You are on page 1of 32

Self-Disorder in Schizophrenia: A Revised View

(2. Theoretical Revision: Hyperreflexivity)

Running title: Self-Disorder in Schizophrenia: Revised View (2)

Louis Sass1,2, Jasper Feyaerts1*

1) Department of Psychoanalysis and Clinical Consulting, Faculty of Psychology and


Educational Sciences, Ghent University, Belgium
2) Graduate School of Applied and Professional Psychology, Rutgers, The State University
of New Jersey, United States

*Corresponding author: Prof Louis Sass, Dept of Clinical Psychology, Graduate School of
Applied and Professional Psychology, Rutgers University, 152 Frelinghuysen Road, Piscataway,
New Jersey, USA 08854. Telephone: 917 513-9798. Email: lsass@rutgers.edu.

word count: abstract (156), text body (6535)

0
Abstract

A growing body of research supports the role of self-disorders as core phenotypic features of

schizophrenia-spectrum conditions. Self-disorders comprise various alterations of conscious

experience whose theoretical understanding continues to present a challenge. This is the second

of two articles that aim to clarify the nature of self-disorders in schizophrenia by considering the

currently most influential, phenomenological model of schizophrenia: the basic-self-disturbance

or ipseity-disorder model (IDM). The previous paper (article 1) presented a state-of-the-art

overview of this model and critically assessed its descriptive adequacy with respect to the

clinical heterogeneity and variability of the alterations in self- and world-awareness

characteristic of schizophrenia. This paper (article 2) proposes a theoretical revision by

considering how hyperreflexivity might form the crucial common thread or generating factor that

unifies the heterogeneous, and sometimes even contradictory features of schizophrenic self-

disorders. We outline implications of our revised model (IDMrevised) for explanatory research,

therapeutic practice, and our general understanding of the abnormalities in question.

keywords: self-disorder; schizophrenia; basic-self-disturbance model; ipseity-disorder model;

hyperreflexivity; revision.

1
Introduction

In our first article, we drew attention to the substantial heterogeneity and variability that

characterize self-disorders in schizophrenia. We showed that alterations of self-experience can

involve not only the oft-noted diminished self-presence in which patients lose the sense of being

the subject or agent of their own experiences or actions, but also increased self-presence, as

when patients feel they are the sole constituting witness, central figure, or prime target of all that

occurs. We noted as well that the field of awareness—the lived world of objects, people, and

situations—can show up in opposite ways: either as lacking organization, as seeming

fragmented, random, and uncertain (decreased ‘grip’); but also as hyper-organized or hyper-

determined, often in a typically grandiose/paranoid manner, such that nothing seems accidental

and everything appears “just so” or as somehow oriented toward or referring to the patient

himself (increased ‘grip’).

These contradictory aspects may not only succeed each other but can sometimes even co-

exist. Their prominence clearly requires revision of the current self-disturbance or ipseity-

disturbance model (IDM)1-3, which specifies only diminished self-presence while also conceiving

‘disturbed grip’ only as diminished grip. In article 1, we suggested the broader notions of altered

self-presence and altered grip/hold, aimed at recognizing that both these dimensions of

awareness can vary toward either diminishment or exaggeration, and that such variation may

occur across subgroups of patients or phases of illness, but also as more moment-to-moment

dynamic shifts and/or combinations at the individual-patient level.

In this second article, our aim is to go beyond these more descriptive issues by focusing

on the theoretical question of how a revised IDM-model can account for these diverse

manifestations. According to the revised model we will propose, it is preferable to focus on what

2
the different manifestations of schizophrenic self-disorders may have in common rather than on

what they purportedly lack. More precisely, we will argue that what the diverse expressions of

schizophrenic self-disorders share is not best conceived as the absence of something that,

supposedly, is constantly present in normal or non-schizophrenic forms of experience—namely,

minimal self or self-presence. The shared factor is better conceived as the presence of something

abnormal, namely, hyperreflexivity, which involves distinct forms of alienation, detachment,

inwardness, and passivization. The self-disturbance model should be re-configured around the

concept of hyperreflexivity.

We will argue for this in two main ways. In the next section, we note difficulties inherent

to the concept of minimal or basic self as well as in its application to schizophrenic self-

disorders. Here we include a brief review of alternative proposals regarding the presumed

essence of self-disorders. In the next several sections, we explain how hyperreflexivity could

serve as a central common thread or generating factor able to unify—and in a sense, to explain 4

—the phenomenologically heterogeneous, and sometimes even contradictory, features of

schizophrenic self-disorders. In a final section, we discuss research and clinical implications of

our proposal.

Self-disorders as disorders of ‘minimal self’: A critical overview

In our previous article, we noted how alterations of self-experience in schizophrenia may

take on various forms and qualities. Beyond this heterogeneity and variability, a more general

challenge concerns how such alterations should best be conceived—comprising questions

regarding what kind, level, or aspect of ‘self’ is affected in self-disorders; in what sense it is

possible for core ‘selfhood’ to be considered disturbed; and whether a felt sense of self actually is

3
a (necessary or regular) feature of ordinary experience (for reviews, see 5-6; for various proposals,

see6-10). Here we provide a brief overview of these debates.

A first issue concerns the seeming contradiction between the supposedly ‘essential’ or

‘universal’ nature of minimal self in human consciousness and its proposed alteration or

disturbance in schizophrenic self-disorders. As discussed (cf. article 1), the IDM’s concept of

minimal self refers not to some contingent quality that only some experiences would possess, but

rather, to a structural dimension of consciousness that is considered a necessary or essential

feature of how all experiences are given to a subject—what phenomenological philosopher

Zahavi describes as a “first-personal character” or “what-it-is-like-for-me-ness”11-12.

On this conception, all human experience is intrinsically—and indeed necessarily—

characterized by first-personal givenness and an accompanying sense of mineness. One may

wonder, however, how this supposedly inalienable character of minimal self could be consistent

with the IDM’s account of self-disorders. How, or in what sense, could self-disorders involve a

disturbance of minimal self if the latter is also assumed to be necessarily preserved throughout

subjective life, indeed to persist as the necessary condition of consciousness itself?

Several responses to this problem have been offered.

One response7 consists of arguing that self-disorders do still involve a disturbance at the

level of minimal self, but that the latter would somehow be merely ‘eroded’ or ‘diminished’

instead of being entirely absent. This solution can seem rather ad-hoc (and in fact was proposed

only after problems with the original model were noted). It would seem, in any case, that such a

dimensional or quantitative understanding of mineness/for-me-ness runs counter to how minimal

self is actually defined and understood in the phenomenological literature (see 11-12; cf. article 1).

