before their eyes, and to carry
have not done otherwise," Rousseau declared, into one system a being who can subsist only in
"and, following the soundest element of those another" (L'E9tat de Guerre).29 Rousseau, who
who have discussed these matters, I have settled thought that a perfectly socialized state (like
on, as the foundation of the body politic, the Sparta) could elevate men, and turn them from
contract of its members." And he concluded by "stupid and limited animals" into moral and in-
asking, "what more certain foundation can obli- telligent beings,30 must have thought Hobbesian
gation among men have, than the free agree- politics incomplete, one "which confines itself to
ment of him who obliges himself ?"26 mere obedience," one which did not attempt to
One may suspect that for Rousseau, con- make men "what there is need that they should
tract theory was more a way of destroying be," but which, through a system of mere mu-
wrong theories of obligation and authority, than 27 Rousseau, Ec. Pol., p. 297.
of creating a comprehensive theory of what is ' Oakeshott, Michael, Rationalism in Politics,
' Rousseau, Pologne, pp. 163-165.
(Methuen and Co., London, 1962), pp. 258 ff.;
23 Rousseau, CS, p.
117. Oakshott, Michael, Introduction to Hobbes' Levia-
24 Ibid., p. 8.
than, (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1957), pp. XXXV-
25 Rousseau, J.-J. Lettres de la Montagne, in L.
Political Writings, edited Vaughan, vol. II pp. 199- ' Rousseau, J.-J., L'ttat de Guerre, in Political
200. Writings, edited Vaughan, vol. I p. 306.
26 Ibid. o Rousseau, CS, p. 20.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
90 THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEW VOL. 64

tual forbearance,31 did not undertake any im- common good morality, is not "obligatory" on
provement in political life. "Let it be asked," citizens, is not founded in right. It is true that
said Rousseau, "why morality is corrupted in Rousseau sometimes spoke as though ancient
proportion as minds are enlightened" ;32 Hobbes systems were constructed by mutual individual
might well have an enlightened view of obliga- consent; but he did not usually speak in those
tion (to the extent that he based it on consent), terms. Even though, for him, all political soci-
but he did nothing about the moral corruption ety, ancient or modern, is artificial in the sense
caused by "private interest" and "individual that it is not the original condition of man, con-
will." tract theory comprehends an additional element
Rousseau, then, held in his mind, at once, of artifice, namely the notion that a society
both the idea that the closely unified political must be created by the will of all its members.
systems of antiquity (as he idealized them) Rousseau rarely spoke as though ancient polity
were the most perfect kinds of polity, and the had been artificial in this sense; he usually said
notion that all political society is the conven- that ancient systems were created, not by con-
tional creation of individual wills through a so- tract, but by the genius of legislators like Moses
cial contract. Holding both these ideas created and Lycurgus. Moses, for example, "had the au-
problems, for while the need for consent to fun- dacity to create a body politic" out of "a swarm
damental principles of political society, for cre- of wretched fugitives"; he "gave them customs
ation of a mere political construct through "will and usages."34 Lycurgus "undertook to give in-
and artifice," are doctrines characteristic of stitutions" to Sparta; he "imposed on them an
what Michael Oakeshott has called the "idiom iron yoke" (Gouvernement de Pologne) .35 It is,
of individuality,"33 the ancient conception of a really, only in the Contrat Social that Rous-
highly unified and collective politics was depen- seau makes much reference to consent or con-
dent not only on a morality of the common tract in ancient politics; the usual emphasis (as
good quite foreign to any insistence on individ- in the 1conomie Politique and Gouvernement
ual will as the creator of society and as the basis de Pologne) is on great men, political education,
of obligation (and Rousseau sometimes recog- and the absence of a highly developed individual
nized this, particularly in the Rconomie Poli- Will.36

tique), but was also dependent on a view of po- One can say, moreover, if one wants to jux-
litical life as the highest, most all-embracing end tapose parts of Rousseau's thought to each other,
of man, and was, moreover, considered both na- that he made fundamental errors in analyz-
tural, and prior, ontologically if not chronologi- ing the unified spirit of ancient politics, by rec-
cally, to the independent existence of self-suffi- ognizing the desirable effects of a morality of the
cient men. Given the ancient view of the morality common good, without recognizing that the very
of the common good and the supreme impor- absence of a notion of individual will as supreme
tance and naturalness of political life, ancient had made that morality (and thereby that
thought had not had to create theories of politi- unity) possible. But, after all these things have
cal obligation (which are needed only when the been pointed out, it remains to be said that
duty to obey is in doubt); politics being the Rousseau was consistently clear that modern ca-
highest end of man, obligation was not a real lamities caused by self-interest must be avoided,
problem, and the task of the great legislator was and that the political systems created by ancient
not to show why men ought to obey, but merely legislators were better than any modern ones.
