You are on page 1of 229

[LrrjvjiJ]ILygj ^LjygJlSUMaUJt

INTKHNATIOKAL ISLAMIC UX1VLBSITY MKT KV<^tm

DIVINE TRANSCENDENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF


ANTHROPOMORPHISM IN FAKHR AL-DIN
AL-RAZl’S KALAM

BY

MOHD FARID MOHD SHAHRAN

A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the


requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy

International Institute
of Islamic Thought and Civilization (ISTAC)
International Islamic University
Malaysia

SEPTEMBER 2006
ABSTRACT

As a religion which upholds divine transcendence as its fundamental element in



»

S'
at divine knowledge, Islam is against any attempt to liken God with the
-j

characteristics of others particularly humans. The strong disavowal of


anthropomorphism shown by Muslim theologians (the mutakallimun) especially
that against anthropomorphism brought by certain marginal schismatic sects
throughout the history of Islamic thought has proved this uncompromising
stance. This dissertation analyzes the refutations of one of the important later
Asharite mutakallimun, Fakhr al-Din al-Razi (1149-1209) against the literal
views of the anthropomorphists who invested God with various anthropomorphic
qualities. Advancing mostly philosophical and logical arguments, al-Razi,
through one of his important theological works, Asas al-Taqdls, set out to prove
that the principle upon which the anthropomorphists maintained that God is a
body and situated in a direction is unfounded and antithetical to the concept of
divine transcendence. He argued that the anthropomorphic views which stem
from the literalism and sensible-imaginal approach of some mar inal Islamic sects

CfQ
have produced a description of God that completely shattered the principle of
divine unity which is the foundation of Islamic understanding of God. Apart
from providing an analysis of his arguments against anthropomorphism, this
study also discusses al-Razi’s understanding on the nature of divine attributes
and how divine transcendence based on his analysis of relevant material from the
Qur’an and hadith transpire in his discussion of attributes. Since
anthropomorphism also springs from the false understanding of the ambiguous
verses of the Qur’an (mutashdbihdt), this study examines al-Razi’s views of
muhkamdt and mutashdbihdt and the role of ta \vll (allegorical interpretation) as
the appropriate device in understanding the meaning of those ambiguous verses.
It also demonstrates how al-Razi, who believes that there should not be
contradiction between the Scripture and the established rational principle, applied
ta\vil in comprehending some of the verses of the Qur’an and the Prophetic
traditions.

ii
Oojl ^Z2J>Jj>

^x^yLt JL^j (/a yJ^JI JI Jjv^JJ (Z^ Ic^a^J ^J>JI lA^jJI JI LZZ^’- ZZ* ^zJ^JI 01
«■ -Z

oli^ll ol5jr>txJJ oLl^> lA-J Jt^3 Oil AyZ cAjO JS (A4>J^


(J^ill ^lA- z^O ^z^OAol ^a*^3SCaJoI ^J«z <_z^ zzOI <-ZsJo <^z_5^JI aJI . iA-tP V-AA
(A-IJu^ c3l*Z ^^'^*zV*ljl '‘-''^A"^ LA-^-*^A_A-ioI I (A^ll C^A-H 1^.

u^p-lz (Z^l 0>l JAA J-A>z ^ZoJI Iz^ .^<^LAI gZsJoI IJu ia^^J

JJ-I ^"^01 <J^ ‘ ’ ^OU (Z^l < JpOJI


A 7<V

cZ a^J JJa (jy 03 J' zA3 Ail §JA J^ Qxz2^ lz.a)I


* * • £ *
OA-II IjJbl 01 oJJ iaALAJ iaxjlvJjJI (Jt>JI (^jJzJI ^zlwl (a^-Jj! azJSj! zjy
-Z *
Jl^ ixJ) oL ^zj^z J
■YAP'

iaJ^

cz*J* jJI *JJI J^ ot u>jJJI ^i>l Ail . Jl^ A^l lA^Z iM*jJ- UJb^ iMj J lZ^-I
p
JAu ^3il JI ^^Juu iA-AJaaJI JjH (2Z c£AJ (Aa-v^-J (ASzJI

JJ^ JI IA^UpJIS JI J cZ^J jjJ jrji^j C?JII ^J>JI cX^JI •V

t, ~ ~ ' p
JZjiB ^>VSI eA^ <z*-^ 3 lZ2^
Q
APPROVAL PAGE

The dissertation of Mohd Farid Mohd Shahran has been approved by the following:

Mohamad Zaini Olhman


Supervisor

Ssekamanya Siraje Abdallah


Internal Examiner

Alparslan Acikgenc
External Examiner

Yahya Miehot
External Examiner

Ab Rahim Ismail
Chairman

iv
DECLARATION

I hereby declare that this dissertation is the result of my own investigations, except

where otherwise stated. I also declare that it has not been previously or concurrently

submitted as a whole for any other degrees at HUM or other institutions.

Mohd Farid Mohd Shahran

Signature Date

v
INTERNATIONAL ISLAMIC UNIVERSITY MALAYSIA

DECLARATION OF COPYRIGHT AND AFFIRMATION OF


FAIR USE OF UNPUBLISHED RESEARCH

Copyright © 2000 by Mohd Farid Mohd Shahran. All rights reserved.

DIVINE TRANSCENDENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF


ANTHROPOMORPHISM
IN FAKHR AL-DlN AL-RAZFS KALAM

No part of this unpublished research may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,


or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying,
recording or otherwise without prior written permission of the copyright holder
except as provided below.

1. Any material contained in or derived from this unpublished research may


only be used by others in their writing with due acknowledgement.

HUM or its library will have the right to make and transmit copies (print or
electronic) for institutional and academic purposes.

The HUM library will have the right to make, store in a retrieval system and
supply copies of this unpublished research if requested by other universities
and research libraries.

Allirmed by Mohd Farid Mohd Shahran.

Signature Date

vi
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

“A ah wi l up to suitable ranks and degrees, those of you who believe and


who have been granted knowledge.” - al-Mujadilah 58:11

First and foremost, I wish to acknowledge Associate Prof. Dr. Zaini Othman
whose supervision and continuous encouragement has brought to the completion
of this dissertation. Without his comments and advice, this dissertation would
have never been able to take its present form.

My heartiest gratitude also goes to Prof. Dr. Syed Muhammad Naquib al-Attas
whose sagacity and erudition brought me first to 1STAC in my journey to pursue
knowledge. The interesting series of academic courses plus the resourceful
library of the institute under his leadership provided me a lively intellectual
atmosphere. I would also like to thank Prof. Dr. Wan Mohd Nor Wan Daud who
has been my constant mentor and teacher in the institute.

I wish to acknowledge my colleagues especially Dr. Mohd Zaidi Ismail and Dr.
Mohd Sani Badron who, through their stimulating discussions, have continuously
provided me with fresh insights in intellectual matters.

My genuine indebtedness also goes to my parents for their enormous sacrifice


throughout my life. No words can express my feelings towards them, nor can
anything I do compensate such sacrifice. This study would have been impossible
without the support of my wife, Arba’iyah Mohd Noor, who is at the same time
striving to complete her own Ph.D. dissertation. Finally, I wish to dedicate this
dissertation to my children, Aishah Sofia, Sarah Arifah and Abbas Fakhri with
sincere prayer that they will one day be better than their father in seeking true
knowledge.

“And Allah has full knowledge and is well-acquainted with all things.” (al-
Hujurat 49:13)

vii
CONTENTS

iii
Abstract in Arabic
iv
Approval Page
v
Declaration Page
vi
Copyright Page
vii
Acknowledgements
xi
List of Abbreviations

INTRODUCTION
Statement of the Problem
Al-Razi as a Champion Against Anthropomorphism
Objective of this Study
10
Previous Studies and the Scope of this Study
15
Sources of the Study
Methodology and Significance of this Study
Plan of the Study
CHAPTER ONE: DIVINE TRANSCENDENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF
ANTHROPOMORPHISM: A THEOLOGICAL BACKGROUND 19
Introduction: Rational and Scriptural Basis of Divine Transcendence... 19
Terms Employed to Designate Divine Transcendence 23
God’s Immanence and the Problem of Anthropomorphism 27
The Polemic of Anthropomorphism: Main Groups 29
i. The Anthropomorphists (Mushabbihah ) 29
1.1. Main Views of the Mushabbihah 32
1.11. Epistemological Method of the Mushabbihah 35
ii) TheMutazilah 37
iii) Ibn Hanbal 40
111.1. BilaKayf. 44
111.11. The Hanabilah 47
iv) The Ashairah 51
iv.i. Abu Hassan Al-Ashari 51
iv.ii Abu Hamid al-Ghazali 58
Conclusion 63

CHAPTER TWO: DIVINE ATTRIBUTES IN AL-RAzI’S KALAM 66


Introduction 66
Conception of the Attributes 67

viii
The Polemic Concerning the Nature of Divine Attributes.................... 70
Al-Razi’s Views on the Nature of the Attributes and their
Relation to the Essence....................................................................... 79
The Eternal and the Originated......................................................... 82
Classification of the Attributes......................................................... 86
Divine Transcendence as Reflected in al-Razi’s
Classification of Attributes............................................................... 90
Unicity (wabdaniyyab)

M
Eternity (Qidam)

<1
Baqa ’ (Permanence)........................................................................... 100
God’s Being Distinct from Originated Things
(Mukbalafatubu li al-Hawaditb)...................................................... 101

CHAPTER THREE: TEXTUAL AND RATIONAL BASIS OF THE


DIVINE TRANSCENDENCE...................................................................... 104
Introduction......................................................................................... 104
Kitab Asas al-Taqdls......................................................................... 105
The Arrangement of Kitab Asas al-Taqdls.................................... 108
The Importance of Asas al-Taqdls................................................... 109
Rational Proofs of Divine Transcendence......................................... Ill
The Rational Principle Underlying the Musbabbibab’s Notion of
God........................................................................................................ Ill
Al-Razi’s Counter Arguments........................................................... 117
God as an Existent beyond Sense Perception.................................. 118
God as an Existent without any Resemblance (sbablb)................ 120
Classification of Existents.................................................................. 121
The Cause of the Principle (Tllat al-Hukm)................................... 124
Negation of the Spatial and Bodily Aspects with regard to God. 127
Characteristics of Spatial Bodies........................................................ 127
Textual Arguments on the Transcendence of God......................... 132
Surat al-Ikblas......................................................................... 133

CHAPTER FOUR: MUHKAMAT, MUTASHABIHAT,


AND THE ROLE OF TA WIL IN RAZES THOUGHT........................... 140
Introduction......................................................................................... 140
The Mubkamdt and Mutasbabibdt in the Qur’an......................... 140
Qur’anic Origin: Surah Al‘Imran, Verse 7.................................... 142
The Legitimacy of Interpreting the Mutasbabibdt......................... 147
Can There be Anything in the Qur’an that is Beyond our
Knowledge?.......................................................................................... 149
Linguistic and Technical Meaning of Mubkam and Mutasbabib.......... 153
Ta \vll as a Method for Understanding the Mutasbabibdt..................... 154

ix
The Importance of Reason as the Source of Ta wil: An
Epistemological Analysis 159
Rational and Traditional Proofs 161
Solution to the Contradiction between Rational and Traditional
Proofs 168
Ibn Taymiyyah’s Response 170

CHAPTER FIVE: AL-RAZI’S TREATMENT


OF THE ANTHROPOMORPHIC VERSES 174
Introduction 174
God’s Image and the Form of Adam 175
God’s Face 181
The Vision of Allah (Ru’yat Allah) 186
The Affirmation of Direction (al-jihah) with regard to God. 192
God’s Hand 198
Conclusion: Al-Razi’s General Method in Treatin

CfQ
the Anthropomorphic Verses 200

CONCLUSION 203

BIBLIOGRAPHY 207
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

Arbain Al-Razi, Kitab al-Arbain ft Usui al-Din

Asas Al-Razi, Asas al-Taqdls

Controversies Fathalla Kholeif, A Study on Fakbr al-Din al-Razi


and His Controversies in Transoxiana

El First Encyclopedia of Islam

EI2 Encyclopedia of Islam, New Edition

Fakbr al-Din Salih Zarkan, Fakbr al-Din al-Razi wa Ara’ubu al-


Kaldmiyyab wa al-Falsafiyyab

Farq Al-Baghdadi, Al-Farq bayna al-Firaq

Fas I Ibn Hazm, al-Fasl ft al-Milal wa al-Abwa’ wa al-


Nibal

Ibanah Al-Ash'ari, al-Ibanab ‘an Usui al-Diyanab

Irshad Al-Juwayni, al-Irsbad ila Qawdti al-Adillab ft Usui


al-Ftiqad

Lawdmi Al-Razi, Lawdmi al-Bayyindt Sharh Asma’Allah


Ta‘ala wa-al-Sifdt

Maalim Al-Razi, Maalim ft Usui al-Din

Mabahitb Al-Razi, al-Mababith al-Mashriqiyyah ft ‘Ilm al-


Ilabiyydt wa al-Tabi‘iyydt

Mabsul Al-Razi, al-Mabsul ft ‘Ilm al-Usul

Maqalat Al-Ash'ari, Maqalat al-Islamiyyin wa Ikhtilaf al-


Musallin

Masail Al-Razi, al-Masall al-Khamsunft Usui al-Din

xi
Matalib Al-Razi, al-Matalib Aliyah min al-Ilm al-Ilahi

Milal Al-Shahrastani, Kitab al-Milal wa al-Nihal

Muhassal Al-Razi, Muhassal Afkar al-Mutaqaddimin wa al-


Mutadkhkhirin min al-TJlama’wa al-Hukama’wa
al-Mutakallimin

Muqaddimah Ibn Khaldun, Muqaddimah

Nihayat Al-Shahrastani, Nihayat al-Iqddm fi Tim al-Kalam

Sharh al-Aqald Al-Taftazani, Sharh alAqarid al-Nasafiyyah

Tafsir Al-Razi, al-Tafsir al-Kabir

Tahafut Al-Ghazali, Tahafut al-Faldsifah

Ta \vil Ibn Qutaybah, Ta \vil Mukhtalif al-Hadith

Theology Yasin Ceylan, Theology and Tafsir in the Major


Works of Fakhr al-Din al-Razi

xii
INTRODUCTION

STATEMENT OF THE PROBLEM

The Qur’an is replete with messages of the transcendence of God. Apart from

emphasizing the unity of God (tawhfd), many verses expound the absolute
dissimilarity between God and His creatures.1 The mutakallimun, concurring

with this enormous stress laid by the Qur’an, affirmed that divine transcendence

(tanzih) is one of the underlying principles in arriving at the understanding of

God. However, the Qur’an, as well as the Prophetic traditions, also employ

anthropomorphic (tashbih) language in describing some of God’s qualities and

actions. God, for example, is described as having ‘limbs’ such as hands,2 face3 and

eyes.4 He is also described as sitting (on the Throne),5 descending (to the earthly

heavens),6 forgetful,7 feeling angry8 and happy.9 Verses with these descriptions,

known as those whose meanings are not clearly established (ayat mutasbabihat),

depict a somewhat different aspect of divine reality compared to the verses which

emphasize the absolute uniqueness of God. As far as the history of kalam is

concerned, this contrasting description of God was not in the beginnin felt as a

tension or contradiction but later on, due to geographical expansion of Islamic CfQ

territories and conversion of people from various religions into Islam, there

1 Such as the verse, “Nothing is like unto Him” (laysa ka mitblihi shay*), al-Shura 42:11, and
“There is none like unto Him” (lam yakun labukufuwan a had), al-Ikhlas 112:4.
2 Al-Qur’an, Sad 38:57, al-Fath 48:10.
3 Al-Qur’an, al-Qasas 28:88.
4 Al-Qur'an, Hud 11:37, Ta Ha 20:39, al-Tur 52:38.
5 Al-Qur’an, Ta Ha 20:5.
6 Based on a Hadith which says, “God waits until three quarters of night and He descends to the
earthly heaven and says, “Is there any one who seek my pardon or make a prayer, until the
dawn,” Ibn Khuzaymah, Kitab al-Tawhid \va Itbbat Sfat al-Rabb (Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-
'Ilmiyyah, 1983), 126.
7 Al-Qur’an, al-Tawbah 9:67
8 Al-Qur’an, al-Nisa’ 4:93
9 Ibn Maj ah, “Masajid”, no. 800, Sunan. Ed. Muhammad Fuad 'Abd al-Baqi (Bayrut: al-
Maktabah al- 'Ilmiyyah, 1954), vol.l, 262.

1
emerged different sects which insisted on taking the literal meaning of the

mutashdbihat. They soon began attributing anthropomorphic qualities to God.

Thus, the unity and transcendence of God, which is the pristine pillar of Islamic

theology, began to be challenged by these anthropomorphic interpretations.

Although this challenge did not become a major threat to the mainstream Islamic

theology, it compelled the mutakallimun to provide a considerable amount of

substantial and systematic arguments in refuting these ideas.

Apparently, there were many modes of interpretations in dealing with the

anthropomorphic expressions in the Qur’an ranging from crude emphasis of the

literal meanin to the allegorical.10 At the two opposite extremes, there are the
CfQ

ta ctil (divesting God of all attributes) of the Mu tazilah and the Jabmiyyab who

gorically reject any anthropomorphic meanings regarding God’s attributes


pr-b
CD

while at the same time, introducing allegorical interpretation (ta’wil) of the

mutashdbihat verses of the Qur’an. The meanings intended by God in these

expressions, according to them, are conveyed metaphorically; God’s hand is His

power, God’ eye is His essence, and so on. On the other extreme, there were

those who resolutely stuck to the literal meaning and insisted that there are no

other meanings conveyed by these expressions beside the literal ones. Taking

God’s words as absolute and immutable, they confined themselves to accepting

only the literal implications of the expressions. The extreme among them went

to the extent of affirming a physical size of God, that God, for example, is no

larger than the Jabal Qubays in Mecca.11 They were called the musbabbibab,

10 R. Strothman, “Tashbih,” El, vol. 8, 685. Abrahamov identifies three different ways adopted by
Muslim scholars in treating the anthropomorphic expressions. First, those who adopted the literal
meanings of these expressions saying, for example, that God has a face, hands and that He sits on
His throne. Second, those who interpreted these expressions in a figurative way. Thus, God’s
hand implies His power and His sitting on the throne means His rule over the world. Third, who
accepted the sacred text as it is without trying to interpret its modality (kayflyyah'). Binyamin
Abrahamov, “The Bila Kayfa Doctrine and Its Foundations in Islamic Theology,” ARABICA,
Journal of Arabic and Islamic Studies, Tome XLII, No. 3 (Nov. 1995): 365.
11 This is the view of Abu al-Hudhayl, one of the early Mu tazilah. Maqalat, vol.l, 281-282.

2
those who perform tashbib, namely comparing and making God similar with His

creation, especially man, by ascribing human characteristics to Him.

Tashbib emer ed in various degrees as reflected in the different names

CfQ
and designations rendered by heresiographical scholars and mutakallimun to

those who uphold it.12 In general, they were called mushabbibah due to the fact

that they made God similar to His creation by ascribing some of their

characteristics to Him. This assimilation, however, varies depending upon the

nature of the assimilation. Broadly classified, there were at least two forms of
tasbbib prevalent in the history of Islamic thought.13 The first form is plain

literalism wherein the literal meanings of the anthropomorphic expressions were

upheld and metaphorical meanings were rejected. The theological implication of

this position is the affirmation of God having all the anthropomorphic qualities

including the ‘organs’ mentioned in the Qur’an. This view was held by the

extreme segment of the Hanabilah whose anthropomorphic tendency was

rejected even by other scholars from the same theological school. It was

evidenced, for example, in the criticism of Ibn al-Jawzi (d.1210), one of the

prominent Hanabilah, ainst their views.14 The second form of

anthropomorphism is what we term as ‘philosophical literalism,’ a literal approach

that is further substantiated with rational and philosophical arguments. This

approach is best represented by the Karramiyyah and some Shi T individuals such

as Hisham b. al-Hakam and Hisham b. Salim al-Jawaliki who, although started

from the literal understanding of the Scripture, were later on influenced by some

philosophical ideas such as the idea of the eternity of the world. Based on the

12 The mujassimab, for example, were called as such due to their ascription of body (jisrri) to God;
the Hululiyyah were so-called due to their subscription to the idea of divine incarnation (hulul).
Others, however, derived their names from their leaders such as the Karr amiyyah, Hishamiyyah,
Bayaniyyah, and Azaqirah. SeeFarq, 18-40; Maqalat, vol.l, 281-290.
13 These two forms of tasbbih are also al-Razi’s main object of criticism which will be analyzed
later.
14 Ibn al-Jawzi, Daf‘Sbubab al-Tasbbib bi Akuff al-Tanzib, ed. Hassan Saqqaf (Amman: Dar al-
Imam al-Nawawi, 2000).

3
anthropomorphic qualities mentioned in the Qur’an, they try to justify their

ascription of these qualities to God by applying the philosophical concepts of

substance, accidents, atom and body.15

The musbabbibah position, however, must be differentiated from the

position of the early generations of the Muslims (al-salaf) who took a safe and

precautions stand in approaching the problem of anthropomorphism. Their

position was often associated with Malik ibn Anas’s saying that “God’s sitting on

the Throne is known, but its modality is unknown, and belief in it is obligatory

while inquiring about it is an innovation” (al-istiwa’ ma qul al-kayf majbul al-

Iman bibi wajib wa al-su’al anbu bidab).16 Later on, this principle was

developed and known as bila kayf (without modality) in which the

anthropomorphic attributes are accepted without further inquiry regarding their

modality. Although the fine line dividing the salaf and the musbabbibab is

sometimes regarded by their adversaries, the Mu tazilab, as obscure, due to their

rejection of allegorical interpretation (tahvil), one discernible difference, as

pointed out by al-Razi, is that the salaf maintain that the meanings that are

intended by God through these anthropomorphic expressions are not literal,

hence the meanings must be entrusted to God (tafwidma haba ila Allah).17 The

musbabbibab, on the other hand, adhere and insist on the literal and

anthropomorphic meanings and further support their position by their own

rational construction.

15 For further views of the Karramiyyah and these individuals, see al-Farq, 18-36; Milal, 88-96;
W.M.Watt, Islamic Philosophy and Theology: An Extended Survey (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 1985), 79-81; A.S.Tritton, Muslim Theology (Bristol: The Royal Asiatic
Society, 1947), 74-78, 108-112.
16 Milal, 65; al-Baghdadi, Usui al-Dih (Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah, 1981), 113.
17 Asas, 208.

4
AL-RAZI AS A CHAMPION AGAINST ANTHROPOMORPHISM

Among the mutakallimun who had been actively involved in the polemic against

anthropomorphism was Abu 'Abd Allah Muhammad bin 'Umar b. al-Husayn,

better known as Fakhr al-Din al-Razi, one of the most important Ash'arite

>
mutakallimun of the twelfth century. staunch critic of the mushabbihah

views especially those prevailing at his time, al-Razi took the task of defending

the divine transcendence through his systematic refutation of the

anthropomorphic ideas of the mushabbihah especially in his theological work

Asas al-Taqdis. Born in Rayy, northern Persia in 1149, al-Razi (d.1209) was a

famous mutakallim of the thirteenth century. He was a celebrated scholar of his


19 and was regarded as the reviver of Islam in the twelfth century.20 Both
time,18

he and al-Ghazali were esteemed as the founder of the new school in kalam

which was mainly characterized by its maximal employment of logico-

philosophical tools in kalam. Although he was known mainly as a mutakallim,

al-Razi’s brilliant and encyclopedic mind enabled him to write in many fields of

knowledge such as philosophy, logic, fiqh, physics, medicine and astronomy. Ibn

Khallikan rightly acknowledged al-Razi’s great intellectual ability when he

remarked that the latter was the “greatest authority on the Greek sciences of his

time and surpassed all his contemporaries in theology, metaphysics and

18 Information regarding the life and works of al-Razi can be found in many sources some of
which will be continuously mentioned in this introduction. Among the important works that
provide biographical information on al-Razi are Salih Zarkan, Fakhr al-Din al-Razi wa Ara’uhu
al-Kalamiyyah wa al-Falsafiyyah (Egypt: Darul Fikr, 1963); Yasin Ceylan, Theology and Tafsir
in the Major Works of Fakhr al-Dih al-Razi (Kuala Lumpur: 1STAC, 1996); Seyyed Hossein
Nasr, “Fakhr al-Din al-Razi”, in M. M. Sharif, (ed.), A History of Muslim Philosophy,
(Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, 1963), 642-656; Tony Street, ‘Concerning the Life and Works of
Fakhr al-Din al-Razi’, Islam: Essays on Scripture, Thought and Society: A Festschrift in Honour
of Anthony H. fohns, ed. Peter G. Riddell & Tony Street (Leiden: Brill, 1997); G. C. Anawati,
“Fakhr al-Din al-Razi,” EI2, vol. II, 751-755.
19 Al-Razi was also known through other titles such as Imam al-Fakhr and Ibn al-Khatib. He
was bom in a family of scholars and had his father Diya’ al-Din, a well-known scholar of Rayy
as his first teacher. Later on, he studied various disciplines in Rayy and Maraghah under
Muhammad al-Baghawi and Majd al-Din al-Jili (who was also the teacher of Shihab al-Din al-
Suhrawardi) and Kamal al-Din al-Simnani. Theology, 1.
20 Nasr, “Fakhr al-Din al-Razi,” 642.

5
philosophy.” His analytical and philosophical mind can be seen, for example,

through his critical commentaries on a number of Ibn Sina’s works such as al-

22 In kalam, he wrote many monumental works


Isharat and Uy un aTJTikmab.21

such as Mufassal, Arbam fi Usui al-Diri, Matalib Aliyab and Mabahitb al-

Masbriqiyyab, which propound important aspects of kalam, putting him at par

with his predecessors such as al-Baqillani, al-Juwayni and al-Ghazali who had

contributed to the refinement of the Ash'arite kalam. Al-Razi’s independent

approach is also apparent in his disagreements with his predecessors on a number

of issues based on his own justified arguments. His important contribution to

the enrichment of later Ash'arite kalam is also evidenced by the influence of

some of his theological ideas on later Asha rite mutakallimun, such as ‘All al-

Jurjani and Sa cl al-Din al-Taftazani.23 Al-Razi was also known as a mufassir

through his voluminous Qur commentary, Tafsir al-Kabir, which is

re arded as a systematic tafsir due to the great emphasis he placed on describing

the interconnections between the Qur’anic chapters and verses. This is also
associated with his belief in the unity of truth between philosophy and religion.24 25

As far as anthropomorphism is concerned, al-Razi was strongly opposed

by the musbabbibab especially the Karramiyyab. Equipped with strong logical

and philosophical tools together with his courage and convincing eloquent

oratory, he held debates with the leaders of the Karramiyyab and converted

many of them into the fold of Abl al-Sunnab wa al-famaab.26 At the same

21 Ibn Khallikan, Wafayat al-A yan, trans. MacGuckin De Slane (London: Johnson Reprint
Corporation, 1843), vol. 2, 652.
22Although critical of Ibn Sina, al-Razi was also influenced by many of Ibn Sina’s philosophical
ideas. He was also influenced in physics by another scholar, Abu al-Barakat al-Baghdadi.
23 See Chapter Four, 168-169.
24 Theology, 6.
25 See information about Karramiyyab in Chapter One, 29, n.53.
26 See the introduction of M. Saghir Hasan Ma’sumi, Imam Razfs c Ilm al-Akhlaq, being an
English translation of his Kitab al-Nafs \va al-Ruh wa Sharh Quwabuma with introduction and
commentary (Islamabad: Islamic Research Institute, 1970), 6.

6
time, his continuous attacks on their views during his travel in many places,2

had also stirred great hostility among the Karramiyyab against him. They, in

turn, leveled severe allegations against him, and even threatened his life. Similar

hostile attitude towards him was also shown by the Hartabilab and the Isma ills
due to his bitter criticism against their doctrines.27
28 29

Apart from his criticisms against the musbabbibab in his theological

works, al-Razi composed specific work, Asas al-Taqdis2 which was

particularly intended to refute the two forms of tasbbib we mentioned above. In

this work, he underlined the paramount importance of preserving the divine

transcendence by advancing substantial rational and traditional proofs against the

major premises underlying the views of the musbabbibab. Arguing that God is

an existent beyond the reach of human senses, al-Razi further drew attention to

the stark differences between the transcendent understanding of God and the

notion of body (jism) and direction (jibah), the two main qualities which were

attributed to God by the musbabbibab. He made use of the already established

kalam discussion of body (/ism), substance (jawbar) and accident (arad) to show

that God is essentially different from the characteristics of bodies. These bodies

are homo eneous, located in a certain direction and in need of each other and all
CfQ

these are important indications of the physical nature of corporeal beings, which

are utterly inappropriate to the divine nature. In principle, al-Razi maintained

that any attempt to locate God in a direction as attempted by the musbabbibab,

27 Al-Razi’s intellectual life was very much coloured by his travels into various places as well as
having patronized by several rulers. After completed his studies in Rayy, he traveled to
Khawarizm where he held debates with the Mu tazilah. He then moved to Transoxiana and was
accepted at the Courts of the Ghur rulers, Ghiyath al-Din and Shihab al-Din. After receiving
antagonistic and hostile opposition from certain scholars, he left Ghur to Ghaznah where he
stayed for a while in the Court of Ghaznah. He finally settled in Herat where he taught under
the patronage of Khwarizm Shah ‘Ala’ al-Din until the end of his life.
28 Ma’sumi, 11-14; Theology, 3.
29 Ed. Ahmad Hijazi al-Saqa (Bayrut: Dar al-Jil, 1993).

7
would only end up attributing to God characteristics which are impossible to

Him.

God, al-Razi argued, is an existent beyond the grasp of human senses. As

Supreme Being, He has neither any equal nor resemblance (nazir wa sbabib).

The uniqueness of his existence is affirmed both by reason and the Scripture,

hence, no physical principles can be applied to the existence of God. Once the

divine transcendence is upheld, it follows, epistemologically, that the

anthropomorphic verses or expressions in the Scripture cannot be taken literally.

In line with this position, al-Razi put forward an important epistemological

principle that if there is any contradiction between the Scripture with the already

established rational principle, the latter must be maintained. The acceptance of

the former will only lead to the impingement upon the divine transcendence

which has already been firmly established. Furthermore, inconsistency in a

scriptural message is unacceptable since it would denigrate its integrity as a

divine message. As way out, al-Razi maintained that the mutasbabibat verses

must be dealt with in the strong precaution of preserving the divine

transcendence by using the methodology of ta Xvil, an allegorical interpretation of

a verse. Nevertheless, ta\vil must be based on the proper identification of the

ambiguous verses (mutasbabibat) and appropriate assignment of their meanings

based on the verses which have established meaning (mufikamat) and

substantiated by conclusive proofs. Above all that, ta\vil should only be carried

out by qualified people. Al-Razi admitted that tafwid, namely to entrust the

meaning of the mutasbabibat to God, as done by the salaf, is the safest way in

dealing with anthropomorphic verses, yet this should not prevent those who are

deeply rooted in knowledge and those who believe that the whole meaning of the

Qur’an is comprehensible from establishing the appropriate meaning of these

verses.

8
OBJECTIVE OF THIS STUDY

The subject we are dealing in this study can be briefly phrased as the problem of

anthropomorphism (tashbih). In particular, this study is an analysis, through one

of al-Razi’s works, Asas al-Taqdis, of a methodology in interpreting or

understanding the meaning of the anthropomorphic expressions concerning

certain qualities of God mentioned in the Scripture and in the Prophetic traditions

with an underlying emphasis in preserving the divine transcendence. In

achieving this objective, this study aims, first, at examinin al-Razi s views on

CfQ
divine transcendence through his views on the divine attributes. It also seeks to

elaborate his defense of divine transcendence through his refutation, scripturally

and rationally, of the views of the Musbabbibah regarding God. It then analyzes

al-Razi’s method of interpreting the anthropomorphic verses.

Due to the interrelated subject matter of the study, this research dwells

not only within the realm of kalam but also encroaches into another important

field in Islam, namely, tafsir. Simply put, it begins with kalam but ends with

tafsir. Since the principle of divine transcendence is mostly elaborated in kalam,

the theological discussions leading to its establishment is the main concern of this

study, while the problem of understanding the anthropomorphic expressions

through the discussion of mufkamat and mutasbabihat falls under the domain of

tafsir. The selection of al-Razi as its intellectual figure and this topic in

particular is, to us, duly fitting. For our scholar was well known as both

mutakallim and a mufassir. In kalam, as mentioned before, he was an eminent

and notable later Ash'arite scholar whose theological ideas have left repercussions

in the theological discussion of the later mutakallim un. While in tafsir, his

magnum opus, Tafsir al-Kabir, has been regarded as the greatest work both in

volume and importance, encyclopedic in nature combining various disciplines in

9
one work.3 In addition, al-Razi’s mastery of language, philosophy, and kalam

has great significance in his discussion concerning the way the anthropomorphic

verses should be comprehended.

PREVIOUS STUDIES AND THE SCOPE OF THIS STUDY

To the best of our knowledge, there has been no specific study on al-Razi’s views

regarding divine transcendence and anthropomorphism. Neither is there any

particular analysis of al-Razi’s Kitab Asas al-Taqdfs apart from al-Saqa’s

comments as an appendix in his edition of this work.3 Nevertheless, within

more general and comprehensive study on al-Razi’s theological thought, this

subject is included, for example, in Salih Zarkan’s comprehensive study on al-

Razi’s theology, Fakhr al-Dfn al-Razf wa Ara’uhu al-Kalamiyyah wa al-


Falsafiyyah.32 In this work, Zarkan deals with the divine transcendence under

the subject of negative attributes (sifat salbiyyah) which includes the

purification of God from any physical qualities. Another similar work is that by

Yasin Ceylan, Theology and Tafsir in the Major Works of Fakhr al-Dih al-Razf33

These two published works also prove to be invaluable to access al-Razi’s

theological views as a whole.

There are also several articles which partially discuss al-Razi’s view on

some aspects of the problem of divine transcendence and anthropomorphism.30

30 Also known as Mafatih al-Gbayb, this Quranic commentary (32 vols., al-Qahirah edition) is
re arded as the most extensive exegesis based on individual opinion and reasoning (tafsir bi al-
tn

ra V). Its vast discussions cover various kinds of knowledge, including many views of different
sects such as the Mu tazilab, the philosophers, Karramiyyab. The extensive nature of this work
is evidenced, among others, in al-Razi’s discussion of Surat al-Fatihah in which he said that from
this particular chapter alone, 10,000 problems can be extracted. As reported by al-Dhahabi, Abu
Hayyan in his work Bahr al-Muhft remarked that this work “has everything in it except tafsir”
(This statement is also attributed to Ibn Taymiyyah). Al-Husayn al-Dhahabi, al-Tafsrr wa al-
Mufassirun. (Al-Qahirah: Dar al-Kutub al-Hadithah,1986), vol.l, 289-296.
31 See appendix in al-Razi, Asas al-Taqdfs, ed. Ahmad Hijazi al-Saqa (Bayrut: Dar al-Jil, 1993),
229-245.
32 Egypt: Darul Fikr, 1963.
33 Kuala Lumpur: ISTAC, 1996.

10
Shalahudin Kafrawi has written an article Fakhr al-Dih al-Razfs Sources of

Ta’wil: Between Revelation and Reason34 in which he focuses on the role of

revelation and reason in his tafsir. Ta \vil, as a manifestation of the central role

of reason in the interpretation of revelation, dominates the whole article.

Another article which investigates al-Razi’s view on ta\vil and the relation

between reason and revelation is written by Nicholas Heer, The Priority of

Reason in the Interpretation of Scripture: Ibn Taymiyyah and The

Mutakallimun35 Although the central focus of the article is the refutation of Ibn

Taymiyyah of the views of Asharite mutakallimun especially al-Razi, Heer

began by discussing the view of al-Razi on the issue. The Ash'arites’ position

with re ard to the conflict between reason and scripture, according to Heer, is to
CfQ

invariably give priority to reason over scripture and al-Razi was among those

who strongly emphasizes this principle. Binyamin Abrahamov discusses the

view of al-Razi on the transcendent aspect of divine essence and attributes in his

article “Fakhr al-Din al-Razi on the Knowability of God’s Essence and


Attributes.”36 He argues that al-Razi, like al-Ghazali, in his later works changed

his mind concerning human’s knowledge of God’s essence and adopted the

philosophical position that His essence cannot be known. Another relevant

article is Binyamin Abrahamov’s “The Bi-la Kayfa Doctrine and Its Foundations

in Islamic Theology” which elaborates the position of bild kayf especially among

the mutakallimun37 He maintains that the arguments based on the bila kayfa

doctrine had a dual function. One the one hand, they served as a weapon against

anthropomorphism and against figurative interpretation, and on the other, they

34 In Islamic Quarterly: A Review of Islamic Culture, vol. XLIII, no. 3 (Third Quarter, 1999).
35 In Literary Heritage of Classical Islam:Arabic and Islamic Studie in Honour of fames A.
Bellamys, ed. Mustansir Mir (Princeton: The Darwin Press, Inc., 1993).
36 ARABICA, Journal of Arabic and Islamic Studies, Tome XLIX, no. 2 (2002).
37 Ibid., Tome XLII, Fascicule 3 (Nov. 1995).

11
aimed at strengthening the thesis of the unknowability of God’s essence and

attributes.38

The subject of anthropomorphism alone has become the interest of several

people. R. Strothman wrote an article under the heading “tasbbib” in the First

Encyclopedia of Islam in which he analysed the words relating to the issue such

as tasbbib (likening God to His creatures), tamtbil (giving simile to God), ta\vil

(allegorical interpretation), tanzib (keeping God pure) and ta ‘til (divesting God of

attributes). Maintaining that the anthropomorphic verses in the Qur’an have

been interpreted in various degrees, he also admitted the difficulties in

approaching the question since none of the Muslim theologians openly declare

that they are anthropomorphists but rather everyone asserts tanzib as opposed to

tasbbib.39 Nevertheless, the issue of anthropomorphism, according to him, hinges

upon two extreme positions, namely, tasbbib, held by many groups such as the

Karramiyyab and some of the Hanabilab, and ta ‘til which is held by the

Jabmiyyab and the Mu tazilab. He analysed views of some theological figures

who were involved in these polemics such as Jahm bin Safwan, the earliest

muattilab, Ahmad ibn Hanbal, who introduced the bila kayf method, and

Hisham b. al-Hakam, a stark exemplar of the anthropomorphists. Strothman,

however, differentiates between tasbbib and tajsim claiming that the latter is less

severe since the mujassimab like Hisham b. al-Hakam usually add the phrase
“not like our body” in their views when comparing God with human beings.40

William Montgomery Watt wrote two articles entitled “Some Muslim

Discussions of Anthropomorphism” and “Created in His Image: A Study in

Islamic Theology,” both found in his book, Early Islam.41 In the first article,

Watt points out that tasbbib was first raised by the Mu tazilab and Jabmiyyab

38 Ibid, 378.
39 Strothman, “Tashbih”, El, 685.
40 Ibid, 687.
41 Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1990.

12
by way of accusing the main body of the ‘orthodox’ Muslim belief of the heresy

of tashbih. Nevertheless, Watt maintains that the Mutazilah and Jabmiyyah

were not influenced by Greek philosophy, but they merely found in the armory

of Hellenistic thought useful weapons against their opponents. The emphasis on

the otherness of God vis-a-vis tashbih, according to Watt, is the contribution of

later theologians in developing one important factor in the Qur’anic conception of

God. As for the method of ta \vil, which to Watt had a much narrower sense than

the word ‘metaphor’ in English, it has become the solving mechanism especially

to the Mu tazilab and the Jabmiyyab in their treatment of the anthropomorphic

verses. On the other hand, there is another method that of bila kayf, or

balkafiyyah, a doctrine which prescribes that we are justified in using mundane

predicates of God without explaining exactly how they apply to Him. By

clinging to the text of the Qur’an and regarding it as the very word of God, the

orthodox, who were very much associated with this method, affirmed that if the

Qur’an spoke of God’s hands and face, then God must have hands and face.

How God, who is incorporeal, can have hands and a face may be difficult to

understand, but this difficulty is not a valid reason for rejecting the words of

Scripture. According to them, one must maintain both the authority of the

Scripture and the incorporeality of God even one cannot reconcile them

intellectually. Watt continues to examine the employment of this method by

the Asbairab and how at a later stage they preferred ta’wil to balkafiyyab. In

his other article entitled “Created in His Image: A Study in Islamic Theology” in

the same collection, Watt evaluates the view of the mufassirun regarding the

Prophetic tradition, “Verily God has created Adam according to his form” (inna

Allah khalaqa Adam ala suratibf) which implies the similarity between the

image of God and the form of Adam. Asserting that this issue has been the

interest of many scholars including theologians, philosophers and Sufis who have

42 Watt, “Some Muslim Discussion,” 88.

13
given various kinds of interpretations, he concludes that the view that rejected

the similarity between God and man won the day.43 Watt concludes that the

study has introduced us to one of the deep tensions in Islamic thought - the

tension between those who hold God’s absolute uniqueness, and those who

believed that there is an affinity between God and man.


In his translation of Kitab al-Mustarsbid44 of al-Qasim ibn Ibrahim

(d.860), an early Sbfab figure, Binyamin Abrahamov has given in his

introduction, resourceful analysis regarding the issue and history of

anthropomorphism. His introduction also includes the discussion of the Qur’an

in al-Qasim’s writings and al-Qasim’s ways of interpretation of the Qur’an which

reveal the basic arguments in refuting the musbabbibab. In his refutation of

tasbbib, al-Qasim, according to Abrahamov, seems to have followed the

Mu tazilab with regard to both content and method; for example, the use of

ta \vil, the discussion of words, prepositions and homonyms, providing pieces of

evidence from the ordinary use of language and from poetry.45 In this six-chapter

work, all efforts are focused on the writer’s refutation of the view of the

musbabbibab particularly that which is based on the Quranic verses, such as the

view that God is in the heavens, God has a soul like the human soul, God is light

just as created light, God is composed of parts, God’s face is like the human face

and that God can be seen in the Hereafter.

Since there has been no specific study of al-Razi’s view regarding divine

transcendence and anthropomorphism, the present work intends to do so. Apart

from tackling the issue of anthropomorphism, this study also examines al-Razi’s

conception of divine attributes which becomes the basis of his thought regarding

divine transcendence. By doing so, this study, at the same time, attempts an

43 Ibid., 99.
44 Under the title Anthropomorphism and Interpretation of the Qur’an in the Theology of al-
Qasim Ibn Ibrahim (Leiden: E.J.Brill, 1996).
45 Abrahamov, Anthropomorphism, 8.

14
evaluation of the later Asbairah position regarding anthropomorphism and how

it differs especially from that of its founder, Abu Hassan al-Ashari. Since the

Asbairah were different from the Mutazilah in their theological approach, it is

also the interest of this study to examine the theological differences between

these two schools.

SOURCES OF THE STUDY

The sources of this study can be divided into four categories: Al-Razi’s own

works, the works of the mutakallimun before and after him, secondary sources

on al-Razi, and other secondary sources. In the first category, the main source of

this study is al-Razi’s Kitab Asas al-Taqdis. Several other kalam works of al-

Razi also serve as our main cross-references. Among the important ones are al-

Muhassal, Arba m fl Usd al- Dm and Ma alim fl Usd al-Dih. We also

depended heavily on al-Razi’s Tafsir al-Kabir, also known as Mafatih al-Gbayb,

especially in examining his interpretations of anthropomorphic expressions in the

Qur’an. As to the works of other mutakallimun, we referred mainly to some of

the works of A sb arf mutakallimun before and after him for comparison such as

al-Ashari’s Maqalat al-Islamiyyih and al-Ibanah, al-Ghazali’s Tahafut al-

Falasifah, and al-Shahrastani’s Nibayat al-Iqdam. Al-Taftazani’s Sbarh al-

Maqasid, and al-Jurjani’s Sbarh al-Mawaqif were consulted mostly for the

verification of al-Razi’s influence on later mutakallimun.

Several secondary sources were also of great help in our study. The ones

on al-Razi are Salih Zarkan’s Fakbr al-Dih al-Razi wa Ara’ubu al-Kalamiyyah

wa al-Falsafah,46 Yasin Ceylan’s Theology and Tafsir in the Major Works of

Fakbr al-Dih al-Razi,47 48Fathalla Kholleifs Fakbr al-Dih al-Razi4* and

Muhammad al-Uraybi’s Muntalaqat al-Fikriyyab inda al-Imam al-Fakbr al-

46 Egypt: Dar al-Fikr, 1963.


47 Kuala Lumpur: ISTAC, 1996.
48 Iskandariah: Dar al-Maarif, 1969.

15
Razi.49 Other sources which are not directly related to al-Razi nevertheless have

provided some insights regarding the issue constitute the last category of our

sources. These includes writings on kalam and Islamic philosophy as a whole

such as William Montgomery Watt’s Islamic Philosophy and Theology: An

Extended Survey,50 Harry A. Wolfson’s The Philosophy of Kalam,51 Alnoor

Dhanani’s The Physical Theory of Kalam,52 and Majid Fakhry’s A History of

Islamic Philosophy 53

METHODOLOGY AND SIGNIFICANCE OF THIS STUDY

Our study focuses on the textual analysis of al-Razi’s Asas al-Taqdis, a work

which contains his arguments against the anthropomorphists. This textual

analysis is preceded by a theological and historical survey on the issue followed

by a conceptual deliberation on al-Razi’s view on divine transcendence which is

exemplified by his discussion on divine attributes. In analyzing the text, other

kalam works of al-Razi, as alluded before, were consulted for corroboration and

cross-reference. Hence, the issue that was analyzed in the text was further

examined with the help of other materials relevant to the text.