There the ‘mineness’ of experience is not established by reference to feelings of greater or lesser

4
intensity but argued for as a logical necessity; and it is difficult to see how it could allow of being

conceived in terms of degrees. As Henriksen et al. 7 point out, even for patients with severe self-

disorders, there is not (and on theoretical grounds, could not be) any relevant doubt about who is

experiencing their symptoms. “[E]ven the pathological experiences under consideration,” writes

Zahavi,11 “retain their mineness and for-me-ness,” their “first-personal character”.

Another common strategy to address this problem has been to introduce a finer

phenomenological distinction regarding the particular kind of ‘mineness,’ that is supposedly

eroded or disturbed in schizophrenic self-disorders. While various proposals exist (e.g. 13-14), the

most prominent distinguishes between the mineness of ‘ownership’ versus of ‘agency’, and

interprets self-disorders as lacking agency while preserving ownership.6

The main problem with this account is that many of our ordinary or somewhat

obsessional thoughts also come unbidden and without a sense of agency, simply crossing one’s

mind, and may even be experienced as imposed and intrusive, yet do not carry the sense or

quality of alienation as found in self-disorders. 15 There is also the fact that schizophrenic loss of

self can pertain not only to such activities as thinking or moving one’s arm—which do have an at

least potentially agentic quality—but also to states and feelings that would normally be passively

enjoyed or endured, such as emotions and sensations: What is altered in these latter experiences

would seem to pertain to possession rather than to agency.

It should be noted, as well, that even the underlying assumption—the idea that a

prereflective sense of self necessarily imbues ordinary conscious experience—is itself not

uncontested.16-18

Some theorists18-19 have, in fact, argued that pre-reflective experience is often and perhaps

typically transparent and impersonal, devoid of any form of self-awareness—as for example,

5
when we are fully immersed and unreflectively engaged in activities. Still others 20 propose a

more open view regarding pre-reflective consciousness, allowing for different shades or degrees

of self-awareness in diverse situations or activities (e.g., contrast the self-aware quality of social

anxiety with the mindless absorption of the long-distance driver). Both views (whether

emphasizing the supposed transparency or the supposed heterogeneity of normal self-experience)

would seem inconsistent with the notion that schizophrenic self-disorders involve loss of some

form of self-awareness presumed to be ubiquitous in non-schizophrenic forms of consciousness.

Hyperreflexivity as the central factor

We see, then, that there are problems with the notion of diminished minimal self as

currently formulated. Though clearly an important symptom, it is not a constant one nor can it

serve as a defining feature of schizophrenia. This is due not only to the importance of antithetical

forms of exaggerated self-presence or “for-me-ness” (cf. article 1), but also (as just noted) to

conceptual difficulties inherent in adapting a supposedly universal or transcendental notion to

capture empirical variations on the psychological plane.

One may speak of alterations or anomalies of self-presence as key factors, but only so

long as one recognizes that these disturbances can deviate in opposite, and perhaps paradoxical,

directions (i.e., not always or only toward diminishment). Philosophers discuss whether a truly

thin notion of “core self” or minimal self-presence should be considered a sine-qua-non either of

subjectivity or phenomenal consciousness itself, or of normal or ordinary consciousness. 7,11,16-22

Here we take no position on these vexed questions. Our focus is on comparative and empirical

issues concerning variations of felt self-presence that might be discernable across diverse

psychiatric conditions or between distinct kinds of human experience. For us, the key opposition

6
would not be between a (presumably normal and constant) presence of self-presence versus its

(supposed) absence or diminishment in schizophrenia, but rather: between more normal forms of

pre-reflective immersion and absorption, however these be understood (that is: whether as

involving minimal self or not), versus hyperreflexive experiences involving altered self-

presence.

The considerable heterogeneity of schizophrenic symptoms (together with their waxing

and waning over time) has long been recognized, and currently fuels skepticism about the

validity of “schizophrenia” as a disease entity or distinct syndrome. 23 Our own emphasis on

opposite and even paradoxical aspects could contribute to such doubts. “Schizophrenia” does,

however, have a long history, and there are reasons to consider it a valid and necessary

category.24 Like nearly all psychiatric diagnoses, schizophrenia is unlikely to be a true “disease

entity,” with a unifying or singular cause and course; rather it is a syndrome comprising a diverse

set of co-occurring features. But this does not mean we must forego all further explanation,

limiting ourselves to listing co-occurring symptoms and signs. We agree with Karl Jaspers’ view

of schizophrenia as a particularly mysterious yet indispensable category, and as one in which

alterations of self-experience have a central importance (Jaspers spoke of abnormalities of the

“Cogito”).25

The IDM is one attempt to clarify and account for the unity of this condition; it describes

a number of aspects that are intimately inter-related in various ways. We will now suggest that a

component of the IDM—hyperreflexivity—may be the best candidate for bringing the disparate

features of the syndrome together by showing their mutual implications and understandable

interactions. Hyperreflexivity can be understood as what Eugene Minkowski 26 termed a trouble

générateur: namely, a shared or unifying theme that permeates all the major symptoms as well as

7
an originating process, an orientation or existential mode that contributes to development of

these same symptoms: see Figure 1, panel B.

Hyperreflexivity’s congruence with both diminishment and increase of both self-presence

and grip—and with the paradox of their co-occurrence—offers a way of understanding what can

otherwise seem the strange or even inconceivable experiences that can occur. We shall argue that

such an approach is congruent as well with the agentic ambiguities of schizophrenia, 27 that is,

with its distinctive combination of quasi-intentional with passively endured factors (of “act and

affliction”28), and with the temporal variability of symptoms29-30 that this combination may help

to explain. As we shall see, such an approach locates the essence of schizophrenia not as

diminishment or loss but as a heightening of the paradoxical heart of human subjectivity itself:

the potential for reflexive self-awareness and self-distancing.

Hyperreflexivity: definition and historical antecedents

Hyperreflexivity defined: Hyperreflexivity can be defined as a rendering-explicit of

aspects of experience that are normally transparent or implicit, as a bringing-to-the-fore what

might otherwise have remained in the background of experience. It obviously implies a kind of

inward-turning but also an extrusion, an alienation of that which is taken as the object of

attention.28,31 Like most words applied to consciousness or subjective life, “reflexive” is

ambiguous. Here it will refer to a condition in which something is directed or turned back upon

itself, and this should be understood in an inclusive sense. The “reflexivity” in “hyperreflexivity”

refers not only to volitional, intellectual, metacognitive, or reflective forms of self-consciousness

(these might be termed hyper-reflective hyperreflexivity), but also to a more passive undergoing

or “suffering” of more spontaneous anomalies of consciousness and attentional or perceptual

8
focus (termed “operative hyperreflexivity”)—as when a patient finds herself noticing, say,

kinaesthetic or proprioceptive sensations in her elbow or eye sockets, or somehow “hearing” the

inner speech that would normally serve as the unnoticed medium of her thinking. The operative-

vs-reflective distinction should be understood, in any case, more as a continuum than a

dichotomy.