in what way-under which kind of regime-they Although it did not always occur to Rousseau
should do so. Legislation was the task of giving that both the merely self-interested will which
the most perfect form to an intrinsically valu- he hated, and the will necessary for consent to
able activity. conventional society, were part of the same
Rousseau, not being a systematic philosopher idiom of modern political thought, and perhaps
(as he often pointed out), never really recon- inseparable, he always thought that mere will, as
ciled the tensions between his theory of obliga- such, could never create a proper political soci-
tion, and his model of political perfection. If one ety. For him, then (whatever the confusions
wants to make Rousseau more consistent than over naturalness, will, or the presence or absence
he cared to be, one must admit that his ancient of either or both in any political idiom), the
ideal model, as the creation, not of a contractual problem of political theory, above all in the
relation of individual wills, but of a great legis- Contrat Social, became that of reconciling the
lator working with political education and a requirements of consent (which obligates) and
31 Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, p. 261. "Rousseau, Pologne, pp. 163-165.
"Rousseau, L'Atat de Guerre, p. 307. 85
Ibid.
' Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, pp. 249-251. ' Rousseau, Pc. Pol., pp. 293-311.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1970 A POSSIBLE EXPLANATION OF ROUSSEAU'S GENERAL WILL 91

perfect socialization (which makes men "one"); modes of political thought, to have common
men must somehow choose the politically per- good and individual will, which gives Rousseau's
fect, somehow will that complete socialization political thought that strange cast which some
which will preclude self-division. Will, though have thought contradictory, a vacillation be-
the basis of consent, cannot be left as it is in tween "individualism" and "collectivism," but
traditional contract theory, with no proper ob- which was not merely that. The problem for
ject. If it is true that it is the source of obliga- Rousseau was more specific and more subtle:
tion, it is also true that merely self-interested how one can obey only his own free will, the
will is the cause of everything Rousseau hated source of obligation, in society; how it is possible
in modern civilization.37 And perfect political to purify this will of mere private interest
forms, Whatever Rousseau might have said and selfishness, which create inequality, destroy
about their being "given," must now (in the virtue, and divide man against himself; how it
Contrat Social) be willed. is possible to insure that this individual will will
Setting all the contradictions and vacillations want only what the common good-preferably a
aside, then, there are two important elements in common good like that of ancient politics-re-
the two views that Rousseau held simulta- quires. It is really a problem of retaining will,
neously: first, that the importance of ancient but of making it more than mere will, so that
polity had to do with its unity and its common society will have a common good and a general
morality, and not with its relation, or lack of it, interest, as if it enjoyed a morality of the com-
to contract theory; second, that individual con- mon good-a morality which Rousseau some-
sent (whatever this might do to the "legiti- times recognized as the real foundation of an-
macy" of Sparta) is needed for obligation, which cient unity.