The significance of this study lies in the following: First, it portrays the

later Ash'arite theological method in comprehending the issue of

anthropomorphism. As the mainstream theological school in Sunni kalam which

have survived and flourished throughout Islamic history, it is important to note

that the Ashairah, as observed by Pines, were able to acquire this position due to

“the solutions they offered to the theological problems associated with creation,

49 Bayrut: Dar al-Fikr al-Lubnani, 1992.


50 Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1985.
51 Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1976.
52 Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1994.
53 New York: Columbia University Press, 2nd edn, 1983.

16
divine knowledge and revelation.” 4 Al-Razi was one of the important Ash'arite

mutakallimun. who contributed to this solution. Second, this study offers an

alternative method to the extreme position in the understanding of certain verses

of the Qur’an prevailing among some Muslims today. A more moderate

interpretation of the Qur’an, as will be shown by this study, will prevent

Muslims from either falling into the abyss of anthropomorphism due to their

strict literalism, or of making God unknowable to mankind by stripping Him of

any attribute. Thirdly, the present study throws some light on the views of

mutakallimun. re arding the relation between reason and revelation and how this
CfQ

epistemological problem should be dealt with in Islam.

PLAN OF THE STUDY

This thesis is divided into five chapters. The introduction, as discussed, explains

the sources and significance of the study. The first chapter provides the

background of the issue by surveying theological views on divine transcendence

and anthropomorphism prior to al-Razi. It gives the rational and scriptural basis

of divine transcendence in Islam including the terms used to indicate divine

transcendence in the Islamic tradition. It continues with an ideological map of

the main theological schools directly involved in the polemic concernin CfQ
the

problem of anthropomorphism commencing with the views of the musbabbibab,

followed by responses against anthropomorphism by different sects, such as the

Mu tazilab and the Jabmiyyab, before it concludes with the views of the

Asbairab prior to al-Razi.

The second chapter deals with al-Razi’s conception of divine attributes

including the definition of attributes and their difference from divine names. His

view on the nature of attributes and their relation to divine essence reflects his

54 Shlomo Pines, Studies in Islamic Atomism, translated from German by Michael Schwarz
(Jurusalem: The Magnes Press, 1997), 1.

17
A sb hr?" inclination as well as his difference, contrary to some claims, with the

Mu tazilab. This chapter further analyzes al-Razi’s classification of attributes

and the position of divine transcendence in his classification and how his position

on transcendence impinges on his classification of attributes and consequently

serves as a strong foundation for his attack on his adversaries.

The third chapter examines al-Razi’s rational and traditional proofs of

divine transcendence, and his arguments for rejecting anthropomorphism. He

refuted two of the most important premises underlying the views of the

anthropomorphists regarding God: first, that God is a body (/ism) or a substance

(jawbar) and second, that God occupies space (mutahayyiz'). We regard this

chapter as the most important one in this study since it focuses on al-Razi’s main

arguments against the Musbabbibab as exemplified in his work Asas al-Taqdis.

Chapter four analyzes al-Razi’s view on muJjkamat and mutasbabibat, the

two important categories of verses mentioned by the Qur’an. It aims at knowing

how al-Razi viewed these two categories and elaborates his method in identifying

and categorizing the verses. This is followed by his views on the way to deal with

the mutasbabibat. This chapter also evaluates Razi’s idea of ta’wil which is

considered as an alternative method in dealing with anthropomorphic expressions

in the Qur’an.

The final chapter demonstrates how al-Razi applied the method of ta \vil

in his explanation and commentary of the anthropomorphic verses in the Qur’an

which appear to be in conflict with the epistemological basis that he has laid

down. A few anthropomorphic expressions that appear in the Qur’an are

selected as examples in elucidating the use of ta ’wil in arriving at an

understanding of anthropomorphic verses in the Qur’an.

18
CHAPTER ONE

DIVINE TRANSCENDENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF

ANTHROPOMORPHISM: A THEOLOGICAL BACKGROUND

INTRODUCTION: RATIONAL AND SCRIPTURAL BASIS OF DIVINE


TRANSCENDENCE

It goes without saying that divine transcendence has been an essential aspect in

describing the attributes of God among the mutakallimun. as well as theologians of

other religions.1 God is described as being unique and bearing no resemblance to

any corporeal and human characteristics. This concept has a firm basis both from

the rational and scriptural point of view. Rationally, the idea of a transcendent God

is harmonious with reason such that any exercise of reason, if it is carried out with

valid and appropriate way will lead to the co nition of the transcendent God.
CfQ

Hence, the Greek philosophers already propounded this idea by maintaining that

among the constituent elements of the notion of God is that He must be

transcendent Being and that He exists apart from both man and the world.2 Harry

Wolfson described the ancient origin of this doctrine in his history of philosophy

and religion:

The conception of God as a being who is above knowledge and


description has been common in religious philosophy ever since Philo.
This conception is generally represented as a philosophic principle
supported by appropriate scriptural quotations.3

1 See the informative survey on divine transcendence in Ian Richard Netton, Allah Transcendent:
Studies in the Structure and Semiotics of Islamic Philosophy, Theology and Cosmology (Surrey:
Curzon Press, 1989); Fadlou Shehadi, Al-Ghaz all’s Unique and Unknowable God (Leiden: E.J. Brill,
1964). For the analysis of transcendentalism and anthropomorphism in the Greek, Christian and
Modern Philosophy, see Etienne Gilson, God and Philosophy (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1941).
2 Etienne Gilson, “The Idea of God and the Difficulties of Atheism,” in The Great Ideas Today -
1969, ed. R.M. Hutchins & M. J. Adler (Chicago: Encyclopedia Brittanica Inc., 1969), 239.
3 Harry Austryn Wolfson, Studies in the History of Philosophy and Religion, ed. Isadore Twersky &
George H. Williams (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1973), vol.l, 98.

19
The philosophers view God’s uniqueness as a direct logical consequence of

the notion of a perfect and simple God. Being the First Cause, God is said to be

pure, incorporeal and free from matter. He is One, simple in all respects, and

transcends every category and classification that human reason can comprehend.

He does not have any genus or differentia, the two elements necessary for

definition of any concept.4 Plotinus, the most important figure in the philosophy

of Neo-Platonism, described God as One, beyond all thought and all beings,

ineffable and incomprehensible, neither essence nor bein nor life can be predicated

CfQ
of Him. He is so transcendent that whatever we say of Him merely limits Him and
we cannot say what He is, but only what He is not.5 He is thus unnamable since

any attempt at expressing Him must of necessity result in a judgment and since a

judgment is made up of several terms, we cannot say what the one is without

turning his unity into some sort of multiplicity.6

Similar emphasis on divine transcendence is apparent in the views of early

Muslim philosophers. Al-Farabi conceived God as the First Cause whose

existence is the most excellent and precedes every other existence. His existence,

therefore, is different in its substance from everything else for “if they have the

same existence there could be no difference and distinction between them.”7

Identifying perfection with uniqueness, al-Farabi also ar ued that if some other
CfQ

things apart from the First Existent were to exist, the existence of the First would

not be perfect.8 Ibn Sina, another great philosopher of Islam, viewed that since

4 Shehadi, 40; Seyyed Hossein Nasr, History of Islamic Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1996), 241.
Similar understanding of God was held by the Neo-Platonists who later left a strong influence on
Medieval, Islamic and Renaissance thought. Thomas Mautner (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy
(London: Penguin Books, 1997), 431.
5 Frederick Coplestone, History of Philosophy (New York: Image Books, 1993), vol.l, 464; Sharif,
vol. 1, 213.
6 Gilson, God and Philosophy, 45.
7 Abu Nasr Al-Farabi, Mabadi’Ara’Ahl al-Madfnah al-Fadlah, trans. Richard Walzer (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1985), 60-61.
8 Ibid., 61. See also Majid Fakhry, A History of Islamic Philosophy (New York: Columbia University
Press, 2nd edn, 1983), 117.

20
God is simple, there cannot be multiplicity in Him either essential or accidental.9

For this multiplicity would become His constituents or parts while God has neither

constituent nor part:

The Necessary Existent cannot have different kinds of parts, each


standing by itself and forming a unit, such as wood and clay in a
house. Nor can such parts be separated in idea (ma ha) but not in
essence (dhat) in the manner matter and form are separate in natural
bodies.10

Based on this simplicity of Necessary Existent, it follows that He must be

without equal and should be characterized negatively through the exclusion of all

similitude to other beings such as havin no enus differentia, definition, place,

CfQ

CfQ
subject, opposite, species, companion, receptivity of motion, or receptivity of

partition.11 12Although these views of the Muslim philosophers were sometimes

regarded as an ‘alienation’ of God from the knowledge of man and have made God

more unknowable to man, they somehow reflect the way reason attempts to

conceive the transcendent aspect of the Divine. Among the mutakallimun, the

Mu tazilah came closest to the philosophers with their description of God divested

from any notion of additional attributes (ta ctil). Anchored by an unwavering

principle of the unity of God, they viewed that since the essence of God is one and

eternal, no other eternal entities should co-exist with the divine essence. God is,

9 Ibn Sina, Danish Nama-i Ala’I, translated, commented and analyzed by Parviz Morewedge,
Metaphysics of Ibn Sina (London: Routlege & Kegan Paul, 1973), 58. Fakhry, 153-154.
10 Ibn Sina, Danish Nama-i, 53.
11 Ibid, 223; Fakhry, 153-154.
12 Netton, after having surveyed the ideas of the Muslim philosophers concerning divine
transcendence, concludes that the language of transcendence they were using is “in fact the mirror
of a gradual intellectual, theological and linguistic alienation from the Qur’anic Creator
Paradigm...from a Qur’anic God who creates, acts in time, guides mankind, and who can in some
way be known to an utterly remote, unknowable God...” Netton, 27. Similar emphasis on divine
transcendence was later found in the ideas of Jewish and Christian theologians such as Maimonides
(d. 1204) and Thomas Aquinas (d. 1274). Maimonides, the most important Jewish philosopher of
the Middle Ages, for example maintained that the negative attributes of God are the true attributes.
Chapter on ‘God’, The Great Ideas, A Syntopicon of Great Books of the Western World, ed.
Mortimer J. Adler (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc, 1952), 396.

21
therefore, known mostly from negative attributes, which mainly affirm what
13
should not be ascribed to Him.

Scripturally, the idea of divine transcendence is emphasized in several

Qur’anic verses which affirm the otherness of God and deny the resemblance of

God with anything other than He. The most important verse is the affirmative,

“Nothing is like unto Him” (laysa ka mithlihf shay*). This verse ains utmost

CfQ
importance amon CfQ
the mutakallimun. as a proof in stressing the absolute

transcendence of God especially from the anthropomorphic meanings. Commentin

CfQ
on this verse, al-Razi remarked, “scholars of tawhia, ancient and recent, argue on

the basis of this verse, against the [errant] views that portray [the essence of] God

as corporeal (/ism), composed of organs and parts, and that He exists (hasilari) in

place and direction.”15


13Apart
14 from this verse, other emphatic verses stressing the

uniqueness of God and the denial of the resemblance of divine essence with other

anthropomorphic qualities are those in Surah al-Ikhlas which describe God as One

and thus contrary to the Christian belief of God the “father” and having

“begotten-son,” and the denial of God bearing any likeness (kufu9) with others.16

Other verses say: “No vision can grasp Him;”17 18


“They
19 cannot encompass Him with

their knowled “Praise and Glory be to Him, for He is above what they

attribute to Him,” 9 and “Glory to Him! He is high above all that they say, Exalted

and Great.”20 While in the Hadith, the emphasis on divine transcendence transpires

among others in the following Hadith that denies the fact that Prophet

Muhammad was seeing Allah:

'Aishah said “If anyone tells you that Muhammad has seen his Lord,
he is a liar for Allah says, ‘No vision can grasp Him’ (al-Anam 6:103),

13 See our discussion on Mu tazilah in this chapter, 37-40 and in Chapter Two, 71-74.
14 Al-Qur’an, al-Shura 42:11.
15 Tafsir, vol. 9, 582.
16 Al-Qur’an, al-Ikhlas, 112:1-4.
17 Al-Qur’an, al-Anam, 6:103.
18 Al-Qur’an, Ta Ha 20:110.
19 Al-Qur’an, al-Anam 6:100.
20 Al-Qur’an, al-Isra’ 17:43.

22
and if anyone tells you that Muhammad has seen the Unseen (al-
Ghayb), he is a liar, for Allah says, ‘None has the knowledge of the
Unseen but Allah’ (al-Naml 27:65) ”21

Divine transcendence is also expressed in the names and attributes of God.

Among the Beautiful Names of God (al-Asma’ al-Husna) enumerated in a Hadith

by Abu Hurayrah,22 some are more emphatic of divine transcendence than others

such as al-Quddus (the Holy), al-Salam (the Flawless), al-All (the Most High),

al-Mutaali (The Most Exalted), al-Aziz (The Eminent), al-Jalil (the Majestic),

al-Majid (The Glorious), al-Wahid (the Unique). While amon the attributes of

CfQ
God bearing strong element of divine transcendence are eternity (qidam),

everlasting (baqa9), unicity (wahdaniyab), being distinct from originated things

(mukbalafatubu li al-hawadith). Although all these divine names and attributes

share the aspect of divesting God of imperfection, yet each of them, as elucidated
by al-Ghazali in his Maqsad al-Asrta, has their individual meanings.23

21 Bukhari, “al-Tawhid,” Sahih, no.7380, vol.15, 395. The edition we are using for Hadiths compiled
by Bukhari is the commentary by al-Qastallani, Irshad al-Sarili Sharh Sahih Bukhari (Bayrut: Dar
al-Fikr, 1990).
22 Bukhari, “Daawat” Sahih, no.70, vol.13, 475. See further elaboration and comments on this
Hadith in al-Qastallani, Irshad al-Sari, 475-479.
23 Al-Ghazali, Maqsad al-Asna fi Sharh Asma’ Allah al-Husna, trans. David Burrell and Nazeh
Daher (Cambridge: The Islamic Text Society, 1992), 24. In this work, al-Ghazali explained the
meaning of each of the Ninety-Nine Beautiful Names of God and how these names can also be
‘shared’ by human beings in the sense that they can imitate, at certain levels, the names and
attributes of God as prescribed by the famous tradition “takhallaqu bi akhlaq Allah”(adorn your
conduct with the decorum that is Godly). In the early part of the work, al-Ghazali also deals with
the theologico-linguistic matters namely on the difference between name (ism), the one named
(musamma), and naming (tasmiyah). This work of al-Ghazali compares with Fakhr al-Din Al-
Razi, Law amic al-Bayyinat Sharh Asma’ Allah Ta ala wa-Sfat. In this work, al-Razi also
enumerated each and every name of God, but he dealt with more issues by dividing this work into
three main categories, the principles and premises (al-mabadf wa al-muqaddamat) in which he
deals with important concepts such as the difference between names and attributes and the views
and methodology used by various groups on these two, on the classification of attributes; the
objectives (maqasid) which contain his enumeration and explanation on the meaning of all the
divine names; and the attachment and conclusion (lawahiq wa al-mutammimat) which deals with
names that do not occur in the Qur’an in regard to God’s essence.

23
TERMS EMPLOYED TO DESIGNATE DIVINE TRANSCENDENCE

The eneric term commonly used in characterizing the transcendence aspect of

UQ
divine names and attributes is tanzib. The word tanzib, which originates from the

basic root n-z-b-, conveys the meaning ‘to make something remote.’24 It refers to

physical remoteness25 but when applied to God, it means to purify Him from any

equal partners (and ad) and from any elements of imperfection and deficiency that
Al-Razi defined it as the sanctification of God’s essence
can lessen His Highness.26 27

from corporeal and bodily attributes as well as purifying His actions from

blameworthy attributes. 27

Semantically, the meanin of tanzib is also conveyed by two other terms,

tasbfh (glorification) and taqdis (sanctification). In fact, if we compare these

terms with the term tanzib, the latter two occur more frequently with various

denotations in the Qur’an. Both terms are used in Surat al-Baqarah to

demonstrate how the angels glorify God: “While we do celebrate (nusabbihj thy
praise and glorify (nuqaddisu) your Name.”28 29
Both terms also appear in the prayer

of the Prophet, “[God] The Most Glorified and The Most Pure, the Lord of the

Angel and the Spirit” (subb uh quddus rabb al-malalkat wa al-ruhj. The term

tasbfh also comes with different verbal denotations such as sabbaha and the

nouns such as subhana, sabha, sabihat. Although the basic meaning of sabbaha

is “to make something remote,” the term tasbfh has later gained a more specific

meaning of glorifying God in religious rituals (ibadat) either through verbal

expressions, action or intention (niyyab).

24 Ibn Manzur, Lis an al-Arab (Bayrut: Dar al-Sadir, 1990), vol. 13, 548.
25 Ibn Faris, Mujam Maqayfs al-Lugbab (Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah, 1999), vol. 2, 555.
26 Murtada al-Zabidi, Taj al-Ar us, ed. ‘Abd. Karim al-'Azabawi (Kuwait: Mu’assasah al-Kuwait li
al-Taqaddum al-‘Ilmi, n.d.), vol. 36, 525.
27 Samih Daghim, Maws u at Mustalahat al-Imam Fakbr al-Dfn al-Razf (Bayrut: Maktabah
Lubnan Nashirun, 2001), 187.
28 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:30.
29 Al-Raghib al-Isfahani, Mufradat A Ifaz al-Qur’an, ed. Safwan ‘Adnan Dawudi (Damshiq: Dar al-
Qalam, 1992), 392.

24
As for the term taqdis, it appears in the Qur’an through the nouns al-quds,

al-quddus, al-muqaddas and the verb nuqaddisu. Al-Quddus, one of the Beautiful

Names of God, is defined by al-Ghazali as:

...the One who is free from every attribute which a sense might
perceive, or imagination may conceive, or to which imagination may
conceive, or by which the conscience may be moved, or which
thinking demands....the Holy is the one who transcends every one of
the attributes of perfection which the majority of creatures thinks of
as perfection....30

Despite these specific meanings, tanzih, taqdis and tasbih are defined by

Muslim linguists interchangeably. Al-Zabidi, in his famous work, Taj al-Ards,

which recorded many definitions from authoritative Muslim linguists, defined

tasbih as “to glorify God and divest Him from all evils” (ta zim Allah wa

tanzihuhu an kulli suj.31 32 33 34the word taqdis is also used in defining the term
While

tanzih namely “to worship and purify God from any partners, resemblance and

form of defections which are not possible to Him” (tabid wa taqdisuhu an al-

andad wa al-ashbah wa In definin

CfQ
taqdis, again the term tanzih is employed, “tathir wa tanzih Allah azza wa

jail a.” A similar vein can be observed in al-Tahanawi and Jurjani when they

defined tasbih and taqdis as “to divest God (tanzih al-Haqq) of the deficiencies of

contingency (al-naqals al-imkari) and characteristics of origination (al-am ar at al-

huduth) and from imperfections in re ard to the essence and attribute.” Apart
CfQ

from corresponding, interchangeable meaning given by the linguists to these three

30 Al-Ghazali, Maqsad al-Asna, 59.


31 Al-Zabidi, Taj al-Ar us, vol. 6, 449.
32 Ibid, vol. 36, 527.
33 Ibid, vol. 16, 358.
34 Muhammad 'All al-Tahanawi, Kashshaf Istilahat al-Ftmun (Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub aPIlmiyyah,
1998), vol. 2, 329; 'All Muhammad al-Jurjani, al-Tarffat (Al-Qahirah: Dar al-Kitab al-Misri,
1991), 71. Al-Tahanawi defined tanzih as the affirmation that “God being alone by His names,
attributes and His essence as what He Himself deserves it,” Kashsbaf, vol. 4, 266, while al-Jurjani
described it as “to diverse God from the attributes of human” (tab ‘Id al-Rabb an awsaf al-basbar),
al-Ta rlfat, 81.

25
terms, they also concurred with the fact that the kinds of imperfection that should

be divested from God through these terms are mainly those which are corporeal,

anthropomorphic and originated.

In al-Razi’s explanation, a more refined meaning of the three terms can be

noticed. Compared to taqdfs and tasbfh, he assigned a more generic meaning to

tanzih. This can be seen clearly when he defined tasbfh as “divesting His essence

of corporeal attributes” (tanzih dhatihf an sifat al-ajsam), while taqdfs as

“divesting His acts of blameworthy attributes and stupidity” (tanzih ‘afalihf an


sifat al-zamm wa na at al-safah).35 This would mean that for him, taqdfs and

tasbfh are two precise ways of expressing the transcendence of God (tanzih), one

relating to the essence and the other to the action. This is perhaps the reason why

al-Razi specifically used the term taqdfs and not tanzih as the title of his book,

Asas al-Taqdfs in which he attacked the anthropomorphists’ position in dealing

with the anthropomorphic verses in the Qur’an. The only incongruity is that if for

al-Razi, it is tasbfh rather than taqdfs that refers to the act of divesting His

essence of corporeal attributes, then the work should be entitled Asas al-Tasbfh.

Apart from these three terms, there are other terms, which are also

employed in expressing divine transcendence. Among them is tawhid which

means, “to make something one.” However, as a religious terminology, tawhfd is


defined as the act of believing that God is One and Unique.36 It is an affirmation of

what is stated by the kalimat al-Tawhfd that “There is no other God but Allah”

following the recurrent affirmations of the Qur’an of its importance such as in

Surah al-Ikhlas, “Qul huwa Allahu ahad” (Say, “He is Allah, the One”) and “wa

ilahukum ilabun wahid” (And your God is the One God, al-Baqarah 2:193). By

affirming the Oneness of God through its various levels (maratib),37 it is at the

35 Tafsf, vol. 1, 391.


36 Al-Tahanawi, Kashshaf, vol. 4, 310. On the linguistic elaboration on the term wahid and ahad,
see al-Raghib al-Asfahani, Risalah fi Zikr al-Wahid wa al-Ahad, ed. 'Umar al-Sarisi (Amman:
Jami'at al-Isra’, 1992).

26
same time an act of divesting God of every anthropomorphic attributes. However,

the emphasis in the meanin of tawhid is more on the affirmation that all God’s

CfQ
attributes, names and acts are but one reality. This broader meaning of tawhid is

apparent in the works of the mutakallimun. when the whole discussion of the

principles of religion (usul al-dm) including God’s existence, His attributes,


Prophethood and matters related to Hereafter are also known as ilm al-tawhld.3s

From the above discussion, we can conclude that the divine transcendence

in Islam is established through number of terms used in emphasizing the

transcendence of God, the most general of which is tanzih. Other terms which are

also in use are taqdis, tasbih and tawhid. In general, all these terms convey the

meaning that God is far from any corporeal and anthropomorphic attributes. They

also imply the purification of God from any imperfections such as having partners

(sahib), a son (walad) and blameworthy acts. Although these terms are sometimes

employed interchangeably to indicate different aspects of the divine transcendence,

they reflect in general the perspicacious attempt by the mutakallimun to fit the

terms with the various aspects of divine transcendence.

GOD’S IMMANENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF ANTHROPOMORPHISM


Apart from the considerable attention placed by the Qur’an on the uniqueness of

God, some verses also indicate the immanent aspect of God which reveals the

intimate facet of the divine attributes. The Qur’an, for instance, describes God as

39 and who is active in


Supreme Being who is nearer to man than his jugular vein,38

creating and sustaining His creations.40 This immanent aspect of God also portrays

to human beings the known aspect of Him vis-a-vis the unknowable aspect

discussed before. Furthermore, there are also verses that allude to the nearness of

38 Titles of some works on usd al-din which contained the term tawhid are indicative of this
broader meaning such as Kitab al-Tawhid of al- Maturidi, Ibn Khuzaymah and Muhammad
Abduh. See further, D. Gimaret, “Tawhid”, in £72, vol. 10, 389.
39 Al-Qur’an, Qaf 50:16; al-Waqiah, 56:85.
40 Al-Qur’an, al-Rahman 55:29.

27
God through anthropomorphic attributions, known as verses with ambiguous
meaning {ay at mutasbabihat).41 In these verses, God is described as sitting on a

throne, having hands.

(makara). Several Hadiths also report that God is angry, happy, 8 cheerful

(tabasbbasba), 9 and having form.50


41 42Naturally,
43 44 45 46
the47question
48 49 that arises is how

to reconcile between the two opposite descriptions of God, the one alluding to the

transcendence (tanzib) of God, that God is absolutely unlike anything, and the

other indicating His similarity to human qualities (tasbbib). “If God is utterly

unique and unknowable,” puts Shehadi, “how can anything at all be said to Him
and if anything said, on what ground?”51 In the attempt to answer the above

questions, the history of Islamic thought has recorded continuous polemics among

various Muslim theological sects. This worsened with the expansion of Islam into

the lands of the ancient world in which people from the religions which previously

subscribed to anthropomorphism converted into Islam such as the Jews, Christians

and Zoroastrians who brought with them the mental categories of their inherited

cultures which already accustomed to thinking in terms of divine immanence,

particularism and concreteness thus could not absorb the radical idea of divine

transcendence.52

THE POLEMICS OF ANTHROPOMORPHISM: MAIN GROUPS

i. The Anthropomorphists (Mushabbihah)

41 Also known as sifat khabariyyah, attributes which are affirmed based on the descriptions in the
Qur’an and Hadith.
42 Al-Qur’an, Sad 38:57; al-Fath 48:10.
43 Al-Qur’an, al-Qasas 28:88.
44 Al-Qur’an, al-Nisa’ 4:164.
45 Al-Qur’an, al-Tawbah 9:67.
46 Al-Qur’an, Al 'Imran 3:54; al-Tariq 86:16.
47 Al-Qur’an, al-Nisa’4:93.
48 Ibn Maj ah, “Masajid”, Sunan, vol.l, 262.
49 Muslim, “Tawbah” Sahih, vol. 17, 63.
50“Verily God has created Adam according to His form” (Inna Allah khalaqa Adam ala suratih!
Muslim, Sahih, no. 7092, vol.17, 175-176.
51 Shehadi, 8.
52 Ismail Raji al-Faruqi, Islam and Other Faiths, ed. Ataullah Siddiqi (Leicester: HIT), 48.

28
The extreme literal approach taken by some sects led them into committin

CfQ
tasbbib, an act of comparing and assimilating God with the attributes of other

beings especially humans. The term musbabbibab (anthropomorphists) is a

eneric term under which, more specific denotations were used by Muslim
CfQ

heresiographers to refer to a particular group with an anthropomorphic bent such

as the mujassimab, those who ascribed bodily attributes to God and the

Karramiyyah, those who attributed to God certain direction and spatial

characteristics.53 Strothman differentiates between the tasbbib and tajsUn arguin

CfQ
that mujassimab like Hisham b. al-Hakam was not really a musbabbib since he

usually added the qualification “not like our body” in describing the bodily nature
of God54 but this, however, will beg the question of the universality of the term

“body”. There were also other anthropomorphic sects who were named after the

names of their leaders, such as the Hishamiyyab, Bayaniyyab and Azariqab.55

Most of the musbabbibab sects did not survive in history due to the direct

confrontation of their views with the principle of the transcendence of God held by

53 The Karramiyyah group was founded by Muhammad bin Karram, a person who appeared to be
ascetic and pious yet was described by the Sunnites of his time as a person “whose exterior is fine
but whose interior is vile.” Farq, vol.l, 21. Al-Shahrastani included them among the Sifatiyyah
(those who affirmed attributes of God), Milal, 92. In the tenth and eleventh centuries they were an
important political force in some regions. Among the views of Ibn Karram and his sect was that
God is a body, having an end and limit below where he comes in contact with His Throne. They
also opined that the Throne is the place of God and God physically touches the Throne. It follows
that God, according to them, is no larger than His Throne on the side where He touches it and no
part of Him overhangs it! Those among them who believed in God’s nearness to the Throne
maintained that His being a body means that He exists by Himself. From this idea, they developed
the view that ‘any two things which exist by themselves must either be in contact with each other
or separate from each other. Further, God, for them, is a unit of essence and a unit of substance,
His names are only accidents existing in a primordial body. They believed that it is possible for a
number of accidents to inhere in God’s essence. Apart from al-Shahrastani’s al-Milal and al-
Baghdadi’s al-Farq, their rational arguments are treated at length by al-Razi in his Kitab Asas al-
Taqdis, and some scattered views of the Karramiyyah in al-Razi’s Muhassal and Arba m. Further
references to the Karramiyyah’s views can be found in Suhayr Mukhtar, al-TajsFn ‘inda al-
Muslimin: Madbhab al-Karramiyyah (Al-Qahirah: al-Qahirah University, 1971); W. M. Watt,
Islamic Philosophy and Theology: An Extended Survey (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
1985), 79-81; A. S. Tritton, Muslim Theology (Bristol: The Royal Asiatic Society, 1947), 108-112;
C.E. Bosworth, ‘Karramiyyah’, EI2 (4), 667.
54 Strothman, “Tashbih”, 685.
55 Maqalat, vol. 1, 281-290; Farq, 18-40.

29
the majority of the Muslims. Since their works were scarcely extant, we can only

read their views through the works of the mutakallimun and the Muslim

heresiographers. As a matter of fact, the musbabbibab did not form a particular

school since their views are mostly associated with individual figures especially
from the Sbfab.56 We, therefore, do not subscribe to the view that the

musbabbibab, theologically, gained its strength in the early period of Islam under

the leadership of Ibn Hanbal.57 58This is due to the fact that, Ibn Hanbal, as we will

show later, was not an anthropomorphist as he maintained the bila kayf position

which is different from tasbbib.53 There are also proofs which indicate that Ibn

Hanbal also employed allegorical interpretations in dealing with anthropomorphic

expressions.59 It was the extreme views of some of his followers that implicated

the allegation of anthropomorphism against Ibn Hanbal.60 However, we concur

with the fact that later, especially by the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, the

musbabbibab had gained some ground in influencing certain quarters of the

Muslims due to the rise of some individuals with their anthropomorphic views

regarding God. This can be seen from the considerable coverage of their views in

the heresiographical works of Muslim scholars within this period such as al-Milal
wa al-Nihal of al-Shahrastani,61 al-Farq bayna al-Firaq of 'Abd al-Qahir al-

Baghdadi,62 and Ibn Hazm’s al-Fasl fi al-Milal wa al-Abwa’ wa al-Nihal!63

56 Tritton, 48.
57 Wesley Williams, in his article, “Aspects of the Creed of Imam Ahmad Ibn Hanbal: A Study of
Anthropomorphism in Early Islamic Discourse,” International Journal of Middle East Studies, no.
34 (2002): 442, argued that after Ahmad Ibn Hanbal assumed leadership of the traditionist camp
during and immediately following the mihnah, anthropomorphism achieved “orthodox” recognition.
To substantiate his arguments, he also tries to prove that Ibn Hanbal, through his view of some
verses and HadUh, was indeed an anthropomorphist. Ibid., 443-444.
58 Al-Razi, I tiqad Firaq al-Muslimm wa al-Mushrikih (Al-Qahirah: Maktabah al-Kulliyyat al-
Azhariyyah, 1978), 99.
59 Al-Ghazali, Faysal al-Tafriqah, trans. & intro. Sherman A. Jackson under the title On the
Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam: Al-Ghazalfs Faysal al-Tafriqa (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2003), 101-102. On the elaboration of this proof, see pp. 43-44 of this chapter.
60 See elaboration of the views of the Handbilah in this chapter, 48-51.
61 Milal, pp. 88-96.
62 Farq, vol. 2, 18-36.

30
Though the musbabbibab were somehow placed in a different classification within

these works, their views are, no doubt, afforded great length. Al-Shahrastani

placed the musbabbibab and the Karramiyyah under the general heading of

Sifatiyyah (the Affirmists of divine attributes) under which also includes the

64 This is based on the wider classification between those who affirm the
Asbairah.63

attributes, regardless of their validity, and those who reject them such as the

Mu tazilah and the Philosophers. As for al-Baghdadi, although he dealt

independently with the Karramiyyah and the musbabbibab, yet he re arded all of

CfQ
them as sects that erred from true Islamic teachings.65 While Ibn Hazm did not

specify any sect, he discussed them by section (fasi) which included the topics on

taw hid and the denial of tashbib, the notion of divine attribute, istiwa’ and
others.66

The increasing influence of the musbabbibab is also evident in the special

attention given to this group in the form of refutations and debates by some

prominent scholars like al-Razi in his Asas al-Taqdfs, and al-Amidi in his Gbayat

al-Maram. In the Asas al-Taqdfs with which we will be dealing thoroughly in the

last three chapters of this thesis, al-Razi put forward various rational and

traditional arguments in refuting the anthropomorphic position of the

Karramiyyah. While in Gbayat al-Maram, al-Amidi assigned one of his eight

theological laws (qanuri) to refute the arguments of the anthropomorphists.67

Apart from these works, there were also celebrated debates reported to have taken

place during this period between the Karramiyyah figures and the Ash arI scholars

among which was the debate between Ibn Haysam, the famous follower of Ibn

63 Fa si, vol. 2, 277-292. Further analysis of the methodology of treating the sects within these three
works can be found in the introduction of the translation of Abu Mansur al-Baghdadi’s Farq by
Kate Chambers Seelye, Farq, 1-17.
64 Milal, 88-96.
65 Farq, vol. 2, 18-36.
66 Fa si, vol 2, 227-292.
67 Sayf al-Din al-Amidi, Ghayat al-Maram fi cIlm al-Kalam, ed. Hassan Mahmud 'Abd Latif (Al-
Qahirah: Lujnah Ihya’ al-Turath al-Islami, 1971), 157-200.

31
Karram, and Ash‘arite scholar, Ibn Furak. Another one was between Ibn Haysam

and another Ash‘arite scholar, Abu Ishaq al-Isfarayini with the presence of the
Ruler at that time, Sultan Mahmud Ibn Sabkatkin.68

i.i. Main Views of the Mushabbihah

Although the mushabbihah come under various names and denominations, as

classified by al-Baghdadi, they are divided into two main groups.69 The first are

those who liken the essence of God to the essence of what is other than He. This is

due to their literal understanding of some Qur’anic verses which imply bodily

characteristics to God as well as the quality of other creations such as light and

time.70 Among those who liken the essence of God to the essence of human bein

CZ)
bn
are the Sabafyyah, one of the Shiah extreme sects, who identified ‘All with the

essence of God.71 The extremity of their views was so evident when some of them

who were executed by being burnt at the stake at the command of ‘All himself,
replied, “Now we know that you are God for none but God punishes with fire!”72

Al-Ash‘arl reported that some mujassimah groups ascribe to God various

attributes of the human being and other creations, that God has a body, that He

can be measured (miqdar), that He is situated in a place (makari) and that He

moves (yataharrak). Some of these opinions were attributed to a number of


Rafidah73 and Mutazili scholars such as Hisham bin al-Hakam,74 Abu al-

Hudhayl75 and Ibn Rawandi.76 Hisham, who is regarded by Tritton as the finest

8 Suhayr Mukhtar, 87-88.


69 Farq, vol. 2, 30.
70 Such as the verse “Allah is the Light of the heavens and the earth” (al-Nur 24:35) and “and
nothing but time (al-dahr) can destroy us” (al-Jathiyyah 45:24).
71 The Sabatyyah are the followers of 'Abdullah ibn Saba’ who exaggerated with respect to ‘All,
maintaining that he was a Prophet. ‘Abdullah even exaggerated further by saying that ‘Ali was
God. He spread propaganda of this belief among erring Kuffites. The story of this group was
reported to ‘Ali who ordered a number of them to be burnt in two pits. Farq, vol.2, 41.
72 Farq, vol. 2, 31. Most of these groups were related to the extreme group of Rafidah, a Shiah sect.
73 The Rafidah also known as Imamiyyah were one of three most important Shiah groups apart
from the Ghaliyah and Zaidiyyah. They were so-called due to their rejection (rafada) of the
leadership of Abu Bakr. They agreed that the Prophet explicitly declared the leadership of ‘All in

32
example of anthropomorphist figure,7 was reported as saying that God’s

measurement is seven times the length of a human arm (sab at al-asbbar) while

Abu al-Hudhayl was saying that God is smaller than Jabal Qubays, the highest
mountain near Mecca!78 * * * groups are the Bayaniyyah who liken God to light,
74 Other

the Mugbjriyyab who liken God to human beings and the Hululiyyab, who held
that God inheres in their Imams.79

The second group comprises those who liken the attributes of God with the

attributes of what is other than He. Al-Baghdadi included in this group

individuals from the Mu tazilah, such as al-Nazzam,80 who drew a similarity

between the words of God and the words of the human being, position that

emerged from their contention that the Qur’an is created. According to the

replacement of himself. They also held that most of the Companions of the Prophet went astray
when they did not make allegiance to 'All. Maqalat, vol.l, 88-89.
74 He was among the heads of the Rafidah who wrote many books and was good in oratory. Fast,
vol. 2, 269, n.4. Al-Baghdadi nevertheless still considered him within the fold of Islam since he
affirmed the obligatory character of the precepts in the Qur’an and the binding force of the
fundamentals of the law of Islam. Farq, vol. 2, 32; Among his theological belief is that God knows
through an originated knowledge (Um muMatbj Qadi 'Abd Jabbar, Sharh Usui al-Khamsah, ed.
'Abd Karim 'Uthman (Al-Qahirah: Maktabah Wahbah,1965), 183.
75 Abu al-Hudhayl Hamdan b. al-Hudhayl al-'Allaf was an early Mu tazilah. He was born in 748
and died in 840. He was called ‘Shaykh of the Mu tazilah’ due to his wide influence amon the

tn
Mu tazilah. He was a fluent speaker and vigorous in his argument. Apart from his
anthropomorphic views, he viewed that God is knowing with His knowledge and His knowledge is
His essence; He is powerful with power and His power is His essence and so on. He also opined
that there are acts of will which have no substrate, and that by these acts God is willing. Milal, p.
46; M. M. Sharif, vol. 1, 207-208.
76 He was a respected early Mu tazilah. Among his views are that human reason is sufficient to
determine the knowledge of God and the distinction between good and evil, that miracle is absurd,
and that the world is eternal. Fakhry, 96.
77 Tritton, Muslim Theology, 50
78 Maqalat, vol.l, 281-282. See also Farq vol. 2, 32-33. In relation to Hisham’s views, Strothman
seems to defend his tajsjm in his article on tashbih, by differentiating between tashbih and tajsjm
in the sense that tajsjm is allowed as long as it is affirmed that the body which is ascribed to God is
different from the human body. Strothman, 687.
79 Farq, vol. 2, 31.
80 Abu Ishaq Ibrahim ibn Sayyar, called al-Nazzam lived during the reign of al-Ma’mun. He was
the student of Abu al-Hudhayl al-'Allaf and was also a poet. He studied Greek philosophy well and
made full use of it in his works. His views include the denial of God’s power over evil, denial of the
will of God, the theory of latency and manifestation (kumun \va buruz) which prescribes that
creation is to be re arded as a single act of God by which all things were brought into being
tn

simultaneously and kept in a state of latency. From the latent state they were brought gradually
into the state of manifestation. Sharif, vol.l, 208-211.

33
Mu tazilab, since God does not possess real attributes, which are eternal, the

Qur’an, as the speech of God is therefore not eternal but created. Some

Mu tazilab and Karramiyyab also held that God’s will is of the same genus and is
created just as the human will.81 Although in principle the Mu tazilab were in

opposition to the musbabbibab, especially in regard to the treatment of the

anthropomorphic expressions in the Qur’an, in this case some of them agreed and

arrived at the same conclusion. This irony can be explained by saying that the

tasbbib that al-Baghdadi claimed these Mu'tazilites individuals were holding is

rather a loose kind of anthropomorphism. For it only relates to the issue of God’s

speech (kalam Allah), while these Mutazilite individuals were strongly against the

notion of bodily God held by other anthropomorphists.

Van Ess proposes another detailed categorization of anthropomorphism

based on the verses of the Qur’an.82 He divided it into four main categories: (i)

anthropomorphism proper that concerns God’s outward appearance namely His

shape, eyes, hands and face. These descriptions, according to van Ess, are mostly

metaphorical in meanin but were interpreted by a number of Shi'ite theologians in


CfQ

the anthropomorphic sense; (ii) God’s actions such as sitting on the throne, His

descending and approaching humankind. The Prophet Muhammad’s night journey

(isra9), mostly elaborated in the Prophetic traditions is also described by some

scholars in anthropomorphic tone; (iii) God’s feelings and passions, for example,

his mercy (rahmab), wrath (gbadab) satisfaction (rida) and cunning (mnfcr); (iv)

Passive anthropomorphism which indicates God as being the object of perception


and that He can be heard and can be seen.83

81 Farq, vol.2, 34-35.


82 Josef van Ess, “Tashbih wa Tanzih”, EI2, vol. 10, 342-343.

34
i.ii. Epistemological Method of the Mushabbihah

As stated earlier, the starting point of the mushabbihah’s understanding of God is

their literal interpretation of the Qur’an where the anthropomorphic verses are

taken at face value. This is evidenced, for example, through their own affirmation,

as reported by al-Shahrastani:

The anthropomorphists maintain that, “We do not add anything of


ourselves, nor do we pursue questions which the early community
had not raised.” They further say, “What is between the two covers
is God’s word. This is also what we affirm.”84

By implication, this literal interpretation of the Qur’an brought about

unexpected problems to the musbabbibab. The Karramiyyab, for example, based

on the literal understanding of God’s sitting on the throne (istiwa9) and some

Hadiths concerning the same issue, were forced to accept the existence of

directions in relation to God. When the meanin of “God is established above the
CfQ

throne”85 and “He descends to the earthly heaven” (nazala ila sama’ al-durtyaf6

were taken literally, they concluded that the directions of ‘above’ and ‘below’ can

be ascribed to God. They further added that since God sits on the throne, He can

thus be above the Throne and there is a part of Him that is touching the throne.87

As consequence, the Karramiyyab affirmed the direction of ‘above’ with regard

to God but denied the other five. 8 They even said that that part of God which

touches the Throne is not bigger then the Throne itself in size.89

34 Milal, 91.
85 Al-Qur’an, Ta Ha 20:5.
86 In the Hadith narrated by Abu Sa'id and Abu Hurayrah, the Prophet says, “God waits until three
quarters of the night and then He descends to the earthly heaven and says, ‘Is there anyone who
seeks my Pardon or makes a prayer,’ until dawn.” Bukhari, “al-Tahajjud bi al-Layl” Sahih, no.
1145, vol.3, 223.
31 Milal. 92.
88 'Abd Allah Baydawi, Taw Hi' aI-Anwar min Ma tali ‘ al-Anzar, along with Mahmud Isfahan’s
commentary Matali‘al-Anzar, Sharh Tawali 'al-Anwar, ed. & trans. Edwin E. Calverley and James
W. Pollock (Brill: Leiden, 2002), vol. 2, 756.
89 Milal, 92.

35
Apart from strict literalism, the unrestrained usage of the faculty of

imagination (kbayaliyyab) and the senses (tissiyyab) in comprehending the reality

of the essence of God is another epistemological cause that brought about the

musbabbibab’s anthropomorphic leaning. As they encountered expressions in the

Qur’an regarding God’s anthropomorphic attributes, they compared them to

human attributes and since what is God’s is not to be found in the physical world,

imagination takes over. This can be seen, for example, in the inclination of some

of them to come up with a whimsical description of God such as that of Muqatil

bin Sulaiman who said based on the literal meaning of the word al-samad in Surah

al-Ikhlas, that God is solid and massive, not hollow, hence He does not need food

and sexuality. While Dawud al-Jawarlbi viewed that God can only be massive in

the lower part and has to be hollow from His waist upward since His speeches
come from His mouth.90 Attacking this false method, al-Razi maintains that the

knowledge of God’s acts and attributes is beyond the power of imagination (al-
kbay aliyyab) and sense experience (al-Jfssiyyab).91 If the knowledge of God’s acts

and attributes is beyond the grasp of imagination and sense experience, it is a

fortiori that the knowledge of the essence of God, which is more abstruse, is to be

beyond the comprehension of these two faculties.92

The musbabbibab also utilized a rational principle which they adopted

from those employed by the philosophers in defending their anthropomorphic

view. We will discuss at length their rational principle in Chapter Three when

analyzing al-Razi’s Kitab Asas al-Taqdfs. But, in brief, they based their arguments

on a physical principle which explains the nature of substance and accidents, two

basic kinds of existents in the Islamic cosmological doctrine. The nature of the two

is that either one inheres in the other as in the case of accidents which inhere in

90 Josef van Ess, “Tashbih wa Tanzih”, EI2, vol. 10, 342.


9iAsas, 22-23.
92 Ibid., 23-24. Further explanation of al-Razi’s psychology can be found in Razi, Kitab al-Nafs wa
al-Ruh wa Shark Quwahuma, trans. & intro. M. Saghir Hasan Ma’sumi under the title Imam Razfs
Ilm al-Akblaq (Islamabad: Islamic Research Institute, 1970).