Historical antecedents: The relevance of such inwardness and associated alienation have

long been recognized in classic psychiatric accounts of schizophrenia that are attuned to the

subjective dimension. The importance of inwardness is already evident in Eugen Bleuler’s notion

of “autism,”32 which refers to the turning-away from the external and social world that he viewed

as a defining symptom of schizophrenia.33 Both Eugene Minkowski’s “loss of vital contact” 26 and

Wolfgang Blankenburg’s “loss of natural self-evidence” 34 (of the sense of obviousness or the

taken-for-granted) reflect this turning inward. Together they capture the accompanying

alterations of external and social reality (heightened alienation, devitalization, derealization; a

sense of things being uncertain and arbitrary) that prevail, often giving rise to metaphysical

questioning and “existential reorientations”.35 i

The hyperreflexive aspect is perhaps clearest in Klaus Conrad’s influential account of

early schizophrenic symptoms, which he describes as involving a two-faced alteration,

simultaneous and complementary, in the experience of both world and self. 36 These are first, the

Apophany: a heightened awareness of uncanny meaningfulness or significance (the term derives

from the Greek for “to become manifest”), and second, Anastrophe: a “stepping-back” from

normal absorbed experience that Conrad describes as a turning-inward, auto-observation,

“permanent consciousness,” or “spasm of reflexion” that suppresses one’s normal and

spontaneous world-orientation and “living toward the future.”

9
The Japanese psychiatrists Kimura Bin37 and Nagai Mari38 describe a kind of constant and

involuntary “self-witnessing” as the key feature. Their subtle but difficult account of self-

witnessing brings out the inherently paradoxical aspect of schizophrenic selfhood, involving

both a heightened self-presence and a simultaneous sense of an alien subjectivity within—and

even, the achieving of heightened self-presence only at the cost of a certain alienation from one’s

immediate subjectivity. Kimura and Nagai describe the kind of self-consciousness found in

schizophrenia as unusual insofar as the consciousness that is somehow watched by itself does not

thereby lose its quality as consciousness or as a gazing upon the world (i.e., its awareness of a

certain “for-me-ness” of its own experience). Such paradoxical forms can hardly be captured by

a simple notion of diminished self-presence or minimal self, since they incorporate the increased

(albeit paradoxical) self-presence that is inherent in a more acute experience of oneself as a

knower.

The term “hyperreflexivity” was introduced through discussion of the myriad parallels

between classically schizophrenic experience and expression and that typical of the modernist

and postmodernist art, literature, and thought of the 20 th century—that is, of artists (and

movements) who turned the normally tacit foundations of both art and experience into the main

subject of their work.28 Such artists and movements engendered all manner of conceptual and

experiential contradictions—and did so by taking subjectivity or mental life as both the prime

object of attention and the “sovereign subject” or constituting center of all that exists (as what

Foucault termed the “empirico-transcendental doublet” 39). Such contradictions are indeed

“paradoxes of the reflexive.”28 The parallels between madness and modernism can serve to

illuminate schizophrenic phenomena that are too readily dismissed as demented, regressed, or

10
simply incomprehensible, but that, in fact, demonstrate the peculiar, and often paradoxical,

patterns inherent in such inwardness, alienation, and reflexivity.28,40-41

Let us return to the experiential abnormalities described in our first article, but considering them

now in light of “hyperreflexivity.” We consider, first, manifestations of exaggerated self-presence

—whose association with hyperreflexivity might seem particularly obvious. Then we consider

diminished self-presence before turning to various paradoxical manifestations.

Hyperreflexivity and exaggerated self-presence

The hyperreflexive aspect of exaggerated self-presence is, perhaps, almost too obvious to

require elaboration. It would seem that exaggerated self-presence just is a heightened awareness

of one’s own being aware. It is, after all, a bringing-to-the-fore of something that would normally

be taken for granted and thereby recede to the background, or, perhaps, would not be registered

in consciousness at all—i.e., the sheer fact of existing as, or of having, a field of conscious

awareness (and thus: of the “for-me-ness” of the experienced world).

Derealization and exaggerated self-presence: Patient complaints regarding the

fraudulence, flimsiness, or ephemeral quality of experiential objects—very common in

schizophrenia42-43—may reflect how the world can seem derealized in the presence of this

hyperreflexive self-awareness of awareness as such: “I see things devoid of substance … what I

see is only a play, a Punch and Judy show; it is clumsy, vulgar, unpleasant and, above all, false; it

doesn’t really exist”44. “There is no reason for believing in the existence of an unobservable like

an external world, and therefore my mind, cluttered with surprisingly uncooperative images, is

my only reality”45.

11
Here the “for-me-ness” seems to be exacerbated and extended, not diminished: A person

who experiences even real-world objects, persons, or events as lacking a certain independence

and solid reality may be hyperaware of her own consciousness as the (constituting) medium of

experience, and therefore of objects in the external world as having what might be termed a

“coefficient of subjectivity.”46

Increased grip and exaggerated self-presence

Exaggerated for-me-ness seems relevant as well for exaggerated grip, whether in what we

have described as its mystical or its ontologically paranoid form. In the mystical case, a

heightened sense of coherence and salience evokes feelings of higher unity or mystical

wholeness, such that patients feel directly aligned with ultimate aspects of reality that may have

previously remained hidden.47-48 Here there seems a homogenization and effacement of

boundaries: the significance of mind-world or subject-object distinctions recedes in the presence

of a hyperreflexive awareness that renders all things quasi-subjectivized and thereby equivalent.

In the paranoid case, the sense of oneself as the conscious center of things grounds the

feeling that other conscious centers must be attending to oneself as the ultimate centerpoint and

therefore as the target of greatest interest. This hyperreflexive interpretation of paranoia may also

account for its often ‘ontological’ character in schizophrenia (cf. article 1), i.e., the fact that such

paranoia is often not limited to particular persons or entities (as would be the case in, e.g.,

delusional disorders),49 but tends to extend to the whole of reality, for example, as involving

impersonal gazes or cameras that possess a ubiquitous or allover mode of presence, both internal

and external. One patient is “examined throughout my life—secret cameras and microphones

12
whirring in my head”50. “There was something there,” said another, “beneath me, behind me,

between and above me. Everywhere and always”42.