is needed because the state is conventional. It is Looked at from this point of view, all of the
impossible to make every element of Rousseau paradoxes and "problems" in Rousseau's theory
both consistent and true to the political princi- become comprehensible: why will must be re-
ple that he tried to establish: that will is not tained, and why it must be made "general";
enough, that perfect polity alone is not enough, how general laws will promote the common
that will must be united to perfection, and that good, but why not law, but legislative will, is
perfection must be the standard of what is final; why a great legislator can suggest perfect
willed. And this, perhaps, is the source of that political forms, and why he cannot merely im-
odd idea, general will: a fusion of the generality pose them. Above all, it is clear that this point
(unity, commonality) of antiquity with the will of view helps to explain the greatest paradox in
(consent, contract) of modernity. What makes all of Rousseau-that is, the paradox created by
Rousseau, without doubt, the most utopian of the fact that, in the original contractual situa-
all great political theorists, is his insistence that tion, the motives needed by individuals to relin-
even a perfect political system be willed by all quish particular will and self-interest, and to
subject to it. "Undoubtedly," he said, "there is a embrace a "general" will and the common good,
universal justice derived from reason alone; but cannot exist at the time the compact is made,
this justice, to be admitted among us, must be and can only be the result of the socialization
mutual . . . conventions and laws are necessary, and common morality that society alone can
therefore, to unite rights with duties, and to ac- create.40 It is certain that if either an ideal of
complish the purposes of justice."38 Though social perfection (Sparta), or a notion of con-
"that which is good and conformable to order is ventional society created by mere will, were
such by the nature of things, independent of enough for Rousseau, he never would have in-
human conventions,"39 those conventions are yet sisted on a combination of will and perfect so-
required. cialization, on a general will. There would, in
Rousseau's political thought is a noble at- fact, be no paradox at all, if perfection were
tempt to unite the best elements of contract only a formal question, if the state were
theory, of individual consent, with his perfect, founded on a morality of the common good and
unified ancient models, which, being founded on obligation were not a central problem. A great
a morality of common good, had no private wills legislator, like Moses or Lycurgus, could create
to "reconcile" to the common interest (which the best forms, and obedience would be only a
was natural), and thus no need of consent, no question of correspondence to a system natur-
need of contract. It is this (perhaps unconscious ally and rationally right. But Rousseau said that
and certainly unsystematic) attempt to fuse two a new-born people must, in order to will good
laws, be able to "appreciate sound political prin-
7Ibid.,pp. 307-309.
' 4 Ibid., p. 44. Cf. Rousseau, J.-J., Des Lois, in
Rousseau, CS, pp. 37-38.
S Ibid, p. 37. Political Writings, edited Vaughan, vol. I p. 331.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
92 THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEW VOL. 64

ciples" ;41 these cannot be merely given to them, society "may be said to have reached the high-
but must be willed. Why is it that "the social est attainable peak of perfection."46 It is only,
consciousness to be created by the new institu- in other words (keeping in mind which societies
tions would have to preside over the establish- had attained peaks of perfection), when society
ment of those same institutions,"42 unless, some- is much like highly unified ancient society, that
how, the people must understand and will the "perfection" is reached; it is only "in so far as
system? There would be no paradox of cause several men conjoined consider themselves as a
and effect (the central problem of sound poli- single body"47 that a general will can operate.
tics) in Rousseau if men did not have both to This transformed society must be governed
will, and to will a perfection which presupposes on the basis of common interest (which has be-
(on Rousseau's own terms) a transcendence of come something more than traditional common
mere will, and the attainment of all the advan- "interest"); only general laws, the creation of a
tages of a morality of the common good, with- general will (sovereignty), can govern the com-
out actually having that morality, which would mon interest.48 Laws must be perfectly general,
destroy obligation. because the general will which makes them
It remains to show that the attempted fusion "loses its natural rectitude when directed toward
of individual will and common-good morality is any individual and determinate object."49 The
comprehended in the notion of the general will. sovereign (the people when "active," when will-
ing fundamental law) must, of course, make
II such law: "the people subject to the laws should
Rousseau begins the Contrat Social, not with be their author; only those who are forming an
the conception of general will, but with a fairly association have the right to determine the con-
traditional contractarian view of the origin of ditions of that society."50 But, if fundamental
society. Men being naturally (if not by law is the creation of a general will, how does
nature) 43 perfectly independent and society such a will come about? It cannot be the sum of
made necessary only by the introduction of individual wills, for "the particular will tends by
property (and the consequences of this intro- its nature to partiality,"51 and this, clearly, has
duction), men unite by contract to preserve been the source of modern "calamities." Law
themselves and their property. In this conven- must be willed by those subject to it, for will is
tional society, there is an area of common inter- the source of obligation. Yet mere wills can
est, "for if the opposition of private interests never yield generality, and law must be per-
made the establishment of societies necessary, it fectly general, which can happen only "when the
is the agreement of these same interests that whole people legislates for the whole people."52
made it possible."44 It is "what these several in- If general laws alone, composed with a view to
terests have in common," says Rousseau, "that the common good, were enough, there would be
constitutes the social bond." It is only on the no problem; but even the most general laws
"basis of this common interest that society must must be willed. How can a self-interested multi-
be governed."45 tude "by itself execute so great and difficult a
Rousseau does not talk in these rationalistic, project as a system of legislation?"53 How can a
contractarian terms for very long. Soon enough genuine general will, which will create general
it turns out that society's "common interest" is "conditions" for society, arise?