36
substance, or that they are distinct from each other in a direction as in the case of

substance or body. To the musbabbibab, this principle is applicable to all

existents. Since God and the world are two existents, and God does not inhere in

the world, He must, therefore, be distinct from the world in a direction. Al-Razi

rephrased these arguments as follows: Since God and the world are two existents

(rruiwj udayn), it is necessary for reason to conclude that either one of them is

subsisting in the other, or that they are mutually distinct (mubdyin). For God to

be subsisting in the world is tantamount to incarnation (Au/z3) which is

categorically impossible. Hence God must be distinct from the world in a


direction.93

ii. The Mu tazilah

The Mu tazilah were well known for their strong defense of divine transcendence.

They were called ‘People of Justice and Unity’ (Ahl al-Adi wa al-Tawhfd) due to

their strict insistence on the unqualified Unity of the divine essence. Thus, they

regard transcendentalism to be a necessary prerequisite of tawhid. Among the

important implications of this doctrine of unity is their denial of the existence of

divine attributes.94 With regard to their response to anthropomorphism, it is

recorded that, together with the Jahmiyyah 95 they were the first who raised the

issue by accusing the main body of the faithful of heresy in the form of tashbib,

of likening God to the creatures.96 Using mostly rational arguments and also

93 Asas, 21.
94 This issue will be dealt further in the next chapter.
95 Jahmiyyah were the followers of Jahm b. Safwan who developed a consistent negative theology
on the basis of Neoplatonic philosophy where God is beyond being. Josef van Ess, “Tashbih wa
Tanzih”, EI2, vol. 10, 343. According to Watt, very least were known regarding this group to the
extent that no name are known of any members of this sect. Most of their references were known
through the opponents. W.M. Watt, “Djahmiyyah”, EI2, vol.2, 388.
96 W. Montgomery Watt, “Some Muslim Discussions,” 86. In his work al-Radd ala al-Jahmiyyah,
Ibn Hanbal regarded both Mu tazilah and Jahmiyyah as identical since their views concur in such
matters as the denial of Beatific Vision and other divine attributes, the createdness of the Qur’an
and the problem of ta \vil. But they nevertheless differ in some other matters such as free will and
predestination where Jahmiyyah believed in predeterminism (mujbirah) while Mu'tazilah believed in
Qur’anic verses such as the phrase “There is nothing like unto Him”97 98
and “Sight

reaches not to Him,” they disproved any attempt to imply any physical view

regarding God. They rejected attribution to God in a literal sense of anything that

suggested that He had characteristics of a body. Hence, we read al-Ash'ari’s

account of the Mu tazilah doctrine in his Maqalat, which begins with their long

statement of denial of anthropomorphism:

The Mu tazila agree that God is One; there is nothing like him; He
is hearing, seeing, He is not a body, not a form, not flesh and blood,
not an individual (shakhs), not substance nor attribute; He has no
colour, taste, smell, no heat, cold, moisture nor dryness, no length,
breadth nor depth, no joining together nor separation, no movement,
rest nor division; He has no sections nor parts, no limbs nor
members; He is not subject to directions, left, right, in front of,
behind, above, below; no place comprehends Him, no time passes
over Him; inadmissible for Him are contiguity, separateness and
inherence in places; He is not characterized by any attribute of
creatures indicating their originatedness, nor by finitude, nor
extension, nor directional motion; He is not bounded; not begetting
nor begotten; magnitudes do not comprehend Him nor veils cover
Him; the senses do not attain Him; He is not comparable with men
and does not resemble creatures in any respect; infirmities and
sufferings do not affect Him; He is unlike whatever occurs to the
mind or is pictured in the imagination; He is ceaselessly first,
precedent, going before originated things, existent before created
things; He is ceaselessly knowing, powerful, living, and imagination
does not comprehend Him; He is not heard by hearing; (He
cu
(Z)

thing, not as the things, knowing, powerful, living, not as (men are)
knowing, powerful, living; He is eternal, alone, and there is no
eternal except Him, no deity apart from Him; He has no partner in
His rule, no vizier (sharing) His authority, no assistant in producing
what He produced and creating what He created; He did not create
creatures on a preceding model; to create a thing was no easier and
no more difficult for Him than to create another thing; He may not
experience benefit or harm, joy or gladness, hurt or pain; He has no

free will (qadariyyab). While regarding faith (imari), Jabmiyyab hold that it constitutes only
strong belief in the heart while Mu tazilab hold that it includes belief, utterance and acts. Mahmud
Subhi, Fi Ilm al-Kalam: Mu tazilab (Bayrut: Dar al-Nahdah al-'Arabiyyah, 1985), vol. 2, 112-113.
97 Al-Qur’an, al-Shura 42:9.
98 Al-Qur’an, al-An'am 6:103.

38
limit so as to be finite; He may not cease to exist, nor become weak
or lacking; He is too holy to be touched by women or to have
consort and children."

As elaborated by Qadi cAbd al-Jabbar, the spokesman of Mu tazilah, the

basic premise which precede the denial of God having the above attributes is that

they are all attributes of the body. God cannot be a body since a body constitutes

length and depth and all these cannot be attributed to the eternal God.99
100 He

further said:

If He the Exalted is a body, he will be originated, while the eternity


of God is already established. It is impossible for bodies to be
separated (infikdk) from originated characteristics namely union
(ytima*) and disunion (iftiraq), movement (al-Jiarakah') and rest (al-
sukunf101

Consistent with the above divine transcendence, the Mu tazilah viewed that

the anthropomorphic verses in the Qur’an and Sunnah should be interpreted in an

allegorical way (ta\viT). The failure to do that would result in God losing His

attributes of being the Creator and the Everlasting; if God were like created things,

He could be neither the Creator nor the Everlasting. Hence, for the Mu tazilah, all

statements concerning God that imply bodies are symbols with a higher meaning,

for the deity is simple and formless. Thus, by God’s eyes and eyelids and sight we

are to understand His power of overseeing all things and His all-encompassing

knowledge. God’s hands mean the effectual nature of His energy, for it is with our
own hands that we accomplish our most useful and valuable work, and so on.102

From the principle of the Unity of God held by the Mu tazilah, the following

beliefs necessarily result as corollaries: the denial of the Beatific Vision, since vision

is not possible without place and direction, of Him is therefore neither

99 Maqalat, vol.l, 235-236. With slight modification, we follow the translation of W. M. Watt, in
The Formative Period of Islamic Thought (Oxford: OneWorld, 1998), 246-247.
100 'Abd Jabbar, 218.
101 Ibid.
102 Watt, The Formative Period, 248.

39
possible in this world nor in the Hereafter; belief in the created speech of God, that

the Qur’an is an originated work of God and that it came into existence together

with the prophethood of the Prophet of Islam; God’s pleasure and anger are not

attributes but states, because anger and pleasure are states and states are mutable,

whereas the essence of God is immutable.103

iii. Ibn Hanbal

Ahmad bin Hanbal is undoubtedly one of the most important figures in the early

phase of the history of kaldm. Strict and rigorous in his position especially against

the ultra-rational tendency of the Mu tazilah and the Jahmiyyah of his time, he

profoundly influenced the development of kaldm to the point where strains of his

thought can be deciphered from the strict theological understanding of his

followers, the Handbilah throughout history to the modem day Wahhabi


theology.104 Among traditional scholars, he was considered the paragon of orthodox

theology due to his persistence in his defense of doctrines outlined by Tradition

(the Qur’an and Hadith) and his great perseverance ainst the series of
prosecutions by the establishment of his time against him.105

Ibn Hanbal’s religious position is strongly associated with Hadith. His

doctrine is characterized by the spirit to make both the Qur’an and Hadith the sole

authorities in the field of dogma. This comes as no surprise since he was, in the

first place, a compiler of Hadith, of which he reportedly memorized 700,000.106

His collection of Hadith, al-Musrtad, is one of the exceptionally important works

103 See further Maq al at, vol.l, 235-244; Sharif, vol.l, 199-219; Watt, The Formative Period, 209-250.
104 On Wahhabism, see Louis Alexander de Corancez, The History of the Wahhabis, trans. Eric
Tabet (Reading: Garnet Publishing, 1995); Hamid Algar, Wahhabism: A Critical Essay (New York:
Oneonta, 2002); Natana J. Delong, Wahhabi Islam: From Revival and Reform to Global Jihad
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).
105 In the reign of al-Ma‘mun, who took the Mu tazilah’s doctrine of ‘the createdness of the Qur’an’
as the official State doctrine, Ibn Hanbal was imprisoned for his uncompromising insistence that
the Qur’an is the eternal, uncreated word of God. See further Muhammad Abu Zahrah, Tarikh al-
Mazahib al-Islamiyyah (Al-Qahirah: Dar al-Fikr af Arabi, 1989), 496.
106 Abu Ya'la, Tabaqat al-Hanabilah (Bayrut: Dar al-Ma rifah, n.d), vol 1, 6.

40
in the field of Hadith. Al-ShaffI, the great faqih and imam madhhab,

acknowledged Ibn Hanbal as the most knowledgeable man in Hadith and rijal (the
narrators of Hadith) and used to refer to him regarding these matters.107 Even his

important work on aqidah bears the name of al-Sunnah which is strongly

indicative of his strict, uncompromising position on the Tradition in this field.108

Due to his strict adherence to the text, what is beyond the text, as far as

the knowledge of God is concerned, is to Ibn Hanbal unreliable and considered

innovation (bidam, position that is also linked closely to the position of the

Companions of the Prophets. For Ibn Hanbal, the tradition (Sunnah) does not only

mean conforming to the prescriptions given by the Prophet but also to refrain from

what the Prophet did not do and from what he forbade:

The fundamental principle of Sunnah, in our opinion, consists in


clinging to that which the Companions of the Prophets of God
conformed to, following their example, and abstaining from heretical
innovations.10

This is perhaps the reason why Ibn Hanbal never had systematic kalam

doctrine of his own. His doctrinal works are in fact a collection of Qur’anic verses,

Hadiths and narrations from earlier scholars. He even warned his questioners

against the danger of codifying his thought since this would conflict with the
principles laid down by the Qur’an.110 Parallel to this position, Ibn Hanbal rejected

the use of ta’wil (allegorical interpretation) particularly in kaldm since ta’wil is an

107 Ibid.
108 Ibn Hanbal considered the body of Hadiths as the most immediate, protected and direct
injunctions from God, to thus be the highest authority in matters of religion. Their preservation
through the mechanism of isnad, which is phrased by Azmeh, as the “power of uninterrupted
traditions” has become the strong point in strengthening the position of Ibn Hanbal and later on
that of the Hanabilah. Aziz Al-Azmeh, “Orthodoxy and Hanbalite Fideism.” Arabica: Revue
D Etudes Arabes XXXV (1988): 259.
109 Quoted in Ibn Qudamah, Tafrim al-Nazar fl Kutub Ahl al-Kalam, trans. George Makdisi
under the title Censure of Speculative Theology (Cambridge: E.J.W Gibb Memorial, 1985), 15. It is
under this pretext that Ibn Hanbal considers the Mu tazilah and the Jahmiyyah as men of
innovation (ahi al-bida ) and hence, could neither lead a prayer nor become a judge. Abdullah b.
Ahmad Ibn Hanbal, al-Sunnah (Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah, 1985), 10.
110 H. Laoust, Ahmad bin Hanbal, EI2, vol.l, 274.

41
opinion, and it is not lawful to give an opinion on the attributes of God, because

sometimes by interpreting the verse in a way not intended by God, we would fall
into perversity.111

Based on the above epistemological foundations, it is not difficult to predict

Ibn Hanbal’s position on the issue of divine attributes and anthropomorphism. For

Ibn Hanbal, to believe in God is to believe in the descriptions of God that appear in

the Qur’an and what has been described by the Prophet. The attributes that were

mentioned in the Qur’an must be affirmed as realities including those of the

mutashabihat. His comment on the term wajb (face of God) runs as follows:

God, may be extolled and exalted, has a face unlike shapes which are
formed and substances which are limited, but face which He
described in this verse, “Everything will perish except his face” (al-
Qasas 28:88). Whoever changes the meaning of the verse, deviates
from it. It is a face in reality and not in a figurative way.112 113

Elsewhere, he asserted:

In one of the sound Hadiths about the Messen er of God, it is said:


CfQ

“The Prophet has seen his Lord.” This is transmitted from the
Messen er of God himself...Belief in that and counting it is true is
CfQ

obligatory. 113

111 As a matter of fact, this position in Islamic tradition is called tafwfd, to entrust the meaning to
God, or tawqif to hold up the meanings. Both convey the idea of the affirmation of dogmatic
articles without a qualification that would carry one beyond the bounds of one’s given textuality.
According to Azmeh, it is based on the assumption that the sense of the divine statement is
comprehensible to us only within the terms of the very statement. Yet to the critiques of this
method especially among the rationalists, this kind of strict, literal position is described as
hashwiyyah, which literally means useless and prolix discourse, the term generally used to refer to
the People of the traditions (ashab al-haditb) who uncritically interpret the meaning of crude
anthropomorphic traditions. This kind of preaching style dogma is a form of knowledge which is
devoid of epistemic content. It is a purely affirmative form of expression and belongs properly to
an act of devotion more than to one of intellection. Al-Azmeh, “Orthodoxy,” 256, 266; EI2, vol.3,
269.
112 Binyamin Abrahamov, “The Bila Kayfa Doctrine and Its Foundations in Islamic Theology,”
ARABICA, Journal of Arabic and Islamic Studies, Tome vol. XLII, No. 3, (Nov. 1995): 366.
113 Watt, W. M., Islamic Creeds, 31.

42
Regarding istiwa’, he affirmed that “God was on the Arsh (Throne), and
the Kursiyy (Footstool) was the place of His Feet.”114 As with other

anthropomorphic expressions in the Qur’an, Ibn Hanbal affirmed their existence

without much explanation:

God is hearing undoubtedly, and seeing undoubtedly. He is knowing


and not ignorant, generous and not mean, forbearing and not hasty,
remembering and not forgetting, awake and not sleeping, near (with
His favour) and not ne lectful. He moves and speaks and considers

CfQ
(or observes); He sees and laughs; He rejoices and loves and dislikes;
He shows loathing and good pleasure; He is angry and displeased; He
is merciful and pardons; He impoverishes and enriches and is
inaccessible. He descends every night to the lowest heaven as He
wills. “There is nothing like Him, and He is the hearing and seein

CfQ
(one) (al-Shura 42:11). The hearts of human beings are between two
of the fingers of the Merciful; He turns them as He wills, and
bestows on (or holds back from) them what He wants. He created
Adam by His hand in His image. The heaven and the earth on the
day of resurrection are in His hand. He places His foot in Hell and it
shrinks, and by His hand he takes from Hell a group of people.11

Despite this strict adherence to the Scripture, Ibn Hanbal is still, in some

places, forced to resort to ta’wil, especially in responding to the rational groups.

Al-Ghazali, in Fay sal al-Tafriqah, pointed out that Ibn Hanbal have figuratively

interpreted three Hadiths: first,“The Black Stone is the right (hand) of God on

earth,” second, “The heart of the faithful is between two of the All-Merciful’s

fingers”, and third, “Indeed, I find the breath of the All-Merciful (nafs al-
Rahman) coming from the direction of Yemen.116 Elsewhere, after affirming that

God knows everything and nothing is hidden from Him, Ibn Hanbal added:

If any innovator and opponent tries to prove (the opposite) by God’s


words, “We are nearer to him than his neck vein” (Qaf 50:16), and
“He is with you wherever you are” (al-Hadid 57:4), and “there is no
meeting of three except where He is the fourth...and He is with them

114 Ibid., 36.


115 Ibid., 37.
116 Al-Ghazali, Fay sal al-Tafriqah, 101-102.

43
wherever they are’ (al-Mujadilah 58:7), and similar ambiguous verses
of the Qur’an, then say (in reply to him) that these mean (God’s)
knowledge.117

Though Ibn Hanbal was very strict in affirming the existence of this sifat

al-khabariyyah, it is this exceptions of ta \vd that, among others, has become the

basis of others not to brand him as a mushabbih. Al-Razi defended Ibn Hanbal’s

position from the attack of the Mutazilites affirming that the latter upheld divine

transcendence and was far from being a mushabbih. Ibn Hanbal, maintained al­

Razi, put his faith and trust regarding the meanin of the verses on God without

CfQ
ascribing any similarity between God and human being.

iii.i. Bila Kayf

The literal affirmation of anthropomorphic expressions in the Qur’an and Hadith

is, however, qualified by an important qualification that is the denial of the

knowledge of the modalities of these qualities, known as bila kayf (without

knowing how). This expression can be traced from the famous statement of Malik

b. Anas (d. 995) regarding the istiwa’ that “God’s sitting on the Throne is known,

but its modality is unknown, the belief in it is obligatory and the inquiry about it

is innovation” (al-istiwa’ ma lum al-kayf mojhul al-iman bibf wajib wa al-su’al

119 Nevertheless, it was Ibn Hanbal who developed it into a doctrine


anhu bid ah ).118

which was later closely associated with his school of thought.120 In relation to this,

the doubt raised by Joseph Schacht regarding the association of Ibn Hanbal with

this doctrine by arguing that there is no evidence that the latter was using the term

in his works121 is, for us, unfounded. For Ibn Hanbal did allude to this fact in his

Kitab al-Sunnab and Manaqib, by saying that “one must believe in God without

seeking to know the mode of the theologomena [divine essence] and leave to God

118 Al-Razi, I tiqadat, 99.


119 Abrahamov, “Bila Kayfa Doctrine,” 366.
120 Ibid.
121 Wesley Williams. “Aspects of the Creed,” 448.

44
the understanding of his own mystery, renouncing the vain and dan erous

CfQ
122
subtleties of dogmatic theology.” Even if we take the view of Schacht that Ibn

Hanbal did not use the term, Schacht is still mistaken, for person may not

necessarily use a specific term when discussing a certain theme especially, as in the

case of bila kayf, when the term was coined later and thus not necessarily used

verbatim by earlier scholars like Ibn Hanbal. What matters more is the content of

the doctrine. And this is true in the case of Ibn Hanbal especially when we take

into account his strict literalism when dealing with anthropomorphic verses in the

Qur’an.

Reverting to the idea of bila kayf, it can be observed that this doctrine is

based on a few textual presuppositions. First, as alluded to earlier, the principle

that the Qur’an and the Hadiths of the Prophet are the highest authority in

religion. This position is based on another premise, namely, that the Qur’an is
perfect and contains everything that is needed by the Muslims.122 Moving from
123 124

that, the third presupposition is that one should not say about God’s attributes

more than what the Qur’an and the Prophet have made clear. This also implies

that, as far as the knowledge of God and His attributes are concerned, those

matters outside the pronouncement of the Qur’an and the Hadiths are extraneous

and even considered innovations. Moreover, the Qur’an has made it clear that

there is nothing like Him, which means that the attempt to contemplate about

the nature of the Godhead is utterly useless. Hence the proper way to deal with the

anthropomorphic verses is to follow the consensus or ijmac of the Companions of

the Prophet and their Followers (tabi un), that is, to keep silent on those areas upon

which the Prophet also kept silent.

122 H. Laoust, “Ahmad bin Hanbal,” 274.


123 Based on the Qur’anic verse which says, “But with His knowledge, there is not a grain in the
darkness of the earth, nor anything fresh or dry but is inscribed in a Clear Book.” Al-Anam 6: 59.
124 Al-Qur'an, al-Shura 42:11.

45
Another strong argument used by the Hanabilab in defending the MJ kayf

doctrine is the verse of the Qur’an which affirms that only God knows the

meaning of these verses:

He it is Who has sent down to you the Book. In it are the verses basic
or fundamental (of established meaning). They are the foundation of
the Book. Others are not of well-established meanin But those in

CTQ
whose hearts is perversity follow the part thereof that is not of well-
established meaning, seeking discord, and searching for its hidden
meanings. But no one knows its true meanings except Allah. And
those who are firmly grounded in knowledge say, “We believed in the
Book; the whole of it is from our Lord. None will grasp the Message
except men of understanding.”125

This verse is a reminder to Muslims not to tamper with the meaning of the

anthropomorphic verses since only God knows their meanings. However, there is

also another interpretation which may invalidate this argument, namely, that by

considering the ‘vraw’ as an attached conjunction (yvaw al-ataf), which gives the

meaning that only God and those who are deeply rooted in knowledge are those

who know the meaning of this verse. Yet the Hartabilab’s reply to this, through

the ton ue of Ibn Taymiyyah, another staunch follower of Ibn Hanbal, is that even
CfQ

if this interpretation is granted, these two different contradictory meanings are still

valid. For both meanings actually refer to two different aspects: the first refers to

the meaning of the words, which is known to those scholars, and the second refers

to the modality (kayfiyyab) of these words, which only God knows. In fact, it is

the combination of these two interpretations, according to Ibn Taymiyyah, that


became the basis of the doctrine bila kayf.126

We may also, thus far, observe at least two important criteria underlying

the bila kayf methodology in approaching the anthropomorphic expressions of the

Qur’an. First, it is a strict adherence to the authority of the Qur’an in the sense

that the literal meaning of the verses must be upheld absolutely. This is in line

125 Qur’an, Al 'Imran 3:7.


126 Abrahamov, “Bila Kayfa Doctrine,” 374.

46
with the position of the Hanabilah as the Upholders of the Traditions (Ahl al-

Had.ith') as compared to the usage of the rational way. Once the Qur’an affirms,

for example, that God has face, the affirmation must be absolute. Second, it is the

total negation of corporeal qualities to God. The word ‘kayf in Arabic specifically

refers to an inquiry into the corporeal features of a thing. Hence, in order not to

fall into anthropomorphic attributions to God due to a preceding strict and literal

affirmation of meaning, this affirmation is immediately qualified by the denial of

any form or modality in regard to the mentioned attribute. In other words,

however similar the attributes of God to the human qualities, the underlying

principle must be denial of the real similarity. Among the implication of this

qualification, as stated by Abrahamov, is an attestation to man’s inability to know

God’s essence.127 While Arberry viewed that this qualification as a recognition

particularly by Ahmad ibn Hanbal of the limitation of human reason thus offering
resolution to the conflict between reason and revelation in Islam.128 129

iii.ii. The Hanabilah

The position of Ibn Hanbal was later developed by his followers, the Handbilahn)

Although the Hanabilah shared the same strict inclination with Ibn Hanbal, it is

noteworthy to point out the diversity within this school especially the inclination

of some of its members to go overboard either in using the rational approach of

ta or to be more strict and consequently fall into the abyss of

anthropomorphism.130 As put by Abu Zahrah, Hartabilah can generally be divided

into three main groups: (i) those who inclined towards the rational approach which

127 Ibid., 367.


128 A. J. Arberry, Revelation and Reason in Islam (London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1957), 22.
129 Among the prominent Hanbalite figures after Ibn Hanbal are both his sons Salih (d. 879) and
‘Abdullah (d. 903), Abu Dawud al-Sijistani (d. 888), Abu Hatim al-Razi (d. 890), Abu Bakr al-
Khallal (d. 923), al-Barbahari, Abu Yala al-Farra’ (d. 1066), Abu al-Wafa’ Ibn 'Aqil (d. 1119), Abu
al-Farraj Ibn al-Jawzi, Muwaffaq al-Din Ibn Qudamah (d. 1223), Ibn Taymiyyah (d. 1350) and Ibn
al-Qayyim al-Jawzi (d. 1729). In modern times, this school is also associated, though with certain
reservations, with Muhammad ‘Abd Wahhab. (d. 1792).
130 Abu Zahrah, Tarikh al-Mazahib al-Islamiyyah (Al-Qahirah: Dar al-Fikr al'Arabi, 1989), 79.

47
is closer to the Ashairab and the Mutazilab; (ii) Those with the strict literal

approach thus falling into the trap of anthropomorphism that is in variance with

the teaching of Ibn Hanbal; (iii) those in the middle position who emphasized the

importance of the text while not ignoring the utilization of reason. As an example

of the Hanabilab who were rationalists, we read the attack by Ibn Qudamah

(d.1223) against his fellow scholar, Ibn 'Aqil (d.1119), who, according to the former

was influenced by the Mu tazilah in using ta’wil on the anthropomorphic verses.131

Ibn ‘Aqil, who was also in favour of al-Hallaj’s mystical pantheism, was also

reported to be forced to revoke his belief by reading his retraction letter before

reat assembly with the presence of state authorities and witnesses.13 As to the
CfQ

anthropomorphic inclination among the Hartabilab, it is evidenced from the fact

that some of them were severely criticized by Ibn al-Jawzi (d.1200), an

authoritative Hanabilab jurist, for committing tashbih. Ibn al-Jawzi denounced

them and denied the fact that these people were the followers of the early

generations (salafiyy un) as they claimed themselves to be and that their views
were not the views of Ibn Hanbal.133 By treating the problem of divine attributes at

the level of the senses Ibn al-Jawzi asserted that their discussions degraded to the

level of laymen (aw am) thereby destroying the good name of their own madbbab:

I observe among our people (ashaburta) those who were saying about
the fundamentals [of the religion] which are not appropriate, and this
refers to the writings of three persons: Abu 'Abdullah bin Hamid, his
friend al-Qadi [Abu Ya'la] and Ibn al-Zaghuni. They wrote books
that have disgraced the [Hanbalite] school. I saw that they have
descended to the level of common people and have taken the
attributes at the level of senses (ala muqtada al-hiss).134

131 See Ibn Qudamah, 21.


132 George Makdisi, Ibn Aqil: Religion and Culture in Classical Islam (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 1997), 5.
133 Abu al-Farraj Ibn al-Jawzi al-Hanbali, Daf' Sbubab al-Tanzib bi Akuff al-Tanzib, ed. Hassan
Saqqaf (‘Amman: Dar al-Imam al-Nawawi, 1992), 97-99; Abu Zahrah, Tarikb al-Mazabib al-
Islamiyyab (Al-Qahirah: Dar al-Fikr alcArabi, 1989), 193.
134 Ibn al-Jawzi, Dafe Sbubab, 97-99.

48
Ibn al-Jawzl even reckoned them as innovators of the Hanbalf school.

Qadi Abu Yada (d. 1066), one of the three persons referred by Ibn al-Jawzl who

wrote al-Mu tamad fi Usui al-Dih, was also spoken ill by some fuqaba’ of the

Hanabilab, saying that he had “disgraced the Hanabilah in a way that even the
1
ocean water cannot wash it.”

A much earlier Hanbalite, Ibn Khuzaymah had written book Kitab al-

Taw hid wa Ithbat Sfat al-Rabb in which he affirmed that God possesses form

(surah), a face, eyes, hands and other limbs mentioned by the Qur’an. Maintaining

that he is the follower of Ahl al-Sunnab wa al-Athar, as other Hanbalites, Ibn

Khuzaymah insisted that he only argued based on what have been underlined

(mastur) by the Qur’an and authoritative Hadi ths.135


136 He thus described God, for

example, as having two hands as mentioned by the Qur’an and both of this hands

are right hands as reported by the Hadith.137 138


He affirmed that like human beings,

God has a face but God’s face is everlasting (based on the verse wa yabqa wajhu

rabbika) and veiled by light (based on the Hadith which says that God’s face is

veiled by a light which whenever it is unveiled, the face of God will burn

everything that is beheld by His sight (la’ahraqat sabahat wajbihi kullu sbay’

adrakabu basarubu), while the face of human beings will perish.139 As we will see

later, it is these literal views of Ibn Khuzaymah as well as those of other literalists

from the Hanbalites that became the points of attack by al-Razi.

Another Hanbalite scholar who also came under strict scrutiny with regard

to his position on anthropomorphism was the famous fourteenth century polemist,

Ibn Taymiyyah. He was responsible for spreading Hanbalism in the later stage of

its historical development. Like other Hanabilah, he rejected ta ’wil as the mean of

Qur’anic interpretation, arguing that its acceptance will imply that revelation is not

135 Ibid.
136 Ibn Khuzaymah, Kitab al-Tawhid, 21.
137 Ibid., 27.
138 Al-Qur’an, al-Rahman 55:27.

49
clear guidance as it is suppose to be and the Prophet did not fulfill his role as the

interpreter of the Qur’an.1 This position, which arose from his rejection of

figurative expression (majaz) in Arabic language, has led him to hold that all

expressions used in the revelation are used in the real sense (haqiqab') including

141 Consequently, as reported by Ibn Hajar, Ibn


the anthropomorphic ones.140

Taymiyyah had mentioned certain words concerning doctrine which imply

anthropomorphism.142 For example, in one of his sermons where he had cited the

Hadith of Allah’s descent (to the nearest heaven), he apparently climbed down two

steps from the mimbar and said: “like this descent of mine (ka nuz Hi hadha).”143

In Ta’sis fi al-Radd Asas al-Taqdis, written by Ibn Taymiyyah as a reply to al-

Razi’s views against the extreme Hanabilab, he affirmed that God is at the top of

the Throne when he was discussing regarding the issue of istiwa’. He ar ued that

CfQ
al-arsh in the linguistic sense means al-sarir (elevated seat or couch), so named

with respect to what is on top of it (yva dbalika bi al-nisbab ila ma fawqihi), just

as a roof is so named with respect to what is under it (ka al-saqfibi al-nisbah ila

ma tahtibi). Therefore, if the Qur an attributes throne to Allah, it is then

140 Siraje S. Abdallah, “Al-Ghazali and Ibn Taymiyyah on the Legitimacy and Status of 'Ilm al-
Kalam,” (Ph.D. dissertation, ISTAC, HUM, 2000), 97. For Ibn Taymiyyah’s criticisms on the
priority of reason especially in al-Razi’s work, see Chapter Four, 171-174
141 Ibid., 100.
142 Ibn Hajar al-'Asqalani, al-Durar al-Kaminab fial-A yan al-Mi‘at al-Tbaminah (Bayrut: Dar al-
Jil, n.d.), vol. 1, 154. According to Ibn Hajar, people considered Ibn Taymiyyah as an
anthropomorphist [mujassim] because of what he mentioned regarding the anthropomorphic
qualities of God in his al-Aqfdah al-Hamawiyyah and dX-Aqidab al-Wasadyyab and other books
of his, such as Allah’s hand, foot, chin, and face being literal attributes of Allah (sifat haqiqiyyah
lillah) and that He is established upon the Throne with His essence. Nevertheless, it is also reported
that Ibn Taymiyyah had repented of his own free will from all the above on the 25th of Rabi ‘al-
Awwal of the year 707H, and that it was witnessed by a huge array of scholars and others. Ibid.,
148.
143 Ibid. This view of Ibn Taymiyyah which was based on the Ibn Batutah’s report, however, was
disputed by the JJanabilab through the following arguments: i) that all the writings of Ibn
Taymiyyah regarding God’s descent (haditb al-nuzuT) did not at all mention what Ibn Batutah
claimed he was uttering, ii) there is a conflict between the date of the incident claimed by Ibn
Batutah that is in the month of Ramadan 726H and the date Ibn Taymiyyah was imprisoned (early
Sha'ban 726H) until he died in 728. iii) Even if the saying of Ibn Taymiyyah took place, he might
had said with a negation, ‘not like this descent of mine’ (la ka nuzuli hadha) but the negation
might not being heard by Ibn Batutah. Ahmad b. Hajar al Batami, Naqd al-Kalam al-Muftori’ ala
al-Hanabilah al-Salafiyyin (Doha: Maktabah Ibn Qayyim, 1993), 42-45.

50
known that this Throne is, with respect to Allah, like the elevated seat is with

respect to other than Allah. This makes it necessarily true that He is on the
Throne.144 Regarding the charge that the Hanabilah ascribed body to God, Ibn

Taymiyyah in the same book maintained that the Qur’an, the Sunnah, and the

consensus (of scholars) nowhere say that all bodies are created (lam tantiq bi anna

al-ajsam kullaha muhdathahf nor that Allah Himself is not a body (yva anna

Allah laysa bi jismf None of the imams of the Muslims have ever said such

&
thing. Therefore, he claimed, if he also chooses not to say it, it does not expel him

from religion nor from shariah.145

iv. The Asha irah

The position of the Asha irah can be regarded as the middle course between the

two extreme positions of the Mu tazilah and Jahmiyyah, on one hand, and the

mushabbihah, on the other. In what follows, we will analyze the views of two

major Ash arI figures prior to al-Razi on this issue. They are Abu Hassan al-

Ash’ari, the founder of the school and Abu Hamid al-Ghazali, the leader of the

later Asha irah movement. Both of them not only represent the two stages of the

development of Ash’ari kalam146 but also had dominantly coloured the whole

spectrum of this school’s position on this issue.

iv.i. Ab u Hassan al-Ash ari

Trained in the school of speculative theology of the Mu tazilah, Abu Hassan al-

Ashari utilized excellently his masters’ apparatus against them, at the same time

reaffirming the main principles of traditional theology which so far were associated

144 Muhammad Zahid al-Kawthari, Maqalat a/-Kuwthur/’(Al-Qahirah: Maktabah al-Azhariyyah li


al-Turath, 1994), 395.
145 Ibid.
146 As far as the history of Ash arf kalam is concerned, it’s development can generally be divided
into two stages; the early school (al-awwalurf) which started from the time of it’s founder al-
Ash'ari onwards and the later school (al-muta’akhkhirun) whose inception was marked by the
coming of al-Ghazali. See Muqaddimah, 466; Syed Muhammad Naquib al-Attas, A Commentary on
the ffujjat al-Sddiq of Nur al-Dih al-Raniri (Kuala Lumpur: Ministry of Culture, 1986), 211-213.

51
mainly with Ibn Hanbal. His reverence for Ibn Hanbal is obvious in the outset of

his most important theological treatise, al-Ibanab, in which he also laid down his

important sources in kalam:

The belief we hold and the religion we follow are holding fast to the
Book of our Lord, to the Sunnah of our Prophet, and to the traditions
related on the authority of the companions and the successors of the
imams of the Hadith; to that we hold firmly, professing what Abu
'Abdullah Ahmad bin Muhammad Ibn Hanbal professed, and avoiding
him who dissents from his belief, because he is the excellent imam
and the perfect leader, through whom God declared the truth,
removed error, manifested the modes of action, and overcame the
innovations of the innovators, the deviation of the deviators, and the
skepticism of the skeptics. The mercy of God be upon him, for he is
an eminent imam and an exalted, honoured friend.147

Based on the foundation laid down by Ibn Hanbal, al-Ash'ari developed

further the simplicity of the traditional theology to become something with a more

strong rational foundation to the extent that it finally emerged as a school in itself.

Klein, in assessing this contribution of al-Ash’ari, comments that the latter has:

drafted the kalam into the service of orthodoxy, took a mean


position-half way between rationalism and anthropomorphism-and
paved the way for the subsequent rationalization and
intellectualization of Islam. 148

The difference between al-Ash’ari and Ibn Hanbal is obvious in a few

respects. While Ibn Hanbal, due to his simplicity in approach, did not present his

own theology in a systematic way, al-Ash'ari, on the other hand, had a complete

theological system presented in a few of his major works such as al-Ibanab fTUsd

al-Diyanah, al-Luma c and Maqalat al-Islamiyyih. Secondly, in presenting his

theological arguments, al-Ash'ari, unlike Ibn Hanbal, also utilized speculation to

arrived at his conclusions. For that matter, Hadith was not the main concern of

Ash'ari compared to Ibn Hanbal.

147 Ibanah, 49.

52
With regard to the divine attributes, al-Ash'ari had in principle a similar

position to Ibn Hanbal, namely, to affirm in the absolute manner, the existence of

divine attributes. Ibn 'Asakir (d.1175), the historian of Ashairah regarded al-

Ash'ari as “the most redoubtable champion of the affirmists (mutbbit un) who

avoided the extremes of ta ‘til and tashb ih.”149 Al-Ash'ari’s affirmative position is

demonstrated mostly in his al-Ib anah fl Usui al-Diyanah, a work which manifests

virtually almost the same strict literal position of Ibn Hanbal. However, it is

important to note that, compared to his other theological works such al-Luma 'and

Risalah Istihsan al-Khawd fl Ilm al-Kalam ,150 al-Ibanah is highly combative in

tone and has less speculative arguments. This is due to the fact that al-Ibanah, as

affirmed by Ibn 'Asakir, is his first theological work after his conversion from

Mu ’tazilah151 and it is purposely written as a refutation against the latter.152 Bein

polemical work against supra-rational school of the Mu tazilah, a strict

affirmative position is highly expected. McCarthy, a researcher of al-Ash'ari who

even doubts that al-Ibanah in the form which we have it is a genuine work of al-

Ash'ari, gives another contextual justification of this different tone of al-Ibanah.

He viewed that the difference in style and approach could be explained on the basis

that “Ibanah is really a kind of conciliatory gesture which al-Ash'ari made to the

Hanabilah.”153 As a matter of fact, if this reason is granted, we may safely suggest

149 Richard J. McCarthy, The Theology of Ash drI (Bayrut: Imprimarie Catholique, 1953), 148.
150 Compared to al-Luma‘ and Risalah Istihsan al-Khawd fi Ilm al-Kalam, al-Ibanah is
characterized more by a strict, literal and combative style, a method which is closer to that of the
Hanabilah. In al-Luma for example, the style of al-Ash'ari is rather in a dialogue form. He tackled
various philosophical and kalam issues and seemed more appreciative towards both disciplines.
151 McCarthy, 231. See also Ibanah, 29. A. J. Wensinck who also agreed with this view explained
that since al-Ibanah is one of the earliest writings after his conversion it bears his desire to
proclaim his return to the traditional faith and to defend it on scriptural and traditional ground. A.
J. Wensinck, The Muslim Creed: Its Genesis and Historical Development (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1932), 93.
152 At the outset of al-Ibanah, al-Ash'ari pointed out his audience rather clearly, “To begin with,
there are many deviators from the truth among the Mu tazilah and ahi al-qadr whose straying
desires have inclined them to the acceptance of the principles of their leaders...” Al-Ash'ari
continued to summarize their tenets and subsequently refuted them. Ibanah, 46.
153 McCarthy, 232. See also lb anab, 28.

53
that al-Ashcari’s view in al-Ibanab must not be his final position on this issue, as
claimed by certain quarters.154

In al-Ibanab, as alluded to before, al-Ash'ari held strictly to the bila kayf

position of Ibn Hanbal by affirming the anthropomorphic attributes of God as

literally expressed by the Qur’anic verses:

...God is seated on the Throne as He said in the Qur’an, “The


Merciful is seated on the Throne,”155 and He has a face, as He said,
“but the face of your Lord shall abide resplendent with majesty and
glory,”156 and He has two hands, without modality (bila kayfa) as He
said, “I have created with My two hands”157 and as He said “Nay!
Outstretched are both His hands,”158 and that He has an eye, bila
kayfa as He said, “Under our eye it floated on.159 ”160

Since his adversary in this work was mainly the Mu tazilab who basically

denied altogether the independent existence of divine attributes, al-Ash'ari seems

did not differentiate between anthropomorphic attributes and other attributes. For

immediately after the above paragraph, al-Ash'ari continued:

and that anybody who thinks that the Names of God are other than
Him, he is in error; and that God has knowledge, as He said, “in His
knowledge He sent it down161”...162

154 The issue regarding the time al-Ibanah was written has become a point of dispute and
controversy between the researchers of al-Ash'ari. The point of contention is whether it is an early
work of al-Ash'ari after his conversion from the Mu tazilah position or it is his latest work in his
life. The date of al-Ibanab is indeed crucial especially in deciding the position and methodology of
al-Ash'ari with regard to the issue of tasbbib. There were strong claims by the so-called neo-
Hanbalite and the modern Wahabis that al-Ibanab was actually the last work of al-Ash'ari, which
implies that al-Ash'ari had denounced kalam and converted into strict Hanbalism in his later life.
Quoting Ibn Kathir, they divided the life of al-Ash'ari into three phases; His Mu tazili life, his
early conversion in which he still upheld the tavvil position on anthropomorphic attributes and
finally his move back to the real Salafi Hanbalf position which is manifested in his last work, al-
Ibanab.
155 Al-Qur’an Ta Ha 20:4.
156 Al-Qur’an al-Rahman 55:27.
157 Al-Quran, Sad 38:75.
158 Al-Qur’an Sad 38:75.
159 Al-Qur’an al-Qamar 54:14.
160 Ibanah, 50.
161 Al-Qur’an al-Nisa’ 4:164.
162 Ibanah, 50.

54
Another indication that shows how near al-Ash‘ari’s position was to that of

Ibn Hanbal is in the issue of istiwa’. Al-Ashcari, in this case, even affirmed the

direction of ‘above’ with regards to God when he substantiated his position that

God is above the sky by using the oft-quoted Hanbali argument that this [that

God in the direction of ‘above] is one of the reasons why Muslims raise their hands

when asking supplication from God.163 The Hadith of rtuzul which describes that

God descends to the lower heaven,164 is also quoted by him in proving the fact that

God is in the direction of above.165

Parallel to this position, Al-Ashcari slammed the method of allegorical

interpretation in understanding anthropomorphic expressions, as done by the

Mu tazilah. As a pure Arab whose genealogy can be traced to one of the Prophet’s

companion, Abu Musa al-Ashcari, he used this authority to dismiss the use of

some meanings as an interpretation of the anthropomorphic expressions in the

Qur’an. He argued that in the Arabic language and in the use of Arabic

conversation, one may not say that “I have done this and so with my two hands”

to mean with “my two graces,” for it is not in line with the usual classical Arabic

language. Even if one argues that this usage is based on the consensus of the

community (ijma\ the Muslims, according to al-Ashari, would not agree upon

this position. As to the argument that this is based on analogical reasoning (qiyas),

al-Ashari rejected this view and regarded it as baseless.166

Al-Ashari argued that the meaning of these anthropomorphic expressions

must be construed in their specific forms since the context in which the

expressions take place is specific. Hence, he dismissed the Mu tazilah argument

that istiw a’ must be interpreted as “to have power over something” (istawla y

163 Ibid., 83.


164 The full version of the Hadith runs as follows: “God descends every night to the lower heaven
and says, “Is there any who has a request? And I will grant it him. Is there any who asks
forgiveness? And I will forgive him - until dawn arrives”. It is reported by Abu Hurayrah and Abu
Sa'id al-Khudri, Ibn Khuzaymah, Kitab al-Tawhfd, 126.
165 Ibanab, 83-84.
166 Ibid., 89-90.

55
God’s being seated on the Throne cannot mean His having the
mastery that is common to all things; and it is necessarily true that its
meaning is a being seated that belongs particularly to the Throne not
to all things.167

This is generally the position of al-Ash'ari in al-Ibanah. No lengthy

clarification is given in support of a particular view and not much rational basis is

put forward in substantiating the arguments. On the other hand, the attempt of

rational justification is disallowed. Most of the views are focused more towards

affirming the existence of the divine attributes rather than affirming the

transcendence aspect of God which is also equally important as far as al-Ashari’s

kalam is concerned. To explain this phenomena we are again directed to

contextually view that since his adversaries, against whom al-Ashcari’s refutations

are directed to in al-Ibanah were the Mutazilah who had taken an extreme

transcendence position regarding the divine attributes to the extent falling into

ta ctil, it seems that it is not al-Ashari’s concern in this work to emphasize the

transcendence aspect of divine attributes as compared to the affirmative aspect

(thub ut). For that matter, we will look at his other works to find out al-Ashari’s

views on the aspect of tanzib.

A stronger emphasis on the transcendence of God appears in al-Ash'ari’s

other important work, al-Luma f. In the chapter on God’s existence and attributes,

al-Ash ari answered the question, “Why do you claim that the Creator is unlike

creatures?” by bringing forward a highly logical and philosophical answer:

If He were like them, His relation to temporal production would be


the same as theirs. And if He were like them, He would have to be
like them either in all respects or in some one respect. So if He were
like them in all respects, He would be temporally produced, as they
are, in all respects. And if He were like them in some one respect, he
would be temporally produced in that respect in which He was like
them. But it is impossible for the temporally produced to have pre­

167 Ibid., 84.

56
existed eternally. And God Most High has said; “There is nothing
like unto Him” (42:11); and, “No one is His equal” (112:4).168

In an answer to another question, “Why do you deny that God Most High is

body?” he explained:

We deny it because the speaker must mean: Why do you deny that
God is long, broad and united? - or he must mean calling God a body,
even though He be not long, broad, united and deep. Now if he
means, why do you deny that he is long, broad and united? - as that
is said of the bodies of which we have experience - why this is
impossible, because the united is not one thing. For the numerically
least of unions is that of two things, since the thing which is one
cannot be united to itself. But we have shown above that God is one
thing. Hence it will be false to say that He is united. On the other
hand, if the speaker means: Why do you not call God a body, even
though He be not long, broad, and united? Because it is not for us to
assign names, and we may not call God by a name which He has not
pplied to Himself and which has not been pplied to Him by His
Apostle and on which and the meanin of which there is no
CfQ

consensus of the Muslims.169

Through the above explanation, it is clear that the view of al-Ash ari

regarding the divine attributes is based mainly on two important methodologies,

namely affirmation of the attributes, on one hand, and tanzih and the denial of

tashbih, on the other. Though the same basis is used by Ibn Hanbal, the

difference between the methodology of al-Ash ari and Ibn Hanbal can be seen

from the former’s strong rational emphasis on the denial of tashbih aspect which

seems wanting in the latter and his followers. In Klein’s words, “al-Ash'ari is as

much a conservative and a traditionist as Ahmad; but has a far more acute mind,

and cannot be satisfied with Ahmad’s obscurantism.”170 This is also perhaps the

reason, apart from the tashbih inclination of the Hanabilab, why al-Ash'ari’s

position was later established as an independent school rather than being conceived

168 McCarthy, 9.
169 Ibid.,11-12.
™ Ibanah, 35.

57
as one under the Hanbalites. In fact, al-Ashari himself had some disagreements

with the Hanabilah against whom he later wrote his tract, Risalah fi al-Istihsan

al-Khawdfial-Kalam.

iv.ii. Ab u Hamid al-Ghaz all

Abu Muhammad ibn Muhammad al-Tusi al-Ghazali (d.llll) was the one who led

the second stage of Ashari kalam characterized mainly by a more rigorous


employment of formal logic in theological discussions. 171 His defense of this

rational tool is apparent not only in his offensive works meant to destroy his

adversaries’ arguments, such as Tahafut al-Falasifah and al-Radd ala al-

Batiniyyah, but also in his explicative tracts such as Qawaid al-Aqald, Risalah

al-Qudsiyyah and Iqtisad fi al-I tiqad. Due to this highly discreet use of logic by

al-Ghazali, we can see a more thorough, systematic and refined arguments in his

kalam compared to any of his predecessors, which is the reason why he gained the

title of ‘The Proof of Islam’ (Hujjat al-Islam).