The prominence of hyperreflexivity (though not the term) is essential to the French

psychiatrist Henri Grivois’51 account of schizophrenia as being grounded, in its origin and

essence, in the patient’s experience of his own centrality in the universe (“centration”) and of

everything being somehow concerned with or directed toward him (“concernement”)—as

discussed in our previous article. And these, in turn, could obviously account for what, since

Bleuler, have been recognized as the most common delusions in schizophrenia: those involving a

sense of grandiosity or of persecution—delusions that, in their specifically schizophrenic form,

appear to be grounded in a fundamental alteration in the way in which self and reality in general

are being experienced.ii

Hyperreflexivity and loss of self

Experiences of diminished self-presence may seem, at first, to be antithetical to all that

has just been described, yet they too can be bound up with hyperreflexivity.

One route is already elaborated in the IDM1-2 and earlier in Sass’s Madness and

Modernism28: A hyperreflexive focusing or concentration on aspects of experience that would

normally be lived through in an implicit manner—and would thereby serve as the medium of a

sense of self—can result in these dimensions of experience being objectified, alienated, or

reified. (This may affect, e.g., the inner speech supportive of thinking or the kinesthetic and

proprioceptive sensations of the body.) In the current IDM this is described as undermining a

supposedly normal and constant sense of implicit self-presence (“minimal self”). It can also be

thought of as disrupting the spontaneous flow of absorbed experience: as inserting self-related

13
stimuli into what might otherwise have been a transparent, world-directed, or meaning-directed

flow.22

In accord with either interpretation, the patient may well be expected to complain of a

certain “loss of self”—referring thereby either to a loss of implicit self-presence that would

normally be present, or simply to a disappearance of a familiar kind of engaged spontaneity.

“You’re on automatic pilot and you’re an observer,” reported one patient. “You’re doing all kinds

of stuff but it’s like you’re not really present, as if you’re observing everything from your own

perspective. When you’re observing, you participate less.”42

Some such experiences of loss-of-self may result from operative hyperreflexivity, in

which disruptive sensations seem, so to speak, to pop out in an automatic or non-volitional

fashion and interrupt more spontaneous or habitual modes of awareness and action. Others may

involve more reflective forms of hyperreflexivity, in which self-directed attention would have a

more secondary as well as a partially volitional quality. The patient may, for example, attend in a

somewhat intentional or goal-directed fashion to normally implicit sensations of which she finds

herself becoming aware (or to other kinds of abnormal perceptual experiences felt as unusual), iii

perhaps in order to monitor or somehow control their disruptive effect—even though (as noted

above) this very attentiveness is liable to exacerbate the very alienation or abnormality she is

attempting to control.

Something like this hyperreflexive progression has been documented in longitudinal

studies regarding the development of schizophrenic “first-rank symptoms” from the initial and

underlying subjective phenomena known as “basic symptoms”. 52 The symptom sequence begins

with a kind of “basal irritation”,53 a disconcerting awareness of alterations in one’s experience of

perceiving, thinking, or the body, often involving sensations that would normally have remained

14
in the experiential background (a kind of operative hyperreflexivity). Patients who eventually

developed symptoms involving loss of bodily possession, for instance, had earlier experiences of

“irritating disturbances of bodily feelings or cenesthesias”, such as electrical or migrating

sensations or subtle feelings of enlargement or diminishment of body parts. 53 Over time such

awareness becomes increasingly acute, inspiring subtle experiences of “somatopsychic” or

“allopsychic depersonalization or derealization” that are accompanied, as well, by “complicated

processes of adaptation and coping,” including “checking efforts” and attempts to give meaning

or exert control over these emerging sensations (reflective hyperreflexivity)—all this typically

leading eventually into classic symptoms of truly not owning one’s own thoughts, or perhaps of

one’s body being influenced from without.53

Here, it seems, the awareness and the experiential alterations should not be viewed as two

separable things (as if the first were a mere noticing of the second). The very fact of being so

aware (so focally aware) may actually alter the experiences in question through a kind of

reification, a process whereby subtle background forms of awareness are made to take on the

more explicit qualities of an object of focal attention—thereby manifesting what R.D. Laing

aptly termed “phantom concreteness.”46 Antonin Artaud, who suffered from schizophrenia,

experienced his own facial sensations, normally lived tacitly from within, as taking the form of a

“vitreous” masklike membrane that seemed to rise off from his own face.54

It should be noted, as well, that the very act of searching for oneself can be understood as

a futile and perhaps counterproductive attempt—for as various philosophers (Hume, early Sartre,

and many Buddhist thinkers) have argued, there may be no self if the latter is defined as some

necessary and constant object, or even as a reliable sense of presence. In such cases, in fact, it

may be the very looking for something that, by its very nature, cannot actually be found, that

15
brings on a sense or an awareness of ungrounding that would not be present in normal, ongoing

experience.

Hyperreflexivity and dualities of disturbed grip

The seemingly contradictory dualities of grip are no less striking and no less explicable in

light of hyperreflexivity.

A hyperreflexive or self-conscious awareness of one’s own centrality can naturally

generate a sense of things being organized around oneself or of being—oneself—the prime

object of all awarenesses. We have considered how this may give rise to delusions of reference,

the ontological paranoia of a “watcher-machine,” or the sense of nothing being random since

everything is somehow organized in relation to oneself (usually the patient cannot say just how).

Antithetical developments can also occur, however, given a second factor. This is the fact that

withdrawal from direct and vital engagement with the external object-world—which can also be

inherent in hyperreflexivity—may weaken or undermine the normal, purpose-ridden affordances

that lend pattern to one’s field of awareness, thereby undermining the normal sources of

organization and meaningfulness.55

These two possibilities correspond to the classic distinction made between two main

types or syndromes of schizophrenia, the “paranoid” and the “disorganized” or “hebephrenic”

types. Research shows that these classic subtypes do not in fact separate out very clearly, with

many patients showing both types of symptoms at different stages of their illness or even

manifesting both disorganization and paranoia at the same time. 56 (Recognition of this

overlapping has led to elimination of the subtype designation in the latest diagnostic system.)

The common thread of hyperreflexivity can help explain how these two aspects—seemingly so

16
opposed—might stem from a shared underlying core, from different potentialities inherent in

hyperreflexive withdrawal.

Symptom and countersymptom: Paradoxes of the reflexive

It appears, then, that hyperreflexivity can capture the co-existence of symptom and

counter-symptom that (as Vygotsky noted, see article 1) seems endemic to schizophrenic

conditions. Diminished and heightened self-presence; loosened and tightened grip; grandiosity

and paranoia: both sides of each of these dualities can be understood as manifestations of the

inwardness and alienation implicit in this introversive form of existence. These two sides of a

coin are sometimes combined in representative schizophrenic symptoms that capture their

paradoxical complementarity—as with the influencing-machine delusion whereby the patient

Natalija posits herself as both the godlike center of all that appears and as a mere machine

manipulated by mysterious others.57

A closely related duality is apparent when Schreber recounts how his paranoid sense of

being watched and controlled by the ‘nerves’ and ‘rays’ of God was intimately related to his own

quasi-divine importance as the ultimate center of reality. 58-59 It is perhaps not surprising (indeed,

perhaps is inevitable) that the one who feels himself to center or anchor the world (“I have the

sensation that everything turns around me” is a common schizophrenic experience 36 ),

should also be the person toward whom all meanings and messages are directed, the very one

whom everything concerns—as if everything orients around oneself, rather like iron filings

pointing toward a magnet. In this sense centration and concernement are complementary or

mutually interdependent—two sides of a coin. There may, however, be times when one or the

17
other takes the fore, leading to oscillations between a more grandiose and a more paranoid

orientation.