not merely what a lot of private interests have It is on this point that Rousseau is weak, un-
in common: society, when it is perfect, is a characteristically weak; he is always able to say
complete transformation of these private inter- what a general will must exclude, but he cannot
ests; it is only when "each citizen is nothing, say what it is. And this should come as no sur-
and can do nothing, without all the rest," that prise. For, strictly speaking, the idea of general
will is an impossibility; the ideas of generality,
"Ibid. (CS).
and of will, are mutually exclusive. Will, what-
42Ibid.
ever its crudity as a psychological construct, is
43 Since, for Rousseau, the pre-social man is a
characteristically a concept of individuality, of
"stupid and limited animal," and becomes a moral ' Ibid, p. 42.
and intelligent being only in society, there is a 47 Ibid., p. 113.
sense in which man's highest nature (rather than 4 Ibid., pp. 26, 29-30, 38-40.
original nature) is social. Cf. Rousseau, J.-J., Le'ttre 49 Ibid., p. 32.
a Al. Philopolis, in Political Writings, edited by ' Ibid., p. 40.
51 Ibid., p. 25.
Vaughan, vol. I, p. 223.
52 Ibid., p. 38.
4 Rousseau, CS, p. 25.
4rb 7bid. - Ibid., p. 40.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1970 A POSSIBLE EXPLANATION OF ROUSSEAU'S GENERAL WILL 93

particularity, and it is only metaphorically that tion and legislation, is set forth, with little or no
one can speak of will as "general." No act of reference to consent or to will.58
philosophic imagination can conjure up anything But, much of the time, and particularly in
but a personal will. What can be imagined (and the Contrat Social, Rousseau speaks not in the
what, in any case, Rousseau admired in ancient idiom of the common good, but of a tension be-
society), is not really a "general" will, but a po- tween particular will and general will, and of rec-
litical morality of common good, in which indi- onciling these wills.69 Indeed, the whole concept
vidual will is, to be sure, not suppressed, but of political virtue is entirely tied up with this
simply does not appear in contradistinction to, reconciliation of wills, as Rousseau demonstrates
or with claims or rights against, society. What in the h'conomie Politique. There he says that
gave ancient polity (particularly in theory) its the "first and most important rule of legitimate
unity was not the concurrence of many wills on or popular government" is "to follow in every-
central points of common interest; rather a thing the general will," but that, in order to fol-
moral idiom in which extreme socialization was low the general will it must be known, and
natural, and in which there was little notion of clearly distinguished from individual or particu-
"will and artifice," gave rise to this unity. lar will, and that "this distinction is always very
There are a number of revealing passages in difficult to make, and only the most sublime vir-
which Rousseau observes that something like a tue can affordsufficientilluminationfor it."60 A
political morality of common good, rather than few pages later, he says that "if you would have
a general will, is necessary for the unity and the general will accomplished, bring all particular
commonality which he desires-for example, at wills into conformity with it; in other words, as
the end of Book II of the Contrat Social, where virtue is nothing more than the conformity of
he discusses "the most important of all" laws, the particular wills with the general will, estab-
"which preserves the people in the spirit of its lish the reign of virtue."6' Is it not clear that
original institutions," that is, "manners, morals, the argument is circular?-that conformity of
customs and, above all, public opinion . . . a fac- particular to general will creates virtue, and
tor with which the great legislator is secretly that virtue is necessary to bring particular will
concerned when he seems to be thinking only of into conformity with general will? This circular-
particular regulations."54 Here Rousseau does ity is not due to the fact that Rousseau had no
not, of course, speak of consent or will, but of a clear conception of virtue; on the contrary, an-
kind of political education which will promote a cient politics were models of virtue, as he de-
common good. scribed them.62 The circularity is caused by
And he gave other indications that he knew trying to make virtue as unity, as commonality,
that unity was the consequence of thinking dependent on reconciliation of particular to gen-
about political relations in terms of a common eral will, whereas in fact (and as Rousseau rec-
good, rather than in terms of "cancelling out" of ognizes on adjoining pages of the same treatise),
private wills "all the mutually destructive pluses virtue as conformity to a common good morality
and minuses," so that a "general will remains as is the creation of great legislation and political
the sum of the differences."55 Indeed, in the education. Vacillation on the true source of an-
J9conomie Politique he said that if men "were cient unity and commonality (reconciliation of
early accustomed to regard their individuality wills, or absence of will), is the cause of the cir-
only in its relation to the body of the state, and cularity of the concept of virtue in Rousseau;
to be aware, so to speak, of their own existence moreover, this circularity reflects the same kind
merely as a part of that of the state, they might of cause-effect paradox as that referred to at the
at length come to identify themselves in some end of part I. In both cases, Rousseau knows
degree with this greater whole. ..."56 If chil- perfectly well what he admires: the virtue of
dren are educated in state laws which promote ancient society, and the perfection of laws in an-
only a common good and a common morality, cient society. It is only when, in both cases, he
"they will learn to cherish one another mutually tries to describe the possibility of these attrib-
as brothers, to will nothing contrary to the will
'Rousseau, Pologne, chapters II-IV; Rousseau,
of society."57 There are similar passages in the
J.-J. Projet pour la Corse, translated F. Watkins,
Gouvernement de Pologne, and in the Projet
in Political Writings, p. 300.