Epistemologically, al-Ghaz all viewed that both aql and naql have their own

respective functions in channelling knowledge to us, position that was, in

principle, not that alien to the Asharite mutakallimun before him. Yet, what sets

him apart is that, for him, knowledge that comes through naql must also be within

the ken of reason, otherwise the meaning of the revelation must be interpreted

through ta\vH. This epistemological principle reveals his concern in seeking an

absolute harmony between reason and revelation in Islam. It also implies his

continuous emphasis on the aspect of the transcendence of God which was much

171 See Muqaddimah, 466; al-Attas, A Commentary, 211-213. The mutakallimun from the early
school were more associated with the dialectical method which was known at that time as adab al-
kalam or adab al-jadal. This method, also termed as al-naqd al-jadalf (in contradistinction to the
method al-naqd al-falsafi of the later theologians), was used mostly through the form of query
and answer (su’al wa jawab), i.e. in the style “if somebody says, we answer” (wain qala qallun
qulna ) or “one cannot say that...because we would answer” (yva la yuqalu inn a... li ’anna naquliT).
See Josef van Ess, “The Logical Structure of Islamic Theology”, Logic in Classical Islamic Culture,
ed. G.E. Griinebaum (Wiesbaden, Otto Harrassowitz, 1970), 22.

58
impaired by the wrong understanding of tajsim - inclined to by some sects of his

time such as the mushabbihab, Batiniyyah and to some extent the Hanabilah.

No doubt, this epistemological principle influenced tremendously his notion

of divine transcendence. As alluded to before, the emphasis on the transcendence

of God indeed gains a higher position in al-Ghazali’s exposition of kalam. In his

Risalah al-Qudsiyyah, al-Ghazali maintained that belief in God is based on the

pronouncement, “There is no god except Allah, Muhammad is His Messenger” (la

ilab ilia Allah, Muhammad Rasul Allah). This two-part formula, in turn, consists

of four important pillars: confirmation of the essence of God, of His attributes, His
works (afal) and the truthfulness of His Messenger.172 All these four parts consist

of ten fundamentals. In affirming the first pillar of belief, which is the essence of

God, half of the ten fundamentals (arkan) assigned by al-Ghazali related to the

manner of affirming the transcendence of God especially in the form of denying

God’s anthropomorphic characters. These five components are, the affirmation

that God is neither a substance (jawbar), nor a body (jism), nor an accident (arad),

that He is not limited by direction (jibah) nor settled in a location (makan), and

Under the second pillar, the affirmation


that He can be seen (in the Hereafter).173 174

of the attributes of God, again among the important underlying divine attributes is

that God is exalted above and immune from any incorporation in originated things

(munazzahan an hulul al-hawadith)™

In explaining further the sub-section that the essence of God is exalted

above the notion of limitation by any direction, the different approach brought

about by al-Ghazali appears clearly when he denied the impossibility of ascribing

God with the ascription of the notion of direction by pointing out the relativity and

originated nature of the notion of direction:

172 Al-Ghazali, Risalah Qudsiyyah, ed. & trans. A. L. Tibawi under the title ‘Al-Ghazali’s Tract on
Dogmatic Theology’, The Islamic Quarterly, vol. 9 (1965): 95.
173 Ibid.
174 oa

59
...direction is either up or down, right or left, front or behind, and
these were created by Him through His creation of man. He created
him with two extremities, the one rests on earth and is called foot,
and the other, its opposite, is called head. The notion of up was
originated to indicate what is above the head and the conception of
down to indicate what is near to the location of the foot. Even if an
ant creeping along a ceiling: what is down in relation to its position is
still up in relation to ours...all directions are therefore originated
through the fact that man is originated...Is it possible then that He
was in all eternity limited by direction which is originated or that He
becomes limited by direction after He had none?...All this is
impossible for the mind to conceive. For the conceivable is that
whatever is limited by direction is also limited by space like
substance, or is limited by substance in the same way as accidents

This view indicates refinement of arguments within the later Ash ari

mutakallimun. in their exposition of the divine attributes. If al-Asff arl before this,

due to the acceptance of the literal meaning of the anthropomorphic verses of the

Qur’an, affirmed the notion of direction ‘above’ with regard to God, al-Ghazali is

more cautious and elaborative in explaining the issue. This also shows stronger

emphasis, on the part of al-Ghazali, to stress the more harmonious explication of

the divine reality between the Qur’anic text and the rational principles which are

not fully developed in the views of his master al-Asff arl.

For that matter, as far as anthropomorphic expression is concerned, al-

Ghazali was compelled to resort to an interpretive position. When dealing with the

Qur’anic meaning of istiwa’, for example, he stressed:

The eighth fundamental is the knowledge that He most high is


settled upon His Throne, in the sense which He most high intended
by settlement. [This is a sense] which is neither inconsistent with
His ma nificence nor implies any of the characteristics of [the finite
CfQ

such as] origination and annihilation. It is in the sense which He


intended by His saying in the Qur’an “Then He lifted Himself
(istawa) to Heaven when it was smoke.” That was in no other way
except by His Omnipotent power as the poet said, “Bishr has gained*

175 Ibid., 102.

60
control over Iraq without sword or bloodshed.” Such interpretation
was forced upon the people of truth (ahi al-Jyaq). Likewise those
who seek the hidden meaning were forced to resort to interpretation
of the verse, “He is with you wherever you are” which generally is
interpreted to mean “by His omniscience.” Similarly the words of
the Prophet, “The heart of the believer is between the two fingers of
the Merciful” were interpreted to mean “subject to His
omnipotence...” Otherwise, if the apparent meaning [on all these
matters were adopted] it would necessitate the impossible, and what
leads to impossible is itself impossible.176

Notice how al-Ghazali began by asserting the traditionists’ premise that the

nature of istiwa9 is actually according to what is intended by God Himself. Yet, for

him, this meaning is not something totally unknown to us, as what was repeatedly

claimed by the Hanabilah who quoted the Prophet’s Hadith on the authority of

Malik b. Anas.17 On the other hand, we can comprehend the meanin through the

CfQ
use of the word linguistically either in the Qur’an or on other occasions. On top of

that, what seems more important for al-Ghazali is that the meaning must not

impair the understanding of the nature of divine Reality as expounded by other

Qur’anic verses, a principle which manifests itself clearly in the pillars of faith

(ark an al-iman). Even worse, this understanding must not lead to an ascription to

the divine essence of something that is unworthy. Hence, istiwa’:

...if taken to mean settlement or possession, it would necessitate that


He who settles upon the Throne or possesses it, is a substance in
contact with the Throne and that He is either equal to it in size, or
lar er or smaller. But this is impossible, and what leads to the
CfQ

impossible is itself impossible. 178

In anticipating the critique of the Hanabilah, al-Ghazali has excellently

demonstrated how ta \vil is permissible not only in comprehending the

176 Ibid, 102-103.


“God’s sittin on the Throne is known, but its modality is unknown, the belief in it is obligatory
tn

and the inquiry about it is innovation” (al-istiwa ma turn al-kayf majbul al-iman bihfwajib wa al-
su ’al anhu bid ah).
178 Al-Ghazali, Risalah Qudsiyyah, 103.

61
anthropomorphic expressions, but is also a valid methodology in dealing with these

matters. Drawing his arguments from metaphysics which seems wanting within

the Hanabilab, al-Ghazali identified five levels of existence the ignorance of which,

have brought various Muslim sects to charge one another as unbelievers. The five

levels are ontological (wujud. al-dhatf), sensory existence (JJlssi), conceptual


existence (khayalf), noetic existence (aqlf) and analogous existence (shabab f).1S0

While there is no room for ta^vil for the things with ontological existence, any

rational interpretation of expressions in the Scripture or Hadith which refers to any

of these levels other than the ontological is valid and cannot be regarded as tellin

CfQ
lies about the Qur’an or the Prophet. With the introduction of these levels of

existence, al-Ghazali is giving more rooms to ta’wil at the same time trying to

place things into context and identify the final limit beyond which person will

fall into the abyss of unbelief (kufi).

179 In regard to the use of ta ’wil, we are very much aware of al-Ghazali’s warning against the usage
of this method in understanding the verses of the Qur’an in his work, Iljam al-Aw am. Yet as the
title clearly indicates that this warning is addressed to the general masses of the Muslims, plus the
nature this study is for the higher level of understanding, the view we take still stand.
180 Ontological (wujud al-dbati) refers to the real, concrete existence of things external to both the
senses such as the existence of heavens and earth, animal and plants. Sensory existence (Jussi)
refers to the things that acquire form through the visual power of the eye, while they have no
existence outside the eye, like the Prophet saw Gabriel on several occasions. This is due to the
extreme purity of the inner self of someone. On the lower level, it is like a person who sees the line
of fire when he move an amber in a circular motion. Conceptual existence (khayali) refers to the
physical image of things that are normally perceived through the senses in instances where these
things themselves are removed from the reach of the senses. For example when we close our eyes
after seeing an elephant, we can still see the form of an elephant. Noetic existence (aqli) refers to
instances where a thing possesses a functional nature (ruh), haqiqah and ma ha, but the mind
isolates its essence without positing any physical image of it in the imagination, the senses or the
outside world. For example, one can perceive the physical image of a hand through the senses, or
one can simply conceptualize it in the imagination. Hand also connotes an essence which is its
epseity namely the ability to size and to strike. The ability to seize and to strike them is the ‘noetic
hand’. Analogous existence (sbabahi) refers to instances wherein a thing itself does not exist,
either as an image or in reality, either in the outside world or in the senses, the imagination or the
mind, but something analogous to it that possesses some quality or attribute peculiar to it exists.179180
Al-Ghazali, Faysal al-Tafriqab, trans. & intro. Sherman a. Jackson under the title ‘On the
Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam: Al-Ghazali’s Faysal al-Tafriqa’ (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2003), 93-96.

62
From the above explanations, we can make some important observations

with regard to al-Ghazali’s overall methodology in dealing with the transcendence

of God and the understanding of the anthropomorphic expressions in the Qur’an.

First, with regard to the issue of divine attributes, al-Ghazali is still loyal to the

Asharites’ affirmative position as opposed to the ta ‘til position of the Mu tazilah,

which means that he affirmed the existence of the attributes to the essence.

Second, there is a stronger emphasis by al-Ghazali on the transcendence of God in

particular against the anthropomorphic implications. This consequently leads to

the third observation, namely, that there is a continual insistence on the rationally

harmonious exposition of the divine nature with the employment of allegorical

interpretation (taw/l) by al-Ghazali in treating the anthropomorphic expressions.

This insistence will become more obvious later when we deal with al-Razi’s views

on a similar topic.

CONCLUSION

From the above theological mapping of the main groups, we can observe that in

dealing with the issue of anthropomorphism, Islamic sects in general are divided
into three main divisions. 181 First, those who strongly emphasize divine

transcendence, hence interpret the anthropomorphic expressions in a figurative

way. Second, those who emphasize the superiority of revelation, the result of

which is the adoption of the literal meanings of these anthropomorphic

expressions. The extreme among them fall into tashbih, the act of comparing and

assimilating God with human attributes. The third are those who accept the

meaning of these expressions as they are without trying to interpret their modality

181 It is important to note that this classification is based on the methodology taken by these groups.
It, therefore, must not be taken in its strict sense since there may be individuals who, as far as
general methodology is concerned, adhere to one group but are also employing some specific
methodology of others. Hence, we might encounter that in some cases there are exceptional cases
such as in the example of Ibn 'Aqil and Ibn al-Jawzi who are Hanabilah yet employed the first
approach. On the other hand, there are individual in Mu tazilab who also being included in the
mujassimab group such as Hisham bin al-Hakam and Ibn al-Rawandi.

63
and quality (kayfiyyab). The first group escapes the complication of the problem

by moving away from the literal, anthropomorphic meanings toward their

allegorical meanings. This is the position of the Jahmiyyab but was later more

associated with the Mu tazilah who were more systematic in their articulation of
ideas compared to the Jahmiyyab.132 However, the second and third groups, i.e.,

the musbabbibah and bi la kayfiyyah, though proceeded from similar startin

CfQ
point namely a literal understanding of anthropomorphic verses, arrived at slightly

different conclusions. The former, due to their tenacious adherence to the text,

ended up describing God with various anthropomorphic qualities. To this group

belong the majority of the mujassimab and musbabbibah and some segments of

the Hanabilab. While the latter group, though still in some way branded by some

as committing tasbbib through the terms hashwiyyah, uncritical interpretation of

the anthropomorphic verses, they were somehow restrained by the qualifying

mechanism of balkafa, position associated to the early generation of Muslims


183
(al-salaf) which later on was developed by Ibn Hanbal.

Between these groups, there were also those who, epistemologically,

combined the two approaches hence cannot strictly be placed within the above

divisions. Such position can be said in regard to the Asbairah. Although the

approach of the leader of this school, Abu Hassan al-Ash'ari was closer and more

akin to Ibn Hanbal’s approach, the later Ashairah managed to strike middle

round in their theological views between the ta ‘til of the Mu tazilah and the
CfQ

tafwid or literalism of the Hanabilab. This role was mainly played by al-Ghazali

but later on as we will show in this study, it is continued by Fakhr al-Din al-Razi.* *

182 The Jahmiyyab and Mu tazilah are two sects which were associated with the denial of the
attributes of God and the usage of allegorical interpretation. Although they were together in this
aspect, they somehow differ in other aspects such as in the case of the human acts, in which,
Jahmiyyab believed that human actions were pre-determined by God while the Mu tazilah believed
that human beings create their own actions which is more consistent with the denial of divine
attributes. See Milal, 41, 72-74; Farq, vol.2, 13; W.M. Watt, Islamic Philosophy, 46-55.
183 Watt, Islamic Philosophy, 98-99; Williams, 442.

64
A deeper analysis of the method used by these sects will also reveal to us

that they actually center around two important epistemological inclinations: those

who emphasize more on the role of revelation, and those who stress reason. Unlike

the experience of the Western philosophical tradition, which reached the extent of

conflicting these two sources of knowled e, 184 the problem in the history of Islamic

CfQ
theology is characterized by the degree of emphasis given to these two channels of

knowledge. Concerning divine attributes in particular, those sects which stress the

superiority of revelation will accordingly incline towards ithb at, the affirmation, in

the absolute sense, all the divine attributes expressed by the revelation including
185 On the other hand, Islamic sects with a strong
the anthropomorphic ones.184

rationalist tendency would adopt tanzih, that is to remove altogether

anthropomorphic meanings from divine attributes, while at the same time try to

prevent any complication arising from the apparent tension between reason vis-a-

vis revelation. The de ree of inclination among these groups towards these two
CfQ

inclinations is, of course, different depending on the strength of their

epistemological and religious backgrounds.

184 See the conflict between Christianity and Science, faith in reason for example, in David C.
Lindberg & Ronald L. Numbers (eds.) God and Nature: Historical Essays on the Encounter between
Christianity and Science (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986); David Jasper & T.R.
Wright (ed.), The Critical Spirit and the Will to Believe (Humpshire, 1989).
185 It is to this inclination that al-Shahrastani alluded to by the term Muthabbit un (the Affirmists)
with Ashairah as the leaders, but also includes the musbabbihah such as the Karamiyyah. Milal,
88-96.

65
CHAPTER TWO

DIVINE ATTRIBUTES
IN AL-RAZI’S kalAm

INTRODUCTION

In the preceding chapter, we have traced the historical and intellectual

background of the issue of divine transcendence and the problem of

anthropomorphism including the views of various groups either in support of

anthropomorphism or in opposition to it. Since this issue centered mainly around

the discussion of divine attributes, particularly the nature of those attributes

which are based on the divine and Prophetic reports (sifat khabariyyab\ this

chapter will further analyze al-Razi s thought concernin the divine attributes

CfQ
which include the definition of attributes and their difference from divine names.

Also, it will discuss al-Razi’s views regarding the nature of divine attributes and

their relation to divine essence. Further, it will look into his classification of

attributes and the position of divine transcendence in his classification and how

his position on transcendence influence his classification of attributes and

consequently stood as a strong foundation for the attack against his adversaries.

This discussion becomes the basis of the topic in the following chapter, namely

al-Razi’s view on the transcendence of God as expounded in his Kitab Asas al-

Taqdfs. A clear understanding of al-Razi’s conception of divine attributes in his

theological system will enhance our knowledge of comprehending the reason for

his position with regard to anthropomorphism.

CONCEPTION OF THE ATTRIBUTES


Derived from the verb wasafa which literally means ‘to furnish’ (halla),1 the

term sifah is defined as ‘a mark or a characteristic inherent in something

1 Ibn Manzur, vol. 9, 356-357.

66
described, by which the latter is known’ (al-amarab al-lazimab bi dbat al-

mawstf alladbf yurafu bib a) 2 3It also denotes something that subsists in an

essence artm bi al-dbat) or in a locus (al-mahall). Although as a noun, the

term sifab does not occur in the Qur’an, the verb wasafa is mentioned thirteen

times,4 mostly to indicate improper and false descriptions used by the unbelievers

for God,5 such as in the verse “and they falsely, having no knowledge, attribute

to Him son and daughters. Praise and glory be to Him, for He is above what

they attribute (yasifun) to Him.”6 The absence of the term sifab in the Qur’an

led some mutakallimun to deny the existence of God’s attributes as in the case of
Ibn Hazm, an early tenth century literalist (zahiri) mutakallimun of Spain.7 He

also viewed that the application of the term sifab to God is an innovation in

religion (bidab) because it was not mentioned by the Prophet and the

Companions.8

The non-presence of the term in the Qur’an, however, is not a strong

reason for other mutakallimun to reject the existence of the divine attributes.

What seems to be more important was the ontological status of the attributes

rather than its terminological occurrence in the Qur’an. This can be seen

through the fact that the continuous debate between the Asbairab and the

Mu tazilab regarding the nature of divine attributes was centered more on the

relation between the attributes and the divine essence, that either the attributes

existed in addition to the essence or they were identical with the essence. In

2 Al-Jurjani, al-Tarifat, 145.


3 Al-Tahanawi, vol. 4, 338.
4 Al-Qur’an, 16:62, 16:116, 12:18, 12:77, 21:18, 21:22, 21:112, 23:91, 23:96, 6:100, 37:159, 37:180,
43:82.
5 Ibn Manzur, 356.
6 Al-Qur’an al-An am 6:100. Other verses are al-Anbiya’ 21:22; al-Saffat 37:159, 180; al-Zukhruf
43:82. See further the analysis of this term in Harry Austryn Wolfson, The Philosophy of Kalam
(Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1976), 112-132.
1 Fa si, vol. 2, 283.
8 Ibid. Ibn Hazm claims that the term 'sifab was devised by the Mu tazilah and the masters of
the kalam who did not follow the true path of the early Muslim (salaf al-salih).

67
addition, throughout the polemics concerning divine attributes, the reality of

divine attributes is not only referred to by the term sifah, but also by other terms

such as ma ha (meaning/idea), hal (state), ashy a’ (things) and lazim


(concomitant)9 which were constantly used by the mutakallimun. Even the

Mu tazilah who advanced more philosophical and rigorous arguments in their

denial of the existence of divine attributes, still used the term sifah in their

explication of the reality of the divine attributes. This can be seen, for example,

from the fact that the subtitles of Shark Usui al-Khamsah by the Mu tazili

scholar 'Abd al-Jabbar also employed the word sifat when referring to divine

attributes.10 In fact, the earliest mention of the term 'sifah', occurs in the report

of the teaching of the founder of the Mu tazilah, Wasil bin 'Ata’.11

According to al-Razi, although there is no mention of the term sifah in

the Qur’an, its existence is already implied by the phrase 'Asma' al-Jfusna (the
Beautiful Names of God) which appears four times in the Qur’an.12 These Names

refer to God’s descriptions of Himself in the Qur’an, further enumerated by the

Prophet in a long Hadith narrated by Abu Hurayrah.13 Except the name ‘Allah,’

which is a proper name (ism alam) that refers to the essence, almost all these

names are derived from attributes.14 Since a noun or a name can either be

name of an essence or a name based on an attribute which describes the essence,

the meanin of attributes are, therefore, subsumed under names. In addition, all
CfQ

9 See in-depth discussion on these terms in Wolfson, The Philosophy, 112-132.


10 'Abd. Al-Jabbar, 151,182. Among the subtitles of this book under the general heading al-
Tawhid are ‘Words on the Divine Attributes’ (al-Kalam fi al-Sfat), and the ‘On the Way How
God Deserves the Attributes, (fi Kayfiyyah IstihqaqihiTa ala li al-Sfat).
11 Wolfson, The Philosophy, 118.
12 Theology, 88. The verses are al-Araf 7:180; al-Isra’ 17:110; Taha 20:8; al-Hashr 59:24.
13 In a long Hadith, Abu Hurayrah narrates that “to Allah belong Ninety-Nine Names, those who
enumerate them shall enter Paradise...” The Hadith continues with the enumeration of the
famous Ninety-Nine Names of God. See Law ami', 109.
14 Law ami', 109. According to al-Razi, the name ‘Allah’ is a proper name (ism alam) which
means it is conventional (mawduah) and is not derived from other name or attributes. It is the
name that is singled out by God to refer to Himself. Ibid., 108. Cf. Al-Ghazali, Maqsad al-Asna,
51.

68
words that yield meaning can be regarded as names. For, semantically, the word

‘ism’ is derived either from the word ‘al-sumuw' (exaltedness or prior) or from

‘al-samah’ (to mark),15 16


both 18 which can be applied to all words. For, as far as
17 of

its function as a signifier (dalil), word is prior to its signified meaning

(madia), while every word is also meant as a mark or a signification to

particular meanin Therefore, al-Razi maintained that “every meanin fu

CfQ
word, is necessarily a noun.” And in the Qur’an, the verse which says, “He

taught Adam all the Names” indicates the generality of the word ism when God

teaches Adam all the Names (al-asma9) including those which the grammarians

classify as verbs (ft /) and propositions (harf)}* Hence, for al-Razi, although the

term sifah does not occur in the Qur’an, its reality (haqiqab) is continuously

emphasized in the Scripture. This would imply that other descriptions of God in

the Qur’an such as al-Malik, al-Qadir, al-Qayy um, although regarded as names

of God, are ipso facto His attributes. In line with this view, early mutakallimun

such as Ibn Kullab,19 whose views were very much similar to those of the

Asha Irak, affirmed the similarity between names and attributes of God, thus

interchangeably employed both of them to refer to the various Quranic

descriptions of God.20

Despite this close affinity between the words ism and sifah, Al-Razi,

however, admitted that there are differences, in the strict sense of the terms,

between the meaning of these two especially when they are dealt with in

15 Law ami', 27.


16 Ibid.
17 Ibid.
18 Ibid.
19 Died in 845, 'Abdullah ibn Sa'id Ibn Kullab was the most influential mutakallimun in the ninth
century. He was Shafi T in fiqh and in kalam he argued against the Mu tazilah. His chief
contribution to kalam was his elaboration of the doctrine of the attributes of God. He asserted
that for each name, such as ‘Powerful,’ ‘Knowing,’ ‘Eternal’, there was an attribute of ‘Power,’
‘Knowledge,’ or ‘Eternity’ which later on became known as sifat ma aniby the Ashairah. Watt,
The Formative, 286-287.
20 Wolfson,The Philosophy, 118.

69
different disciplines. The rammarians specify the noun, as opposed to verb or

CfQ
proposition, to mean a single word which refers, by convention (bi al-wad),

O
rt
meaning without referring to a specific time (zaman). The mutakallimun, on the

other hand, view both terms in their relation to the essence. When we re ard the

CfQ
essence in relation to itself (min daythu hiya hiya) it is called ism, but when we

re ard the essence as being qualified with certain attributes (min daythu innaha
CfQ

< 21
mawsufab bi sifah mu ayyanah), we call it sifah. Hence, the terms ‘heaven,’

‘earth,’ ‘boy,’ and ‘wall’ are asma’ while ‘creator,’ ‘provider,’ ‘long’ and ‘short’ are

sifat. In this sense, ism can be seen as prior to sifah since it is the root (asalah),

while sifah is its derivative (mushtaqqab).21


22 23

In the scheme of existent things (mawj udat), attribute, in contrast to the

essence (dhat), is an accident (arad). In one of his classifications of existents, al-

Razi classified existent things into two main categories: those whose reality are

independent from known things (mustaqillah bi al-malumiyyah) and those

whose reality are dependent the known things. The first category is further

divided into that which does not need a substratum for it to reside which is called

essence (dhat), or that which does need a substratum to reside in, which is called

attribute (sifah). As for the second category, it refers to pure relations (idafat wa

al-nasab).

THE POLEMIC CONCERNING THE NATURE OF DIVINE


ATTRIBUTES
The majority of the mutakallimun did not dispute the fact that the Qur’an

enumerates many names and attributes of God. On the other hand, what became

21 Law amie, 28.


22 Ibid.
23 Al-Razi, Shark Uyun al-Hikmah (Tehran: Mu’assasah al-Sadiq li al-Taba'ah wa al-Nashr,
1994), vol. 3, 7-8. In another classification, al-Razi classified existents other than God into two
main categories, essence and attributes. The essence are sub-divided into two, mujarradat
(essence which are abstracted from any relation to bodies) and jasmaniyyat (bodies). While the
attributes are subdivided into rational (aqliyyah) and sensible (hissiyyah), the first is nobler since
it lasts while the second revolves. Law ami‘ 186.

70
the point of contention is the nature and status of these attributes especially in

relation to the divine essence. The question that was raised is that whether the

divine attributes, in particular the seven Sfat Ma ani, have a real, independent

existence vis-a-vis the essence. If this is so, how do these independent existents

affect the unity of the divine essence? These are amon the issues which became

CfQ
the polemics between various schools in the history of kalam. The theological

positions concerning this issue range from the diametrically opposed views of the

mutakallimun. namely the Mu tazilah (and the Philosophers) who denied the

existence of divine attributes, and those whom al-Shahrastani referred to as “the

Affirmers of Attributes” (al-Sfatiyyah), among whom, the Ashairah were the


25 Between and within these two poles, there are many other views
foremost.24

such as the view of the philosophers who accepted only negative and relative

attributes, the views of Abu Hashim of the Mu tazilah who re arded attributes

CfQ
as ahwal (states) which cannot be predicated either as existents or non-existent,

and the views of some Mu tazilf individuals who accepted only two divine

qualities namely Knowledge and Power.26 Before we embark on the discussion of

al-Razi’s views on this issue, we will first elaborate, as a background, the position

of the two major schools involved in this polemic, namely, the Mu tazilah and

the Ashairah.
who upheld the unity of God (tawhid) as the first pillar
The Mu tazilah,27 28

of their five theological principles (usul al-khamsah)2S denied the independent

24 Sfat Ma ani are the existents which subsist in the divine essence. They are power (Qudrah),
Will (Iradah), Knowledge (77m), Life (Hayah), Hearing (Sam), Sight (Basar), Speech (Kaiam).
The term ma ani is a plural form of maha, a term used by the mutakallimun to refer to the
reality of the attributes which is the cause (illah) of God being attributed as Knowing, Living,
Powerful and so on. It was first employed by the Mu tazilah such as Muammar but later on
became a common expressions in kalam. For further discussions on ma ha see Wolfson, The
Philosophy, 147-167.
25 Milal, 77.
26 Theology, 90.
27 See their position on anthropomorphism in Chapter One, 37-39.
28 The five principles are basic theological pillars elaborated by the early proponents of the
Mu tazilah in defining their theological position. Other four principles are: justice (adl), the

71
existence of divine attributes. They argued that since the essence of God is

without any division, there must be no other entity that co-exists with it.29 The

existence of something that is necessary and eternal, superadded to the divine

essence will only lead to the plurality of eternals as reflected in the statement of

Wasil b. 'Ata’ (d.l31H), the founder of the Mu tazilab,30 that “to assert the

existence of an eternal entity or an eternal attribute, is tantamount to saying


there are two Gods.”31 Since eternity is peculiar to the description of God’s

essence, eternal attributes that exist additional to the essence would also have

share in divinity.32

Denying the existence of attributes superadded to the essence, the

Mu tazilab maintained that God cannot be Knowing through (the attributes of)

Knowledge, Powerful through Power, Living through Life; otherwise this would

mean that His Knowledge, Power, Life and His essence are different existents
(mawjudat mutagbayyirab) which are eternals.33 Qadi 'Abd al-Jabbar (d. 1024), a

later spokesperson of the Mu tazilites, ar ued on the impossibility of the


CfQ

attribute of knowledge:

If God the Exalted is Knowing through the attribute of


Knowledge, it [the Knowledge] would either be known, or not. If it
is not known, it cannot be affirmed...if it is known, it either exists
or does not exist. It cannot be non-existent. If it exists, it is
either eternal or originated, and all these are false.34

promise and the threat (al-wa wa al-wa Td), the intermediate position (manzilah bayna
manzilatayn) and the commanding of right and the forbidding of evil (al-amr bi al-maruf \va
al-nahy an al-munkar). For the fundamental ideas of the Mu tazilab, see 'Abd Jabbar, Shark
Usui al-Khamsah; Sharif, vol.l, 199-219. As for the historical account of their doctrines based on
individual views, see Josef van Ess, Tbeologie und Gesellschaft im 2 und 3 Jahrhundert Hidschra:
Eine Gescichte des Religiosen Denkens im Fruben Islam, (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1992), Band
3, 4 & 5; William Montgomery Watt, Islamic Philosophy, 46-55.
29 Milal, 39. Before the Mu tazilab, there were individuals who denied the existence of the
attributes such as Ja'd ibn Dirham and Jahm bin Safwan.
30 Matalib, vol. 3, 227.
31 Milal, 43.
32 Ibid., 42.
33Maalim, 158.
34 Qadi 'Abd Jabbar, Shark Usui al-Khamsah, 183.

72
Moreover, the existence of independent attributes would also imply that

the essence is in need of the attributes, and to be in need of something is a


quality impossible for God.35 If the essence and attributes are conceived as

different independent realities, this would lead to state of composition

(murakkab) in the divine essence, a condition which is contradictory to the

divine unity. This position, according to the Mu tazilab, if held by Muslims,

would make them worse than the Christians (al-Nasara) since the latter only

affirmed one essence with three different attributes with hypostatic existence

(oknum), while the Asbairab would affirm nine different things: one essence,

and at least eight attributes!36 37

In order to avoid pluralism in God’s essence, the Mu iazilah were of the

view that divine attributes are mere names or as modes (ahwaT). They also

re arded these attributes as being either relative in nature such as God is the
CfQ

Creator and Sustainer, or negative such as that He is free from matter.38 The

attributes are mere mental constructs and do not exist additional to the essence.

They are, in fact, the essence itself. Power, Life, Knowledge and other attributes,

therefore, are all identical with His essence. In the words of one of the earliest

Mu tazili of Basrah, All al-Jubba’i (d. 915):

35 Ibid., 157.
36 Ibid, 159. Cf. SharhalAqald, 51.
37 Wolfson, The Philosophy, 133. The theory of modes was expounded by Abu Hashim al-Salam
(d. 933), the son of al-Jubba’i. This theory is a modification of early theory of ma ha by another
early Mu tazili, Muammar ibn 'Abbad al-Sulami (d.842). Ma ha is described by the latter as
something that resides in the body that causes the existence of accidents such as motion, rest,
whiteness and blackness. From this, the term maha was used later by the mutakallimun to
designate the thing that causes God to be described as Knowing, Powerful and so on. While in
the theory of modes of Abu Hashim, hal is described as something that is attributed to God such
as Knowingness and Powerfulness, but it is regarded as neither existent nor non-existent. See
further Nihayat, 52-60; Wolfson, The Philosophy, 147-166, 167-182.
38 Nihayat, 51.

73
God the Most exalted deserves these four attributes, namely, of
being Powerful, Knowing, Living and Existing by His essence (li
dhatihf)39 40

To escape from the accusation of stripping altogether the divine attributes

from the essence (ta etil), the Mu tazilah represented the attributes with other

terms which were more indicative of their close identity with the essence. For

example, they affirmed that that which is related to known things (ma I um), as

far as the divine essence is concerned, is not knowledge itself but God’s

knowingness (L4/zmzyyu/?) which is, again, identical with God’s essence. The

same case applies to other relational attributes such as Qadiriyyah and

Hayyiyah.49

Another issue which is related to the nature of the attributes is the

problem of the relation between the temporal and the eternal being. This

concerns, in particular, the attributes which are related to the originated temporal

beings, such as God’s Knowledg which is related to the known things

(ma lum), and God’s Will, which is related to the things willed, and so on. The

question is that if the divine essence is eternal, are these relational attributes also

eternal while at the same time related to things, which are created, temporal and

ever-changing? If these attributes are, on the other hand, originated, can they

reside in something eternal, which is the essence? It is this paradox that led the

Mu tazilah to deny the existence of the divine attributes.

The contentions of the Mu tazilah can be observed as being in parallel

with the views of the philosophers who, in order to uphold the four

characteristics of the Necessary Being (Wajib al-Wigud), namely, necessity,

39 'Abd. al-Jabbar, 182. Among the proponents of the Mu tazilah, there were slight differences in
their sayings, yet the underlying principle was still the negation of the independent reality of
attributes. Abu Hashim, for example, expressed it as “God deserves the attributes...in His
essence ” (yasta/iiqquha li ma buwa alaybifidhatihi), while Abu al-Hudhayl said that “God is
knowing through knowledge which is Himself [His essence].”
40 Arba m, 159.

74
eternity, unity and perfection, arrived at the same conclusion of denying the

divine attributes. The philosophers viewed God as a simple (basff) and pure

(mahd) being, without any quiddity or essence (mahiyyab wa haqfqab). God

cannot be defined since He does not share any genus with anything else, hence

the intellectual and logical classification of genus and differentia cannot be


pplied to Him.41 They argued that if an attribute is predicated to God, it could

either be necessary (yvajib) or contingent (mumkin). If it is necessary, it would

either become rival to the Necessary Being and thus necessitate plurality and

composition in His essence, which will destroy His unity and simplicity

(basff), or, it will not be qualified as an attribute since an attribute is in need of

an essence and this is not the characteristic of a Necessary Being.43 Furthermore,


41 42

if it is contingent (mumkin), it will lead to the fact that God’s essence is both

cause (fail) and recipient (qabil) simultaneously. This is so because every

contingent needs a cause and the cause is the essence. Hence, the essence is both

the cause of the attributes and at the same time becomes the recipient of the
attributes, which is impossible.44 If this combination is within the essence, it will

lead to the composition of the essence but this will contradict the fact that the

essence is simple (basff). Furthermore, to be a recipient would mean that the

essence is in need of the attributes and that which is in need of something else is

originated. The philosophers also ar ued that an attribute does not enter the
CfQ

quiddity of an essence nor become constituent element of it. Hence, it is

always subordinate to the essence which is its cause. This makes the attribute an

accident, something caused and not eternal.45

41 Tabafiit, 123.
42 Ma talib, vol. 3, 228. To the philosophers, if God is composed of essence and attributes, this will
lead to the fact that the essence is in need of the attributes since every composition needs its parts
for it to be completed, and everything that is in need of something else is in itself contingent
(mumkin), hence in need of a cause. This is impossible in the case of God’s essence.
43 Matalib, vol. 3, 227-228.
44 Arba in, 157; Law ami' 31; Matalib, vol.3, 228.
45 Tabafiit, 114.

75
In sum, the views of the Mu tazilah and the philosophers regarding

divine attributes can best be grasped through Al-Shahrastani’s recapitulation of

their principle of unity:

The Necessary Existent can only be One. His existence is his


necessity (wujuduhu wujibuhu), and His necessity is His reality
(Jiaqiqatuhu) and His reality is His oneness (wahdatuhu). His
oneness is His particularity (takhassusuhu), and His particularity is
His specificity (ta ayyunuhu), without distinguishing necessity
with existence, and existence with reality and quiddity. And it is
from this [argument] they denied the attributes of God additional
to the essence ...

If the Mu tazilah, due to their denial of the divine qualities, were called

the muattilah or ‘those who divest God from any attribute,’ they were

confronted by those who were termed by al-Shahrastani as the Sfatiyyah, the


‘Affirmers of the divine attributes.’46
47 48 49
Although al-Shahrastani also included

within this group those sects who affirmed anthropomorphism, such as the

Karramiyyah and the mujassimah, the real opponent of the Mu tazilah, as far as

philosophical and intellectual expositions are concerned, were the Asha irah, who,

in the history of kalam, had leveled a severe criticism against most of the

principles upheld by the Mu tazilah. Another group, the Hanabilah who also

affirmed the existence of divine attributes, were mainly satisfied with their ‘bila

kayf position and did not come up with strong philosophical arguments in

answering the position of the Mu tazilah.

The Ashairah, based on scriptural proofs, argued that the divine

attributes exist additional to the essence. The Qur’an affirms that God has
„48 «N
knowledge in the verses, “He has sent it down with His knowled

female conceives or bears save with His knowledge.” God is also described as

46 Nihayat, 100.
47 Milal, 77.
48 Al-Qur’an al-Nisa’ 4:166.
49 Al-Qur’an al-Fajr 35:11.

76
having power through the verse, “The Lord of all might, the Unshaken,” 0 and so

51 Since these attributes have been singled out


on with regard to other attributes.50

clearly by the Qur’an, their existence cannot be said to be identical with the

essence. Due to these separate indications between God and His attributes, the

Ashairah maintained that these attributes are not identical with the essence but

are rather the medium through which God is related to His creatures. God,

therefore, is Knowing by virtue of Knowledge, Powerful by virtue of Power,

Living by virtue of Life, Willing by virtue of Will, and so on. Al-Ash'ari, in al-

Luma \ gave further proof of the existence of the attribute of Knowledge and

highlighted the flaw in the Mutazilites’ argument:

...He must be Knowing either by Himself or by a knowledg

CD
which cannot be Himself. Now, if He is Knowing by Himself, He
Himself would have to be Knowledge. For, if one said that God is
Knowing by a quality distinct from Him, he would have to say
that this quality is Knowledge. But Knowledge cannot be
Knowing, nor can the Knower be Knowledge, nor can God be
identified with His attributes...hence, since the Creator cannot be
Knowled e, He cannot be Knowing by Himself. And if that is
CfQ

impossible, it is certain that He is Knowing by a Knowledge which


cannot be Himself.52

The attributes cannot be conceived of as being identical with the essence

since it will lead to the confusion between the essence and the various attributes

which God described in the Qur’an. Furthermore, an absurd conclusion would be

obtained with re ard to the attributes themselves wherein the attributes of


CfQ

Knowledge, for instance, would be identical with Power and Life, and that it also

would be identical with the Knowing One, the Living One, and the Powerful

One. It would also lead to the conclusion that He who is of necessary existence

50 Al-Qur’an al-Dhariyat 51:58.


51 See the Ash'arite scriptural arguments in affirming the existence of these attributes in 'Abd al-
Qahir al-Baghdadi, Usui al-Dih, 90-109.
52 McCarthy, 19. The proof on the dependent reality of divine Knowledge is also applicable to all
God’s essential attributes such as Life, Power, Hearing, and Sight.

77
would not subsist in His own essence.53 While defending the position of the

Asbairab, al-Shahrastani attacked this strange conception of unity of the

Mu tazilab and the Philosophers through the following remark:

You say that He is Origin, Cause, Intelligent and Intelligible, but


there is no connection between these relations and if you can
postulate a plurality of relations, the mutakallim can postulate
attributes. To strip God of the latter is to strip Him of the
former.54

Despite the emphasis on the difference between attributes and essence, the

Asbairab also maintained that the attributes are not exclusively independent of

the essence in the sense that the two are seen as two separate entities. This is

because attributes are attached to the essence as accidents are attached to the

substance. Their existence is, therefore, accidental in the sense that they cannot
exist in themselves and need the essence as their substratum (rnahall).55 This

position of maintaining both the independent and identical aspect of the

attributes vis-a-vis the essence held by the Asbairab is oftenly described through

the statement that “the attributes, being together with the essence, is not the

essence, neither is it other than the essence ” (al-sifab ma a al-dbat la buwa wa

la gbayrubu). “This is how,” explained al-Razi, “our school’s predecessors

(ashaburta) described the relation between the divine essence and divine
attributes.”56 To them, this statement is neither paradoxical nor contradictory, as

criticized by the Mu tazilab for it explains the real nature of both the essence

and the attributes of God. The first part of the statement shows that the

attributes have an independent reality (baqfqab) that is different from the

53 Shark al Aqa Id, 51.


54 Nib ayat, 51.
55 Tahafut, 114.
56 Arbam, 164; Muhassal, 13. Cf. al-Ghazali, al-Iqtisad ff al-I tiqad, trans. 'Abd Rahman Abu
Zayd (New Delhi: Kitab Bhavan, 1994), 65; al-Baghdadi, Usui al-Dm, 90.

78
essence, while the second part emphasizes the dependence of the attributes to the

essence due to their accidental nature.

The nature of the attributes, according to the Ashairah does not impair the

unity of the divine essence since the existence of the attributes is not the same as

the existence of the essence. The existence of the attributes is accidental and it
depends on the essence as their substratum.57 If the concern is that as accidents,

the attributes must have been caused by an efficient cause, as argued by the

philosophers, “there is no reason,” replicated al-Ghazali, “why it should be

regarded as impossible for the attributes to exist in the essence yet still be eternal

and independent of the efficient cause.” In other words, there is no problem of

having this kind of pluralism with regard to the essence of God since that is its

reality. In fact, as remarked by al-Taftazzani, there is no dispute amon the Ahl

CfQ
al-Sunnah on the question of the multiplicity and plurality of the attributes of

the Deity as to whether they are distinctly separate or not. The plurality of

eternal essence is impossible but not the plurality of “one essence and its
attributes.”58

We can, thus far, identify a few major issues that formed the core of the

ar uments of the contendin views regarding the nature of divine attributes.


CfQ

CfQ

First, the issue of whether the attributes are identical with the essence or they are

distinct and existing in addition to the essence. Second, the question of the

plurality of eternals that arises from the idea of the additional existence of the

attributes. Third, the relation between the eternal attributes, especially those

attributes related to some divine actions, with its objects that are originated and

plural. Related to this issue is the question of how the essence can be both the

cause and recipient of attributes, active and passive at the same time. These are

57 Tabafiit, 112.
58 Sharh alAqald, 52. For further elaboration on the position of the Ashairah on the affirmation
of God’s attributes, see lb anah, 94-106; Irshad, 46-77; al-Ghazali, al-Iqtisad, TI-91.

79
the issues which we will further examine in the following paragraphs in the light

of al-Razi’s views on divine attributes.

AL-RAZl’S views on the nature of the attributes and


THEIR RELATION TO THE ESSENCE

Al-Razi, as the other Ashairah, affirmed the existence of attributes that are

superadded to the essence. For him, these attributes function as relations

between the essence and the object of that relation, such as knowledge (i7m),

which is the relation between the knower (Sim) and the things known (ma turn).