Here a useful analogy is that of a sniper who, peering through his gunsight, naturally

senses his own centrality as the point-of-origin of what seems the all-powerful cone of awareness

that splays out before his own scrutinizing eye, yet who must realize as well (all the while, or

perhaps, just before pulling the trigger) that all enemy glances might seek out and potentially

converge on him, thereby transforming his own sovereign viewpoint into the target of a kind of

ontological “search-and-destroy” mission. This might serve as a real-world analogy for the co-

occurrence (or possible oscillation) between exaggerated self-presence and all-encompassing

paranoia that are two aspects (antithetical, yet also complementary) of a hyperreflexive

awareness of the “for-me-ness” of the experiential world.

Two models: “Hyperreflexivity” versus “diminished minimal self”

Variability: We have noted hyperreflexivity’s compatibility with, and indeed, its ability to

account for, the remarkable diversity of schizophrenic phenomena—which includes seemingly

antithetical symptoms that might seem mutually exclusive. Also significant is this construct’s

compatibility with the variability of symptoms, referring now to how symptoms may wax or

wane over time, sometimes imposing themselves forcefully but at other times fading away. 29-30

By contrast, “diminished minimal self” suggests a persistent condition (and has indeed

sometimes been understood as such) 60 that is supposedly invariant, though somewhat changeable

in its expression; it refers to an underlying state of being rather than to any process that may have

brought this state about. The concept has rightly been criticized for its seeming inability to

18
account for why sense of self appears “relatively intact prior to illness onset” but then is lost, and

also for how this sense could possibly be regained or reconstructed in processes of recovery.61

What hyperreflexivity describes is, by contrast, something more like an orientation, a

shifting form of attention or a tendency, a propensity to adopt a distinctive kind of inward or

alienated attitude that unsettles the taken-for-granted and disrupts concentration and habitual

forms of spontaneous flow. Like the self-centrality it grounds, the tendency toward

hyperreflexivity may be a latent vulnerability trait. It is understandable that such an attitude

might develop its own inertia and persistence, becoming almost habitual, but also that it is likely

to wax and wane in accord with internal moods or other states and in reaction to external events

or interpersonal experiences that may be experienced as threatening or soothing 62—and that these

shifts may occur spontaneously, as a mindset that can overtake a person yet without being

entirely beyond control. Recent methodological developments in the modelling of

psychopathological dynamics63 may allow empirical confirmation of these ideas, e.g., by

studying whether temporal increases in hyperreflexive patterns are predictive for the

development of psychotic symptoms, and/or whether decreased hyperreflexivity characterizes

periods of remission and recovery—thereby testing a phenomenological model of the onset and

development of schizophrenia spectrum disorders that can complement and enrich current

prediction approaches.64

Persons with schizophrenia describe such variability and, with it, the possibility of having

some modicum of control.27 Patients do sometimes manage to quiet their voices, often by

engaging in familiar forms of practical activity, like shoveling snow or washing the dishes. 65-66

They may also bring on unusual experiences through intense hyperreflexive concentration that

can bring about a sense of self-alienation but also a sense of universal centrality. 67 The latter

19
propensity—for intense concentration—may typically be described, in psychiatry, as a defect,

deficiency, or weakness, but could be thought of equally well as a capacity, perhaps even a kind

of talent—for as Kimura notes, persistent “simultaneous reflection” is something that normal or

non-schizophrenic people do not have the ability to sustain.37

Hyperreflexivity and the “natural attitude”

Earlier we described the apparent variability of self-presence in more standard and clearly

non-schizophrenic forms of experience (e.g., variations of self-presence in absorbed versus more

self-aware activities or situations). What is it, we may ask, that differentiates these from the

diminishment or exaggeration of self-presence characteristic of schizophrenia? Is it, for example,

a matter of type or of degree? Or is it related to the specific nature of the hyperreflexivity that

predominates in schizophrenia68?

We have already suggested some differences intrinsic to the state of consciousness

involved (tacit-becoming-explicit, the peculiarities of involuntary self-witnessing). There may

also be quantitative differences in the intensity of the processes or in how often or long they

persist, or in the degree to which the person is able to flexibly modulate forms of tacit immersion

and states of reflexive consciousness. But beyond this it may be necessary to describe as well,

certain limitations on how seriously such changes are taken, given what could be described as the

person’s existential attitude or orientation.iv

For most “normal” individuals, indeed for most people who are not in the schizophrenia

spectrum or currently psychotic, something like what phenomenologist Edmund Husserl termed

the “natural attitude” prevails as an underlying foundation or overarching framework, and as a

set of constraints, regarding reality-in-general, that persist as the underlying and unchangeable

20
framework of waking life. This includes assumptions, normally too obvious to be spoken or

thought, that preclude either of the polarized extremes to which hyperreflexivity can lead: such

“urdoxa” (foundational presuppositions) as the fact that there is an external world, that other

subjectivities distinct from but akin to us exist, and that one does oneself exist (though without

any insistence on its being in every moment recognized from within). One may ask whether it is

the fragility of a person’s grounding in this attitude and its urdoxa that makes schizophrenic

hyperreflexivity possible or distinctive (for this suggestion, see 70-71): perhaps only then can a

person engage in such inward, unconventional, and alienating forms of self-consciousness which

can lead to extreme experiences either of loss of self or of its apotheosis. Or to the contrary, is it

that hyperreflexivity undermines the urdoxa—which, as it were, can be suspended or even

dissolve under the hyperreflexive gaze? The hyperreflexivity characteristic of schizophrenia

often has a “transcendental” flavor, given its tendency to “bracket” or set aside the “natural

attitude” that is presupposed in normal forms of both consciousness and self-consciousness—that

is, to take “subjectivity” rather than objective reality as primary. (By contrast, the natural attitude

is interpersonally grounded, practically oriented, and typically realist regarding external

reality72)v

These two dimensions—hyperreflexivity and lack of adherence to the natural attitude—

seem in any case to be intimately related. 28,47,74-75 Together they seem to capture, if not the

“essence” (which may not exist) then at least the distinctive signature of the diverse yet real

unity, of that nest of paradoxes—human, all-too-human—that is schizophrenia.