pour la Corse, in which the idea of a morality of ' Rousseau, CS, pp. 40-41.
the common good, reinforced by political educa- 60 Rousseau, 12c. Pol., p. 293.

54Ibid., P. 58.
61 Ibid., p. 298.
mIbid., p. 29. 62Rousseau,Pologne, chapters II-III; Rousseau,
5 Rousseau, Pc. Pol., pp. 307-308. Rome et Sparte, in Political Writings, edited
I1bid., p. 309. Vaughan, vol. I pp. 314-320.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
94 THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEW VOL. 64

utes in terms of reconciled will that he falls trying (however unsystematically) to reconcile
down. Nor is this surprising; for, as has been will and perfect socialization, these problems
noted, he did, sometimes, recognize that the ab- could not exist: the new state could not be con-
sence of the very notion that caused all his sidered a fictitious being (for it would educate
problems-will as supreme-had constituted the men to think something different); one would
greatness of antiquity. All the paradoxes, circu- not think of his political role as a "contribution"
larities and vacillations in Rousseau are caused (because one would be naturally part of a
by the attempted fusion of moral-political idi- greater whole); and there would be no conflict
oms which are incompatible on fundamental between man and citizen (because the distinc-
points. tion would not exist). Is not the paradox that a
A clear illustration of just this point is Rous- man must be "forced to be free"67 if his particu-
seau's treatment of Brutus in the Histoire des lar will does not conform to the general will an
Moeurs; in that fragment Rousseau, observing indication that Rousseau tried to gain the ad-
that "it will always be great and difficult to sub- vantages of a common-good morality (particu-
mit the dearest affections of nature to country larly in the Contrat Social) through reconcili-
and virtue."63 cites Brutus' execution of his ation of wills, and this only because will is nec-
treasonous sons as an example of this "submis- essary to obligation?
sion," not ever mentioning that this was no case There is, finally, in Rousseau's most system-
of "submitting" particular will to a general will, atic political work (the Contrat Social), no pos-
but (more likely) a case of a common-good mo- tulation of a political morality of the common
rality (coupled with the rights of the Roman good as the source of the much-desired unity.
pater familias) at work. Yet in other works Rather, there is a constant attempt to bring
written at about the same time, he makes no particular will into conformity with general will
reference to submission of will in Roman soci- through the efforts of a "great legislator." What
ety, and talks only of legislation and political the great legislator, in his wisdom, knows to be
education.64 good, supplies the absence of a common-good
Nonetheless (and despite these vacillations), morality. Now, the difference between the great
it is easy to see why a fusion of political idioms legislator of ancient politics and Rousseau's ideal
was attempted. For even though perfect social- legislator, corresponds exactly to the difference
ization was Rousseau's ultimate ideal, consent between giving a presupposed unity (without
and will, as the source of obligation, were too strong will) a perfect form (antiquity), and
important to be summarily discarded. Thus the making people will perfect forms (modernity).