As it is necessary to affirm the existence of the essence (al-dhat), it is equally

necessary to affirm the existence of the relation (nisbab) and the attribution
(idafab):59

The knower (al- alim) is he who senses the [known] thing and it
becomes manifest [to his understanding]. Sense, perception and
manifestation cannot take place without there being a specific
relation between the knower and the known. And this relation and
connection, referred to as ‘ta alluq’ are necessarily affirmed.
Otherwise, God cannot be described as Powerful and Knowing.60

The connection or the relation alluded to above certainly refers to something

other than the essence. That is why, according to al-Razi, the proof of the

existence of the essence is other than the proof of God having the attributes of

Knowledge or Power. We need another differentiating proof (dalil munfasil) to

substantiate the existence of the attributes or relations apart from the proof of

the existence of God which mainly refers to the essence. In other words, we can

conceive the concept of God’s essence while being unaware of His attributes of

Living and Knowing. Elsewhere, al-Razi put forward this argument differently,

59 Arba ‘in, 156; Matalib, vol. 3, 224.


60 Matalib, vol. 3, 223.

80
that our knowledge of the existence of a Necessary Being does not lead us

directly to the knowledge of these attributes:

The decisive proof of this difference is that when we know the


cessation of things possible of existence (intiha’ al-mumkinat) to
the being-existent of Necessary Existence in itself, it does
necessitate knowing that God is Knowing, Powerful in a way we
have previously mentioned. That which is known is different from
what is unknown. Hence, God being Knowing and Powerful is not
ipso facto His essence.61

Hence, there is a clear distinction between our knowledge of God’s existence

that refers to His essence and our knowledge of the fact that He is attributed to

other attributes such as Knowledge, Power and Life. The denial of this relation

will subsequently lead to the denial of the fact that God is All-Knowing and All-

Powerful. To say that God is All-Knowing and All-Powerful is equivalent to


saying that God has Knowledge and Power.62 Furthermore, there is a difference

between the attributes of Knowing and Living that would prevent us from
conceiving both of them as identical.63 Both of them refer to different quiddities

(mahiyyat) categories (maqulat) and definition (Azdd).64 God’s Knowledge, for

example, encompasses the necessity (wajib), the possible (mumkin) and the

impossible (muhal), whereas His Power relates only to those which are possible
of existence.65 The objects of God’s Power (al-maqdur) could not remain as

they were (objects of Power) after they had existed since God has already

exercised His Power by bringing them into existence. If they still remain as the

object of Power, it will be superfluous, and hence, impossible, although they can

still be the objects of knowledge of God (al-ma I urn):

61 Arba m, 156. Law ami ‘, 34; Mas all, 51.


62 Matalib, vol.3, 223.
63 Ibid., 225.
64 Ibid., 227.
65 Theology, 95; Matalib, vol. 3, 226.

81
The Powerful (al-Qadir), if the object of His Power attains to
existence, He will not remain powerful in regard to bringing this
object into existence. For, bringing into existence that which is
already existing, is redundant and this is an impossibility (muhal).
Power has no effect on what is impossible, and the object of
Power, after it attains to existence, ceases to be one. However, it
would remain as an object of Knowledge (malum) after it has
attained existence...this necessitates difference between
Knowledge and Power.66

This argument falsifies the view that all the attributes are in fact one and

identical with the essence. God is, therefore, not devoid of attribution and cannot

be ascribed as only the essence, as held by the Mu tazilab, or to pure existence as

conceived of by the philosophers. In relation to that, al-Razi criticized the

Mu tazilah for looking at the principle held by the Asbairab in their statement

that “al-sifab ma a al-dbat la buwa wa la gbayrubu” from only the linguistic

and literal point of view through their claim that this statement is contradictory

and confusing. On the other hand, this condition should be perceived from the

context in which the discussion has taken place:

Our position is that if what you [those who oppose] meant by two
different things (al-gbayyirayn) are things which are independent
in their essence and reality (bi al-dbat wa al-haqfqab), we do not
accept [the situation] that essence and attributes are two things
different based on this interpretation. But if what you meant by
two different thin as two things, distinct one from the other or
CTQ

one is an attribute to the other and the other is the one’s attribute,
why did you say that an affirmation of two others which are
distinct based on this interpretation is false?67

In relation to the above issue, the accusation that the idea of the additional

existence of attributes is similar to the Christians’ idea of the trinity, is, for al-

66 Ma talib, vol.3, 226.


67 Arba m, 164-165. Al-Razi, similar to al-Ghazali, affirmed that the existence of two independent
eternal entities in the sense that one is the attribute of another is possible and will not impair the
unity of divine essence. Tabafiit, 112-113.

82
Razi, erroneous. The Christians’ Trinity attributes different independent eternal

entities to the three hypostases through their idea of the incarnation in the body

of Mary and Jesus, while the mutakallimun, as explained before, did not

subscribe to that idea.68

THE ETERNAL AND THE ORIGINATED

As we alluded to before, one of the strong criticisms by the Mu tazilah against

the theology of the Ashairah is regarding the nature of the relation between the

eternal essence and its attributes that are associated with the originated things.

How is it possible for the divine essence, which is eternal, to be the substratum

of originated things (cd-hawadith)? Al-Razi, on this question, affirmed that in

principle, it is impossible for the essence of God to be the substratum for any

originated things since this would violate the principle of divine unity.

Nevertheless, in the case of divine attributes, he qualified that an attribute can be

contingent in itself (mumkin li dhatiha) yet necessary through the divine


These attributes are contingent by virtue of being related to originated
essence.69 70

things, such as in the case that God is an Agent (al-Fail) who brings the world

into existence. To say that the attribute of bein an Agent as eternal is


CfQ

impossible since God cannot be attributed to being an Agent prior to the

existence of the world (as the effect of the Agent). For it is impossible for

something to be a cause without the act of causing effects (al-fail wa la fit

muhal). The same applies to other attributes such as Knowing and Seeing.

These attributes, in relation to contingent beings, can only be affirmed in God

when the contingent beings come into existence. For example, God can only be

said as Knowing and Seeing the world when the world already exists.71 In this

68 Law ami‘ 32.


69 Arba m, 120; Theology, 91.
70 Muhassal, 158.
71 Ibid., 159.

83
respect, these attributes are regarded as contingent. Ceylan, in analyzing this

argument of al-Razi, considers it as “unprecedented argument containing

difficulties.”72 This is because, by allowing the presence of temporal qualities in

God’s essence, al-Razi has here violated his own principle which deny the

temporally originated things to subsist in the essence of God73 as evidenced in the

case of his strong attack ainst the views of the Karramiyyah. However, al-

Razi seems to have his own justified arguments when he maintained the

contingency of the attributes in relation to the temporal things. He argued that

the contingent nature of the attributes is only applicable to the real attributes

which are followed by relations (al-sifat allati talzimuha al-idafat) such as

Knowing and Powerful.74 These are attributes which have their objects such as

the object of knowledge (malum) and the object of power (al-maqdur). These

attributes are eternals by virtue of being subsisted through the divine essence yet

in themselves they are contingent due to their connection with their objects.

Elsewhere, al-Razi maintained that in the case of relative attributes, what

changes is the relation of the attributes to something, not the attributes itself

since relations do not exist externally.75 This multi-facets justification makes his

argument more complicated compared the simpler yet firmer position of his

predecessor, al-Ghazali who insisted that both essence and attributes are eternal

based on the argument that just as the essence of the Necessary Being is eternal

72 Theology, 91.
73 Mu ha ssal, 158.
74 Theology, 93. Al-Razi classified attributes in general into three categories: i) real attributes (al-
sifat al-.haqfqiyyah') that are free from any relations (idafaty ii) real attributes that are followed
by relations such as the attribute of knowledge which is related to the known things, and power
which is related to the object of power (maqdury iii) pure relation, such as the condition of a
thing situated on the left or right. In the case of attributes with relation, changes will occur.
Nevertheless, in the case of real attributes, there will be no changes in them since any changes in
real attributes will mean that these attributes are not among the perfect attributes of God (sifat
kamaT) and this means that the essence of God is defective (naqis) before the existence of the
attributes. Furthermore, if the essence of God is receptive of temporal attributes, this receptivity
will be among the criteria of the essence and it is eternal with the essence. If the receptivity is
eternal, the existence of originated beings is also eternal and this is impossible. Arba m, 120.
75 Mu ha ssal, 159.

84
and independent of an efficient cause, His attributes are also eternal and

independent of an efficient cause, and there is no question of pluralism in this

sense.76

The fact that attributes are contingent in themselves yet can subsist

through the eternal essence seems already established in the theological thought

of the later Ashairab after al-Razi. They did not re ard this situation as

CfQ
something that would compromise the unity of the essence. Al-Taftazani, in his

commentary of al-Nasafi’s al-Aqald, pointed out that there is no absurdity in

comprehending that the attributes necessarily exist in the essence of the

Necessarily Existent, but in themselves they are possible existents since this

eternal attributes subsists in the essence of the eternal. The attributes, then can

be said to exist necessarily in Him (God), and are not separated from Him.

Therefore, according to al-Taftazani, we must say that Allah, taken with His

attributes, is eternal.77

In the exposition of the transcendent unity of existence (wahdat al-

wujud) by the Sufi metaphysicians whose ontology was closer to the Asharites’

kalam, the double nature of divine attributes is also maintained. It is expounded

within their conception of the manifold and diverse self-manifestation of the

Reality. As lucidly elaborated by al-Attas:

the Attributes have a dual aspect: one describes the Divine Essence
and is identical with it (because this aspect is in fact the first
aspect of the Divine Names); the other describes itself, or rather it
describes the Essence as qualified by it...the former is eternal; the

76 Tabafiit, 111-113, 129. Al-Ghazali also questioned the terms used by the philosophers such as
Necessary Being (Wajib al-Wujud), receptive cause (illab qabiliyyab), which to al-Ghazali were
not in line with the divine reality and thus misunderstanding of these term was the source of the
confusion of the philosophers. He even ridiculed them by saying that they were using
philosophical jargon like ‘possible’ (mumkin), contingent (ja^z), subordinate (tabi6 ), inseparable
accidents (lazirri), effects (ma lul), with the intention of scaring the laymen.
77 Sharh alAqald, 52. According to al-Taftazzani, not every eternal is a God, so the existence of a
number of gods is not to be implied from the existence of eternals. The term eternals should not
be used lest the estimative faculty (al-wabrri) go so far as to think that each of the eternals
subsists in itself and that the divine attributes are predicated upon it.

85
latter is non-etemal. It is from this latter aspect of the Divine
attributes that the realities of things are constituted.78

As for the question of God being the cause and recipient at the same time,

al-Razi did not see any contradiction on this matter, since in other cases such as

that God knows the universals, as propounded by the philosophers themselves,

God, in this case, is receptive to the objects which are caused by Him.79 For al-

Razi, to be a recipient did not necessarily indicate that the essence is in need of

the attributes. For, although the essence is the cause of the attributes, the

essence is being perfected by itself (mustakmilab bi nafsiba) not through the

attributes.80 Hence, in this case, the essence is not ‘in need’ of the attributes. The

philosophers too, added al-Razi, were not consistent in their view on this issue

since their view that God as the ‘First Cause’ already assumed positive

relationship with the caused world. This fact would contradict their own

principle that God cannot be active and passive at the same time.81

Al-Razi observed two basic reasons for the whole polemic on divine

attributes. First, the premise that unity (wahdab) is perfection while multiplicity

is an imperfection. This premise caused the exaggeration of unity to the extent

of denying the divine attributes. Second, the idea that an existent which is

powerful over all things, knowing all known things are more perfect than an
existent that does not have these attributes.82 This was the concern of those who

affirmed the existence of the divine attributes. Although the objective of both

78A1-Attas, A Commentary, 37. According to al-Attas, the sufis’ ontological doctrine, although
similar in some respects to Ash’arite theology, there are also some differences between them the
fundamental of which, is the question whether it is quiddity or it is existence that is
fundamentally real. The Ash antes is closer towards affirming the primacy of quiddity which led
them to the affirmation of the doctrine of God’s difference from originated things. The sufis, on
the other hand, affirmed the fundamental reality of existence, hence although they maintained
that God is different from originated things in point of determination and individuation, they are
not different in point of existence and reality. Ibid., 44.
79 Theology, 92.
80 Law ami \ 32.
81 Theology, 92.
82 Law ami‘ 33.

86
parties was to affirm God’s perfection and greatness and to deny His

imperfection, the former over-emphasized the Unity of God while the second

tried to save God from being stripped away of any attributes, making Him

unknown. 83

THE CLASSIFICATION OF THE ATTRIBUTES

The mutakallimun classified divine attributes based on various rounds. The

CfQ
most common among them is the classification of attributes into the necessary

(a I-wajibab or tbub utiyyab) and the negative (al-mumtani ah or salbiyyah)?4

However, given the complicated nature of the background of the polemic

concerning divine attributes, more refined classifications of divine attributes were

put forward especially by the later mutakallimun. Al-Razi’s classification can be

seen as one of them since it reflects response to the Mu tazilah’s denial of the

real and independent attributes. On the other hand, based on the affirmation of

existence of an independent attributes apart from the divine essence, al-Razi

classified divine attributes into three main divisions: attributes of essence (sifat

dhatiyyahf attributes that subsist in the essence (ma hawiyyab) and attributes of

action (fi liyyah)?5 Attributes of the essence refer to names (alqab) signifying the

essence such as the Existent (Mawjud) and the Eternal (Qadfmf or among the

negative attributes, the One (Wahid), the Rich (Ghaniy) and the Holy (Quddus).

These attributes of essence, affirmed al-Razi, are not the essence itself, neither

are they part within the quiddity of the essence (juz Un dakhilun fimahiyyat ai­

dhat) but they are external to the essence. They are further divided into three:

either real (haqfqiyyah), relational (idafiyyah) or negative (salbiyyah). The real

attributes refer to attributes exist in the real sense apart from the essence such as* * *

83 Ibid.
84 Ibid., 36. In kalam, sifab wajibab are also known as sifab tbub utiyyab while sifab mumtani ah
are called sifab salbiyyah
85 Ibid.

87
existence. While the relational attributes signify those attributes that are re arded

CfQ
as pure relations, such as the condition of a thing in the left or right. In this case

the essence of the thing does not change but only the relation.86 87
This
88 kind of

attributes in relation to God, are infinite in number. 7 The ne ative attributes

CfQ
(sifat al-salbiyyah) refer to the qualities which are impossible to be ascribed to

God such as He being a body or an atom (jawbar), contingent or originated. Also

included in this class are the attributes that cannot be said of all other existents

such as being Holy (Quddus), Flawless (Salam), Self-sufficient (Gbaniyy), and

Unique (Wahid). These attributes will be dealt with in depth in the next chapter.

Regarding the attributes that subsist in the essence (sifat ma hawiyyab),

they allude to the realities/ideas (ma an) that subsist in the essence such as when

we say God is Knowing (‘Alim), Powerful (Qadir) and Living (Hayy).ss Al-Razi

did not seem to distinguish between sifat ma ‘ani and sifat ma hawiyyab, the

former being the cause and the latter being the effect or implication of the

ma ani as conceived by some Ash'arite mutakallimun after him.89 He,

86 Arba Tn, 120.


87Fakbr al-Din al-Razi, 226. Examples of these attributes are the object of worship (ma bud) and
object of gratitude (masbkur).
88 Ibid.
89 The Asharites who came later than al-Razi such as al-Sanusi further divided the sifat
ma hawiyyab into another class namely sifat ma ani referring in particular to the realities/ideas
that subsist in the essence. See Ibrahim al-Bayjuri, Hasbiyab alaMatn al-Sanusiyyab (Bangkok:
Maktabah Muhammad al-Nahdi, 1812), 24. Hence, while the attributes of ma hawiyyab are more
regarded as the effect of the divine essence having these ideas (ma an) that subsist in it, sifat al­
ma ani describe the very realities from which of ma hawiyyab being implied. Seven ma ani which
are considered as fundamental are Power (Qudrab), Knowledge (Ilm), Will (Iradab), Life (Hayy),
Hearing (Sam), Seeing (Basar) and Speech (Kalam). The attribute of Power is affirmed through
the contingency (imkan) of the world and it’s coming into existence from non-existence. If, on
the other hand, the world is necessary, it cannot be related to the Power of God. The attribute of
Knowledge is known through the nature of His creation being wisely implemented (muhkimab)
and refined (mutqinab) such as the human body. While His attribute of Will is affirmed through
the proof that some of His creation is prior to others, although it is possible that the contrary is
the case. This priority and posteriority, in turn, needs a determiner (mukbassiss) who has a will.
The fact that God has Knowledge and Power proves that He has the attribute of Life. While the
attributes of Hearing and Seeing are proven by the fact that both of them are His attributes of
perfection (sifat al-kamal) without which He will be ascribed as deaf and blind, which are

88
nevertheless, affirmed the existence of these ma ani subsisting in the essence as

apparent in his contention with the Mu tazilah we have alluded before. Some

mutakallimun identified these attributes with the notion of modes (ahwal), an

ontological status between existents (mawjud) and non-existents (madum).

Explaining somehow the similar reason as those mutakallimun who affirmed the

sifat, these affirmers of ahwal maintained that the causes that resulted the
existence of these ahwal are the ma ahi subsist in the essence.*90

With respect to the attributes of action, they signify the process of


issuance of an effect from the divine power (sudur athar min qudrat Allah).91 92

Hence, the meaning of Creator (al-Khaliq) is none other than the coming into

existence of a creation through God’s power, while the meaning of Sustainer (al-

Raziq) is the arrival of the sustenance (rizq) to the human being through His

power. 92

With regard to those attributes which are derived from the divine names,

al-Razi presents a more comprehensive classification by dividing the attributes

into seven categories:

i) Purely real attributes, such as Existence (Mawjud) and Life


(Wy)-
ii) Purely relational attributes, such as an Object of worship (Ma bud)
and Object of gratitude (Mashkur).
iii) Negative attributes that are exclusively His, such as Self-sufficient
(Ghaniyy) and Unique (Wahid )
iv) Real as well as relative, such as Knowing (Alim) and Powerful
(Qadir).
v) Real as well as negative, such as Eternal (Qadhn) and Pre-eternal
(Azali).
vi) Relative as well as negative, such as the First and the Last.

impossible for Him. The same case applies to the attribute of Speech, since the opposite of it is
mute which is an imperfection Th A: hr al-Dm al-Razi, 82-83.
90 Law ami e, 44.
91 Ibid.
92 Ibid.

89
vii) Real, relative as well as negative, such as Absolute Sovereignty
(Mutt)93
Another division of divine attributes is those which are called al-sifat al-

kbabariyyab (attributes known through their direct citation in the Qur’an and

Hadiths), mostly referring to the anthropomorphic attributes. These attributes

are further classified into the attributes of essence (dbatiyyab) which refer to

attributes such as eyes, hands, face, legs, fingers and thighs; and attributes of

action (filiyyah), indicating God’s acts such as sitting (istiwa9), ascending (nuzul)
and coming (majf)94 Al-Razi maintained that these anthropomorphic attributes

do not imply their literal meaning hence they must be interpreted to other deeper

meanings congenial to the principle of divine transcendence. To hold to these

anthropomorphic qualities in their literal, superficial meaning would definitely

lead to attributing a body (/ism) to the divine essence, which is tantamount to

polytheism and unbelief. He offered comprehensive way of making an

allegorical interpretation (tawil) of these qualities in his special book Asas al-

Taqdfs which will be the main concern of the following two chapters.

DIVINE TRANSCENDENCE AS REFLECTED IN AL-RAZI’S


CLASSIFICATION OF THE ATTRIBUTES

Divine transcendence received special attention in al-Razi’s classification of

attributes. This is mainly due to two basic reasons. First, which is more internal,

is the continual stress of the Qur’an on the fact that God is unique and does not

Al-Razi maintained that the verses stressing the differences of


resemble others.95 96

God in the Qur’an are verses with clear and established meanings (muhkamat)?6

Hence, any other descriptions of God including those verses with obvious

93 Law ami 41-42. Cf. Al-Ghazali’s classification of attributes based on divine names in his
Maqsad al-Asna, 59-162.
94 Jabir Zayd al-Samiri, al-Sifat al-Khabariyyab bayna al-Mutbabbitm wa al-Mu’awwilfn
(Khartoum: Dar al-Sudani li al-Kutub, 1995), 56.
95 See Chapter One, 23-24.
96 Asas, 30.

90
meanings should not contradict this already clear principle. God must be purified

from any description, which will shatter His divine transcendence, hence any

kind of resemblance between God and the creations is not to be compromised.

Refuting the views of some groups among the theologians who held that the

essence of God, insofar as it is an essence, is similar with other essences, and that

the only difference is in some specific attributes (such as Necessary Existence,

Absolute Power and Knowledge), al-Razi insisted that the difference between

God and the creations is in re ard to the essence, not to the attributes, essential

CfQ
not accidental.97 He argued that if God is similar with other than He with regard

to the essence, then what is applicable to other things will also be applicable to

God, which is impossible.98

The second reason for al-Razi’s emphasis on divine transcendence is the

views of some heretical sects within the community of Muslims who propounded

the anthropomorphic idea of God, as well as to the idea of incarnation of the

Christians. Among the heretical sects are the Karr dmiyyah who held that God is

body and the Hanabilab who insisted on the literal meanings of the

anthropomorphic verses, the implication of which also led to the position of

tajsim. Others were the false Sufis who viewed that there is a union (ittihad)

between God and His creations. As for the Christians, they held that God was

incarnated in the body of Jesus. Responding to these sects, there were several

important affirmations put forward by al-Razi in emphasizing the divine

transcendence which also became the basic characteristic in describing the

attributes of God: that God is not a body (laysa bi jisrn), that He is exalted from

being situated in a place, direction (jihah) and space (al-hayyiz), that the

attributes are eternal and do not receive changes, that God is free from colours

97 Arba m, 96. Among those who hold to this view is Abu Hashim, the early Mu tazilab who
views that there are four attributes which make God different from other than Him: Existentness
(al-Mawjudiyyab), Knowingness (al-'Alimiyyab'), Powerfulness (al-Qadiriyyaby Livingness (al-
Hayyiyah). Ibid.
98 Ibid., 98.

91
(cdwari), odours (raw^i'A) and tastes (/u rim), that He is free from sensual delight

(al-lazzab) and suffering (al-alam). These are basically responses to the

Karramiyyah who, in their description of God, ascribed these qualities to Him.

Against the false Sufis who held the principle of ittihad, al-Razi affirmed that

God cannot be united with other beings." If it were so, there would be logical

confusion as to the status of the two after the union. If the two still prevail after

the union, it cannot be said to be a union in the real sense. While if both do not
prevail, there will be a non-existence (udnm).99
100 As for the Christians, al-Razi

refuted that God is not a substance (jawhar) and that He cannot incarnate in
something either through His essence or His attributes.101

In what follows, we will deliberate on al-Razl’s views concerning divine

transcendence which mainly take place within his discussion on the negative

attributes. Al-Razi viewed divine transcendence as a foundation for the

discussion of the divine attributes as a whole in the sense that before asserting

that God has the attributes of perfection such as Knowledge and Power, it must

be affirmed that He is beyond any possibility of having any similarities with any

other being. Among the negative attributes in which divine transcendence is

distinctly discernable are Unicity (wahdaniyyah), Eternity (qidam), Permanence

(baqa9), Self-subsistent (qiyamuhu binafsihi), He is different from all other

realities (mukbalafah li sa’ir al-haqa’iqy In explaining further these transcendent

aspects of the attributes, we will therefore treat these attributes individually.

99 Al-Razi differentiated between the false and the true Sufis. In al-Masall, he remarked that
there were some groups of Sufis who claimed the love of God and held the idea of union with God
(ittihad). They quoted the passage from Abu Yazid al-Bistami which says, “Praise be to me,
How great am I” (sub han f mazamu sba’ni), and from al-Hallaj “I am the Truth” (ana al-Haq).
These false Sufis misconstrued the interpretation of the saying of Abu Yazid and al-Hallaj who
do not mean to imply the idea of union with God. “Abu Yazid,” qualified al-Razi, “was an arif
billah whose noble character is far from being associated with the school that holds to the idea of
union and incarnation (ittihad wa huld)”. Mas all, 41-42.
100 Ibid., 42.
101 Masall, 33-44.

92
Unicity (Wa hdaniyyan)

Wahdaniyyah conveys two basic meanings: the denial of partners and equals

As to
with regard to God, and the denial of multiplicity in the divine essence.102 103

the first meaning, the Qur’an stresses repeatedly that God is One, such as in the
verse, “and your God is the One God” (wa ilahukum ilahun wahid).1Q3 The

Qur’an repeats 13 times the phrase that affirms Allah as the One God (ilahun

wahid) while it is mentioned 29 times that there is no God other than He (la ilaha

ilia huwa). All these phrases often expressed in refutation of the polytheist

(mushrikun), the Christians, the Jews and the Dualist (the ancient Persians who

Unicity not only means that God is One but also He is


believed in two gods).104 105

transcendent and it is evident through the historical context of the revelation of


the famous verses of Surah al-IkhlasiQ5 in which the Prophet is commanded to

reply affirmatively to a group of Christians who inquire about the description of

his God that He is One (Allahu a had). When they replied that “you are one and

your God is [also] one,” the Prophet answered, “There is nothing like unto Him”

(laysa ka mithlihf shay106 In regard to the second meaning, the multiplicity of

the divine essence will imply composition in the divine nature which is a

characteristic of a possible being.

The Qur’an uses both ahad and whtid in describing God. Scholars differ

on whether both terms convey the same meanin As for those who view that

both terms are dissimilar, al-Razi mentioned three differences between them.

First, the meaning of wahid is more specific in the sense that its meanin is
CfQ

102 Fakbr al-Dfn al-Razi, 234.


103 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:163.
104 EI2, vol. 10, 389.
105 According to al-Razi, this chapter concerns the knowledge of ‘the essence of God’. It is called
al-Ikblas (purity) because it contains purely the exposition of the negative attributes which are
the attributes to purify the belief in the essence of God (sifat al-jalal). This surab is also referred
to by others by names such as al-tawhid, al-tafrid, al-tojrid, al-najat, al-ma rifab, al-bara’ab.
Tafsir, vol. 11, 357.
106 There were also some other different reports, according to al-Razi, which said that it was the
polytheists, or the Jews, who had asked the Prophet about his God. Ibid., vol.11, 357.

93
included in the term a had. and not vice versa. Secondly, the term a had is more

emphatic in the sense that if we say, “no one can resist that person” (fulan la

yuqawimuhu ahad), it definitely excludes anyone. Thirdly, wahid is used in the


affirmative form while ahad is used in the negative.107 While these differences

may be applicable in the purely linguistic domain, it may not be applicable in

terms of their occurrences in the Qur’an. For the term ahad, which is said to be

used only in the negative form, appears in the positive form in Surah al-Ikhlas

(Qul huwa Allah ahad). Further, there is certainly an exclusive affirmation of

uniqueness of God in the term wahid—similar to the term ahad—referring to

God in many places in the Qur’an such as the verse “Say, ‘But in truth He is the

One God (ilahun wahid) and I truly am innocent of joining other with Him,”’108 109

and in the well-known ay at al-kursf, “and your God is One God” (wa ilahukum

ilahurt wahid).1 Therefore, we are inclined to the view that the terms ahad and

yra hid in terms of their explication of the divinity in the Qur’an, convey the

same meaning and regard the differences emphasized by al-Razi as more

linguistic in nature.

Described as a union (mojami) of all the negative attributes, the term

ahad, vis-a-vis the name Allah which is the union of the positive attributes,

according to al-Razi, encompasses the denial of all the qualities improper for God

such as being composite, occupying space, divisible, and subsisting in a

substratum:

As to the congregation of the negative attributes, it is the Oneness


of God (al-ahadiyyah). This is because the meaning of ahadiyyah
is the condition of a reality, in itself, which is free from any kind
of composition. For, every composed essence is in need of each of
its parts, and its parts are in need of each other...and that which is
in need of the others is possible in itself (mumkin li dhatihf) ... the
deity which is the creator (mabda*) of all the creations cannot be

107 Ibid., vol. 11, 359.


108 Al-Qur’an, al-An am 6:19.
109 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah, 2:163.

94
possible...when Oneness is affirmed, [it follows that] it is necessary
for Him not to occupy space (mutahayyiz) because for every thing
that occupies space, its right side is different from its left side, and
everything with this quality is divisible (munqasam), and the One
is impossible to be divisible...110

Apart from scriptural proofs, al-Razi advanced some other strong

philosophical arguments asserting the unicity of God.111 The basis of all these

arguments is that partnership in divinity implies imperfection and weakness

whereas Oneness signifies perfection. The oft-quoted amon them is the

CfQ
argument of the Asha Irak which is called the argument of reciprocal hindrance

(dalil al-tamdnu ci) and ar ument of successive occurrence (dalil tawarudf). The
CfQ

former refers to the fact that the multiplicity of gods will lead to contradictions

and disagreement between them and the latter proves the redundancy of their

actions if they agree on something.112 Both of these arguments are explained

through the following example: If there are two gods and both of them wish to

move a body, either one of the following three possibilities will happen: (i) that

both of them will move the body; (ii) both of them will not move the body; (iii)

or one of them will move it without another. The first is impossible because

since each of them can initiate the move, the movement by both of them will

negate this individual necessity. It also implies that both of them are in need of

each other, which is a sign of weakness in both of them. Furthermore, it is

impossible, as far as Necessary Existence (Wajib al-Wujud) is concerned, for one

J Tafsir, vol. 11, 361.


111 The knowledge of divinity, according to al-Razi, is divided into three: First, that which cannot
be attained by report (al-sam ) namely, those which the truth of the reports themselves are based
on them such as the knowledge of the essence of God, His Knowledge, Power and the truth of
miracle. These can only be attained by reason. Second, knowledge which cannot be reached
unless through reports and only their possibility can be affirmed by reason. Third, knowledge
that can be reached by both reports and reason. Included in this division is the knowledge of the
Oneness of God. Tafsir , vol. 11, 359.
112 Ma alim, 58. Dalil al-tamanu T has its Quranic basis that is the verse which says, “If there
were in the two of them [the heaven and the earth] gods other than Allah, these two would be
corrupted.” (Al-Quran, al-Anbiya’ 21:22)

95
effect to proceed from two causes (ijtimac al-mu’athtbiray n ala athar wahid).

Both gods also cannot move the body successively since this is an act of

redundancy (tahsil al-hasil). The second is obviously impossible since it shows

the weaknesses of both of them. If in the case where one of them wants to move

the body while the second does not, it is also impossible to assume that both

wishes are not accomplished, since that which prevents the wish of one god is, in

turn, the accomplishment of another s wish. In this case, if one od cannot move

CfQ
the body, it means that the wish of the other is accomplished. The third is

absurd because it proves that the second god is unable to move the body despite

the fact that He, like the first one, also has the same ability. 113

In another argument, al-Razi disproved the possibility of multiple gods

having identical attributes by asserting that if two gods share virtually the same

characteristics there will be no meaning to multiplicity. While if they only share

some of the characteristics such as their necessity (wujub) but differ in others,

this will imply that there is composition in God. Here, it shows that there are at

least two parts and this will logically lead to an infinity since every part can be

further divided due to the fact that there will always be the part which is similar,

namely necessity (al-wujub), and the other which is its particularity (al-
kbususiyyab) and individuation (ta ayyuri).113
114 This logical argument is called the

argument of equivocation and distinction (dalil al-ishtirah wa al-imtiy az).

Al-Razi also put forward another argument based on the logical principle

in denying multiplicity in the Necessary Being. If God were multiple, the

difference between them is either through their essences (bi al-dhatiyyat) or not

through their essences. If the former is the case, the Necessary Being will then

be genus under which there are species. This would imply that there are

113 MuAissal, 194; Arba m, 222; Matalib, vol.2, 135-136; Ma alim, 58; Mas all, 58; Sharh alAqald,
37-38; al-Bajuri, Shark Jawbarat, Y22-Y22; Fakbr al-Dih, 236.
114 Ma alim, 57-9; Arba m, 222; Mabahitb, vol.2, 474; Matalib, vol. 2, 119-20; Fakbr al-Dfn al-
Razi, 234-238.

96
differentia which distinguish all species. Since the differentia is the cause (al-

illab) of existence of the species under a genus, there would be double existence

(mawj udan marratayn) apart from the first necessary existence.115 Furthermore,

the second existence will imply that the existence of the Necessary Being is

dependent on the differentia:

the necessity of the existence by its essence (wujub al-wujud bi


al-dbat) in its very meaning is that the non-existence of others will
not necessitate its non-existence. But with regard to it being
constituted by a differentia, the non-existence of the differentia
will necessitate its non-existence. It is therefore [in this case like]
one which is not related to others and [at the same time] related to
others, which is absurd.116 117 118

On the other hand, if they are not different through their essences they

will be the species constituted by the individuals (al-ashkhas). This too is

impossible since it would be in need of a differentia in order to be distinguished

from the other individuals in the species. In this regard, the existence of

Necessary Being is necessitated not by itself but by others (wajib ligbayrihf).

The idea of composition in divine essence seems to be strong

philosophical point in refuting the idea of multiple gods. This is based on the

premise that every composition is contingent, hence is antithetical to the very

nature of the Necessary Existence. Therefore, while the first meaning of

wahdaniyyab denies partners to God and partnership implies contradictories, the

second meaning constitutes the denial of any composition in God’s essence. “It is

uncharacteristic of the Necessary Being,” asserted al-Razi, “to have parts that are

perceivable (hissiyyah), such as the body, or rationally deduced (aqliyyah) such

as the partition of bayula and forms (surah).99 * The argument is that if God is a

composite, He is in need of His parts and the parts, in turn, are also in need of

115 Mabahitb, vol.2, 474; Matalib, vol.2, 122.


116 Mabahitb, vol.2, 474; Matalib, vol.2, 121-123.
117 Matalib, vol.2, 122-123.
118 Mababith, vol.2, p. 477.

97
the other parts. Since every composite thing is possible (mumkinf it cannot be

the quality of a Necessary Being. On the counter attack by the Mu tazilah

regarding the position of the Ashairah on the composition of essence and

attributes, al-Razi made it clear that in this case, there is no multiplicity involved

since the essence is one and necessary in itself. What is other than the essence is
possible. The unicity remains despite the existence of the attributes.119

Eternity (Qidam)

Qidam, as understood by the mutakallimun, means without beginning.120 Hence,

when God is said as eternal, it means that He exists at each moment without any

point of beginning. Eternity can also be understood as “timeless” in the sense


that God exists beyond time.121 The most popular argument for the eternity of

God by the mutakallimun is the proof that is based on the notion of origination

(al-buduth). They argue that if God is not eternal, there will be an infinite regress

since originated things will continually need an originator ad infinitum.122 Al-

Baghdadi recapitulates the mutakallimun argument:

If the creator [of the world] is originated, He would be in need of


an originator. If His originator is also originated, there will be
need for a third originator, and this will continue until no end,
which is impossible. What leads to the impossible is itself
impossible. It follows definitely from this impossibility the
necessity of God being eternal.123

Al-Razi, nevertheless, disagreed with this argument. It can be refuted, for

example, by an argument that says that it is possible that the originator of the

world is also originated but the originator, on the other hand, was created by

119 Fakhr al-Dih al-Razi, 234.


120 Mu Vassal, p. 82.
121 Richard Swinburne, Is There a God? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 9.
niArba m, 92.
123 Al-Baghdadi, Usui al-Dm, 72; Irshad, 20.

98
something eternal.124 In this case there will be no infinite regress. By this

counter-argument, al-Razi was referring to the philosophers’ idea of emanation

which views that the world is emanated from the Active Intellect (al-Aql al-

Fa (aT)125 which, in turn, was caused by another intellect up until the First

Intellect (al-Aql al-Awwal) which was emanated from God.

Realizing this difficulty of the mutakallimun who ar ued on the basis of

CfQ
eternity and origination (qidam wa buduth), al-Razi, on the other hand, looked at

the issue from the perspective of necessity and contingency (wujub wa imkarT).

Since God is necessary, He must be eternal, for the opposite would mean that His

existence is dependent on others and He will be receptive of non-existence.

Having the possibility of receiving non-existence is the quality of a contingent

being and this is contrary to God’s necessary existence. Therefore, it is affirmed


that God is eternal and subsisting.126 127This argument reminds us of his other

view that the proof of God’s existence is the contingency of the world, not its

origination. This is because for al-Razi, contingency is prior to origination in

terms of the explanation of the process of creation since it is the receptive cause

of the need (illat al-hdjah) of a creator. In other words, the need for a creator in

the contingent beings lies not in it being originated but in its potentiality to exist.

Thus, origination comes after the influence of the determinant which is

subsequent to the attraction of this influence by the receptive cause, which refers

to contingency.128 Al-Razi, in this case, was consistent in emphasizing the

124 Arba m, 92.


125 Also known as Agent Intellect.
126 Fakbr al-Dm, 290.
127 Arba m, 68. Al-Razi defined contingency as ‘that whose existence or non- existence is not
impossible (kawn al-sbay’ff nafsihibi hayth la yamtanicwujuduhu wa la adamuhu imtinacan
wajiban) and origination as ‘an existent which is preceded by non-existence’ (kawn al-wujud
masb uqan bi al-adarri). Ibid.
128 Arba m, 68; Theology, 83.

99
philosophers’ notion of contingency vis-a-vis the mutakallimuris notion of

origination in theological discussion.1

According to Cevian, the idea of eternity with re ard to God is so superior

CfQ
and self-evident that it no longer became a matter of disagreement among the

130 It is supported by the fact that all the divine attributes also
mutakallimun..129

share the unique quality of eternity. The only dispute was whether eternity was

re arded as a positive attributes (sifah ijabiyyah) existing additional to the


CfQ

essence, or as a necessary concomitant to the essence. Al-Asn ari and some of

his immediate followers regarded eternity as one of the positive qualities.131 Al-

Razi, nevertheless, following other mutakallimun, insisted that eternity was not

an attribute additional to the essence. He put forward two arguments in

supporting this position. First, if eternity is to be viewed independent from the

essence, then the Necessary Being will be in need of it for His perfection which is

contrary to the principle of the self-sufficiency of the Necessary Being. Thus,

eternity is an inherent quality in the very being of Wajib al-Wuj ud. Second, if

the Necessary Being is eternal due to an attribute which is separable, then this

independent quality of eternity would itself have to be dependent on another

eternity which again, by necessity, would be either self-sufficient or dependent.

If the first is the case, it would have to be identical with the Necessary Being,

which is a fallacy. While if the second is true, it would imply infinite regression
(tasalsul) or circular causation (dnvvr), both of which are absurd.132 This second

argument echoes the argument of al-Ghazali in Iqtisad. which points out the

implication of infinite regression if eternity is conceived of as an additional


quality to the divine essence.133

129 Theology, 100.


130 Ibid., 103.
131 Ibid., 101.
132 Ibid, 102
133 Al-Ghazali, al-Iqtisad, 26. According to Ceylan, the reason why the theologians rejected
eternity as an independent attributes is that they wanted to stress that eternity must not be

100
Al-Razi viewed that eternity is a negative attribute. He refuted the

Mu tazilab who claimed the opposite on the basis that qidam is denial of a prior

non-existence of something, and to deny denial was for them positive

attribution. Following that, they argued that eternity cannot subsist on the
essence which is also eternal since it will lead to infinite regression (tasalsul).134

Al-Razi disagreed with the above view through the logical argument that eternity

is the denial of the fact that something is preceded by non-existence, and to say

that something is preceded by a non-existence is a positive statement. To deny

positive statement is to affirm the negative.135

Baq a (Permanence)

Al-Razi’s proof of the Attribute of permanence (baqa9) is closely related to the

proof of eternity (qidam) since the former is the denial of non-existence after

existence while the latter is the denial of non-existence before existence. Hence,

according to al-Razi, the proof for qidam is also the proof for baqa’.

As we have seen in the arguments for the eternity of God, the arguments

on divine permanence also centered on the fact that God is a Necessary Being,

whose very quality is in need of an endurance as its prerequisite. Similarly, the

notion of Necessary Existence in itself, must mean that it is, in the first place,

not receptive of non-existence. That which does not receive non-existence, must

be subsisting (abadf).136

Al-Razi disagreed with the Asbairab who were of the view that

permanence is an attribute that exists additional to its existence (zaldatan ala

wujudihf) which means that God subsists through the attributes of permanence

considered as a secondary property of God like other divine attributes. That is why eternity was
not the point of dispute between the mutakallimun and the philosophers. Theology , 102.
134 Arba Tn, 158; Matalib, vol. 3, 229.
135 Arba Tn, 164.
136 Al-Razi, MasaTl, 28.

101
(baqa9). To al-Razi, since God is an existent necessary in Himself (wajib al-

wuj ud), He cannot exist through something external to Himself. Since

permanence is closely related to His existence, God cannot subsist through baqa9

which is external to the essence. Furthermore, if God subsists through the

attribute of permanence, this would imply that the latter is itself necessary

existence in itself (wajib al-wujud li dbatibf), which is impossible. 138 This is in

line with al-Razi s view that baqa is a ne ative attribute which does not have

CfQ
real existence.

The notion of independent existence of baqa’ will lead to either infinite

regression (tasalsul) or circularity (dawr). If permanence subsists through

another attribute of permanence, it will lead to tasalsul, since this permanence

will further need another permanence. If, on the other hand, it subsists by the

essence, it will lead to circularity since the essence also depends on it. If it

subsists by itself, then it will be necessary existence by itself and the essence on

the other hand will be necessary through it, which is impossible.139


137 138

God’s Being Distinct from Originated Things (Mukhalafatuhu li al-


Hawaditb)
This topic will be dealt with in a more detailed manner in the next chapter,

particularly when we discuss al-Razi’s Kitab Asas al-Taqdfs. Nevertheless, to

put it briefly, for al-Razi, the distinction between God and other possible beings
is by their essence, not through an attribute, which is additional to the essence.140

By this, al-Razi was trying to put an absolute difference between God and others,

following the spirit of the Qur’anic verse which strongly affirms that, “There is

nothing like unto Him.” Any kind of essential similarity ascribed between God

and others would definitely impair the divine transcendence. Hence the

137 Samih Daghim, Maws uat Mustalahat Ilm al-Kalam al-Islami, vol.l, 283-284; Muhassal, 174.
138 Ma alim, 51. Muhassal, 174. This view is also the view of al-Baqillam and al-Juwayni with
which, al-Razi is in agreement.
139 Fakhr al-Dih al-Razi, '292.
140 Ma talib, vol.l, 313; Muhassal, 154.

102
difference must be essential and not accidental. If the difference is accidental,

there will be similarity between the essence of God and others, and this will lead

to the condition that the contingent does not need any cause, which is

impossible.141 This view is in disagreement with many other views. The

majority of the mutakallimun, said al-Razi, were of the view that the difference

between the essence of God and other contingent being was due to the attributes
possessed by the essence.142 The Mu tazilah and the philosophers had something

in common on this issue. The former, through the view of Abu Hashim in

particular, viewed that the essence of God is similar to other essences in their

essential nature. They only differ in terms of states (A#Z).143 While the latter

whose view can be seen in Ibn Sina’s writings, asserted that the essence of God is

identical with His existence. Existence is something that is shared by all existent

beings. The difference between them is that God’s existence is not accidental to

the essence while other existents are.144 Al-Razi, in this case, tried to emphasize

the absolute transcendence of God through the denial of essential similarity

between God and others. Following from this strict position, he also attacked the

position of the anthropomorphists, particularly the mujassimab, who viewed that

God is similar to other creations in terms of body but they are different in terms

of other attributes, just like a man and a horse are similar in terms of animality

but different in terms of other attributes.145 This is, to al-Razi, impossible due to

the fact that there are other necessary characteristics of the body such as

occupying place (mutaJyayyizab), finite (mutanahiyah) and composite

(murakkabY all of which are ainst the nature of eternal God.

141 Muhassal, 154.


142 Arba m, 96.
143 Ibid., 154. The states, according to Abu Hashim, are four: Life (al-Hayyab), Knowingness (al-
Alimiyyahy Existentness (al-Mawjudiyyah) and His being powerful (al-Qadiriyyah).
144 Ibid., 154.
145 Asas, 35.

103
CHAPTER THREE

TEXTUAL AND RATIONAL BASIS OF THE DIVINE


TRANSCENDENCE

INTRODUCTION

From the discussion in the last chapter concerning the divine attributes in general,

and the negative attributes (sifat salbiyyab) in particular, it becomes clear that the

transcendence aspect of God is undoubtedly an essential part in arrivin at the

CfQ
knowledge of God. This is due, inter alia, to the fact that the transcendence

aspect of God serves as the foundation of other attributes. As we have observed

and will continually encounter in al-Razi’s theological thought, the arguments for

the divine transcendence have been further strengthened and refined through the

responses given by the mutakallimun to the challenges from various external

factors including from those heretical groups which have undermined the

foundation of the divine transcendence. In al-Razi’s case, his confrontations with

the anthropomorphists such as the Karramiyyah and a segment of the Hanabilah

forced him to put forward a more refined and forceful philosophical argument as a

result of which, a stronger foundation of the divine transcendence in his kalam

works was established. Having stated that, it is our purpose in this chapter to

elaborate further on al-Razi’s proofs in establishing a stronger foundation of the

divine transcendence. We will examine al-Razi’s arguments, rational and textual,

that, in principle, attack two of the most important premises which underlie the

views of the anthropomorphists regarding God: first, that God is a body (/ism) or a

substance (jaw bar) and second, that God occupies space (mutahayyiz}. Our

approach is to first present the argument of the anthropomorphists and then

followed by al-Razi’s refutations.

104
KITAB ASAS AL-TAQDIS

Before we proceed, it is important to introduce the main reference we were using

in elaborating most of al-Razi’s arguments against anthropomorphism, namely, his

Kitab Asas al-Taqdfs (Book on the Basis of the Purification of God). According to
Ahmad Hijazi al-Saqa who edited this work,1 Asas al-Taqdfs, also known as

Ta’sis al-Taqdfs,2 which was dedicated to the ruler of his time, al-Malik Sayf al-

Din al-Ayyubl3 (reigned between 1199-1218), is a rejoinder to the writing of Ibn

Khuzaymah (d.923), tenth century Hanball scholar who wrote Kitab al-

Tawhid wa Itbbat Sfat al-Rabb containing the affirmation of the literal meaning

of the anthropomorphic attributes of God.4 We did not, however, come across any

statement from al-Razi throughout Asas al-Taqdis mentioning Ibn Khuzaymah’s

name, nor the specific objective of refuting Ibn Khuzaymah as claimed by al-Saqa.