Implications for research and treatment

21
This revision of the IDM (see Figure 1: panel A+B) has implications for both research

and treatment. Consider first the issue of neural correlates and neurobiological modelling.

The neural plane: The minimal-self model would seem to motivate, most naturally, a

search for a shared neural factor that (supposedly) would underlie the various forms of

diminished minimal self experience—almost a kind of holy grail that would index and perhaps

account for this supposedly key abnormality that is assumed to lie at the core of the overtly

diverse abnormalities of schizophrenic experience. Hyperreflexivity suggests an orientation that

is more diverse and modest in its ambitions—and more in line with current empirical research on

neurobiological correlates.

The neural correlate in question would, of course, be expected to be associated not

primarily or exclusively with diminished self (nor with the hypotheses of diminished meta-

cognitive awareness76), but with the forms of self-conscious introversion captured by the

hyperreflexivity notion. And these, in turn, might be expected to be heterogeneous, given the

diverse ways in which “hyperreflexivity” may occur—e.g., sometimes as an automatic popping-

out of kinesthetic sensations that would normally have been unnoticed or suppressed (“operative

hyperreflexivity,” perhaps bound up with salience dysregulation77); sometimes as a more

purposive scrutiny of background sensations or assumptions (“reflective hyperreflexivity,”

perhaps bound up with hemispheric irregularities78); and still othertimes as passivized

withdrawal from practical activity underlying exaggerated experiences of inwardnesss and

personal centrality (perhaps correlated with hyperactivation of the DMN: Default Mode

Network79 ) or else confusion regarding what is experienced as being “inner” versus as “outer”

(perhaps correlated with unusual positive correlation of DMN with the CEN: Central Executive

Network80). Rather than a unipolar abnormality, there seems a general instability—reflected, e.g.,

22
in predictive-processing studies showing weaker but also stronger “priors” in psychosis 81, or in

DMN activity/connectivity being sometimes weakened but other times strengthened82.

We suspect that, rather than having any single neurobiological correlate, schizophrenia

needs to be appreciated in its diversity—the heterogeneity of its symptoms going along with a

heterogeneity of neural correlates. The unity underlying (or coexisting with) this diversity may

need to be identified on the psychological and indeed the phenomenological plane—as involving

what might be termed a final common pathway, a “real” or “robust pattern” 83, a kind of “attractor

basin”84 (or “strange-attractor” basin85—allowing for heterogeneity and fluctuations) whereby the

different aspects of hyperreflexivity (in both operative and reflective forms) occur in a variety of

both causally interacting and mutually implicatory ways. 4 Such a basin could, of course, have a

variety of more distal causal factors, both genetic and environmental.

Psychological treatment: Implications for treatment were addressed at the end of the

previous article. There we discussed the nature of heightened self-presence and tightened grip, an

appreciation of which can help overcome the tendency either to find such experiences

incomprehensible and alien, or else to oversimplify by viewing them as forms of secondary

defense potentially subject to intellectual or cognitive refutation. It helps the clinician to

appreciate the central importance of centration itself, and thus of key symptoms such as

delusions of reference, grandiose delusions, and delusions of omniscience.

The most significant implications may pertain less to any specific therapeutic technique

and more to an atmospheric shift.86 This would involve overcoming a kind of epistemic injustice

that is widespread and difficult to dislodge: that of condescending to the patient’s perspective by

viewing it not only as inaccurate but as somehow less developed or mature than that of the non-

psychotic individual.87 Instead of viewing the seemingly contradictory claims as indicating

23
failures of logic or regression to primitive modes, “hyperreflexivity” allows them to be, at least

in some instances, appreciated as higher-level paradoxes, indeed as “paradoxes of the

reflexive.”28,39-40.

Final comment

The central role of hyperreflexivity (especially of transcendental hyperreflexivity) for

understanding schizophrenia is, of course, only a hypothesis, and will need, over time, to prove

its superiority to alternative hypotheses. Here we have argued that hyperreflexivity accords with

the diversity of symptoms in schizophrenia; can account for its distinctive paradoxes; and offers

a way of understanding its agentic ambiguities and of conceiving its variability over time. We

have suggested various empirical and practical implications. We note as well that whereas

diminished “minimal self” suggests a loss of the kind of self-consciousness that seems almost

definitive of human nature, “hyperreflexivity” views schizophrenia squarely within the human

domain—indeed, as an exaggeration of forms of awareness (involving self-consciousness and

self-questioning) that are likely to be unique to our species.

Acknowledgements

The authors want to thank Barnaby Nelson, Mario Alvarez, Wouter Kusters, Stijn Vanheule, Matt

Millar, and several anonymous reviewers for their helpful feedback on earlier versions of this

article.

References

1. Sass LA, Parnas J. Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophr Bull 2003; 29:
427-44.

24
2. Sass L, Borda JP, Madeira L, Pienkos E, Nelson B. Varieties of self disorder: a bio-
pheno-social model of schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull 2018; 44: 720-27.
3. Nelson B, Parnas J, Sass L. Disturbance of minimal self (ipseity) in schizophrenia:
clarification and current status. Schizophr Bull 2014; 40(3): 479-82.
4. Sass LA. Explanation and description in phenomenological psychopathology. J
Psychopathol 2014; 20(4): 366-76.
5. López-Silva P. Mapping the psychotic mind: a review on the subjective structure of
thought insertion. Psychiatric Q 2018; 89(4): 957-68.
6. Gallagher S. Relations between agency and ownership in the case of schizophrenic
thought insertion and delusions of control. Rev Philos Psychol 2015; 6: 865-79.
7. Henriksen MG, Parnas J, Zahavi D. Thought insertion and disturbed for-me-ness
(minimal selfhood) in schizophrenia. Conscious Cogn 2019; 74: 102770.
8. Billon A, Kriegel U. Jaspers‘ dilemma: the psychopathological challenge to subjectivity
theories of consciousness. In: Gennaro R, ed. Disturbed consciousness: New essays on
psychopathology and theories of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2015: 29-
54.
9. Lane T. The minimal self hypothesis. Conscious Cogn 2020; 85: 1-18.
10. Humpston CS. The paradoxical self: awareness, solipsism and first-rank symptoms in
schizophrenia. Philos Psychol 2018; 31(2): 210-31.
11. Zahavi D. Self and Other: Exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2014.
12. Zahavi D, Kriegel U. For-me-ness: what it is and what it is not. In: Dahlstrom D,
Elpidorou, Hopp W, eds. Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology. Routledge; 2015: 36-
53.
13. Bortolotti L, Broome M. A role for ownership and authorship in the analysis of thought
insertion. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 2009; 8(2): 205-224.
14. Billon A. Does consciousness entail subjectivity? The puzzle of thought insertion. Philos
Psychol 2013; 26(2): 291-314.
15. Rasmussen A, Parnas J. What is obsession? Differentiating obsessive-compulsive
disorder and the schizophrenia spectrum. Schizophr Res 2022; 243: 1-8.
16. Allweis L. Self-consciousness without an “I”: a critique of Zahavi’s account of the
minimal self. Res Phenomenol 2022; 52(1): 84-119.
17. McClelland T. Four impediments to the case for mineness. In: García-Carpintero M,
Guillot M, eds. Self-Experience: Essays on Inner Awareness. Oxford University Press;
2023: 50-65.
18. Howell RJ, Thompson B. Phenomenally mine: in search of the subjective character of
consciousness. Rev Philos Psychol 2017; 8(1): 103-27.
19. Dreyfus HL. Overcoming the myth of the mental. Topoi 2006; 25: 43-9.
20. Schear JK. Experience and self-consciousness. Philos Stud 2009; 144(1): 95-105.
21. Zahavi D. Thin, thinner, thinnest: defining the minimal self. In: Durt C, Fuchs T, Tewes
C, eds. Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture: Investigating the Constitution of the Shared
World. The MIT Press; 2017: 193-200.
22. Howell RJ. Transparency and subjective character. In: García-Carpintero M, Guillot M,
eds. Self-Experience: Essays on Inner Awareness. Oxford University Press; 2023: 77-98.
23. van Os J, Guloksuz S. Schizophrenia as a symptom of psychiatry’s reluctance to enter the
moral era of medicine. Schizophr Res 2022; 242: 138-140.