general will, though an impossibility, was a ne- "All" in the contractual period "stand equally in
cessity. need of guidance."68 Individuals "must be
"Actually," said Rousseau, "each individual obliged to bring their wills into conformity with
may, as a man, have a private will contrary to, their reason," that is, they must will that which
or divergent from, the general will he has as a is, in itself, rationally best. The combination of
citizen" (Contrat Social).65 This could not, of individual consent and the legislator's guidance
course, be the case in a state with a common- "will effect a union of understanding and will
good morality reinforced by legislation and edu- within the social body."69 And what is rationally
cation (the system sketched in the JZconomie best (to avoid that self-division caused by half-
Politique). The passage cited from the Contrat socialization) is the perfectly united and com-
Social shows that in that work, the most "con- munal polity of antiquity. The legislator, who
tractarian" of Rousseau's writings, and the clos- effects the bringing of will into conformity with
est thing he had to a systematic political theory, reason (not by force, but through persuasion
neither mere will nor perfection wins out alone. and religious devices), supplies the defect of
For in the Contrat Social, there is the possibility common-good morality, and simply gets each in-
that a private person (already a concept of dividual to will something like the laws which
modern individualism) may regard "the artifi- would have resulted from such a morality. What
cial person of the state as a fictitious being," Rousseau ultimately has, then, is not a "general
and that this "may make him envisage his debt will" (which is inconceivable), but a "will to the
to the common cause as a gratuitous contribu- general," which is conceivable if one recalls that
tion."66 It seems clear that if Rousseau were not political perfection requires both truly general
laws and consent to them. Rousseau did not,
"Rousseau, J.-J., Histoire des Moeurs, in Politi- could not, abolish will-but he prescribed the
cal Writings, edited Vaughan, vol. I p. 337.
4Rousseau, Ec. Pol., pp. 302-310. "'Ibid.
" Rousseau, CS, pp. 18-19. a Ibid., p. 40.
' Ibid., p. 19. ` Ibid.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1970 A POSSIBLE EXPLANATION OF ROUSSEAU'S GENERAL WILL 95

form that it must take, and this form is clearly will, rather than law itself, is supreme, and that
derived from the generality and unity of ancient the entire social system can be abolished by will,
polity (as Rousseau saw it)-but without a mo- for "there is not, and cannot be, any sort of
rality of common good, which would have de- fundamental law binding on the body of the
stroyed obligation. people, not even the social contract."72
Moreover, not only the form of laws (gener- The theory of Rousseau, then, ultimately re-
ality) is derived from ancient models; the con- duces itself to two elements: the need for a
ditions under which good laws (and indeed good great legislator to create a "general will," and
states) are possible, are little more than ideali- the extreme limitations put on this legislator by
zations of ancient political circumstances. A peo- the fact that this general will, though (of
ple is "fit for legislation," according to Rous- course) general, is still will, and must be will.
seau, if it has no old laws, if it is free from Both elements are the consequence of attempt-
threats of invasion and can resist its neighbors, ing to unite all the requirements of will with all
if it is small enough that its "individual mem- the advantages of perfect socialization. The leg-
bers can all know one another," if it can get islator may formulate and propose general laws
along without other peoples, if it is "neither which will produce perfect socialization., and he
very rich nor very poor," and can be self-suffi- can get them "willed" through religious devices;
cient, and if it is one which "combines the firm- but the sovereign cannot be permanently bound,
ness of an old people with the docility of a new even by perfect laws, and can change these
one."70 Clearly most of these conditions of the laws and even dissolve society. Thus neither
possibility for good polity are abstracted from perfection nor will has all the claims in Rous-
Rousseau's idealized version of ancient city- seau; but will can finally be, even if only in a
states, particularly Sparta. Not only the form of destructive way, triumphant, for if a people "is
a good political system, then, but also the em- pleased to do itself harm, who has a right to
pirical conditions which could make such a sys- prevent it from doing so?"73
tem possible, are derived from Rousseau's mod- It is not meant, by analyzing Rousseau in
els of perfection. this way, that he was always perfectly consis-
What has been said thus far may be summa- tent in desiring that particular wills should con-
rized in this way: 1) a perfect state (that is, a sent to that which an ancient morality of com-
perfectly socialized, united and communal state) mon good would require; indeed, he vacillated
would have perfectly general laws (that is, laws on several points, notably in his treatment of
dealing only with Rousseau's vision of a com- civil religion, in which he allowed any tolerant
mon good); 2) but laws, especially the most sect to exist, so long as it did not claim exclusive
general laws, must be willed by everyone subject truth or refuse to subscribe to the basic articles
to those laws, in order to be obligatory-and of civic religious policy.74 Above all, though,
they must be made obligatory, for society is Rousseau insisted that each socialized man
merely conventional; 3) therefore, will must should somehow "obey no one but himself," and
take the form of general laws; 4) but will tends thought he had found a solution to this prob-
to the particular, and law, though the creation lem in making the conditions of society (laws)
of will, must somehow be general; 5) moreover, perfectly general and equally applicable to all,
for particular wills to appreciate the necessity of so that, the conditions being equal for all, and
general laws, effect would have to become willed by all, "it is in the interest of no one to
cause; 6) therefore, a great legislator, whose in- make [social requirements] burdensome to the
struction can supply the defect of a morality of rest,"75 and that, since the society cannot wish
the common good-the only morality which to hurt all its members by enacting bad general
would naturally produce general laws-is neces- laws, society need offer its members no
sary; 7) but this legislator is impossibly rare, guarantees.76 But this system is essentially mod-
and, in addition, he cannot create laws, however ified by the fact that a will to general laws abso-
general and good, for sovereignty is inalien- lutely cannot be attained with mere wills as
able; 8) thus the legislator must have recourse they are (the cause-effect problem again), but
to religion, and use it to gain the consent of in- only through the influence of a great legislator;
dividuals to the general will; 9) but now "con- by Rousseau's assertion that there is no real
sent" is something less than real consent, since limit to the extent of undertakings possi-
an irrational device has been used; 10) finally,
the whole system is saved for individual will by 72
Ibid., pp. 17-18.