Nevertheless, based on al-Razi’s strong comment on Ibn Khuzaymah’s Kitab al-

Tawhid in the work of the former, Tafsfr al-Kabfr, which clearly shows his

intense disagreement with the content of the latter’s work, there is a reason for us

to concur with al-Saqa’s claim. In this tafsfr, while commenting the verse “laysa

ka mitblibi sbay ’ ” (al-Shura, 42:11), al-Razi remarked:

Ibn Khuzaymah has cited argumentations of our predecessors


(ashaburta) regarding this verse (laysa ka mitblibi sbay9) in a book
called “al-Tawhid ” which is in reality a book of polytheism (kitab
al-sbirk).5 *

1 The edition of Asas al-Taqdfs by al-Saqa was published by Dar al-jil (Bayrut, 1993) based on
two manuscripts; first, a copy available at Dar al-Kutub al-Misriyyab (23222 B), microfilm no.
20864 and Kurdistan Copy, no. 1328.
2 Fakhr al-Djh al-Razf, 28; Introduction by Ahmad Hijazi al-Saqa in Asas, 8.
3 Ibn Abi Usaybi'ah, Uy un al-Anba’ff Tabaqat al-Atibba’ (Al-Qahirah: Matba'ah al-Wahbiyyah,
1882), 23. In Asas, al-Razi mentioned the name of this ruler namely Abu Bakr bin Ayyub. Asas,
12.
4 This statement is given by al-Saqa in an appendix of his edition of Asas al-Taqdfs, 229. In this
appendix, apart from alluding to the contextual ground of the writing of Asas al-Taqdfs, he also
summarized al-Razi’s position regarding this issue as well as the criticisms made against al-Razi’s
views later by Ibn Taymiyyah. Al-Saqa also included in the appendix, his survey on the issue of
al-haqfqab wa al-majaz regarding God’s attributes in the Taural.
5 Tafsir, vol. 9, 582. This view of Ibn Khuzaymah is based on the Hadith which says that “God’s
face is veiled by a light which whenever it is unveiled, the face of God will bum everything that is

105
Al-Razi continued to explain what he meant by the above

statement:

...for he is a man of confused words, lacking in understanding (qalfl


al-fabm) and deficient in intellect (naqis al-aql). He says, ‘we
affirm that God has face and...at the face our Lord is light,
brightness (dya9*) *and
6 7beauty
8 (baba") that if its veil is uncovered, His
face will burn everything that his sight (basarubu) beholds. The
face of our Lord is denied of destruction and annihilation (al-balak
wa al-fana’y.An another chapter he says that the Qur’an indicates
that there is similarity between the essence of God and His creatures
in many attributes...6

In this work, Ibn Khuzaymah, following some of the Hanabilab, defended

the position of what he re arded as “the right way to comprehend the


CfQ

anthropomorphic expressions of God.” Affirming that God has limbs-a face,

eyes, hands that are both right, and that God is sitting on a Throne that is situated

above the seven heavens, Ibn Khuzaymah maintained that this is the right

position in arriving at the meaning of the anthropomorphic expressions. This

knowledge, added Ibn Khuzaymah, is known through the Book of God and what

is transmitted from the Prophet based on true and established chain of authorities

(al-asanfd al-tbabitab al-sahihab). In one of his sayings quoted in the

introduction of Kitab al-Tawhfd, he went to the extent of charging those who do

not comply with this position, namely, to affirm that God is sitting on His

Throne, and that He is sitting above the seven heavens (is taw a fawqa sab a

samawat), with being unbelievers and as such that they could be killed and their
property confiscated.9 With regard to the anthropomorphic verses, Ibn

seen by His sight” (la’ahraqat sabahat wajhibi kullu shay ’ adrakabu basarubu). Ibn Khuzaymah,
Kitab al-Tawhfd, 19.
6 TafsT, vol. 9, 582.
7 Ibn Khuzaymah, Kitab al-Tawhfd, (dhal).
8 Ibid, 21.
9 Ibid. This saying is narrated by al-Hakim from Muhammad bin Salih bin Hani’ who heard it
from Ibn Khuzaymah.

106
Khuzaymah held firmly to the principle also held by most of the Hanabilah, that

we have to affirm what God has affirmed regarding Himself without drawing any

resemblance between the divine characteristics and any of His creatures.10

Apparently, the reason why al-Razi did not specify Ibn Khuzaymah’s name

in Asas is that al-Razi regarded the latter as representing a larger group namely

segment of the Hanabilah whose literal approach and ideas regarding God are

excessive. 11 In few places in this book, before putting forward certain

arguments, al-Razi spelled out that it is to the Hanabilah that the said arguments

12 In general, al-Razi described the Hanabilah as those who


were directed.11

maintain that God possesses organs and limbs and therefore affirm parts and

divisions with regard to God (itarafubi kawnihi murakkaban min al-ajza’wa al-
ab ad).13

Apart from Hanabilah, another group that al-Razi explicitly mentioned in

Asas as his object of refutation is the Karramiyyah, a group that flourished in the

central and eastern part of the Islamic world from the ninth century until the

invasion of the Moghul.14 Compared to other sects, the Karramiyyah were quite

significant in the historical context of al-Razi’s theology mainly due to his

continuous polemic with this group. He even had a bitter experience with them

when his debate with a popular Karramiyyah figure, Majid al-Din 'Abd al-Majid
better known as Ibn Qudwah15 in the Ghurid capital, Firuzkuh on the year 1198

was reported to have caused a popular uprising among the Karramiyyah thus

forcing al-Razi to return to his hometown.16 Even his death was said to be caused

11 See our elaboration of the Hanabilah in Chapter One, 48-51.


n Asas, 19-20, 58.
13 Ibid, 20, 58.
14 See Chapter One, 32, fn. 48.
15 Ibn Qudwah was the leader of Karramiyyah after the death Ibn Haysam. He was the
contemporary of al-Razi and received support from some courtiers of Sultan Shihab al-DIn al-
Ghuri.
16 Theology, 3.

107
by him being poisoned by this group. 7 As a result of this long debate with this

sect, we thus find in al-Razi’s theological works, many ar uments of the

CfQ
Karramiyyah elaborated and refuted, as clearly exemplified in the As as al-Taqdfs.

Likewise, it is through al-Razi’s works also that the views of the Karramiyyah got

to be known by later scholars. As to the basic ideas of the Karramiyyah, al-Razl

explained that although they maintain that God is One, Infinite and Simple, they

specified God in a direction, which implies that He can be pointed by the senses

(mash ar ilayhi bi hasab al- hiss'):

...they [the Karramiyyah] are not saying about the organs and limbs
(al-a da’wa al-jawarfh) [like the Hartabilah] but they view that God
is specified (mukhtass) by those under the Throne. This sect also
assumes (yahtamilu) three directions regarding God; either God is
engaged to the Throne, or that God is distinct from it by an infinite
farness (bud), or God is distinct from it with a finite farness. Each
of these views is held by three different groups within the
Karramiyyah. They also disagree on whether God is specified by
these directions through His essence or through an eternal agent
(ma ha qadfm)...

Apart from refuting these two groups, another central concern of Asas al-

Taqdfs is to explain the proper way to comprehend the meaning of the

anthropomorphic verses in the Qur’an and the Prophetic traditions in order to

maintain the transcendence and purity of the divine essence from any corporeal

and anthropomorphic qualities. In so doing, al-Razi focused on two important

points: to deny God as a body (jism) and to deny Him as occupying space

(mutahayyiz). This is followed by his explanation on how to understand the

anthropomorphic verses that occur in the Qur’an and the Prophetic traditions.

This involves the identification of muhkamat and mutashabihat verses of the

17 Al-Dhahabi, Tarikh al-Islam \va Wafayat al-Mashahir wa al-A lam, ed. 'Umar ‘Abd al-Salam
Tadmuri (Bayrut: Dar al-Kitab al-Arabi, 1997), 215.
18 Asus, 68-69.

108
Qur’an and the proper implementation of ta \vil in understanding the

mutasbabibat.

THE ARRANGEMENT OF KITAB ASAS AL-TAQDS

Al-Razi arranged this work into four main sections. First, proofs that God is

exalted from the characteristic of body (jismiyyab) and occupying space (al-

hayyiz); second, the allegorical interpretations (al-ta^vil) of the ambiguous verses

from the Qur’an and the Hadiths; third, an affirmation of the position of the early

generation (al-salaf) who propounded the authoritative understanding of the

anthropomorphic verses; fourth, additional related issues. In the first section, as

pposed to the anthropomorphists’ view, al-Razi maintained that there is an


o

existent which cannot be grasped by the senses, and that it was not necessary that

all existents should have their equal (nazir) and resemblance (sbabib) in order to

exist. Next, al-Razi put forward numerous textual and rational arguments to

prove the fact that God is beyond body, space and direction. In the second

section, he enumerated all the anthropomorphic attributes that occur in the

Qur’an and Hadiths followed by the proper allegorical interpretations on the

meaning of each of them. In the third section, he advanced the views held by the

early scholars (al-salaf) concerning the issue including their position on the

interpretation of an important verse in Surah Ali 'Imran, verse 7, which mentions

the understanding of two kinds of verses mufkamat and mutasbabibat. Finally,

al-Razi deliberated over some extraneous issues, such as the differences between

the mujassimab and musbabbibab and their status in Islam.

THE IMPORTANCE OF ASAS AL-TAQD1S

The significance of this work lies in the fact that it represents the opinion of later

mutakallimun, especially the Asbairab against the views of the

anthropomorphists. Although there were also other theological works of the same

109
nature during later period, they only deal with the subject as part of the whole

theological works such as al-Shahrastani’s Nibayat al-Iqdam, Baydawi’s Tawali

al-Anwar, al-Baghdadi’s Usui al-Dih and Amidi’s Gbayat al-Maram. Asas al-

Taqdfs, on the other hand, was written with a specific motive, namely, to provide

substantial refutation to the anthropomorphists.

Given the background of al-Razi’s views on attributes, this work is also

seen as that which steers a middle course between ta til (denial of attributes) of

the Mu tazilab and the tasbbib of the musbabbibab. One may argue that al-

Razi’s method in this work is very much similar to the method of the Mu tazilab

especially on the employment of taXvil. Nevertheless, as we will see later, there

are some differences between al-Razi’s method and the method of the Mu tazilab.

It is not an exaggeration to say that Asas al-Taqdis, in terms of its strong

refutation against the anthropomorphists, is, in some way, comparable to al-

Ghazali’s refutation of the philosophers, namely in his Tabafut al-Falasifab. If al-

Ghazali in his Tabafut has destroyed the views and arguments of the philosophers

regarding God and the world, al-Razi in this work has demolished the

anthropomorphists’ foundation by presenting strong rational philosophical and

scriptural arguments against their views. Just as the Tabafut later received strong

reprisal from a great Muslim philosopher, Ibn Rushd through his work Tabafut

al-Tabafut, in the same way, Asas al-Taqdis of al-Razi has been refuted later on

by one of the most important spokesmen of the Hanabilab, Ibn Taymiyyah

through his works Ta’sis fiRadd Asas al-Taqdfs and Muwafaqat Sahih al-

110
Manq ul li Sarih al-Ma q ul.19

RATIONAL PROOFS OF DIVINE TRANSCENDENCE

Having briefly introduced this important work, we will proceed to analyze its

main content commencing with al-Razi’s rational arguments in upholding divine

transcendence. As have been mentioned, al-Razi’s main focus in this work was to

refute the arguments of two of his main adversaries, namely, the Hanabilah and

the Karramiyyah. Although these two groups had some differences in the details

of their doctrines, the similarity between them can be discerned at least in two

important points. First, they began their views with the literal understanding of

the anthropomorphic verses that mention God as having ‘organs and limbs’, and

that God is ‘in’ the heavens, sitting on His Throne. Second, which is the

consequence of the first, is that the views of both sects bear the implication that

God is a body. Specifically, the view of the Hanabilah that God has organs will

lead to the idea that God is composed of parts which is the characteristic of bodies

while the view of the Karramiyyah that God is in a certain direction implies that

God occupies space, which is also the nature of a body. The Karramiyyah, who

were more philosophical in their approach, even asserted explicitly that God is

either a body or a substance (jawhar), and that He is above the earth and that He

19 Ibn Taymiyyah is a well-known Hanbali scholar who upheld Ibn Hanbal’s traditional position
and attacked many of the Ashairah and Mutazilab views. (See our separate discussion on Ibn
Taymiyyah in Chapter Four, 171-174). Regarding the anthropomorphic issue particularly in
response to al-Razi’s ideas in Asas al-Taqdis, he wrote a rejoinder under the title al-Ta’sis fiRadd
Asas al-Taqdis. The content of Ibn Taymiyyah’s refutation is also included as volume 24, 25 and
26 of another Ibn Taymiyyah’s work, the al-Kawakib al-Darimi Somewhat similar refutations of
al-Razi’s views are also available in the first volume of Ibn Taymiyyah’s famous work, Muwafaqat
Sahih al-ManqH li Sarih al-Ma qul (Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah, 1985), also known as Dar’
Ta arud al- Aql wa al-Naql. One-third of the content of the latter is also available in the margin
of his other Minhaj al-Sunnab al-Nabawiyyab fi Naqd Kalam al-Sbiah wa al-Qadariyyab.
Partial translation of Dar’Ta arud namely on the commentary of Risalah Adhawiyyab of Ibn Sina
is available in Yahya J. Michot, “A Mamluk Theologian’s Commentary on Avicenna’s Risalah
Adhawiyya: Being a Translation of a Part of the Dar’ al-Taarud of Ibn Taymiyya, with
Introduction, Annotation, and Appendices.” Journal of Islamic Studies, 2003, 2 parts. 14 (2): 149-
203 & 14 (3): 309-363.

Ill
was the locus of temporal events.2 Since this notion of body became the

underlying principle of both sects, al-Razi therefore devoted great effort toward

refuting the notion of the body with regard to the Deity.

THE RATIONAL PRINCIPLE UNDERLYING THE MUSHABBIHAH’S


NOTION OF GOD

The main rational principle held by the mushabbihah in their effort to justify God

as a substance serves as a background to al-Razi’s arguments on the transcendence

of God. Of the two sects mentioned above, the Karramiyyah were the real

proponents of these rational principles. They expounded their arguments in a

series of logical premises, which they claimed as and must be accepted

necessarily. From these principles, they came to the conclusion that God is a

substance (jawhar) and a body (jism), hence, He is qualified to be ascribed with

one of many directions. The Hanabilah, due to their bila kayf approach and strong

rejection of rational philosophical arguments in theology, satisfied themselves

mainly with a literal meaning of the verses.

The logical principle held by the Karramiyyah which led them to the

view that God is a body (substance) and that God can be specified by one of many

directions was put forward as follows: “For every two existents, one must either

subsist in the other (Jialan fi al-akhar) or be distinct and free from the other in
21 In Asas, al-Razi reproduced the words of Ibn al-Haysam,22
terms of direction.”20

one of the important proponents of the Karramiyyah regarding this

20 Nihayat, 43.
21 Asas, 70.
22 Ibn Haysam (d.1016) was the mutakallimun among the Karramiyyah who elaborated the
groups’ theology and technical vocabulary. He was the founder of the Haysamiyyah, one of the
seven sects of the Karramiyyah. He tried to rectify the anthropomorphic view of Ibn Karram by
saying that what the latter said regarding God as a body actually means that God subsists by itself
(al-Qaim bi nafsibi); Suhayr Mukhtar, al-Tajsfm inda al-Muslimm, 76; Bosworth,
“Karramiyyah,” 668.

112
principle in the latter’s argument against an Ashi ari
<■ i 1
scholar, i 23
Ibn Furak:

There is no doubt that for every two existents in the visible world (fi
al-shabid), it is necessary that one of them is attached to the other
(muhayithan li al-akhaf), or it is distinct from the other (mubayinan
anhu) in terms of direction.23
24

This principle seems to be the most important principle held by the

musbabbibab in proving the bodily nature of God. It also occurs in other

Ash'arites’ works such as in al-Shahrastani’s Nihayat al-Iqdam25 and al-Baydawi’s

Tawali (al-Anwar. Al-Shahrastani presented the principle as follows:

If two self-subsistent objects be supposed, they must either be side


by side or separate and so in local relation to each other. From this,
they argue that God must either be in the world or external to it.
‘Within’ per se necessitates proximity and contact, and ‘without’ per
se necessitates separation and direction.26

While in al-Baydawi’s words:

The intuition of reason observes that of [any] two existent things,


one either must be functioning within the other, as a substance and
its quality, or must be distinctly separated from [the other] in
direction, as are the heavens and the earth. But God, praise be to
Him, is not a substrate for the universe, nor does He inhere within

23 Abu Bakr Muhammad ibn al-Hasan ibn Furak al-Isfahani was born circa 941 in Isfahan and
studied in both Basra and Baghdad. In 982 he was invited to Nishapur by the Emir to teach in a
madrasah specially built for him. His presence in Nishapur is said to have led to a great flowering
of various studies there. He died in 1015 by poisoning reported to be done by the Karramiyyah
after he defeated them in an argument. His main work dealt with the application to God in Hadith
of anthropomorphic characteristics. Similar to al-Razi, he asserted as a general principle that it is
better to interpret these texts in accordance with the conception of God as transcendent, for which
there is a clear basis in revelation, then to do the opposite, by interpreting literally texts which
have not been fully understood, thereby endangering the conception of God’s transcendence. Watt,
Islamic Philosophy, 80-81.
24 Asas, 70.
25 Nihayat, 45.
26 Ibid., 45.

113
it, so He is entirely distinct from it in direction.2

This principle is not new in the discussion of kalam since it refers to a theologico-

cosmological principle referring to the nature of the originated being (muhdatb). To the

mutakallimun, existents are divided into: (i) the Eternal One (al-Qadim) whose existence

does not have the initial moment, and (ii) the originated or the created (al-muhdatb)

which has the initial moment of existence. The Eternal One refers to God while the

originated refers to the creation other than God (alam). The originated, in turn, are

divided into: (i) that, when it exists, occupies space and it is called substance or atom

(jawbar); (ii) that which does not occupy space, called accident. While the nature of

substance is that each of them is distinct from each other in terms of direction, the

accident subsists in the substance and therefore can be said as having the same direction

or place with the substance. Further, all substances are homogeneous in nature and there

is only one kind (jins) of substance. Accidents, on the other hand, consist of different

types and kinds, the amount of which was not agreed upon by the mutakallimun^

27A1-Baydawi, Tawali ‘al-Anwar, vol. 2, 758. Al-Baydawi also presented another rational argument
by the mushabbihab, which runs, “A body requires both a particular space and a particular region,
because of the fact that it is self-subsistent. God, praise to Him the Most High, has a
commonality with [a body] in this fact, and thus He also has a commonality with it in requiring
these two factors.” Ibid. Al-Shahrastani argued against this argument by highlighting the
confusion brought by the Karramiyyah through the word ‘self-subsistent’ by which they based
their argument. Nihayat, 46.
28 Alnoor Dhanani, The Physical Theory of Kalam (Leiden: E.J.Brill, 1994), 16. This classification
was generally accepted by the majority of the mutakallimun, both Mutazilah and Ashairah.
Nevertheless, they disagreed on whether the non-existent (al-ma dum) can be an object or not.
The Mutazilah affirmed this view by saying that ‘objects which do not exist’ can be said to be
objects while the Ashairah denied it. This is because for the Mu tazilah, the true nature of an
object was its status as an object of knowledge which includes the non-existents (ma dum) while
for the Ashairah, the nature of an object is its status as an object which exists, hence, the non-
existents are not objects of knowledge. The Ashairah, therefore, confined their classification of
existents only to objects which exist (mawjudat) and these comprise objects which have some first
initial moment of existence, namely created things, and that which does not have an initial moment
of existence, namely God who is Eternal. Created objects are either objects which require a
substratum in which they inhere, namely accident (arad), or objects which occupy space
(muta/iayyiz) and do not need a substratum, namely substance (jawhar), sometimes referred to as
body (jism). Accidents are incorporeal while substances are corporeal. The smallest unit that
constitutes substance is atom (jawhar al-fard). Atoms, according to the mutakallimun, are
homo eneous and when they are combined, they will form bodies. The mutakallimun held that the
tn

created worlds consist of corporeal substances and incorporeal accidents which inhere in
substances, and that the properties of objects arise both from the intrinsic nature of atoms which
constitute them and from the accidents which inhere in them and also the combination of these

114
To the Karramiyyah, this classification is applicable to God in the sense

that the essence of God is the substance (jawhar), a place or locus in which the

attributes inhere, while the attributes, since they cannot exist by themselves, are

accidents, and therefore are in need of the essence as a substratum for them to

subsist. The Karramiyyah, as put by al-Shahrastani, explained their argument as

follows:

We agree that God has essence and attributes. The attributes do not
at all stand in the same place (lyayth) as each other nor are they
spatially related, because that which subsists in another is not
susceptible of space, but they all subsist in His essence, i.e. in the
place where His essence is. The distinction between the essence and
qualities [attributes] is that the essence has a place of its own so that
the qualities are in reference to it while the qualities have not. The
word place (Jyayth) cannot be used of the qualities...thus direction by
which the Deity can be located can be asserted.* 29

To relate the above view with the principle held by the Karramiyyah we

mentioned earlier (that for every two existents, one of them must either be

dependent on the other or be distinct and free from the other in terms of

direction), it is apparent that the Karramiyyah considered this principle as the

most universal principle which is applicable even to God. Since the essence of

God is analogous substance which functions as a substratum for the


O
cu

attributes that do not possess real existence, God can, therefore, be regarded as a

substance or a body. This is basically the line of argument of the Karramiyyah

which supports their view of an anthropomorphic God.

The Karramiyyah also substantiated their view using the ‘argument based

on existence’ which, ironically, was also used by the mutakallimun, especially the

atoms with their inherent accidents to form larger units. For example, their combination to form a
living composite which is the human body. Ibid. 5,17. Cf. Al-Attas, A Commentary, 30-31; Shlomo
Pines, Studies in Islamic Atomism (Jurusalem: The Magnes Press The Hebrew University, 1997),
1-31. On the classification of existent things see Muhassal, 52-144.
29 Nihayat, 45.

115
Ashairah, in their argument for the Vision of God.3 They argued that since the

things that have directions in this visible world are substance and accident, there

must be a common cause to these two to be in such a condition. Analysis shows

that there is nothing common to all these substances and accidents except two

things: existence and origination (al-wujud wa al-huduth). Origination (hudutb)

cannot be the true cause of this principle since origination, similar to contingency,

is not a positive judgment or an existential attribute (sifah mawjudab). This is

due to the fact that origination is regarded as an existence that is preceded by

non-existence and non-existence cannot be the basis of a judgment.30


31 Hence, only

existence (yvujud) remains as the cause of this principle (that substance and

accidents have direction). Further, existence is common to both worlds, the

perceptible and imperceptible (al-sbabid wa al-ghalb). Since God, who is

imperceptible, exists, therefore He is also included in this principle. To put this

argument in another way, since existence is the basis of the condition of

substance and accidents being within a certain direction, and since God also exists,

He is also in a direction. In Asas, al-Razi summarized one of the proponents of

the Karr amiyyah, Ibn Haysam’s view on this principle:

It is indubitable that for every two existents in the visible world, one

of them must either be dependent on the other or it is distinct and

free from the other in terms of direction. The nature of every two

existents is also in the manner that either it is specifically being

substance or an accident32 or that which has a commonality between

substance and accident (amr mushtarak bayrta al-jawhar wa al­

arad). And the common aspect between the two is either

origination (al-hudutb) or existence (al-wujud). All are false except

30 Controversies, 112-113. See further discussion on Ru yatullab in Chapter Five p.186-192.


3iArbam, 192.
32 This view means that bein a substance or accident in themselves cannot be the cause for them
tn

being in a direction, for the absurdity of the same thing having two different causes is entailed.
We must, therefore, find a common quality which is shared by these two.

116
existence. Hence, it is necessary that the cause of this judgment is

existence. [Since] God is an existent, it is necessary that He, the

Exalted, is either attached to [resides in] the world or distinct from it


in a direction.33

Moving from this conclusion, the Karramiyyah further argued that since

God is not residing within the world, this would lead to incarnation (al-hciliT)

which is rejected in Islam, God, therefore, must be distinct from the world in a

direction:

The anthropomorphists (ahi al-tashbih) maintain that the world and

the Creator are two existents. Every two existents, either one of

them resides (hal) in the other or is distinct from it...they state that

incarnation is impossible. Hence, it is affirmed that God is distinct

(mubayinan) from the world through a direction (bi al-jihah). In


this way they argue that God is qualified by space and direction.34

To summarize the arguments of the Karramiyyah, their arrival at the idea

of an anthropomorphic God is based on four major premises:

i) That for every two existents in this visible world, it is necessary

that either one of them subsists in the other (as in the case of

accidents) or that it is distinct from the other in a direction (as in

the case of substance).

ii) Since this principle embraces both substance and accidents, it

cannot be based simply on the fact that substance is a substance

or accident is an accident. There must be something that is shared

by both of them.

33 Asas, 70.
34 Ibid., 21.

117
iii) This principle is also not based on origination since origination is

an ‘imperfect’ cause. This is due to the fact that it is re arded as

CfQ
an existent which is preceded by non-existence.

iv) The only basis of this judgment is existence. Since God exists

and since existence is similar both in the visible and invisible

worlds, God is therefore applicable to this principle.

To put the view on a stronger footing, the Karramiyyab also claimed that

this principle is something known by reason necessarily (ma lum bi al-darurab).

In other words, it is impossible for an existent to exist without direction. The

existence of two existents (mawj udayn) beyond the seven directions is, according

to them, false because it is in opposition to the necessary knowledge (al- ilm al-
or _
chruri). They argued further that when something is affirmed by reason

necessarily, it cannot be refuted by any rational argument (nazariyy at) since the

status of self-evident knowledge (badibiyyat) is higher than rational knowled

and an objection of the former by the proof from the latter amounts to an

objection against the fundamental (al-‘a si) by the secondary (al-far ).35
36

AL-RAZl’S counter arguments

In response to the views mentioned above, al-Razi focused his attack on two

important points. First, to destroy the rational principle held by the Karramiyyah

by challenging the basic premises underlying this principle. In so doing, al-Razi

advanced two premises which ran contrary to the principle held by the

Karramiyyah. First, that it is rationally possible that there is an existent beyond

the grasp of the human external senses. Second, that it is not necessary for an

existent to have a resemblance or a likeness (nazir wa shabih) in order for it to

exist. Al-Razi’s second focus was to advance a series of rational proofs on the

35 Ibid., 16.
36 Ibid., 17. This is because in terms of the degree of knowledge, necessary statement is higher than
the statement through deductive arguments in the sense that it gives a priori kind of knowledge.

118
impossibility of ascribing the notion of space to God which serves as the basis of

denying God as a body and substance. In what follows, we will deliberate upon

these points in detail.

GOD AS AN EXISTENT BEYOND SENSE PERCEPTION

Following his unwavering insistence on the priority of divine transcendence, al-

Razi contended, against the position of the anthropomorphists, that the existence

of being that is beyond place and direction is possible and is not contrary to

reason or common-sense. Following the majority of mutakallimun, al-Razi

affirmed that as a Necessary Being, God is exalted from the physical world and

therefore cannot be characterized by the attributes similar to the things in the

physical world. This will entail that God also cannot be placed in any direction

>
and therefore cannot be indicated by the senses (yusbaru ilayhi bi al-/iiss).

matter of fact, this transcendent aspect of God was already affirmed by the

mutakallimun as an important aspect of the knowledge of God in kalam.

In relation to this world, God is neither residing in this world nor is He

separated from it through any spatial distance or specific direction as claimed by

the Karramiyyah. Al-Razi asserted:

Verily, we affirm the existence of an existent that cannot be


indicated by the senses (la yumkirt an yushar ilayhi bi al-Hss), be
He here or there, or we affirm the existence of an existent which
cannot be specified to be in space or direction, or we affirm the
existence of something which does not inhere in the world, neither is
He distinct from it through any of the directions...all these
expressions are different yet the meaning is one.37

This view, according to al-Razi, is a well-established position since it is

affirmed by the majority of scholars and authoritative men of reason (al-uqala’

al-mu tabirm). It, therefore, invalidates the principle of the Karramiyyah that

37 Ibid, 16.

119
God is in a direction is a priori knowledge. A priori knowledge, according to al-

Razi, will not be dissented by so many people particularly the intelligent ones:

The majority of the authoritative men of reason (al-uqala’ al-


mu tabirm) concur that God is exalted, He does not occupy space
(mutahayyiz\ nor is He specified in any direction. He neither
resides in the world nor is He separated from the world through any
sense of direction. If this view is necessarily known to be false, then
the majority of the reasonable people will be against necessary
knowledge.38 39 *

Al-Razi further attacked the view of the Karramiyyah that this principle is

self- evident, through the following arguments:

i) the knowledge of the principle is arrived at through detailed

proof (dalil munfasil) and this is not the nature of self-evident

knowledge whose conclusion is known at once.

ii) the conclusion of the principle is not as certain as the other self-

evident knowledge such as the formulation ‘one plus one equals

to two’ or the statement that affirmation and negation do not co-

exist (al-nafy wa al-itbbat la yajtami an).

iii) the principle is rationally incomplete since it only includes two

possibilities, namely that either one of the existents subsists in

the other or it is distinct from the other in a direction. There is

another possibility that is an existent that neither subsists in the

other nor is it distinct from the other in a direction. This is an

existent which is beyond the grasp of the senses.

By proving the possibility of an existent that is beyond the grasp of the

senses, al-Razi had weakened the principle of the Karramiyyah and disproved its

universality and its applicability to all existents. Al-Razi concluded that this

38 Ibid., 17.
39 Ibid., 18. This means that with regard to the principle, reason cannot immediately and necessarily
affirm that when we think of God and the world, it must be either God subsist in the world or He
is distinct with the world in a direction.

120
principle was therefore erroneous and rather based on their wild ima ination and

CfQ
fancies that could not be accepted in the description of divine realities.40

GOD AS AN EXISTENT WITHOUT ANY RESEMBLANCE

Contrary to the view of the Karr amiyyah, Al-Razi also affirmed that reason can

accept an existent, that is God, which does not have any resemblance in this

world. In other words, it is reasonable that there is an existent that possesses

certain attributes yet all existents other than He are different from Him in every

respect:

it is self-evident that reason does not reject the existence of an


existent which is characterized by some specific attributes such that
all thin other than it are different with it in these specificities.
CZ)
CrQ

Since this fact is not rejected by reason, we, therefore, know that the
non-existence of a likeness of something does not necessary lead to
its non-existence (la yalzam min adami nazir al-sbay’ adam
dbalika al-shay*).41

In this statement, al-Razi explicitly rejected the anthropomorphists’ view

that reason cannot begin to think of an existent that is neither connected

(muttasilan) to the world nor separated (munfasilan) from it, unless there is a

resemblance to it. For al-Razi, the recognition by the intellect of an existent does

not necessarily depend on the prior recognition of something similar to it.

Similarly, the non-existence of a resemblance of something does not lead to the

non-existence of that thing (adam al-nazir wa al- musawf la yujab al-qawl bi

adam al-shay "j.42 Here, al-Razi was trying to solve an important epistemological

question raised by the anthropomorphists, whether the human mind is able to

comprehend something that is totally different from whatever his mind had

experienced. The principle that something must have likeness in order to be

known might be true in regard to empirical, sensible things. For, there must be

40
Ibid.
41 Ibid., 26.
42 Ibid., 27.

121
some similarity for something to be known or defined, at least in terms of genus.

However, this principle certainly cannot be applied to the divine existence since

God, being unique in Himself, possesses attributes which are also unique to

Himself and these attributes do not resemble any of the attributes possessed by

other than Him. He is in His own category which is above and beyond the

categories of the substance and accident:

There is no doubt that God is different from these two divisions


(substance and accident) in His Unique Reality (bi haqfqatibf al-
makhsusab). If He were not distinct in His unique reality, He will be
either similar to the substances or the accidents. This would
necessitate Him to be originated like substances and accidents, which
is impossible.43

CLASSIFICATION OF EXISTENTS

The weakness of this principle is also apparent when it can be falsified through

number of counter-examples. There are some existents, as affirmed by the

philosophers, which neither occupy space nor do they reside on something that

occupies space such as intellects (al-uqul\ souls (al-nufus), the heavenly souls

(al-nufus al-falakiyyah) and prime matter (al-bay da). The Mutazilab, for

example, affirm that will (iradat), aversion (karahat), instinctive desire (sbabwab),

conviction (itiqad) and reason (nazar) also do not exist in a location.44 Al-Razi

also brought up many other cases in which even in this world, many things

alluded to human beings are free from the notion of ‘direction and space’ such as

the human self that is referred to by the term ‘I’. The existence of relations

(idafat) such as ‘father-ness’ and ‘son-ness’ also do not inhere in any space and

direction, neither do they subsist in any substance. For many things in this world,

43 Ibid., 76.
44 Ibid., 72; Dhanani, The Physical Theory, p. 16. In this book, Ibn Muttawayh, an early Mu tazili
is quoted enumerating those which are affirmed through proofs as accidents which includes among
others colors, tastes, odors, location, adhesion (ta ’Iff), force (i timad), life and annihilation (fana).

122
when they are regarded strictly in their quiddities and essences, they are
comprehended in a manner that is free from any notion of space and direction.45

Evidently, the main error of the Karr amiyyah lies in their confused

classification of existents (aqsam al-mawj udat). Following the classification of

substance and accidents, they reduced existents to that which occupies space and

that which resides in something that occupies space; but they missed the third

category, namely, that which is neither of the two.46 In fact, their classification,

as we have mentioned before, is only applicable to originated things (muJydathat).

The mutakallimun, al-Razi affirmed, maintained that originated things fall either

into something that occupies space or something that resides (qalrri) in something
that occupies space.47 As mentioned earlier, the first class refers to substance (al-

Jawhar), which can further be subdivided into that which is divisible, namely

body (al-jism) and that which cannot be further subdivided (al-jawhar al-fard)

which is the atom. The second namely that which resides in something

that occupies space refers to the accident (al-arad) such as colours and shapes.

There is in fact third class, namely, that which neither occupies space nor

resides in something that occupies space. To this category belong the existents

such as hay Ha and the intellects (uqul). Nevertheless, the basis of this third

classification with reference to originated things was disputed by the majority of

mutakallimun since it leads to the concept of something similar to God in its


quiddity.48 This is the reason why the mutakallimun. affirmed that all existents

other than God consist of either substance or accidents. Hence al-Ghazali, for

example, maintained that the soul is a substance (jawhar) which is applicable to


the above principle.49 Al-Razi, in his classification, disagreed with the view of the

45 Asas, 19.
46 Ibid., 18
47 Muhassal, 92.
48 Ibid., 92.
49 Al-Ghazali, Ma ary al-Quds fi Madarij Marifat al-Nafs (Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah,
1988), 45. In al-Risalah al-Luduniyyah he referred to the soul as a perfect simple substance (al-

123
majority of the mutakallimun. Admitting that the existence of this class might

cause a commonality with God in terms of the ne ation of being in a direction and

CfQ
space, he nevertheless affirmed that this does not necessarily imply that those

under this class are similar to God, since the commonality in negation does not
necessitate resemblance (al-istbtirak fi al-sulfb la yaqtadi al-tamatbul).5Q Al-

Razi, therefore, maintained the existence of another class other than substance

and accidents among originated things, which does not conform to the principle of

the Karramiyyab. Despite this disagreement, both al-Razi and the majority of the

mutakallimun, nonetheless, reed that in the case of God, He is above and

beyond all these categories. Hence, although the third category is similar to God

in that it neither occupies space nor resides in something that occupies space, it is

still something different in reality from God.

The point that should be emphasized here is that in response to the

Musbabbibab’s view, al-Razi stressed the fact that if among originated beings

there is such an existent which is neither contained in space nor positioned in any

direction, what more of God who is the Creator of all these things. To say that

God is neither inside nor outside the world is not a contradiction since God is in a

category by itself which is above and beyond the category and genus of originated

beings. This fact reminds us of the philosophers’ view that since God is simple

(ba sit) and He is not a genus under which different species are classified, He

cannot, therefore, be defined.50


51

THE CAUSE OF THE PRINCIPLE (ILLAT AL-HUKM)

Among the problems raised by al-Razi amid his polemics with the

anthropomorphists is the confusion regarding the cause of the principle held by

them: Is it origination or existence that makes substance and accidents as they

jawhar al-kamil al-fard). Al-Ghazali, al-Risalah al-Laduniyyah, trans. Margaret Smith, Journal of
the Royal Asiatic Society (JRAS), part 2 (April, 1938): 194.
50 Muhassal, 92.
51 Tahafiit, 125.

124
are? As mentioned before, the anthropomorphists were of the view that the cause

of the principle is existence. Hence, since God is an existent, He is also applicable

under this principle. Al-Razi noticed that the Karramiyyah confused the problem

of the cause of the principle when they assumed that substance and accidents are

brought into being by a sin cause while both of them, to say the least, are
different categories caused by different causes.52 53
The fact that substance is

described as that which is distinct from each other in a direction while accident is

defined as that which subsists in the other, shows that both of them are different

and they were brought into being by different causes. Hence, it is true to say that

substance is described as such because of its specific nature as substance and,

similarly, accident is described as such because of its specific nature as accident.

Even if we accept that they cannot be caused by their specific nature of

being substance and accident, al-Razi maintained that we still cannot say for

certain that they must be caused either by existence or origination. There mi

be other causes apart from these two which must be further investigated. “Not

finding something” argued al-Razi, “that does not mean that it does not exist”

(irma adama al-wijdan layadullu ala adam al-wujud) ,54

Although substance and accident are different from each other through

their specific nature, they are nevertheless similar in terms of their bein

CfQ
originated. God, on the other hand, is different from both of them through the

fact that He is eternal, not originated. This is, according to al-Razi, a strong basis

for saying that the cause of this principle is origination rather than existence and

that God, due to His difference from originated beings, is not included in this
principle.55

Among the reasons given by the Karramiyyah as to why they preferred

existence (al-wujud) over origination (al-huduth) is that the principle may be

52 Asas, 75.
53 Ibid.
54 Ibid., 75.
55 Ibid., 76.

125
difficult to be established since we may not know whether in totality something is

originated or not and the ignorance of the originated things will lead to the

ignorance of the principle itself:

If the basis of the principle is the origination, then the ignorance of


the origination of something will necessitate the ignorance of the
principle.56

Nevertheless, to al-Razi, this argument is unacceptable since not knowing

whether something is originated or not will not necessarily lead to the ignorance

of the principle. We would still know the occurrence of the symptoms of some

diseases, for example, although we do not know their causes. Hence, the

ignorance of the cause does not necessarily lead to the ignorance of the effect.

Furthermore, if the ignorance of the cause leads to the ignorance of the effect, it

follows logically that the knowledge of the cause necessitates the knowledge of

the effect. In this case, if existence (al-wujutT) is the cause of things in the visible

world being in a direction, then it is known that everything that exists must be in

direction. However, the majority of the People of Unity (ahi al-tawhia) know

that God exists, yet it does not logically follow that they do know that God is in a
This shows that origination is still the cause and basis of the
specific direction.57 58

principle since it is the only aspect that is shared by jawhar and a rad yet is not

shared by God. Origination, in other words, becomes the differentia between the
co
existence of these two divisions and the existence of God.

Supposing that we agree with the Karramiyyah that existence is the basis

of the principle, al-Razi stressed the fact that existence is not equivocal. There is

still a difference between the existence of corporeal things and the existence of

God. The similarity is only in terms of words (ishtirak lafzi). Al-Razi clarified

further:

56 Ibid.
57 Ibid., 77.
58 Ibid., 76.

126
The Karramiyyah cannot say that the existence of the hidden
(gha’ib) and the perceptible (shahid) is one. If that is the case, it will
lead to the fact that the nature of God is similar with the originated
things from all aspects, or the fact that His existence is additional to
His essence, and they [Karramiyyah] do not agree with these two
points. 59

Furthermore, if existence becomes the cause of this principle of direction,

it follows that even substance, or accident, since they exist, can be further divided

into that which subsists in the other or is distinct from it in a direction which is

clearly impossible. If the Karrarniyyah replied that it is due to the specific nature

of substance and accident that prevents them from being further divided, al-Razi

would have responded by saying that the same is the case with God that it is due
to the specific nature of God that prevents Him from falling into this principle.59
60

Through this rigorous dialectical argumentation, al-Razi gave no possible

room for the Karramiyyah to extend their arguments in defending this principle.

NEGATION OF THE SPATIAL AND BODILY ASPECTS WITH REGARD


TO GOD

Apart from invalidating the principle of the Karramiyyah, al-Razi put forward

strong rational proofs for denying the claim that God is a body and that He resides

in a space, two presuppositions that underlie the views of the Karramiyyah and

the Hanabilah. In order to refute the notion of body in regard to God, al-Razi

examined the notion of occupying space (al-hayyiz) as the fundamental principle

of the existence of body (al-jism) and atom (al-jawhar). Body, as an extension of

atoms, must be in a space in order for it to exist. Therefore, if the notion of space

can be invalidated with application to God, so also will the notion of body:

If we have proved that God the Most Exalted does not occupy space
(laysa bi mutahayyiz}, we have actually proved that He is neither

59 Ibid., 77.
60 Ibid, 77-78.

127
body nor an atom (jawbar fara). For, that which occupies space, if
it is divisible, it is a body, while if it is indivisible it is an atom.61

CHARACTERISTICS OF SPATIAL BODIES

In his refutation of this notion of space, al-Razi argued that since the nature of

spatial bodies (mutahayyizat) is absolutely different from that of God, it is

impossible for all of them to be ascribed to God. He enumerated few basic

characteristics of spatial bodies and subsequently argued that these characteristics

are impossible to be applied to God. The first characteristic of spatial bodies is that

they are essentially homogeneous in their quiddity as a whole (mutamathilayn fi

tamam al-mahiyyahf By asserting that they are similar in quiddity as a whole,

al-Razi was implying that ‘occupying space’ is not an accidental attribute of atoms

and bodies, but rather an essential one, the absence of which will lead to the denial

of both. In other words, it constitutes the very nature of body. If God occupies

space, His quiddity will definitely be similar to them as a whole (fi tamam al-

mahiyyabf

occupying space (mutahayyiziyyah) is not an attribute (sifab) of


something [body]. It is [indeed] the essence itself (nafs al-zat).
Therefore, it is necessary that things which are similar in terms of
occupying space, are also similar in their essences.62

This position also serves as a rejection to an argument by the Karr amiyyah

that God might be similar with other bodies in the attribute of occupying space

but differs with them in other essential attributes. For the Karramiyyah,

occupying space was only an accidental attribute of God, which is also shared by

other bodies and there are still many essential attributes of God that do not

occupy space which differentiate God from bodies. For al-Razi, this view was

untenable since it is not possible for two things to be similar in terms of

occupying space yet different in other specific attributes that have nothing to do

61 Ibid., 45.
62 Ibid., 46.

128
with occupying space. It is also implausible to say, as claimed by the

Karramiyyah, that it is the specific attribute which is essential compared to

occupying space, for it is impossible for these essential attributes to be associated

with occupying space without leading it also to becoming something that occupies

space. In other words, if God is characterized by an essential attribute which does

not occupy space, He cannot be characterized with the attribute of occupying

space without this essential attribute also being ‘infected’ by the attribute of

occupying space:

[as to] the specific [essential] attribute which is not [supposed] to be


bound by space and direction, we will say that it is impossible for
‘occupying space’ to be its attribute by which it subsists (qalmah
biha) because this essential attribute is not specified in space and
directions. Occupying space [on the other hand] cannot be conceived
unless through the notion of direction. Hence, that which
necessarily occurs in direction cannot take place on something whose
occurrence in a direction is impossible.63

Through this refutation, al-Razi has forcibly asserted that occupying space

(mutaJiayyiziyyah) is an essential attribute of bodies and atoms and consequently

denied the possibility of God being attributed by it due to the fact that it will lead

to the conclusion that God is a body. Having affirmed this, al-Razi further

advanced the implications of God being homogeneous in His quiddity as a whole

with bodies:

i) that among the nature of two homogeneous entities is that they

will also be similar in their concomitant attributes (lawazim). It

follows that if God is eternal, bodies are also eternal, while if

bodies are originated, God is also originated.

ii) If God is homo eneous with bodies, some attributes such as


CfQ

Knowledge, Power and Life are possible to be deprived from Him

and they are only possibilities in regard to His essence as in the

63 Ibid, 46.

129
case with bodies. This will imply that God needs determinant

(mukhassis) in order to bring these attributes into existence

which is impossible.

iii) If God’s essence is homo eneous to bodies, then, like bodies, God

CfQ
will be subject to movement and rest. Being receptive to

movement and rest (qabilah li al-harakah wa al-sukuri) is the

attribute of originated things. Since God is eternal, He cannot be

attributed with this attribute.

iv) Being similar to bodies implies that God is composed of units and

every unit will be similar to each other, whereas composition is


impossible to God.64

The second characteristic of things that occupy space is that they are finite

(mutanahiyah). They are so because all things that occupy space have an extent

in space and time which increases and decreases.65 66An atom, for example, is a

finite, indivisible entity which when attached to another will constitute a body.

