You are on page 1of 2

Psychological Medicine (2014), 44, 2013–2014.

© Cambridge University Press 2014

Book Review

Psychological Medicine, 44 (2014). clinician, or the general reader. But the editors have
doi:10.1017/S0033291714000907 done a nice job of balancing these contributions with
First published online 17 April 2014 more accessible philosophical discussions and more
The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, 1st clinically oriented analyses. Perusing the Handbook
edn. Edited by K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. G. T. will serve as a guide not only to traditional crossroads
Gipps, G. Graham, J. Z. Sadler, G. Stanghellini and between philosophy and psychiatry – such as the con-
T. Thornton. (Pp. 1376; ISBN 9780199579563; ceptual analysis of disease, the question of natural
$146.00 hb.) USA: Oxford University Press, 2013. kinds, or the mind-body problem – but also to more
cutting-edge topics, such as neuroethics, the placebo
The bookshelves of philosophers of psychiatry have effect, and theory of mind. The size of the collection
recently been colonized by volumes featuring ar- alone is impressive, although it seems to have taken
rangements of boldly colored geometric shapes on a its toll on the copy-editors: within two pages
stark black background. These are the constituents of (pp. 360–361) for example, the given name of one pro-
the International Perspectives in Philosophy and Psy- minent philosopher of psychiatry is mistaken and the
chiatry (IPPP) series, edited by Bill Fulford, Katherine male pronoun is incorrectly applied to another (a re-
Morris, John Sadler, and Giovanni Stanghellini. grettable oversight in a male-dominated field).
Along with a rich variety of monographs the series in- Whether the Handbook serves as a ‘representative
cludes several edited volumes, including The Oxford cross-section of the new field’ (p. v) or rather of the
Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, co-branded IPPP collection itself is to some extent moot, since
with the Oxford Philosophy Handbooks series and edi- so many working philosophers of psychiatry have
ted by Fulford, Sadler, and Stanghellini, along with published in the series. But the series itself represents
Martin Davies, Richard G. T. Gipps, George Graham, a strong stance about what the new field should be,
and Tim Thornton. This ambitious volume is doubly and as the editors recognize, they ‘have ended up
radical: it makes manifest a vision, actualized by the being perhaps somewhat too closed with little in the
IPPP series, for the burgeoning field of philosophy of way of dissenting voices’ (p. 8). What is this stance?
psychiatry (or, as the editors would have it, philosophy Emphasized throughout is the co-dependency of
and psychiatry), and it contributes to Oxford’s over- philosophy and psychiatry, as the editors encourage
turning of the very idea of the handbook. For par- clinicians to ‘go deep philosophically’ (p. 3) and philo-
ticipating institutions, www.oxfordhandbooks.com sophers to take seriously the lessons psychopathology
offers a new mode for research, in which signature can hold for the philosophy of mind and medicine.
contributions from experts are gathered in one place. The editors (and, to varying degrees, the contributors)
The volumes in the series are ‘living’: new chapters envision philosophy as engaging with psychiatry in a
are added online, and linked through a user-friendly ‘responsibly product-oriented’ (p. 1) way, with a
database. Each is accompanied by free online re- focus on practice instead of theory. The ‘service user
sources, in this case two valuable additions – a manual voice’ is at the center of this normative picture, and a
of descriptive psychopathology assembled by V. Y. partiality towards the clinic and away from biomedical
Allison-Bolger, and a database of personal narratives research is apparent in the humanist slant of many
of madness edited by Jayasree Kalathil. of the contributions, as well as in the dedication of
The Oxford handbooks aim to collect exciting and only one section to scientific explanation. More than
timely scholarly contributions rather than to provide a biomedical discipline, the Handbook presents psy-
introductory summaries, and they have succeeded chiatry as ‘chiefly about establishing therapeutic re-
here. In this short review it is impossible to summarize lationship and understanding other forms of life’
the content of the 73 chapters, which take a variety of (p. 217).
approaches, historical and social-scientific as well as The volume aims to put philosophy’s shoulder to the
philosophical. But the quality and range of the con- wheel on the side of the humanist clinician, while not-
tributions is spectacular, and anyone interested in psy- ing that ‘the philosophy of psychiatry, after all, for
chiatry will find many things to inspire, inform, and all its recent burgeoning, remains a minnow to the
challenge. Some of the chapters are more technical, neuroscientific whale’ (p. 8). While the opposition to
engaging with theorists from Dretske to Davidson, neuroscientific approaches holds as a generalization
Kristeva to Merleau-Ponty, and will be of interest to about most professional philosophers, it is worth not-
philosophers more than the psychiatric researcher, ing that the implications of neuroscientific (as well as
2014 Book Review

genetic) approaches have been taken up more sym- need resources for thinking critically and creatively
pathetically by notable philosophically proficient psy- about their own commitments. For philosophers or
chiatrists, including Eric Kandel, Kenneth Kendler, clinicians who aspire to the crucial work of integrating
and Steven Hyman. The absence of these viewpoints psychosocial and phenomenological approaches into
notwithstanding, the normative critical stance taken scientific investigation (clearly the book’s target audi-
by the editors will make the volume of interest to read- ence) it will be an outstanding resource.
ers of this journal who have suspicions about the KATHRYN TABB
biomedical whale in whose belly they labor, and who (Email: kct5@pitt.edu)

You might also like