the fact that "a people always has a right to
73 Ibid., p. 57.
change its laws, even the best,"'71that legislative
74 Ibid., pp. 152-155.
7Ibid., pp. 53-54. 7 Ibid., p. 15.
r Ibid., p. 57. 76 Ibid., p. 18.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
96 THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEW VOL. 64

ble between the sovereign and its members;77 some have imagined.81 For legislative will, and
by the idea that the sovereign is the sole judge not law itself, is supreme in Rousseau. Nor can
of how many "powers" of individuals must be Rousseau be easily assimilated to the German
socialized;78 and by the notion that an ideal so- "romantic" tradition of the early 19th century,
ciety should be very highly socialized indeed. It because he would never have replaced general
is modified above all by part IV, chapter II of will with the historical evolution of national
the Contrat Social, which shows, perhaps more spirits; he was clear that history, in itself, can-
clearly than anything in Rousseau, that consent not "justify" anything.82 This non-assimilability
is no longer to be a question of mere volition, to other traditions proves that those who view
and that the general will is something like a Rousseau as a unique and isolated figure are
modified common-good morality. probably correct; he was, in his own words, one
of those few "moderns who had an ancient
The constant will of all the members of the state soul."83
is the general will; that is what makes them citizens
and free. When a law is proposed in the assembly III
of the people, what the voters are being asked is The only object of this study has been to elu-
not precisely whether they do or do not approve cidate the concept of the general will, and to
of the proposal, but whether or not it is in con- clear up some of the paradoxes in the Contrat
formity with the general will, which is their own.Social, by analyzing what Rousseau thought
Each, when casting his vote, gives his opinion on about will and contract, on the one hand, and
this question; and the declaration of the general about perfect political systems, on the other. It
will is found by counting the ballots. Thus when has not been a central object to attack Rousseau
an opinion contrary to my own prevails, this proves
as unsystematic, to reproach him for not ade-
nothing more than that I was mistaken, and that quately reconciling two modes of political
what I though to be the general will was not.79 thought, or to "improve" his ideas by making
them more consistent. No series of conceptual
The meaning of this (usually confusing) pas- ambiguities can detract anything from Rous-
sage can be understood if "common good" be seau's status as the greatest of political psychol-
substituted for "general will"; then it can be ogists and the most eloquent critic of the psy-
seen how general will is constant will, and how chological destruction wrought by inequality.