The body, likewise, is characterized essentially by its extension which also has

capacity to increase and decrease. Al-Razi further argued that every finite thing

is, in turn, possible (mumkiiT) because their nature to increase and decrease is a

possibility. Finally, al-Razi argued that every possible thing is originated because

they are equally predisposed to the possibility of increasing and decreasing, hence

they are in need of a determinant (al-mu’thir) or an originator which is God.67

64 Ibid., 47.
65 Ibid.
66 The majority of the mutakallimun held that a body is composed of a finite number of indivisible
parts that are called atoms (jawhar fard). The number of atoms to constitute a body is, however, a
point of contention among them. To the Ashairah, for, example, it consists of a minimum of two
atoms. Apart from this view of the majority, there were also other theories on the composition of
bodies; a) bodies are composed of an actually infinite number of parts, as held by al-Nazzam; b)
bodies are not composite but they are infinitely divisible; c) bodies are composite but their division
never reaches an utmost limit beyond which no further division is possible. Dhanani, Physical
Theory, 122, 152 n.34.
67 Asas, 48.

130
This line of argument is used by other mutakallimun, especially the Ashairah to

prove that body is by nature originated.

Havin argued that bodies are by nature originated, it is therefore,

CfQ
according to al-Razi, impossible to ascribe God as occupying space since this will

lead to the conclusion that He is finite, possible and originated. This clearly

contradicts the nature of God, who is the originator and eternal.

The third characteristic of things that occupy space is that they are

logically composite hence their constituents are in need of each other. The

explanation is as follows: Bodies are similar to each other in terms of occupying

space but they are different in their individuality (tashakhkbuf). In this case

(different in individuality), occupying space becomes genus under which the

species come. If God is a body, His essence, as one of the species, will therefore

be composed of genus and differentia which is impossible. If, on the other hand,

there is no difference in their individuality, then the occupying space becomes

species under which are individuals and God, in this case, will be one of the

individuals. In both cases, there is an element of dependency, which is improper

to God. For every composition will be in need of others (kullu murakkab fa buwa
muftaqir ila ghairihf).6 This is contrary to God’s nature of being simple (basif).

If the third characteristic refers to logical composition, the fourth

characteristic of spatial bodies is that they are physically composites. For a thing

that occupies space, one side of it will be different from the other side, and all

things with this nature are divisible, and every divisible thing is composite. Since

God’s essence is simple, divisibility will be in contradiction with His nature. Even

if there is such a thin as the unitary atom (al-jawhar al-farcT) as claimed by the
CfQ

atomists, it still cannot be ascribed to God since this will relegate God to being

very small thing in size, and this is a humiliation (al-faqarah). In other words,

the notion of simplicity referred to God is not physical, like the atom. Hence,

69 Ibid.

131
composition, both in terms of logical and physical, is impossible with regards to

God.

The view that God can be specified in space and direction will lead to the

same conclusion of the philosophers, namely, the eternity of the world. This is so

because if God is specified by these two aspects, He must be so specified a parte

ante and parte post (azalan wa abadan) parallel with the eternity of His essence.

However, this will assume that space and direction are equally eternal, which is

impossible. In this case, al-Razi observed some similarity between this position of

the mushabbihab with the views of the believers in the eternity of time

(dabriyyun) who viewed that God is prior to the world in infinite time (muddab

gbayr mutanabiyab) which consequently led to their erroneous view that time is
eternal and hence God is in time and space.70 71 72

In sum, by holding the view that God must be bound to a particular

direction in relation to the world, the musbabbibab reduced the divine reality to

the sensible world, which is conceived through their fancy and imagination, not

through reason:

The judgment which is based on fancy and imagination is


unacceptable with regard to God’s essence and His attributes...This is
our position, the People of Divine Unity and Transcendence (abl al-
Tawhfd wa al-Tanzih) who reject the judgment based on fancy and
imagination with re ard to the essence of God and His attributes.
CfQ

And this is the correct method and the straight way.

Al-Razi concluded his rational argument by quoting Aristotle that whoever

wishes to venture into the knowledge of the divine should prepare himself with

new nature (fitratan ukbra). By a new nature he meant a new kind of thinking

different from that which he used in discussing knowledge regarding physical

70 Ibid., 22.
71 Ibid.
72 Ibid., 24.

132
things. We cannot therefore employ the same reasoning that is used in

understanding the empirical world in understanding the metaphysical realm.

TEXTUAL ARGUMENTS ON THE TRANSCENDENCE OF GOD

Based on numerous verses of the Qur’an and the Prophetic traditions that lay

stress on Divine transcendence, al-Razi expounded various arguments in his

response to the views of the musbabbibab. Since the notion of God upheld by the

musbabbibab, as we have alluded to before, centered around the notion of the

body, al-Razi, in enumerating these Qur’anic verses, intended to show that the

conception of God as expounded in the Qur’an runs counter to the idea of ‘body’

as understood in the science of physics (tabiiyyat), a discipline in which he was

also well-versed. Among the aspects emphasized by the Qur’an that run contrary

to the notion of the body are as follows:

i) The Qur’an upholds the unity and oneness of God while the notion of

body implies multiplicity.

ii) The Qur’an insists on the difference between God and other beings

while the mujassimab’s conception of God leads to a similarity between

them.

iii) God, in the Qur’an, is described as the source of need and dependence

while the notion of body implies dependency.

iv) The Qur an infers that there is no chan in God’s essence whereas

body implies change.

v) God as described in the Qur’an is eternal while bodies will perish.

Surat al-Ikhlas

Al-Razi identified Surat al-Ikblas as the strongest proof of the Qur’an in negating

the idea of corporeality and spatiality of the deity. He maintained that this verse is

among the verses with well-established meanings (jnuhkamat} and whose

133
argument is demonstrative, since it is an answer revealed by God to a specific

question posed by the unbelievers to the Prophet concerning the nature of God.73

The strong affirmation in the form of a command to the Prophet, “Qul huwa

Allabu a had” (Say, He is Allah the One and Only!) at the outset of this chapter

proves the total negation of attributes contradictory to divine unity.

The term ahad, according to al-Razi, denies three things: bodily aspect

(jismiyyah), space (al-hayyiz) and direction (al-jibab). It negates the notion of

body since a body, as construed in the field of physics, is composed, at least, of

two atoms (jawbarayn). Every body possesses at least two different sides which

are distinct to each other, e.g., left and right, up and down, front and back. This

will mean that it is divisible while something divisible is not one and it is against

the principle of divine unity. To the question whether God can be said to be

similar to an atom (Jawbar al-fard) which is also one and cannot be further

divided (al-juz’alladbi la yatajazza9), al-Razi replied that it is still impossible. For

the One (a had) does not only mean indivisible but also something without an
opposite (ddd) and equal (nzdd).74 If God is one like an atom, He can still be

similar to other atoms since every atom is homogeneous and this will violate the

principle of divine unity. It is to this fact, according to al-Razi, that the last verse

of this chapter, “There is none like unto Him” (wa lam yakun labukufuan ahad.)
refers.75 Elsewhere, al-Razi ridiculed the idea of the atomistic nature of the God of

the Karramiyyab who implied God as small and paltry (haqarab).76 As to the

denial of space and direction, al-Razi maintained that the notion of space and

direction is a direct concomitant of the notion of body and atom. For every thing

that is attributed by space and direction, if it is divisible, it is a body, otherwise it

73 Ibid, 30.
74 Ibid, 31.
75 Ibid.
76 Ibid, 20.

134
is an atom. Since the notion of body has earlier been disproved through the

explanation of a had, both space and direction, as concomitants, are false.77

The principle that God is exalted and free from any need or reliance upon

any other than Him is inherent in the notion of al-Samad in the second verse of

the chapter (Allah al-Samad). Al-Samad, according to al-Razi, conveys two basic

meanings. First, as iven by Ibn Abbas, it means a master on whom all things

CfQ
depend in their needs (al-sayyid al-masmud ilaybi fi al-mwatj). Second, it

denotes something compact and not hollow (jawf), or a solid stone out of which

nothin can emerge nor enter.78 The first meaning, according to al-Razi, refers to
CfQ

relative attributes (al-sifat al-idafiyyah), that God is a Lord who is being sought in

every need and every need is not accomplished except through Him, while the

second indicates the negative attribute (sifat salbiyyab), that, as the Necessary

Existent, changes will not occur in the essence and attributes of God.79 80
In relation

to that, al-Razi enumerates various attributes given by the mufassirun which

subsumed under both generic meanings. For example, the meanings which come

under the first one (a Master) are: that God is All-Knowing, the Most Forbearing,

the Creator of all thin the Object of wishes (ragba’ib) and help-seeking, the
CTQ

One and All-Glorious. As to the second meaning, the attributes included that He

is Self-sufficient (Ghani), One who does not eat and drink, and One who endures

when all creatures perish. 80

Resorting to the discussion of the mushabbihah, al-Razi maintained that

with the attribute of al-Samad, it is impossible for God to be a body since a body

will imply dependency on the atoms in the body, while al-Samad is free from any

need. Further, if God has organs as claimed by the musbabbihab, He will

definitely be in need of these organs. Neither can al-Samad run parallel with the

notion of space or direction since He will be in need of space and direction for His

77 Ibid., 31.
78 Tafsir, vol. 11, 362.
79 Ibid.
80 Ibid, 362-363.

135
existence. In fact, the condition of ‘in need of something else’ which is embedded

in the notion of body will run contrary to other divine attributes mentioned in the

verses of the Qur’an such as al-Gbanf (the Rich or the ‘Free of all wants’) in the

verse “But Allah is free of all wants, and it is you that are needy”81 and the

attribute of al-Qayyum (self-subsisting) as in the verse “Allah, there is no God

but He, the Living, the Self-subsisting.”82

The foliowin verse in the same chapter which reads “There is none like
CfQ
unto Him” (lam yakun labu kufuwan a had) is another decisive proof which can

disqualify the musbabbibab's idea of an anthropomorphic God. The denial of the

idea of kufu’ (likeness), or mitbl as mentioned in another famous verse, “laysa ka

mitblibf sbay” or nidd as in the verse “Then set not up rivals (andad) unto Allah
when you know”83 is incongruent with the notion of body. If God is a body,

stated al-Razi, He will then resemble other bodies in their characteristics:

If God Almighty is a substance (jawbar), He will resemble other


substances, and similarly all substances will become duplicates of
Him. If He [on the other hand] is a body, He will become
composition of atoms...Then it is affirmed that this chapter (Surat
al-Ikhlas) is an obvious proof that God is not a body nor a substance,
neither does He reside in a place or direction.84

This textual refutation is based on the principles of physics, which we have

discussed, that all bodies resemble each other (al-ajsam mutamdtbilab) in their

essence, a point which al-Razi continually emphasized in his attack on the

anthropomorphists. This resemblance will mean that whatever major differences

we may observe in terms of the attributes or accidents among bodies (ajsarri),


>

their essences are still the same. man and a horse may look very different in

81 Al-Qur’an, Muhammad 47:38.


82 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:255.
83 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah, 2:22.
Asas, 33.

136
their appearance and accidental characteristics, yet in terms of their essence, as
or
bodies, they are similar.

Based on the above premise, al-Razi affirmed that the difference between

God and man is an essential difference, or to use his terms, difference in

quiddity as a whole (fftamam al-mabiyyab). This affirmation also serves as an

answer to the doubt raised by the musbabbibab as to why it is impossible for God

to be similar to human bein as a body but different in other major attributes,

CrQ
CZ)
just like a man is the same as a horse in terms of their ‘animality’ but different in

some basic attributes. By this, the mushabbihah attempted to show that the

difference between God and man is only in degree but not in kind. A somewhat

similar view was propounded by Abu Hashim, Mu tazili, who regarded the

essence of God as being similar to other essences in their essential nature but only
differ in terms of mode (A^/).87 Ibn Sina, one of the most important philosophers
85 86

of Islam, was recorded by al-Razi as holding the view that the essence of God is

similar to the essence of other than He. This follows from his view that God’s

essence is identical with His existence and existence is something that is shared by

all existents (al-mawj udat). The difference between them is that God’s existence
is essential while that of others are accidental.88 To all the above views, al-Razi

replied that God cannot be said to be similar with other than He in terms of

essences and different with them only through their specific attributes because it

implies that there is a composition in God since those things which are similar are
from those which are different.89 Furthermore, the status of these specific

attributes in God will become possible not essential, while possible things need

determiner to be actualized:

85 Ibid., 35.
86 Ibid.
87 Mu ha sal, 154. Four modes, according to Abu Hashim, that make God different from others, are
the modes of Living (al-Hayyah), Knowing (al- Alimiyyah), Existent (al-Mawj udiyyah) and
Powerful (al-Qadiriyyab).
88 Ibid.
89 Asas, 36.

137
Two essences (al-dbatari), if they are similar, their specific attributes
will be among the possible things (al-j a*iz at), not necessary (al-
wajibat), since things which are similar in essence and quiddity as a
whole (mutamatbilab ft tamam al-dbat wa al-mabiyab) will not
[necessarily] differ in concomitants (al-lawazim). If the Creator is a
body, His specific attributes [which He differs from other than Him]
will be among possible things. If this is the case, it follows that He
is in need of a governor or a determiner. This will falsify His nature
of being God of the world.90

The strong disavowal of any resemblance between God and anything other

than He stressed by the verses discussed earlier signifies the pertinent fact that

not only can God be ascribed to any notion of body, but also the knowledge of the

essence and quiddity (mahiyyab) of God is beyond the reach of human

comprehension. To this point also, al-Razi related the story of Prophet Moses

and Abraham who were posed with the same questions regarding the nature of

God. Prophet Moses, for example, was asked by Firaun on the quiddity of his

Lord through the question “what is your Lord (ma rabbuka)?"91 92


to which, he

answered by explaining the attributes of God, “that He is the Creator of human

beings and their administrator, that He is the Creator of both the heavens and the

earth and all between them (gala rabb al-samawat wa al-ard wa ma bayna

huma).99 This proves that there is no answer to the question of the divine

essence since it is only known to God. As in the case of Prophet Abraham whose

questions rather came introspectively through his skepticism—in his inquisition

of the nature of God—on the changes that occur in the rising and setting of the

stars and the moon, he came to the conclusion that those in which changes occur,
as that which occur in the case of the body, are not fit to be attributed to God.93

The failure of humankind to know the essence of God is also upheld by a number

of Prophetic traditions such as the one which says, “I cannot enumerate your

90 Asas, 36.
91 Al-Qur’an, al-Shu ara’ 26:23.
92 Al-Qur’an, al-Shu'ara’ 26:24.
93 Asas, 33-35. It refers to the story of Prophet Ibrahim in the Qur’an, al-An am 6:75-79.

138
Praise, You are as You praise yourself” (la \ihsi thana’an alayka anta kama

athnayta ala nafsika).94 Another Hadith from Ibn 'Abbas, “Think about the

creation of Allah but do not indulge in speculating on the Nature of God”

(tafakkaruffkhalq Allah wala tatafakkaruft Allah)95

The notion of the body also contradicts other scriptural proofs, namely, the

description of God in the verse, “He is Allah, the Creator (al-Khaliq), The Maker

(al-Barf), The Bestower of forms (al-Musawwir), to Him belong the Most

Beautiful Names.”96 The attribute al-Khaliq connotes the meaning of Estimator

(al-Muqaddir), the One who sets limits to something. If God is a body, He will

be finite and every finite thing will have a limit. Thus, it is impossible for God to

set a limit to Himself. Every finite thing also possesses different aspects of

limitation. It is therefore impossible for God, who describes Himself as the


Q7
Bestower of forms, to limit himself in a form.

Another direct scriptural argument used by al-Razi in attacking the

anthropomorphists is the verse “But they shall not encompass Him with their

knowledg ” 8 and the verse “No vision can grasp Him”99 both of which clearly

prove that God is beyond any measurement (miqdar), shape (shakl) and form

(surah). The mushabbihah may argue usin the first verse, that since God’s body
CfQ

is great in size, their knowledge could not therefore encompass Him. To this

assumption, al-Razi replied that the same may apply to the heavens and the

mountains and oceans, whose size cannot be encompassed by human

knowledge.100

94 Muslim, “Solat” Sahih, no. 1090, vol. 4, 426.


95 Al-Zabidi, Ithaf al-Sadat al-Muttaqih bi Sbarh Ihya’ Ulum al-Dfn (Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-
‘Ilmiyyah, n.d.), vol. 13, 307.
96 Al-Qur’an, al-Hashar 59:24.
91 Asas, 38.
98 Al-Qur’an, Taha 20:110.
99 Al-Qur’an, al-An am 6:103.
100 Asas, 39,

139
CHAPTER FOUR

MUHKAMAT, MUTASHABIHAT, AND THE ROLE OF


TA WIL IN RAZT’S THOUGHT

INTRODUCTION

In the preceding chapter, we have examined how al-Razi established strong

foundation for the divine transcendence in Islam through both rational and

traditional proofs. This foundation serves as a substantial ground for rejecting

any kind of anthropomorphic implication in the understanding of Qur’anic verses

and Prophetic traditions which bear anthropomorphic expressions. The next

question, which is the subject of this chapter, is the implication of this rejection

in al-Razi’s treatment of the anthropomorphic verses. How does al-Razi deal

with the meaning of the mutashabihdt verses? If the Qur’an is described as

being a clear message to humankind, what is the position of those ambiguous

verses in contributing to the clarity of the message of the Qur’an? How should

the descriptions of God, which appear contradictory to rational principles, be

comprehended? What is al-Razi’s position on ta \vil which is commonly viewed as

an alternative way of explaining the meaning of anthropomorphic verses?

THE MUHKAMAT AND MUTASHABIHAT IN THE QUR’AN

The term muhkam is derived from the past participle noun ‘abkama’, which
means to prevent something from corruption (mariabu min al-fasad).1 It implies

something that is made or rendered firm, stable and strong or held secured from
falling to pieces.2 3 According to al-Razi, if one says in Arabic, ‘bakamtu’ or

‘abkamtu,’ he means ‘I resist’ (radadtu) or ‘I prevent’ (manatu). Hence,

1 Ibn Manzur, vol. 12, 143.


2 Edward William Lane, Arabic-English Lexicon (Bayrut: Librarie Du Liban, 1980), vol. 2, 618.
3 Asas , 203.

140
judge (hakim) is the one who prevents injustice from the hands of the unjust,

while a firm building (bind’ muhkam) is a strong structure that withstands the

forces of nature.4 In the Qur’anic context, dydtun muhkamdtun refer to those

verses whose lexical meaning is secured, fixed from further change and

alteration. This means that their meanings are clear and obvious not only in

terms of their linguistic and literal implications but also in terms of the

commands and directions these verses convey such that they neither need further

interpretation in order to be understood nor any proof to be ascertained.

Mutashabih, on the other hand, comes from the root tashabaha which

denotes likeness (al-mithl), similarity and conformity of something to another.5

It means something is similar or resembles another thing to such a manner that it

is difficult to differentiate between the two. It also means something

‘ambiguous’ which is a result of something being similar to another thing.6

According to Ibn Manzur, mutashabih means something whose meaning cannot

be obtained from its word (ma yutalaqqa manahu min lafzihi). This meaning,

added Ibn Manzur, carries two implications: first, that the meaning can only be

known with reference to those verses with established meaning (idha rudda ila
al-muhkam); second, that the meaning cannot be known completely.7 According

to al-Razi, when the Qur’an refers to the Jews’ excuse upon being ordered by

Prophet Moses to sacrifice a specific kind of heifer that “all heifers are alike to

4 Ibid.
5 Ibn Manzur, vol. 13, 504; Lane, vol. 4, 1500. In the Qur’an, it refers to those verses that are
equivocal or ambiguous; i.e., susceptible to different interpretations, or verses unintelligible such
as the commencements of many of the chapters. Mutashabih also means that of which the
meaning is not to be learned from its words; and this is of two sorts: i) one is that of which the
meaning is known by referring it to what is termed muhkam; ii) that of which the knowledge of
its real meaning is not attainable in any way. Ibid.
6 See Leah Kinberg, “Muhkamat and Mutashabihat (Koran 3/7): Implication of a Koranic Pair of
Terms in Medieval Exegesis,” ARABICA, no. XXXV (1988):144. In this article, the author
analyses the definitions given by traditional Muslim scholars and mufassirun and concludes that
both ‘similar’ and ‘ambiguous’ are two basic meanings given by scholars to the mutashabih.
7 Ibn Manzur, Lisan al-Arab, vol. 13, 505.

141
us” (inna al-baqara tasbabaha calayna), 8 this would mean that to the Jews, the

heifers looked the same so that they could not differentiate between them.9 10
The

same ambiguity is meant in the Hadith which says that ambiguous matters

(mutasbabibat) are between two clear positions: the permissible (al-halal) and
the prohibited (al-baram)^

QUR’ANIC ORIGIN: SURAH AL IMRAN, VERSE 7

The root from which the whole discussion regarding the mubkamat and

mutasbabibat verses of the Qur’an sprang, is the verse in Surat Al 'Imran, which

clearly delineates these two kinds of Qur’anic verses:

He it is Who has sent down to you the Book; In it are verses basic
or fundamental (of established meaning i.e., mubkamat); They are
the foundation of the Book; Others are not of well established
meaning (mutasbabibat). But those in whose hearts is perversity
follow the part thereof that is not well- established meanin
Seeking discord, and searching for its hidden meanings, but no one
knows its true meanings except Allah. And those who are firmly
grounded in knowledge say: ‘We believe in the Book; the whole of it
is from our Lord;” and none will grasp the Message except men of
understanding.11

8 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:70.


9 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:118. It also refers to the ambiguity in the hearts of the Jews due to
their doubt and inclination towards uncertainty to which the verse in Surah Al-'Imran refers.
According to Ibn 'Abbas, the Jews were those inclined towards the mutashabihat as they tried to
give metaphorical interpretations to the alphabets that occur in the beginning of certain verses in
the Qur’an. Tafsir, vol.3, 140.
10 Asas, 203. The Hadith that was reported by Nu'man bin Bashir goes: “I heard Allah’s
Messenger (may peace be upon him) as saying this: What is lawful is evident and what is
unlawful is evident, and in between them are the things doubtful which many people do not
know. So he who guards against doubtful things keeps his religion and honor blameless, and he
who indulges in doubtful things indulges, in fact, in unlawful things, just as a shepherd who
pastures his animals round a preserve will soon pasture them in it. Beware, every king has a
preserve, and the things Allah has declared unlawful are His preserves. Beware, in the body there
is a piece of flesh; if it is sound, the whole body is sound, and if it is corrupt the whole body is
corrupt, and hearken it is the heart.” Bukhari, “Kitab al-Buyu ”, no.2, vol.5, 11.
11 Al-Qur’an, Al 'Imran 3:7.

142
According the above verse, the first kind of Qur’anic verses are the well-

established ones (muhkamdt) whose meanings are stable and fixed, and the

second are the mutasbabibdt which are, on the contrary, not clear in meaning.

Apart from this classification, the verse also gives further explanation concerning

the nature of these two kinds of verses. The mubkamat are called the Principle

of the Book (Umm al-Kitab) which, according to al-Razi, means the root of the
Book (asl al-kitab) upon which the content of the whole book depends.12
13 The

Arabs used to call whatever takes similar course with the root as mother (umm)

just like they called the brain as the “mother of the head” (umm al-ra’s) and

Makkah as the “mother of villages” (Umm al-Qura).14 Al-Razi further

mentioned that there are two general views on the meaning of Umm al-Kitab.

First, it is the Preserved Tablet (Lawb Mahfuz) together with all the creations of

the celestial and lower spheres (al-alam al (ulwi wa al-alam al-sufli). This is

based on the Hadith, “There was a time when God existed and nothing was with

Him and He created tablets and wrote on it the states (ahwal) of all the creations

until the Day of Judgment.”15 Second, it refers to God’s knowledge, that God

knows everything existent and non-existent.16 Ibn Kathir, the famous

fourteenth century mufassir, interpreted the term Umm al-Kitab as being the

verses whose meanings are evident and clear in indication and which do not lead

to confusion. They are also the root (asl) from which inferences are drawn when

there are ambiguities in understanding other verses of the Qur’an.17 Other

mufassirurt maintained that these verses are called Umm al-Kitab since they lay

down the principles of Islam and contain the basis of the creed and law, the

12 The name Umm al-Kitab is also ascribed to the first chapter of the Qur’an, al-Fdtibah, mainly
due to the importance of its content.
13 Tafsir, vol. 7, 52.
14 Ibid.
15 Bukhari, 4:169
16 Tafsir, vol. 7, 52.
17 Ibn Kathir, Tafsir al-Qur’an al-'Azim (Bayrut:Dar Ihya’ al-Turath al-'Arabiy, 2000), vol.l,
354.

143
positive and prohibitory law, the basic duties, or the Islamic do ma.18 Based on

CfQ
these descriptions, they identified the muhkamat mainly with those verses which

contain God’s commands such as the performance of prayer, fasting and

pilgrimage. Ibn ‘Abbas, for example, indicated that the muhkamat are those

verses which abrogate other verses; verses which describe what are permissible
and forbidden, laws (hudud), judgments (ahkdrri) and obligations (fara’id).1

Another report also from Ibn ‘Abbas says that the muhkamat are the basic

principles of the Islamic way of life as contained in verses 151-153 of the Surat al-

Anam20 and the verses 23-2521 in Surat al-Isra’.22

As to the mutashabihdt, while their indication is in line with the


muhkamat, they also refer to other meanings.23 It is due to the multiple

meanings implied by these verses that the derivation of their meanings becomes

ambiguous. They are open to more than one way of interpretation. While one

interpretation may lead a believer to the meaning that suits him best and answers

his doubts, he, on the other hand, may be misled. Thus, the above verse in Surah

Al ‘Imran, in light of the two classifications, also indicates that those who are

18 Kinberg, “Muhkamat and Mutashabihat,” 151.


19 Ibn Kathir, vol.l., 354.
20 These verses, which are related to the basic principle of the Islamic way of life, reads as
follows: “Say: ‘Come, I will rehearse what Allah has really prohibited you from: join not anything
as equal with Him; be good to your parents; kill not your children on a plea of want. We provide
sustenance for you and for them; and come not near to shameful deeds whether open or secret.
Take not life which Allah has made sacred except by way of justice and law. This has He
commanded you that you may learn wisdom. Come not near to the orphan’s property except to
improve it, until he attains the age of full strength. Give measure and weight with full justice.
No burden do We place on any soul but that which it can bear. Whenever you speak, speak
justly even if a near relative is concerned; and fulfill the Covenant of Allah. Thus has He
commanded you that you may remember.”
21 The verses are: “Your Lord has decreed that you worship none but Him, and that you be kind
to parents. Whether one or both of them attain old age in your life, say not to them a word of
contempt, nor repel them but address them in terms of honour. [24] And out of kindness, lower
to them the wing of humility and say, ‘My Lord! Bestow on them your mercy even as they
cherished me in childhood’. [25] Your Lord knows best what is in your hearts; If you do deeds of
righteousness. Verily, He is Most forgiving to those who turn to Him again and again.”
22 Ibn Kathir, Tafstr al-Qur’an al-Azim, vol.l, 354.

144
inclined to follow the mutashdbihdt are blameworthy since vagaries in doubt will

lead them to uncertainty and a shaky foundation of belief and practice.

The mufassirurt identified the mutashdbihdt mainly with those

anthropomorphic verses whose meanings are ambiguous due to their resemblance

with human characteristics. Nevertheless, there were also others who associated

the mutashdbihdt with some equivocal words bearing legal implication, such us

the word lams al-nisa’ which can mean either to merely touch one’s wife or to
have sexual intercourse.24 Also linked to the mutashdbihdt are the alphabets

which occur at the outset of some chapters (fawdtih) in which a Muslim should

believe but not to act accordingly.25 Some others viewed mutashdbihdt as matters

whose realities cannot be grasped by people such as the appearance of the Day of

Resurrection, the condition in the Afterworld, rewards and punishment in the

Afterworld, the number of angels in Hell, the appearance of Dajjal before the

End of Days, the rising of the sun from the West, and the duration of the world

and its end.26 According to Kinberg, among all these mutashdbihdt matters, two

of the most crucial and controversial in Islam are the opening letters (fawdtih)

and the anthropomorphic attributes of God.27 28Despite these ambiguous and

controversial implications given by the mufassirun in discussing the meaning of

the mutashabihat, in a more extensive discussion, the inherent meanin of the


CfQ

term mutashdbihdt also conveys some positive meanings, that the verses

resemble one another in eloquence and they confirm each other in the message

they bear. They also resemble each other in beauty and truthfulness. All these

characteristics are ultimately the signs of the miraculous nature of the Qur’an. 28

While there seems to be some general agreement in identifying which

verses constitute the muhkamdt and mutashdbihdt in the field of law and

24 Hamka, Tafsir al-Azhar (Singapore: Pustaka Nasional, 1982), vol. 3, 710.


25 Kinberg, 150.
26 Ibid., 156.
27 Ibid, 156-157.
28 Ibid, 146.

145
jurisprudence, it is not so in the field of theology, particularly when it relates to

some controversial issues such as the issues of freedom and predetermination, the

createdness of the Qur’an and the Vision of God. Different schools have ascribed

verses which incline to their theological positions as muhkamdt, while for others,

these verses are mutashabihdt. “The Mutazilah," al-Razi related, “due to their

rational inclination, viewed the verse, fa man sba’a falyu’min wa man sha’a
falyakfur’ (let him who will, believe, and let him who will, reject)29 as muhkam,

while the verse lwa ma tasha’un ilia an yasha’ Allah’ (but you will not, except as

Allah wills) 30 as mutashabih while the Ashairah viewed the opposite.”31 32


Al-*

Ghazali, in his al-Mankhul min Taliqdt al-Usul listed six different schools

(madhahib) in the identification of muhkamdt and mutashabihdt:


c 32, c < 33
1) Wasil ibn 'Ata’ and 'Amru ibn 'Ubayd who viewed that
muhkam are the warnings of punishment (al-waid) that is
mentioned regarding immoral activities (al-jaralm) and major
sins (kabalr) while the mutashabih are verses about that
warning regarding minor sins (al-saghartr).
ii) Al- Asamm Mutazili jud who flourished under al-
Mu'tasim34 who said that the muhkam are the attributes of the
Prophet in the Taurdt and previous books, while the mutashabih
are his [anthropomorphic] attributes in the Qur’an.
iii) The views of some of the salaf who said that the mutashabih are
the alphabets, while the muhkam are the non-alphabets.
iv) The view of those who said that the mutashabih are verses
identified as abrogated and others are muhkam.

29 Al-Qur’an, al-Kahf, 18:29.


30 Al-Qur’an, al-Insan, 76:30.
31 Asas, 205.
32 His full name is Abu Huzayfah Wasil bin ‘Ata’ al-Ghazzali. He was a pupil of Hasan al-Basri
under whom he studied history and various branches of learning during the reigns of 'Abd al-
Malik b. Marwan and Hisham b. 'Abd al-Malik. He was highly esteemed amon the Mu'tazilah
tn

for his learning and culture. The Mutazilah were known to uphold the warnin of reward and
punishment as one of their main theological principles. Milal, 43-45.
3 He was a follower of Wasil bin 'Ata’ in the circle of the Mutazilah. A transmitter of Hadith
and well-known for his asceticism. He was an emissary of Yazid during the Ummayyad period
but afterwards he became a friend of Mansur whose imamate he accepted. Mansur once praised
him saying, ‘I threw grain out to the people and all gathered it up except 'Amr., Milal, 24,45.
34 Tritton, 126.

146
v) The views of another group of which Ibn Abbas was one who
said that the mutashabih are those verses which are difficult to
be understood by their literal meaning such as the verse
mentioning God being established on the throne (al-istiwa9).
vi) The view of al-Zujjaj who said that all the verses of the Qur’an
are muhkam except the verse of the Day of Resurrection (al-
-
Qiyamah).

LEGITIMACY OF INTERPRETING THE MUTASHABIHAT

The verse 7, Al cImran also becomes the point of contention and continuing

debate among scholars as to who really had the correct understanding of the

meaning of the ambiguous verses (dydt mutashabihat). The contention resulted

from the discord over the punctuation of the phrase in the previous verse of

Surah Al ‘Imran, the verse which says, “no one knows its true meanings except

Allah and those who are firmly grounded in knowledge...” (wa ma ya lam

ta \vtlahu ilia Allah wa al-rasikhun fi al-ilm). The contention is whether there is

punctuation between the word Allah and the phrase wa al-rasikhun fi al-‘ilm.

Those who maintained that the true meaning of the ambiguous verses is known

only to God would read the verse with punctuation separating the word ‘Allah’

and the phrase “those are firmly grounded in knowledge” as the ones who know

the meanin of the mutashabihat. Others took the particle waw as a


CfQ

conjunctive thereby ascribing the capacity of understanding and the right of

interpreting such a text not merely to God but also to those who are firmly

rooted in knowledge.

This debate concerning punctuation, as we shall see later, has deeper

implications for another discussion namely whether or not the meanin of the
CfQ

Qur’an is totally established and clear. Those who are of the view that there are

verses whose meanings are beyond the grasp of the human intellect agree with* *

35 Al-Ghazali, al-Mankbul min Taliqdt al-Usul, ed. Muhammad Hassan Haitu, (Dimashq: Dar
al-Fikr, 2nd edn, 1980), 170-172
36 This was the view of some important companions and linguists such as Ibn 'Abbas, 'A’ishah,
Malik b. Anas, al-Kisa’i and al-Farra’. Tafslr, vol. 3, 145.

147
the position that there is a punctuation in the middle of the sentence which, in

turn, means that even those who are deeply rooted in knowledge will not know

the true import of these verses. Therefore, we should leave the meanings of

these verses to God. While those who regard the whole content of the Qur’an as

established and clear, deny any punctuation in the sentence, thus affirming the

authority of those who are deeply rooted in knowledge to interpret the

mutashabihat verses. Al-Razi himself defended the view that the punctuation

should be after the phrase wa al-rasikhun fi al-(ilm, hence he agreed that not

only does God know the meaning of the mutashabihat, but so also do those who

are deeply rooted in knowledge. This is because it is improper for God to say

something he does not mean or only known to Him. Furthermore, God has

described the Qur’an as being a guidance (hudan) and clear illustration (bayari)
which presupposes that the meaning of the Qur’an can be understood.37

Nevertheless, in Asas, al-Razi elaborated upon the salaf position and their

reasons in restricting the knowledge of the meaning of the mutashabihat only to

God. The core argument of the salaf, according to al-Razi, was to affirm that the

true meaning of mutashabihat is not its apparent meaning and that we must

leave the meanings to God and not indulge in futile interpretations.38 Among

their reasons for leaving the meaning to God are:

i) that the inquiry into the meanings of the mutashabihat is


blameworthy as alluded to by verse seven in Surah Al-'Imran
mentioned before.
ii) those who are deeply rooted in knowledge are praised by God
due to their unshakeable belief in God’s knowledge (yaqulun
amanna billah).
iii) the view that the waw is conjunctive is not in line with the
Arabic science of eloquence (fasahah).
iv) if the knowledge of the meanings of the mutashabihat are also
known by those who were deeply rooted in knowledge, the

37 Al-Razi, al-Mahsul fi 'Ilm al-Usul, ed. Taha Jabir al-'Alwani (Bayrut: Mu’assasah al-Risalah,
1992), vol.l, 386.
38 Asus, 207.

148
Companions and the earlier generations who are nearer to the
Prophet would have narrated the meanings of these
anthropomorphic verses while this was not the case.

CAN THERE BE ANYTHING IN THE QUR’AN THAT IS BEYOND OUR


KNOWLEDGE?

The contention re arding mubkamat and mutashabibat also stems from

discourse regarding the clarity of the Qur’an, that is, the meaning of the Qur’an

wholly established and clear? Is it possible that there are verses or words in the

Quran whose meanin are beyond the knowledge of human beings and only

known to God? In answering these questions, Muslim scholars from the past,

according to al-Razi, were divided into two main groups: first, the mutakallimun

who agreed that all the contents of the Qur’an are established and understood,

and second, most of the jurists, traditionists (ahi al-hadith) and the sufis, who

disagreed with this view. The mutakallimun argued that if there is something in

the Qur’an which is beyond the comprehension of human beings, then the

Qur’an is, therefore, using a language that is not clear, thus contradicting the

very claim of the Qur’an that it is revealed in clear Arabic tongue (bi lisanin

39 Ibid., 211-213. In Tafsir, al-Razi elaborated further the arguments supporting the view of the
salaf that when a word yields a literal meaning and there is a stronger proof that the literal
meaning is not intended by God, what is left are various metaphorical meanings (majazat) of this
word. The selection of one meaning over the others can only be done based on linguistic
preference (tarjib at al-lughawiyyab), yet linguistic preference is conjectural and not
recommendable since the matter has to do with fundamental, specific issues and is not
conjectural. “It is unanimous among the Muslim scholars that conjectural sayings with regard to
God’s essence and attributes is not possible. Second, this verse is preceded by the condemnation of
God of those who seek interpretation (talab al-ta\vll al-mutasbabihat). Third, God’s praise of
those who are deeply rooted in knowledge and who put their faith in God on matters regarding
mutashabibat. Fourth, if there is a punctuation after the phrase al-rasikbun fi al-'ilm and the
next verse starts from the phrase yaqulun amanna bibi, it sounds strange linguistically especially
in terms of its eloquence (fasahah). Al-Razi also quoted the saying of Ibn 'Abbas that there are
four kinds of tafsir of the Qur’an: first, that which everyone knows; second, that which is known
only by the Arabs; third, that which is known by scholars; fourth, that which is known only by
God. The tafsir of the mutashabibat, according to al-Razi, is the fourth. Tafsir, vol. 3, 146.

149
‘arabiyyin mubin). Furthermore, since the Qur’an is a speech (kalam) whose

very meaning presupposes understanding (ifham), the absence of understanding

with re ard to some of the verses will therefore render the speech useless

CfQ
(‘abathari). 1 It is also unacceptable that the Prophet is commanded by God to

warn the people (li takun min al-mundharin), yet in doing so he was given
book with incomprehensible verses.43 42 there are numerous verses in the
40 41Since

Qur’an which urge humankind to contemplate the meaning of the Qur’an (e.g.,

afala yatadabbarun al-Qur’an),44 it is highly incongruous that they are asked to

contemplate verses which are not comprehensible to them. There are several

other phrases and terms which imply that the whole content of the Qur’an is

(clear book), tibyanan li


comprehensible, such as the phrase kitabun mubin45 46

kulli sbay ^(explaining all things), balagbun li al-nas47 (message for mankind)

and ma farratna fl al-kitab min sbay48 (nothing have We omitted from the

Book).

The second group, however, contested the view by saying that not all of

the verses of the Qur’an are meant to be understood by mankind. There are

some verses which are beyond comprehension. They substantiated their view by

drawing an analogy with the act of worship (flbadat). Just as in worshipping

God, there are some acts whose meaning and wisdom can be comprehended by

mankind such as prayer, fasting and almsgiving, while the wisdom of some

others cannot be comprehended such as pilgrimage, so also is the case with the

40 Al-Qur’an, al-Shu ara’ 26:195; Asas, 200.


41 Asas, 200.
42 “Verily this is a revelation from the Lord of the worlds. With it came down the spirit of faith
and truth. To your heart and mind, that you may admonish, in the perspicuous Arabic tongue,”
Al-Qur’an, al-Shu'ara’ 26:195.
43 Asas, 197.
44 Al-Qur’an, Muhammad 47:24; Al-Qur’an, al-Nisa’ 4;82.
45 Al-Qur’an, al-Ma’idah 5:15.
46 Al-Qur’an, al-Nahl 16:89.
47 Al-Qur’an, Ibrahim 14:52.
48 Al-Qur’an, al-An'am 6:38.

150
verses in the Qur’an. There are kinds of speech whose meanings are known

while there are others which are not. The only wisdom for the latter, as in the

case of ‘ibadaf is for the glorification (tazim) and total submission to God

(kamal al-inqiyadf49 Thus, the Juqnbd’and the muhaddithun believed that the

content of the Qur’an, in this case, is divided into two: those whose meanings are

known by human beings and those which are not and whose meaning can only

be known to God. The most obvious proof according to them for this view is the

abbreviated alphabets at the beginnin of some chapters of the Qur an (al-huruf

CfQ
al-muqattaah) whose ultimate meanings are not known.50 Regarding these

alphabets, the fuqaha’ and the muhaddithun maintained that their meaning is

secret, concealed and hidden by God, based among others on the saying of Abu

Bakr that “in every book of God there is a secret and His secret in the Qur’an is

the letters at the beginning of the chapters,” and the saying of ‘All that “to every

book there is a safwah (quintessence) and the safwah of the Qur’an is the

alphabets (tafrdyf).”51 52

Al-Razi himself attempted his own discerning reconciliation with regard

to these two contending views by explaining the context in which both views can

be understood. Maintaining that while there are indications in the Qur’an that

the meaning of the Qur’an is in its entirety established (muhkam) such as “tilka

ayat al-kitab al-hakim” (These are the verses of the Clear Book), and “kitabun

49 Asas, 201.
50 As we may see later, the above position of both the mutakallimun, on the one hand, and the
fuqaha’ and the muhaddithun, on the other, left some impact on their view on taXvil. The
former, parallel with their view that the totality of the Qur’an is established in meaning, pushed
for an allegorical interpretation of those verses dealing with anthropomorphism, while the latter
were satisfied with the position of tafwid, that is, to leave the meaning to God.
51 Tafsir, vol.l, 250. As to the first group, they tried to interpret the meaning of these alphabets.
Al-Razi enumerated 21 different views of the mutakallimun in describing the meaning of these
alphabets, for example, that these alphabets are the name of the verses, the Name of God, part of
the divine names of God, name of the Qur’an, the divine attributes, divine acts.
52 Al-Qur’an, Yunus 10:1.

151
uhkimat aydtuhu” (This is a book with verses of established meanings), 3 there

are also verses which allude to the fact that the Qur’an as a whole, is ambiguous,

such as the verse “Allah has revealed the most beautiful Message in the form of

book, ambiguous and repeating (Allah rtazzala ahsana al-baditb kitaban

mutashabihan matbaniya}” 4 and “Had it been from other than Allah, they

would surely have found therein much discrepancy (yva law kana min ‘indi gbayr
53 Both
Allah lawajadu fihi ikhtilafan kathirany’55 54 assertions, al-Razi maintained,

must be understood from their contextual meanings. The first, namely that the

Qur’an is on the whole established in meaning would indicate that the words and

meanings of the Qur’an are true and established in terms of expression and

meanin compared to other speech. There is no other speech that


CfQ

commensurates to the Speech of God. To say that the Qur’an is in its totality

mutashdbih would mean that some of the verses resemble (yashbah) the other in

their merit (al-busn) and eloquence (fasahah) thus affirming instead of

contradicting each other.56 Al-Razi elsewhere agreed that the miracle of the

Qur’an basically related to its eloquence and not to other aspects such as its

method (uslub) or its account of unseen matters.57 Based on this accommodative

view, it seems that al-Razi was with the view that, as a whole, the meaning of

the Qur’an can be understood since its ambiguity refers to the resemblance in

terms of merit and eloquence.

53 Al-Qur’an, Hud 11:1.


54 Al-Qur’an, al-Zumar 39:23.
55 Al-Qur’an, al-Nisa’ 4:82.
56 Asas, 202; Tafsir , vol. 3, 137-138.
57 Al-Razi, Nihayat al-Ijaz ft Dirayat al-Fjaz, ed. Bakri Sheikh Amin (Bayrut: Dar al-'Ilm li al-
Malayin, 1985), 78-82.

152
LINGUISTIC AND TECHNICAL MEANING OF MUHKAM AND
MUTASHABIH

Linguistically, al-Razi explained that a word (lafz) which is the locus (mawduj
co
of a meaning can either have one or many meanings. If it has one meaning, it

is referred to as the explicit (nass). If, on the other hand, it contains more than

one meaning, it may fall into one of the following categories: i) if the first

meaning is the preponderating one (rajih) compared to the second, the first

meamn is called the manifest (zahir) while the second, the interpreted
CfQ

(mu’awwal). If it has two meanings that are equal and one of them does not

preponderate over the other, both of the meanings are called the equivocation

(mushtarak), and each meaning, when it refers to the individual meaning, is


called generality (mujmal).58
59

Based on this classification, in general, there are four kinds of words that

imply meanings: nass, zahir, muhwwal and mujmal. The first two, namely,

nass and zahir, share the quality of clarity and preponderance in meanin over

CfQ
the other two. The only difference is that a nass is free from contradiction

(manian min al-naqtd) in the sense that it will not go against another nass,

while zahir is open to contradiction as in the case of the mutashabihat verses. As

for mu ’awwal and mujmal, both share the lack of clarity in meaning, and in the

case of mujmal, both meanings are of equal status with one meaning not

preponderating over the other. While in the case of mu’awwal, there is

preponderance with regards to the shared meaning. Now, both nass and zahir are

considered muhkam since they carry a clear meaning (haml al-lafz ‘ala manahu

58 Asas, 203; Tafsir, vol. 3, 138; al-Razi, al-Mahsul, vol.l, 228. Cf. Al-Ghazali’s discussion on the
similar issue in Iysa A. Bello, The Medieval Controversy between Philosophy and Orthodoxy:
ma and Ta ’wil in the Conflict between al-Ghazali and Ibn Rushd (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1989), 52-
65.
59 Asas, 203.