25
24. Tandon R, Keshavan M, Nasrallah H. Reinventing schizophrenia. Updating the construct.
Schizophr Res 2022; 242: 1-3.

25. Jaspers K. General Psychopathology, trans. J Hoenig and MW Hamilton. Chicago:


University of Chicago Press; 1963.
26. Minkowski E. Le temps vécu. Études phénoménologiques et psychopathologiques.
Presses Universitaires de Francee; 2013.
27. Jones N, Shattell M, Kelly T, et al. “Did I push myself over the edge?”: complications of
agency in psychosis onset and development. Psychosis 2016; 8(4): 324-35.

28. Sass L. Madness and Modernism: Insanity in the Light of Modern Art, Literature, and
Thought (revised edition). Oxford University Press; 2017.
29. Myin-Germeys I, Kasanova Z, Vaessen T, et al. Experience sampling methodology in
mental health research: new insights and technical developments. World Psychiatry 2018;
17(2): 123-32.
30. Hermans K, van der Steen Y, Kasanova Z, et al. Temporal dynamics of suspiciousness
and hallucinations in clinical high risk and first episode psychosis. Psychiatry Res 2020;
290: 113039.
31. Cutting J. Morbid objectivization in psychopathology. Acta Psychiatr Scand 1999;
99(Suppl. 395): 30-33.
32. Bleuler E. Dementia Praecox or the Group of Schizophrenias (trans J. Zinkin). New
York: International Universities Press; 1950.
33. Parnas J, Bovet P, Zahavi D. Schizophrenic autism: clinical phenomenology and
pathogenetic implications. World Psychiatry 2002; 1(3): 131-6.
34. Blankenburg W. Der Verlust der natürlichen Selbstverständlichkeit: Ein Beitrag zur
Psychopathologie symptomarmer Schizophrenien. 2nd ed. Berlin: Parodos; 2012.
35. Parnas J, Møller P, Kircher J, et al. EASE: Examination of anomalous self-experience.
Psychopathology 2005; 38: 236-258.

36. Conrad K. Die Beginnende Schizophrenie: Versuch einer Gestaltanalyse des Wahns.
Stuttgart: Georg Thieme Verlag; 1958.
37. Kimura B. Cogito and I: a bio-logical approach. Philos Psychiat Psychol 2001; 8(4): 331-
6.

38. Motobayashi Y, Parnas J, Kimura B, Toda DL. ‘The “schizophrenic” in the self-
consciousness of schizophrenic patients’, by Mari Nagai (1990). Hist Psychiatry 2016;
27(4): 493-503.
39. Foucault M. The Order of Things. New York: Vintage Books; 1970.

40. Humpston C. Paradoxes in a prism: reflections on the omnipotent passivity and


omniscient oblivion of schizophrenia. Philos Psychol
doi:10.1080/09515089.2022.2078187
41. Feyaerts J, Kusters W. On philosophy and schizophrenia: the case of thought insertion.
In: López-Silva P, McClelland T, eds. Intruders in the Mind: Interdisciplinary
Perspectives on Thought Insertion. Oxford University Press; 2023: 77-100.

26
42. Feyaerts J, Kusters W, Van Duppen Z, Vanheule S, Myin-Germeys I, Sass L. Uncovering
the realities of delusional experience in schizophrenia: a qualitative phenomenological
study in Belgium. Lancet Psychiatry 2021; 8(9): 784-796.
43. Fusar-Poli P, Estradé A, Stanghellini G, et al. The lived experience of psychosis: a
bottom-up review co-written by experts by experience and academics. World Psychiatry
2022; 21(2): 168-88.

44. Landis C. Varieties of Psychopathological Experience. New York: Holt, Rinehart and
Winston; 1964.
45. Glass J. Delusion: Internal Dimensions of Political Life. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press; 1985.

46. Laing RD. The Divided Self. Penguin Classics; 2010.


47. Parnas J, Henriksen MG. Mysticism and schizophrenia: a phenomenological exploration
of the structure of consciousness in the schizophrenia spectrum disorders. Conscious
Cogn 2016; 43: 75-88.

48. Kusters W. A Philosophy of Madness. The Experience of Psychotic Thinking. The MIT
Press; 2020.
49. Munro A. Delusional Disorder: Paranoia and Related Illnesses. Cambridge University
Press; 2009.
50. Searles HF. Collected Papers on Schizophrenia and Related Subjects. New York:
International Universities Press; 1965.