citizens are not being asked whether they ap- Nonetheless, it is evident that there is an insur-
prove a proposal, but whether it is in confor- mountable conceptual problem in Rousseau's po-
mity with a common good. litical thought, and it is this: voluntarist theo-
ries are usually composed of two parts, a theory
With all of these modifications in mind, it is of will as a moral agency, and a theoretical
clear that, while Rousseau's theory of society standard of right to which will ought to conform
and law really is, as he insisted, an attempt to (arbitrary willfulness usually being rejected as a
preserve liberty, that liberty is conceived in an standard of right). In Locke or in Kant, the
odd way: it is "obedience to self-imposed law"80 standard of right to which will must conform
(which must, of course, be general law). Lib- (natural law in the first case, universal rational
erty, then, comes down to freeing the individual law in the second) does not contradict voluntar-
of all private dependence by making him "very ism (once one gets around the problem of recon-
dependent on the city" and its general and ciling free will and absolute standards: in itself
equally-applied laws. But, though liberty is a problem which defeated a Leibniz and reduced
obedience to self-imposed law, proper law cannot Kant to hypotheses). But in Rousseau the stan-
be created without modification of will by a dard to which will must conform (ancient per-
great legislator, and thus the very idea of lib- fection, or its equivalent) is itself non-voluntar-
erty is, like other elements of Rousseau, a fu- istic; and therefore will and the standard to
sion of the idioms of individual will and of which it must conform are contradictory. The
highly unified society. It is because of these standard which gives will its object is the very
modifications that Rousseau's political theory 81Cassirer, Ernst, Rousseau, Kant and Goethe,
cannot be so easily assimilated to traditional
translated Gutmann, Kristeller and Randall, (Har-
constitutionalism, or to Kant's theory of law, as
per Torchbacks, New York, 1963), pp. 30 ff.
82Rousseau, J.-J., Premiere Version du Contrat
"Ibid., P. 33. Social, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, vol.
.8blid., p. 31. Ip.462.
"Ibid., pp. 117-118. 83Rousseau, J.-J., Jugement sur la Polysynodie,
8?Ibid., p. 20. in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, vol. I p. 421.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1970 A POSSIBLE EXPLANATION OF ROUSSEAU S GENERAL WILL 97

negation of voluntarism. And it is for this rea- teacher.86 How much more, then, do ordinary
son that Rousseau's political system is somewhat men need the guidance of a great legislator
paradoxical. The idea of general will, the para- when they embark on the setting up of a system
dox of cause and effect in the contractual situa- which will not only aid and defend, but also
tion, the circularity of the concept of virtue-all moralize them! The relation of volition to au-
these are due to an attempt to fuse the advan- thority is one of the most difficult and one of
tages of a politics founded on will, and of one the most inscrutable problems in Rousseau; the
founded on reason and perfection. One must, general will is dependent on " a union of will
in Rousseau, will the kind of society in which and understanding within the social body,"87
one lives, because "to deprive your will of all but that understanding, which is provided by
freedom is to deprive your actions of all moral- authority, weakens the idea of will as an auton-
ity,"84 and this deprivation destroys the obliga- omous authorizing faculty.
tion one has to obey. Yet mere will can yield To project the question on a grander scale,
only particularity and inequality, and will never one can see in Rousseau's political thought an
produce rational perfection. To retain the moral intuitive attempt to reconcile the two greatest
attributes of will, but to do away with will's traditions of Western political philosophy, that
particularity and selfishness-that is the prob- of "will and artifice" and that of "reason and
lem of Rousseau's political thought. It is a prob- nature." (Oakeshott) For general will is
lem which reflects the difficulty which Rousseau surely rationalized will. And yet it is not self-ra-
found in making free-will and rational authority tionalized will in a Kantian sense, but will ra-
co-exist in his moral and political thinking. tionalized by the standards and conditions of
Freedom of the will is as important to the mo- idealized ancient polity.
rality of actions for Rousseau as for any tradi- Whatever Rousseau's means, in undertaking
tional voluntarist; but he was suspicious of the a fusion of two great modes of political thinking,
very faculty, the only faculty, which could and however unsuccessful the attempt to make
moralize. And that is why he urged, in the general will a viable conception, one must al-
Economic Politique, that "the most absolute au- ways, while analyzing and even criticizing the
thority is that which penetrates into a man's in- result, grant the grandeur and importance of the
most being, and concerns itself no less with his effort. For if one could succeed in having the
will than with his actions."85 Can the will be best of both idioms, one would have a political
both morally autonomous and subject to the ra- philosophy which would synthesize almost ev-
tionalizing influence of authority? That was the erything valued in the history of Western politi-
point which Rousseau never settled altogether. cal thought.
Even IRmile,the best-educated of men, chooses 'Rousseau, J.-J., Emile, translated B. Foxley,
to continue to accept the guidance of his (Everyman's Library, J. M. Dent and Sons, London
84Rousseau, CS, p. 9. 1911), p. 444.
85 Rousseau, 1c. Pol., p. 297.
' Rousseau, CS, p. 41.

This content downloaded from 206.246.21.145 on Wed, 12 Nov 2014 15:48:22 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like