51. Grivois H. Le fou et le mouvement du monde. Paris: Grasset; 1995.


52. Klosterkötter J, Hellmich M, Steinmeyer EM, Schultze-Lutter F. Diagnosing
schizophrenia in the initial prodromal phase. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2001; 58(2): 158-64.
53. Klosterkötter J. The meaning of basic symptoms for the development of schizophrenic
psychoses. Neurol Psychiatry Brain Res 1992; 1: 30-41.
54. Sass L. Negative symptoms, schizophrenia, and the self. Int J Psychol Psychol Ther
2003; 3: 153-80.
55. Krueger J. Schizophrenia and the scaffolded self. Topoi 2020; 39: 597-609.
56. Carpenter WT, Tandon R. Psychotic disorders in DSM-5: summary of changes. Asian J
Psychiatr 2013; 6(3): 266-8.
57. Tausk V. On the origin of the ‘influencing machine’ in schizophrenia. Psychoanal Q
1933; 2: 529-30.
58. Schreber DP. Memoirs of My Nervous Illness (trans. Macalpine I, Hunter R). Cambridge:
Harvard University Press; 1988.
59. Sass L. The Paradoxes of Delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the Schizophrenic Mind.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press; 1994.
60. Nordgaard J, Nilsson LS, Sæbye D, Parnas J. Self-disorders in schizophrenia-spectrum
disorders: a 5-year follow-up study. Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci 2018; 268(7):
713-18.
61. Davidson L. Recovering a sense of self in schizophrenia. J Pers 2020; 88(1): 122-32.
62. Pienkos E. Schizophrenia in the world: arguments for a contextual phenomenology of
psychopathology. J Phenomenol Psychol 2020; 51: 184-206.

27
63. Nelson B, McGorry PD, Wichers M, Wigman JTW, Hartman JA. Moving from static to
dynamic models of the onset of mental disorder: a review. JAMA Psychiatry 2017; 74(5):
528-34.
64. Nelson B, McGorry PD, Fernandez A. Integrating clinical staging and phenomenological
psychopathology to add depth, nuance, and utility to clinical phenotyping: a heuristic
challenge. Lancet Psychiatry 2020; 8(2): 162-68.
65. Skodlar B, Henriksen MG. Toward a phenomenological psychotherapy for schizophrenia.
Psychopathology 2019; 52(2): 117-25.
66. Nelson B, Torregrossa L, Thompson A et al. Improving treatments for psychotic
disorders: beyond cognitive behaviour therapy for psychosis. Psychosis 2021; 13(1): 78-
84.

67. Hoffman RE. Revisiting Arieti’s “listening attitude” and hallucinated voices. Schizophr
Bull 2010; 36(3): 440-2.
68. Fuchs T. The psychopathology of hyperreflexivity. J Spec Philos 2010; 24(3): 239-255.
69. Sass L, Pienkos E, Skodlar B, et al. EAWE: Examination of Anomalous World
Experience. Psychopathology 2017; 50(1): 10-54.
70. Van Duppen Z, Sips R. Understanding the blind spots of psychosis: a Wittgensteinian
and first-person approach. Psychopathology 2018; 51(4): 276-84.
71. Jeppsson S. Radical psychotic doubt and epistemology. Phil Psychol 2022;
doi:10/1080/09515089.2022.2147815
72. Husserl E. The Crisis of European Philosophy and Transcendental Phenomenology.
(trans. D. Carr) Evanston IL: Northwestern University Press.
73. Husserl E. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. (trans D. Cairns).
The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
74. Blankenburg W. Der Verlust der natürlichen Selbstverständlichkeit: Ein Beitrag zur
Psychopathologie symptomarmer Schizophrenien. Berlin: Parodos Verlag; 1971.
75. Englebert J, Valentiny C. Le schizophrène comme hyper-philosophe. Le Cercle
Herméneutique 2016 ; 26-27 : 221-36.
76. Lysaker PH, Dimaggio G. Metacognitive capacities for reflection in schizophrenia:
implications for developing treatments. Schizophr Bull 2014 ; 40(3) : 487-91.
77. Howes OD, Hird EJ, Adams RA, Corlett PR, McGuire P. Aberrant salience, information
processing, and dopaminergic signaling in people at clinical high risk for psychosis. Biol
Psychiatry 2020; 88(4): 304-14.
78. Sun Y, Chen Y, Collinson SM, Bezerianos A, Sim K. Reduced hemispheric asymmetry
of brain anatomical networks is linked to schizophrenia: a connectome study. Cereb
Cortex 2017 ; 27(1) : 602-15.
79. Fan F, Tan S, Huang J, et al. Functional disconnection between subsystems of the default
mode network in schizophrenia. Psychol Med 2022; 52(12): 2270-80.
80. Robinson JD, Wagner N, Northoff G. Is the sense of agency in schizophrenia influenced
by resting-state variation in self-referential regions of the brain? Schizophr Bull 2016;
42(2): 270-76.
81. Corlett PR, Horga G, Fletcher P, et al. Hallucinations and strong priors. Trends Cogn Sci
2019; 23(2): 114-127.

28
82. Mingoia G, Wagner G, Langbein K, et al. Default mode network activity in
schizophrenia studied at resting state using probabilistic ICA. Schizophr Res 2012; 138(2-
3): 143-9.
83. Tabb K, Schaffner KF. Causal pathways, random walks, and tortuous paths: moving from
the descriptive to the etiological in psychiatry. In: Kendler KS, Parnas J, eds.
Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry IV: Classification of Psychiatric Illness. Oxford
Academic Books; 2017: 342-60.
84. Bringman L, Helmich M, Eronen M, Voelkle M. Complex systems approaches to
psychopathology. In: Krueger RF, Blaney PH, eds. Oxford Textbook of Psychopathology
(4edn). Oxford University Press; 2023: 103-22.
85. Durstewitz D, Huys QJM, Koppe G. Psychiatric illnesses as disorders of network
dynamics. Biol Psychiatry Cogn Neurosci Neuroimaging 2021; 6(9): 865-76.
86. Sass L. Three dangers: phenomenological reflections on the psychotherapy of psychosis.
Psychopathology 2019; 52: 126-34.

87. Ritunnano R. Overcoming hermeneutical injustice in mental health: a role for critical
phenomenology. JBSP 2022; 53: 243-260.

29
ENDNOTES:

30
i
Exaggerated self-reflection is explicit in Blankenburg’s account of “loss of natural self-
evidence,” though Blankenburg presents such self-consciousness largely as a product (a defensive
reaction) rather than source for this undermining of the obvious or taken-for-granted.34

ii
Such delusions should be understood not merely in terms of their meaningful symbolic content
and in relation to the patient’s biography (as Bleuler and Freud often recommended) but in relation to
the ontological transformations that occur (which is more in accord with Jaspers’ views).

iii
Hyperreflexivity might sometimes be secondary to perceptual anomalies that are not themselves
necessarily hyperreflexive in nature. We would nevertheless argue that, when distinctively
schizophrenic features develop, these are likely to be bound up with hyperreflexivity. See text re
“attractor basin” notion.

iv
Re the typical alterations of attitude and orientation in schizophrenia-spectrum, see EASE
section V35 and EAWE section VI69 (which are highly overlapping).

v
We speak of transcendental hyperreflexivity by analogy with Husserl’s “transcendental” versus
“empirical” forms of reflection.73

You might also like