153
al-rajih). Muhwwal and mujmal, due to their lack of clarity, are regarded as

mutashdbih.60

TERMS/VERSES IN THE QUR’AN

Muhkam Mutashabih

(clarity) (ambiguity)

nass - single meaning mu’awwal - less clearer in


(beyond contradiction) meaning
mujmal - similar meaning
zahir - preponderant meaning
(open to contradiction)

TA W IL AS A METHOD FOR UNDERSTANDING THE


MUTASHABIHAT
Since the mutashabihat verses carry an inherent ambiguity in their meanings,

their understandin is more problematic compared to the muhkamat. Their


CfQ

interpretation becomes more disputable as the Qur’an, the verse seven in Al

'Imran which we have consulted before, warns against preponderating on the

meaning of the mutashabihat.61 Yet, as we have alluded to before, for those who

are of the view that the meanin of these verses is known to those who are
CfQ

deeply rooted in knowledge, the arrival at their meanings can be attained through

the right interpretation by these people. Since the mutashabihat are mainly

identified with the anthropomorphic verses, whose literal understanding can lead

to meanings antithetical to divine transcendence, the need for their proper

assignment of meaning becomes more pressing. Hence, ta \vll, an allegorical and

60 Ibid., 204.
61 “Those in whose hearts is perversity follow the part thereof that is not well-established
meaning.” Al-Qur’an, Al 'Imran 3:7.

154
deeper interpretation of these verses, have become the most appropriate method

upheld by the majority of the later mutakallimun and mufassirun in solving this

problem.

Linguistically, ta’wil is derived from the verb awwala which means to

return. It refers to an effort to understand the meaning by referring back to the

origin. Al-Razi asserted that linguistically ta’wil refers to the tracing of the
meaning of a word to its origin and result (al-marjac wa al-masirf62 When

explaining verses in which the term ta’wil occurs such as the phrase wa ibtigba’a
ta'wilibi63 and the verse regarding Prophet Moses and Prophet Khidr “sa

’unabbi’uka bi ta’wil ma lam tastati ‘alaybi sabran (I will tell you the
interpretation of those things over which you were unable to hold patience),64 al-

Razi clarified that ta’wil in these two phrases means the inclination to inquire

into the explanation of the very intent of a term (ikbbar ‘arnma yarjiu ilaybi al-

lafz min al-mana).6 In this regard, ta’wil bears the same meanin as tafsir.

CfQ
This view is in line with the beginning of the development of tafsir where both

the terms tafsir and ta’wil were used interchangeably.66 67


However, both terms

later gained more intensive meaning, with the first referring to the intensive,

esoteric meaning of a verse, while the second to the exoteric and direct
67
meamn
C/Q

How, then, did al-Razi explain the method of ta’wil with regard to

deriving the meaning of the mutasbabibdt? The first is by underlining the need

for a clear method of classifying the muhkamat and mutasbabibdt. A word said

al-Razi:

62 Tafsir, vol.3, 145.


63 Al-Qur’an, Al ‘Imran 3:7.
64 Al-Qur’an, al-Kahf 18:78.
65 Tafsir, vol. 3, 145.
66 See Shalahudin Kafrawi, “Fakhr al-Din al-Razi’s Sources of Ta’wil: Between Revelation and
Reason,” Islamic Quarterly, vol. XLIII, no. 3 (1999):187.
67 A.J. Arberry, Revelation and Reason in Islam (London: George Allan & Unwin, 1957), 16;
Kafrawi, 187.

155
if it implies two meanings, one meaning is preponderating (rajih)
and the other is preponderated (marjuh). If we take the rajih and
leave the marjub, this situation is called muhkam. If, on the other
hand, we take the marjub and leave the rajih, we arrived at the
mutashabih.63

It is in the second one where the preponderated meaning is preferred that

ta \vil is done. But when do we re ard certain verses as mutashabihat in which

CfQ
ta \vil is needed? What are the situations in which the preponderated meaning

(marjub) should be preferred over the preponderating one (rajih)? Al-Razi

admitted the difficulty in identifiying the mutashabihat for it has been disputed
by many scholars from many schools of thought.69 Nevertheless, what he was

suggesting is that there is a need for a basic rule (al-qanun al-‘asli) that can be
referred to in identifying the muhkamdt and mutashabihat.70 It is apparent from

his explanation that when the preponderating meaning (rajih) of the word is clear

and does not involve any contradiction with any other proofs, then this verse is

called muhkamdt; hence no ta\vll is required. Nevertheless, when there is

another proof which contradicts the rajih to the extent that we have to move to

the meaning that is marjub, this verse is called the mutashabihat, and ta\vil, in

this case, is necessary. This would mean that ta\vil or the preference of the

second meaning of the word is only applicable when there is another proof that

clearly contradicts the literal or predominant meanin of the word.


CfQ

The next question is: what kind of proof can contradict the

preponderating meaning of the word? To al-Razi, not any proof can invalidate

the preponderating meaning of the term. This proof, maintained al-Razi, must

be an external and independent proof (dalil munfasiT). In other words, we

68 Tafsir, vol.3, 139.


69 Asas, 205.

156
cannot use the preponderated meaning without the existence of the external

evidence:

[In the case of contradiction,] if the word of the verse or report is


predominant in meaning (zahiranfi al-mana), we have to leave this
predominant meaning through an external evidence (dalil
munfasil)”. Otherwise the speech of God will be meaningless and
the Qur’an will not be a proof (hujjah). 71

Al-Razi went on to explain the nature of this external proof. This proof

must be rational in nature, for if it is textual, than there will be two

contradictory textual proofs where neither the selection of one proof will be prior

to the other:

This external proof is either textual or rational. If it is the first, we


affirm that if this happened, there will be two contradictory textual
proofs. If there is contradiction between the two, neither the
exclusion of one of them in replacement of the other is prior (laysa
tark ahadahuma li ibqa’ al-akhar awla min al-aks), except to say
that one of the two proofs is decisive (qdti) while the other is zahir,
and qdti is preponderant over the zahir, or to say that each of the
two are zahir, only that one of them is stronger than the other...71 72

Nevertheless, al-Razi did not agree with the view that one textual proof

can be more decisive in terms of its indication (daldlah) compared to another

textual proof due to the fact that all textual proofs are conjectural (maznun)

since they are based on a number of conditions which must be met before they

can be considered as certain.73 “Conjecture (al-zunun),99 affirmed al-Razi, “must

not be relied upon in arriving at conclusions on matters that are established

rationally (al-masall al-‘aqliyyah al-qat'iyyah)”74 Based on the same principle,

he did not accept that one textual proof is clearer than the other. For him, to

71 Ibid.
72 Ibid.
73 For the detail of these conditions, see 164-165 of this chapter (Discussion on rational and
traditional proofs).
74 Asas, 206.

157
move from one textual meaning which is clear to another textual meaning can

only be done with problems dealing with legal matters (masa’il fiqhiyyah) but

not with problems relating to theological matters (masa’il usuliyyahf75 Hence,

for al-Razi, we can only turn away from the literal meaning of a textual proof

once a decisive rational proof has been attained that the literal meanin is

CfQ
unacceptable:

From what we have mentioned, it is established that the movin

CfQ
from the preponderating meaning (zahir) to the preponderated one
(mu ’awwal) is not possible unless there is a decisive [rational] proof
that the preponderating meaning is impossible and rejected.76

Although ta\vil is necessary, al-Razi assigned the role of ta’wil only to

those who are able to do it, and he advised those who are not able to do so to

leave the meaning to God:

When [the impossibility of the literal] meaning take place, it is


necessary for a Muslim to affirm that the intended meaning of this
word is not what is imparted through its apparent meanin Then
at this stage, those who are capable to do ta\vil, should go for it
while those who don’t, should leave the knowledge [of its meaning]
to God.77

Since al-Razi’s main emphasis is divine transcendence, what is important

for him is the insistence on avoiding the literal meaning apparent in these verses.

For that matter, al-Razi did not object the method of the salaf who entrust the

knowledge of the meaning of the mutashdbihdt to God. In fact, to him, to opt

for the salafi position was safe for it is far from the risk of being incorrect in

assigning the true meaning of the anthropomorphic expressions.78 But this does

75 Tafsir, vol.3, 140.


76 Asas. 206.
77 Ibid.
78 For al-Razi, the method of the salaf is different from those of the Hanabilah and the
Karramiyyah who he criticized in Asas al-Taqdis. The salaf rejected the literal meaning of the
verses before assigning the meaning to God, while the Hanabilah, due to their strict affirmation
of the mutashdbihdt as the ‘so-called’ words of God, affirmed their literal meanings.

158
not invalidate the necessity of ta ’wil since ta ’wil is a rational implication of the

rejection of the apparent meaning of the anthropomorphic verses. Once we reject

the apparent meaning, it is either we leave the meaning to God like the salaf or

we assign an alternative meanin in order to make the verses comprehensible.

CfQ
Furthermore, al-Razi seems to conform to the prescriptions of the Qur an that to

arrive at the meaning of the mutashabihdt is possible and can be appropriately

carried out by those who are deeply rooted in knowledge. As a theologian who

continuously emphasized the understandability of the Qur’an, al-Razi inevitably

had to explain the meanin CfQ


of these verses as what he had done in Asas al-

Taqdis.

Al-Razi maintained that most of the groups in Islam affirmed that ta ’wil

is necessary with regard to some of the Qur’anic verses.79 After putting forward

arguments on the impossibility of understanding the verses and the Hadiths in

their literal sense, al-Razi asserted that “ta’wil is something necessary for every

reasonable person (‘aqU)... when it is affirmed based on strong proofs that God

the exalted is pure from any notion of direction and body, it is necessary for us
to assign those verses their proper meanings.”80

THE IMPORTANCE OF REASON AS THE SOURCE OF TA WlL: AN


EPISTEMOLOGICAL ANALYSIS

As we have seen before, al-Razi’s position regarding muhkamdt, mutashabihdt

and ta’wil is influenced by his view on the priority of reason. This priority is

more apparent in his discussion on proof (dalil) where he regarded rational proof

as a foundation in apprehending the meaning of the revelation. In this remaining

analysis, we will look at his view on the rational and traditional proofs and the

epistemological solution when contradiction between the two occurs.

79 Ibid., 91.

159
As a mutakallim and a logician, the consistency between the meanings of

the verses of the Qur’an is, for al-Razi’s, the highest priority in understanding

the revelation. This priority can be discerned, for example, in the way he
organized his great Qur’anic commentary, al-Tafstr al-Kabir.sl Throughout this

voluminous and encyclopedic tafsir which embraces extensive discussions on

various fields such as kalam, philosophy, fiqb, usul, physics, logic and
grammar,82 al-Razi consistently explained the connection of one verse to another

and provided reasonable explication on the relationship between all the

chapters. As remarked by Hussayn al-Dhahabi, it is not sufficient for al-Razi to

only mention one relation, but in most cases, he will mention more than one

relation and this systematic approach has been a distinctive mark of this tafsir to

such an extant that it is considered the most important commentary with

rational-intellectual justifications (al-tafsir bi al-ra ’y).

Not only did he emphasize a systematic explanation amon the verses, al-

CfQ
Razi also stressed the requirement that all these verses must be consistent with

the rational principle. For him, inconsistency between the Qur’anic verses and the

principle of reason will imply that the whole message of the revelation is not

understandable, which is incongruous with the fact that the Qur’an was revealed

to humankind whose essential quality is his reason. Al-Razi maintained that it is

impossible for God to reveal something that has no meaning, for that will render

God as revealing something senseless (budhyan) which implies His81

81 Also known as Mafdtlh al-Ghayb, this Qur’anic commentary (32 vols, Al-Qahirah edition) is
re arded as the most extensive tafsir. It was described by Ibn Khallikan as one that
tn

‘encompassed all remarkable and strange things’ (jamaa fihi kullu gharib wa gbaribah). It
contains vast discussion on various kinds of knowledge, views of different sects such as the
Mutazilah, the philosophers, the Karramiyyah and other Muslim sects. Its extensive nature can
also be seen among others, in his discussion of surah al-Fatibab, in which he says that from this
surah alone, 10,000 problems can be extracted. As reported by al-Dhahabi, Abu Hayyan in his
work Bahr al-Muhit remarked that “it has everything in it except ta/sir”(This statement is also
attributed to Ibn Taymiyyah). Al-Husayn al-Dhahabi, vol.l, 289-296.
82 Ibid, 293.
83 Ibid, 294.

160
Further,
imperfection.84 85 86 87 it is impossible for God to reveal the message of the

religion using language which cannot be comprehended and that is


contradictory.8 Since the Qur’an was revealed to humankind as a clear

explication (bayan) in the Arabic language that is clear (mubin), far from any

crookedness,88 its meaning must, first and foremost, be understandable and

consistent.

RATIONAL AND TRADITIONAL PROOFS

under the topic ‘whether traditional


In his kalam and usul al-fiqh works, 89 90

proofs yield certainty or not,’ al-Razi underlined the priority of reason; that

rational proofs are necessary in any argument to such an extent that they must
be the basis of the traditional (transmitted) proofs (al-adillab al-naqliyyah)99

“Reason,” says al-Razi, “is the foundation for understandin revealed text (‘asl

CIQ
20
al-naql)...if we disprove reason, we have disproved the very tool in understanding

of a revealed text, and once we have disproved it, we have also disproved the

revealed text.”91 Likewise, reason is necessary since it is the source of reflection

(nazar), which is a way to understanding divine matters. Al-Razi maintained

that nazr (reasoning) which he defined as ‘ordering of assents in order to arrive at

other assents’ (tartib tasdlqat li yatawassal biba tasdlqat akbar)92 is necessary in

reli ion since it is the only way for man to arrive at the knowledge of the
CfQ

existence of God. He argued that since the knowledge of the Absolute is

necessary, nazr, as the only way to the knowledge of the Absolute, is also

necessary. This is based on the famous maxim known in usul al-fiqb, namely,

84 Mahsul, vol.l, 385.


85 Ibid., 385-386.
86 Al-Qur’an, Al ‘Imran 3:138.
87 Al-Qur’an, al-Hijr 15:1.
88 Al-Qur’an, al-Zumar 39:28.
89 See Ma'alim, 21-22; Mahsul, vol.l, 385-318; Muhassal, 51-52; Arba'in, 423-426.
90 Ma'alim, 25; Mahsul, vol., 390-391.
91 Mahsul, vol. 1, 406.
92 Muhassal, 40.

161
“that without which the necessary thing does not complete, is itself necessary”

(ma la yatimm al-wajib ilia bihifa huwa wajib).

Compared to traditional proofs, al-Razi viewed the role of rational proofs

as foundational. Traditional proofs, due to their dependent nature on rational

proofs in that they need to be intellectually processed, cannot stand by

themselves. They also cannot be substantiated by other traditional proofs since

this will lead to circularity. In point of fact, the knowledge of the veracity of the

Prophet, which is the basis of the traditional proofs, is acquired through rational

proof:

A proof based on the Qur’an and the tradition (al-Sunnab) depends


on the knowled of the veracity of the Prophet, and this
knowledge [of the truth of the Prophet] is not attained (la
yustafad) by traditional proof, for that will lead to circularity;
rather it is based on the rational proofs. And it is beyond doubt that
this [preliminary] premise [which is based on the rational proof] is
one of the important parts in the validity of the traditional proof.
Hence, it is affirmed that a proof that is traditional in its entire
premise is impossible and false.93
94

Due to its foundational nature, rational proof is a necessary element in any

form of argument. Al-Razi maintained that proofs can either consist of premises

that are entirely traditional, or entirely rational, or composed of the two. The latter

two are possible while the first, namely, that proofs with entirely traditional

premises, due to the reason explained above, is impossible.95 By advancing the above

argument, al-Razi seemed to stress the importance of rational proofs in internalizing

traditional ones in terms of its logical priority. In other words, traditional proofs

must be preceded logically by rational proofs. Any Qur’anic text or Hadith must

first depend on the veracity of the Prophet as the conveyer of the message, and the

93 Ibid., 44. Cf. Irshad, 7.


94 Arbain, 424.
95 Muhassal, 51.

162
Hence, the
truthfulness of a Prophet, in turn, is justified through rational proofs.96 97

traditional proofs, in its final analysis, cannot continuously base themselves on

similar traditional proofs, but must somehow be founded on rational proofs. This is

also based on the logical principle that a branch cannot be stronger than the root.

Since the rational substantiation in this case is prior and is considered the principle

compared to the traditional proofs, its position is more fundamental in determining

the strength of the argument.

Another argument given by al-Razi supporting the priority of reason is that

which is related to the certainty of the traditional proofs. Rational proofs are prior to

traditional proofs because the latter in themselves do not yield certainty (la tufidu

al-yaqin). This is because traditional proofs by their very nature undergo the

process of transmission and this process is based on some contextual conditions that

need to be verified before they can be regarded as certain. The obscurity of these

conditions, according to al-Razi, will lead to a difficulty in understanding a given

traditional proof:

Traditional proofs do not yield certainty [italics mine] since they are
based on the transmission of language (naql al-lughat), grammar
(al-nahw wa tasrify equivocation (al-ishtiraky metaphor (al-
mojaz\ conveyance (al-naql), concealment (al-idmar), priority and
posteriority (taqdim wa takbir), specification (takbsis), abrogation
(ndsikb), and [rational] contradiction (mu arid). All these are
Q7
conjectural (zanniyyab).

These conditions, which are called ‘the ten rational criteria’, were further

elaborated by al-Razi as the followings:

i) The knowledge of language (marifat al-lugbat) which is based


mostly on the solitary narrations (riwdydt al-abad) from the

96 Nibayat, 133-142. The mutakallimun, according to al-Shahrastani, argued that it is possible for God
to send a Prophet because he has the power to choose a man to communicate His will to mankind so
that there is no impossibility in His doing so. They also argued for the possibility of miracles
through rational arguments.
97 Mahsul, vol. 1, 390-391. See also Mnn/zm, 22; Arbatn, 423-426.

163
linguists who are not free from error and disa ree among each

CfQ
other.
n) The correctness of the grammar and syntax (sihhat al-nahw wa
tasrif) with various expressions (i robot) and various meanings
which were also disputed among the grammarians.
iii) Equivocation in the meaning of words (al-ishtirak fi al-lafz) - If
there is equivocation in meaning, the words intended by God
may mean differently from what we understand.
iv) That it is necessary to bear the meaning of a certain word to its
literal (baqiqab) meaning rather than its metaphorical (majaz)
since the latter is numerous.
V) There should be no omissions and concealments or ellipsis (badhf
wa idmar) in the verses, for if it so, denial will become
affirmation and vice versa.
vi) There is no prior and posterior (taqdim wa takbir) with regard
to a narration or verse that will confuse the meanin
vii) There are no general statements (umumdt) without any specific

meanings.

viii) There are no abrogations of verses (nasikh wa mansukh).


ix) There are no contradictions in narrations (mu arid sanii) which
will confuse the true meaning.
x) There are no rational contradictions (mu arid ‘aqlf) whose
existence will lead to metaphorical interpretation of the
98
meanm of the verse.
CfQ

Linguistically, all these conditions are pertinent in determining the

meanm of words. Al-Razi called them “the ten premises” (muqaddamat


CfQ

cashar) which surround the derived meaning of any given textual proof.1 Since

the meanings of traditional proofs are based on language and language is

conditional by the ten contextual matters, the meanings of traditional proofs are

regarded as conjectural (mafnun). Whatever depends on something conjectural is

itself conjectural (al-mawquf bld mafnun mafnun). 1 Hence arguments

98 Arba'in, 424-426
99 For a lengthy linguistic discussions by al-Razi on words and meaning, and their related
problems, see Tafslr, vol.l, 29-50.
100 Arba'in, 424.
101 Ma'alim, 22; Mabsul, vol.l, 407; Tafsir, vol.l, 41-42.

164
(dilalat) which are based solely on traditional arguments, for al-Razi, do not yield

certainty.

Al-Razi, however, made some qualification on this general principle by

allowing the employment of traditional proofs if they are supported by the

mutawdtir reports:

these discussions [on the conjectural nature of the traditional


proofs] in its absolute sense is not true since perhaps the traditional
proof is joined (iqtarana) with matters that are known through
true reports (al-akhbar al-mutawdtirab). These matters will deny
all these possibilities and in this case the traditional proofs, which
are joined with other proofs (al-qaraln), which are affirmed
through true reports will yield certainty.102

The discussion on the priority of reason in any justification is not new in

Ashairah theological thought. Prior to al-Razi, a few other Ashari theologians had

already stressed the importance of reason in understanding revelation. Al-Juwayni,

for example, asserted that what can be proved by revelation must first be accepted

by reason or rendered possible by reason:

If the spirit of the law that has come to us is contrary to the


judgment of reason, on the basis that the law is not contrary to the
judgments of reason, it should be rejected decisively. In this
category, there is no way to formulate a decisive rule on the basis of
tradition.103

102 Arba in , 426; Mahsul, vol.l, 408.


103 Irshad, 196. According to al-Juwayni, what can only be perceived by revelation is the
judgment that affirms the realization of what is possible according to reason but cannot be
decided upon without revelation. This includes the whole body of duties and related matters such
as determining the bad and the good (taqbih wa tab sin), obligatory and forbidden (ijab wa bazr)
and recommended and permitted (badb wa ibahah). Ibid., 195; Muhammad Moslem Adel Saflo,
Al-Juwayni’s Thought and Methodology (Berlin: Klaus Schwarz Verlag, 2000), 96-99. In Irshad
also, al-Juwayni explained that the principles of belief are divided into: i) what can be proved by
reason alone, ii) what can be proved by revelation alone iii) what could be proved by both reason
and revelation. In Burhan, he added another principle namely proof based on miracle (mujizat).
Reason, however, plays an important role for it precedes, in principle, revelation in acquiring
knowledge of religion. Ibid; al-Burhan, ed. 'Abd ‘Azim Mahmud Dayb (Doha: Dar al-Wafa’,
1992), vol.l, 116.

165
Al-Juwayni also affirmed that any question of belief that comes prior to the

belief in the speech of God, the Qur’an, can only be understood or known by reason.

This is because revelation (sam'iyydt) is based on the speech of God, so anything

regarding God’s attributes whose proof is preceded by the proof of the Speech (such

as the attributes of Existence, Knowledge, Life) can only be proven by reason, for

the attribute of Speech can only be given to the One who has such attributes:

As for what cannot be perceived except by reason, all elements of


faith depend originally on knowing the Word of God, the Exalted
and on the necessity of its having the quality of being true. The
evidence supplied by tradition is grounded in the speech of God.
Thus, prior to the affirmation of the speech, what one must
acknowledge cannot possibly be grasped through tradition.104

The position is further strengthened by a-Ghazali who viewed that there are

three categories of theological propositions from which knowledge can be derived: (i)

the propositions which can be known by reason without the need of the evidence

from the Shar; (ii) propositions which can be known by the evidence of the Shar

without the need of reason; (iii) propositions which can be known by both these

means. The examples of the first category are the origination of the world, the

existence of the Originator and His Power, Knowledge and Will. All these, according

to al-Ghazali, are important matters that precede the knowledge of internal speech

(kalam al-nafs) which refers to the Qur’an and they cannot be substantiated by the

same kalam, but through reason. An example of the second category are those

matters that reason can only conceive as possible, such as the Resurrection, the Day

of Judgment, reward and punishment. The truth of these propositions cannot be

known except through revelation. The example of the third category is that which

can take place according to reason and is affirmed by revelation, such as the Vision

104 Irshad, 195; Saflo, 96.

166
of God and that God alone is the Creator of all movements and accidents.105 As to

how reason should react on what comes from revelation, al-Ghazali explained that

there are three attitudes of reason toward traditional proofs: (i) reason can state the

possibility of believing in what is provided by the traditional proofs, as in the case

when traditional proofs are conclusive and positive in their transmission (sanad) and

text (jnatrif (ii) reason may state the impossibility of believing in what is provided

by the traditional proofs, as in the case where the wording of the traditional proofs

must be interpreted because what is brought by the traditional proof is opposed to

the verdict of reason; (iii) reason may take passive attitude and refrain from

making any statement upon either the possibility or the impossibility of believing in

what is provided by the traditional proofs.106

What is clear from the view given by al-Razi’s predecessors regarding the

role of reason is that they generally agreed that reason plays an important role in

substantiating some major foundational aspects of religious doctrines. The

doctrines that come from the traditional proofs must also not be in contradiction

with the principle of reason. What al-Razi did was to pursue further this

position by putting forward the condition in detail. As a matter of fact, al-Razi’s

new way of putting forward the elaboration regarding the status of rational and

traditional proofs influenced many mutakallimun after him in their treatment of

the topic of proofs. For example, in both al-Taftazani’s Sharh al-Maqasid and

al-Jurjani’s Sharh al-Mawaqif, two important works of later Ash'arite kalarn, the

ten conditions discussed above were elaborated as being necessary conditions that
must be satisfied before any scriptural text can yield certain knowledge.107 As

recorded by Heer, al-Taftazani and al-Jurjani classified these ten conditions into

105 Al-Ghazali, al-Iqtisad, 132. See also M.A.R. Bisar, Al-Juwayni and al-Ghazali as Theologians:
with special reference to al-Irshad and al-Ttiqad, (Ph.D. dissertation, Edinburgh University,
1953), 40-41.
106 Al-Ghazali, al-Iqtisad , 133; Bisar, 41-42.
107 Nicholas Heer, “The Priority of Reason in the Interpretation of Scripture: Ibn Taymiyah and
the Mutakallimun”, Literary Heritage of Classical Islam, ed. Mustansir Mir (Princeton: The
Darwin Press, Inc., 1993), 181-183.

167
three general headings: first, that the language of the text must be known for

certain. This includes its vocabulary (lugbah), syntax (rtabw) accidence (sarf);

second, the intent (iradah) of the speaker must be verified which is known if the

text is devoid of changes in the meanings of words (naql), ambiguity (ishtirak),

metaphor (majaz), ellipsis or omission (idmar), limitation (takhsis), and irre ular

CfQ
ordering of words (taqdim wa ta kbir); third, there must be no rational counter

argument (mu‘arid aqli) that conflicts with the meaning of the scriptural text. If

such conflicts exist, the scriptural text must be interpreted allegorically.108

Concerning the last condition, which is pertinent to our discussion, namely that

there will be no rational contradiction within traditional proofs, al-Taftazzani

said:

Among the necessary [conditions], but with respect to which there


can be no certain knowledge (al-jazm), is the absence of a rational
counter-argument (al-muarid al-aqli), since should such
counter-argument exist, scripture (al-naql) would have to be
interpreted allegorically (ta’wil) and shifted from its literal meaning
(zahirihi). The reason for this is that it is impossible to affirm
(tasdiq) both [scripture and reason], because of the impossibility of
believing two contradictory propositions (al-naqidayri) to be true,
or to deny (takdhib) both, because it is also impossible to believe
two contradictory propositions to be false. It is also impossible to
affirm scripture while denying reason, because reason is the root
(asl) to understanding scripture and scripture stands in need of it
and ultimately terminates with it, for, as has been mentioned
previously, the truth of the scripture can be known only through
rational evidence (dalil ‘aqli), and to deny the source in order to
affirm its derivative (al-far) is to deny both the source and its
derivative. The existence of that which implies its [own]
nonexistence is certainly absurd (batil).109

Jurjani’s in his Sbarb al-Mawaqif also commented on the same matter:

8 Heer, “The Priority of Reason,” 182.


109 Al-Taftazzani, Sharh al-Maqasid, ed. 'Abd Rahman 'Umayrah, (Bayrut: 'Alam al-Kutub,
1989), vol.l, 283.

168
The reason the rational counter-argument must be given priority
over scriptural evidence is because they cannot both be operative (la
yumkin al-camal bihima) in the sense that one cannot judge the
implications of both to be false either, because that would violate
the principle of excluded middle (irtifa al-naqidayn).no

SOLUTION TO THE CONTRADICTION BETWEEN RATIONAL AND


TRADITIONAL PROOFS

In Asas particularly, al-Razi laid down the principle that should be upheld when

dealing with any contradiction between a literal understanding of textual proofs

from the Qur’an or Hadith and rational proofs such as in the case of the
anthropomorphic verses.110 How do we, for example, account for the meaning of
111 112

the ‘hand of God’ (yadd Allah) whose literal meaning contradicts the rational

principle that God cannot be ascribed with corporeal and physical attributes. If

such contradictions occur, there are four possibilities that may happen: (i) either

we approve both the rational and textual proofs. This is impossible since

logically, we cannot affirm two contradictories (tasdiq al-naqidayn); (ii) to

disprove both of them which is also impossible, for it denies two contradictories;

(iii) to affirm the apparent meaning of the textual proof and disprove the rational

principle that is contrary to the literal meaning. This option was also, to al-Razi,

unacceptable based on the reason that we mentioned before that the preference of

the traditional proofs at the expense of the rational proofs is undesirable as it will

impin upon the traditional proofs themselves. Since all these three

possibilities are rejected, the only way out, for al-Razi, is the fourth, namely, to

hold to the principle of reason which necessitates that the meanin of these
CfQ

110 Heer, “The Priority of Reason,” 182.


111 Asos, 193-194.
112 If these matters are proved by textual proofs namely the Qur’an or Hadith, it will lead to
circularity (dawr), since God, whose existence is the object of proof, Himself brings down the
Qur’an.

169
traditional proofs are true yet the meanings are not literal. In this case, if the

traditional proofs can be interpreted via ta\vil, they must be so done. In the case

of the word ‘the hand of God,’ since it is not parallel with God’s divine

transcendence, it can be allegorically interpreted as meaning the omnipotence and

power of God. But if the allegorical interpretation (ta\vil) cannot be done in

such way, the knowledge of the meanin of the verses must be entrusted

CfQ
(fawwada) to God.1 This is, according to al-Razi, the general methodology (al-

qanun al-kulliy) that should be followed in dealing with the anthropomorphic

verses.

IBN TAYMIYYAH’S RESPONSE

Al-Razi’s principle that rational proofs form the basis of traditional proofs was

challenged by a Hanbalite scholar, Ibn Taymiyyah (d.1328). Since this challen

is very much relevant to our discussion, we will discuss in brief the ar uments of

CfQ
Ibn Taymiyyah. In his work, Dar’ Taarud al-Aql wa al-Naql, Ibn Taymiyyah

made clear at the very outset of the work, where he repeated al-Razi’s view:

If there is a conflict between scriptural and rational evidence


(adillah al-sarniyyab wa al-aqliyyab), or scripture and reason (al-
sam‘ wa al-aql), or tradition and reason (al-naql wa al-aql), or
traditional text (al-zawahir al-naqliyyab) and rational certainties
(al-qawati al-aqliyyab), or what is expressed in similar terms,
then either [1] both may be accepted as true (yujma baynabuma),
but that is impossible because it violates the principle of
contradiction (jam' bayn naqidayn), or [2] both may be rejected as
false, [and that is impossible because it violates the principle of
excluded middle], or [3] scripture may be given priority [over
reason]. That, however, is also impossible because reason is the
source of scripture (asl al-naql), and if we give priority to scripture
over reason, we should thereby impugn reason, which is the source
of scripture. Furthermore, to impugn the source of a thing is also
to impugn the thing itself. Therefore, to give priority to scripture is*

113 Asas, 194. In this case, perhaps al-Razi was referring to those alphabets that occur at the
outset of some verses in the Qur’an from which no other allegorical meanings can be derived.

170
not only to impugn reason but to impugn scripture as well. It is,
therefore necessary [4] to give priority to reason and either to
interpret scripture allegorically (yuta ’awwal), or to entrust its
meaning to God (yu/hwwud).114

Ascribing the origin of this principle to al-Razi and his followers, Ibn

Taymiyyah claimed that the former has put this principle as a universal law

(qanurt kulliy) in giving proof from the Book of God and the sayings of the
Prophets.115 Ibn Taymiyyah rejected this principle on the basis that it is based on

three false premises: (i) that there exists a conflict between reason and scripture;

(ii) that the alternatives mentioned are limited to four, and (iii) that the three

alternatives rejected are, in fact, impossible.116 In refuting these premises, he

presented forty-four arguments attacking primarily the notion of reason

understood by the mutakallimun.117 The basic outline of Ibn Taymiyyah’s

refutation, as summarized by Abrahamov, is as follows:

I. Reason is not the basis of tradition

II. Arguments against the rational arguments:

1. They are various and sometimes self-contradictory.

2. They contain doubts.

3. They are a mixture of truth and falsehood.

4. They do not coincide with linguistic use.

5. They are not always rational.

III. The arguments of kalam and philosophy are false.


IV. The result of the preference of reason.118

114 Ibn Taymiyyah, Muwafaqdt, 31.


115 Ibid., 32.
116 Heer, “The Priority of Reason,” 189.
117 See further Abrahamov, Binyamin, “Ibn Taymiyya on the Agreement of Reason with
Tradition,” The Muslim World, vol. LXXXII, No. 3-4 (July-October 1992), 257-258; Heer, “The
Priority of Reason”, 181-192.
118 Abrahamov, “Ibn Taymiyyah,” 258.

171
Traditional proofs, according to Ibn Taymiyyah, do not need reason as

their basis since they can stand by themselves. They exist on account of

Prophetic report or other devices whether we know their existence or not.

Furthermore, the content brought by the traditional proofs such as God’s unity,

His names and attributes, His Messenger’s veracity exist whether we know them
or not.119 They do not, in other words, need the justification from reason.

Ibn Taymiyyah also attacked the integrity of reason by saying that

rational principles are relative and sometimes contradictory. It can be seen in the

case of the philosophers who had the highest number of divergence in their

views. Rational proofs also, to Ibn Taymiyyah, combined in themselves truth


and falsities.120 On the other hand, traditional proofs, namely, the revelation, are

greed upon by wise people. It cannot be said that the matters brought by the

traditional proofs contradict reason since they are known through necessary

knowledge which ensues from uninterrupted narrations (tawdtur).

Holding mainly on the method of interpretation of the Qur’an by the

Qur’an, Ibn Taymiyyah disapproved taXvil by saying that everything is already

explained by the Qur’an and the Prophet. He viewed that there is no need to

move from the literal meaning to an alternative meanin of word since


CfQ

whatever alternative meaning that exists must already have been explained by
the Prophet since he is the best qualified person to elucidate the truth.121 In

other words, if there is another meaning intended by the anthropomorphic verses,

the Prophet would have explained it through the traditions. Furthermore, as far

as the essence and attributes of God are concerned, Ibn Taymiyyah is in the

position that we have to affirm of Him whatever He affirmed of Himself in the

119 Ibid.
120 Ibid., 259.
121 Ibid., 264.

172
Qur’an and in the authentic Hadiths.122 Ibn Taymiyyah’s attack on ta’wil was

also based on the claim that there are no standard rule in employing this method.

Since ta \vil is based on reason and reason has already been condemned by him as

subjective and inconsistence, ta’wil is also uncertain. He also questioned the

basis for choosing which verses required ta \vil and which do not.

In sum, Ibn Taymiyyah was of the view that since revelation also contains

the rational principle and it also enjoins the usage of reason, there is in principle

no contradiction between reason and revelation. The content of the revelation

must also be accepted as a whole. The deviation from revelation in one item

leads to the total deviation of the understanding of revelation.123 However, this

leaves an important question unanswered: did he believe that the

anthropomorphic verses really convey the literal meanings to mankind, the

positive answer of which will mean that he is upholding the position tajsim and

tashbih? This explanation becomes more crucial since Ibn Taymiyyah also

rejected the method of tafwid, to entrust the knowledge of the anthropomorphic


verses to God alone.124 To him, since God has ordered man to reflect on the

Qur’an and induced him to understand it, it is therefore inadmissible that He

should have wanted man to deviate from its understanding and knowledge by

conveying a message that is not understood by man. To put it plainly, if he

viewed that there should be no alternative meanings to the anthropomorphic

verses, at the same time we do not accept the fact that these meanings are only

known to by God, what other meanings are left to these verses other than their

literal and anthropomorphic meanings?

122 Ssekamanya Siraje Abdallah, “Ibn Taymiyyah’s Thological Apparoach Illustrated: On the
Essence (Dhat) and Attributes (Sifat) of Allah,” ShajarahJournal of the International Institute of
Islamic Thought and Civilization (ISTAC), vol.9, no.1(2004), 45.
123 Ibid, 270.
124 Heer, “The Priority of Reason,” 188.

173
CHAPTER FIVE

AL-RAZI’S TREATMENT OF THE ANTHROPOMORPHIC


VERSES

INTRODUCTION

In the foregoing chapter, we have analyzed al-Razi’s view on muhkamdt and

mutashdbihdt as well as his methodology of ta’wil as an appropriate modus operandi

in arriving at the meaning of the mutashdbihdt. Also examined is his view on the

epistemological principle regarding reason and revelation particularly concerning the

knowledge of the divine. Having established this epistemological basis in arriving at

the knowledge of God and a clear conception of ta’wil, it is for us now to show how

al-Razi applied this method in his explanation and commentary regarding the

meaning of anthropomorphic verses in the Qur’an which appear to be in conflict

with the epistemological basis that he had laid down. In doing this, our reference

will be mainly his Kitab Asas al-Taqdls in which al-Razi explained in detail the

appropriate meaning of the anthropomorphic expressions in the Qur’an. His al-

Tafslr al-Kabtr is also used as a cross reference for some of his explanations

regarding these expressions.

There are several anthropomorphic attributes mentioned in the Qur’an and

Prophetic traditions. Among them are: words implying organs such as hand,1 eyes,2

face,3 thigh (sdg);4 words which refer to directions, such as above (fawq);5 words

designating actions such as to ascend (nazala, nuzul),6

1 Al-Qur’an Sad 38:75, al-Ma’idah 5:64, al-Fath 48:10.


2 Al-Qur’an, Hud 11:37, Taha 20:39, al-Tur 52:48.
3 Al-Qur’an al-Baqarah 2:115, al-Qasas 28:88, al-Rahman 55:26-27, al-Kahf 18:28, al-An am 6:52, al-
Rum 30:38, al-Insan 76:9, al-Layl 92:20.
4 Al-Qur’an, al-Qalam 68:42.
5 Al-Qur’an, al-An'am 6:18, 61; al-Nahl 16:50.
6 Hadith which says: “God descends every night to the lower heaven and says, “Is there any who has
a request? And I will grant it him. Is there any who asks forgiveness? And I will forgive him - until
dawn arrives.” Ibn Khuzaymah, Kitab al-Tawbid, 126.

174
to come (ja’a, al-majij,' to meet (Uqaj, to grasp (qabd); words that denote self

and individuality such as self (nu/s )10 8 9 soul (ruh);11 words that are similar to
7 and

physical matters such as light (nur);12 indications of spatial meaning such as in the

veil (hijab),13 near (qarb),14 beside (janb)'15 words which refer to feeling such as

laughing (dahk)16 and shy (haya j.17 18

In Asas, al-Razi dealt with all the above expressions, but since our concern is

more towards examining al-Razi’s general approach in arriving at the meaning of

these expressions, we, therefore, do not wish to go into detail as to how al-Razi

employed ta \vil in all the expressions. On the other hand, we will select from them

few examples which are representative of the categories mentioned above and

explain how al-Razi dealt with them. Five examples that we will discuss are those

on God’s image and the form of Adam, God’s face, the Vision of God in the

Hereafter, the notion of direction, and God’s hand.

GOD’S IMAGE AND THE FORM OF ADAM

The controversy surrounding this term lies in the use of the personal pronoun "ha"

(his) in the Hadith of the Prophet, which runs, “Verily God has created Adam

according to His form” (inna Allah khalaqa Adam cala suratihV). There is also

another Hadith in which the Prophet warns a man not to disgrace (taqbahu) the

7 Al-Qur’an al-Fajr 89:22.


8 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:46, al-Kahf 18:110, al-Sajdah 32:10.
9 Al-Qur’an, al-Zumar 39:67.
10 Al-Qur’an, Ta ha 20:41, al-Ma’idah 5:116, al-An am 6:54, Al 'Imran 3:30.
11 Al-Qur’an, al-Hajr 15:29.
12 Al-Qur’an, al-Nur 24:35.
13 Al-Qur’an, al-Mutaffifin 83:15.
14 Al-Qur’an, Qaf 50:16.
15 Al-Qur’an, al-Zumar 39:56.
16 Al-Qur’an, al-Najm 53:43.
17 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:26.
18 Muslim, Sahih, no. 7092, vol. 17, 175-176.

175
face of another since God has created Adam in his form.19 Another Hadith which

comes with a different ending, relates that God has created Adam in the form of ‘the

Most Merciful’ (h/d surat al-RahmdiT). In Asas, apart from the abovementioned

Hadiths, al-Razi enumerated several other Hadiths which convey similar

anthropomorphic meanings: first, a Hadith regarding the last group of people who

God will remove from Hell and to whom God appears twice, first, in the image that

they do not recognize (la ydriftin') to the effect that they reject Him, and then, in

the image which they are able to recognize Him.20 Another Hadith relates that the

Prophet himself had seen God in the best form (/T ahsarti surah) and that God put

His ‘hand’ on the Prophet’s shoulder to the effect that the Prophet felt the coldness

of the touch. Most of these Hadiths mentioned above are also among those quoted

by Ibn Khuzaymah, in his Kitab al-Tawhid, in affirming the literal understanding

of the anthropomorphic expressions of God’s qualities against which al-Razi

attacked.21

As we have mentioned, the controversy of these Hadiths lies in the question

of who the pronoun ‘his’ refers to. A common grammatical analysis of the Hadith

suggests that the pronoun would refer to God, which leads to an anthropomorphic

implication of the similarity between the form of God and humans. Most of the

traditional scholars rejected this meaning not only due to its anthropomorphic
implication of the similarity between God’s form and the human form,22 but also

because of its Judeo-Christian origin. A similar saying appears in the Bible, which

alludes to the fact that God created man in His form in order for man to have control

over the world and its content. The Book of Genesis says:

19 The Hadith goes, “ One of should not say to another that God condemned your face and the face
similar to your face, since God has created Adam in ‘his’ form.” Ibn Khuzaymah, Kitab al-Tawbid,
36.
20 Asas, 101.
21 Ibn Khuzaymah, Kitab al-Tawbid, 36-41.
22 Nevertheless, it was accepted by later Muslim scholars such as Ibn Qutaybah (d.885) which
appears in his work, TaXvil Mukhtalif al-Haditb. It was also brought out by al-Qastallani’s
(Isti’dban, [79]) commentary on al-Bukhari and al-Nawawi’s commentary on Sahih Muslim (al-Birr
[45]); W. Montgomery Watt, “Some Muslim Discussions,” 95.

176
Then God said, ‘Let us make man in our image after our likeness; and
let them have dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the birds of
the air, and over the cattle and over all the earth and over every
creeping thing that creeps upon the earth.” So God created man in his
own image, in the image of God He created him: male and female He
created them.23

In regard to the controversy of the pronoun, al-Razi’s viewed that the

pronoun ‘his’ at the end of the word surah could indicate three possible meanings: (i)

either it means the form of somebody other than the forms of God and Adam; (ii) or

it indicates the form of Adam; (iii) or it refers to the form of God. In the first case,

the contextual meaning of the Hadith, according to al-Razi, is that the Prophet,

when uttering this Hadith, could have referred the pronoun to mean the face of

particular person that has been denigrated by another person. This is further

supported by a Hadith that cites an incident when the Prophet once passed a man

who was beating his servant on the face, and said to him, “Do not beat his face, for
God created Adam in his form.”24 By reminding the man that God created Adam

with the face as that in the form of the man whom he was beating, the Prophet was

implying that to denigrate the ‘face’ of that man was equivalent to denigrating the

face of Prophet Adam as well as other prophets. The reason why the name of

Adam, not men in general, is mentioned in the Hadith, according to al-Razi, is

because Prophet Adam was the first creation who was created with this (human)
form of face.25 In addition to this specific reason, this Hadith also serves as a denial

of stories of what were said regarding the feature of Adam through the Isradiyydt

sources that he was huge in size and that his head nearly touched the sky. This

explanation of the Hadith, on the contrary, affirms that the fomi of Adam

corresponds to the form of a normal human being.26 Provided that the chain of

narrators of this Hadith is sound, it seems to us that this line of interpretation (that

23 The Bible, Revised Standard Version (The British & Foreign Bible Society, 1952), 2.
24 Ta \vil, 148; Watt, “Some Muslim Discussions,” 96.
25 Asas, 97.
26 Ibid., 98.

177
the pronoun refers to other than God and Adam) is the least controversial due to the
fact that it does not involve any form of anthropomorphism.27 28

As to the second meaning namely that the pronoun refers to Adam, al-Razi

believed that this is the most appropriate meaning of this Hadith despite the

rejection of this view by others due to its redundancy in meanin Al-Razi,

however, had his own justification in preferring this interpretation. The first is that

this meaning is in agreement with the grammar of the Arabic language that suggests

the assignment of pronoun to the nearest word mentioned prior to the pronoun:

This is the most prior meaning of the three, since the assignment

O
pronoun (damir) to the nearest words is necessary. In this Hadith, the
nearest word mentioned is Adam (peace be upon him). Hence, the
assignment of the pronoun to it (the word Adam) is prior.29

Second, al-Razi maintained that this second meaning has its moral

justification. For, when Adam was taken out from the heaven due to his

wrongdoing, unlike other creatures, whose forms were transformed by God,30 the

form of Adam was maintained by God as a sign of respect and nobility. Hence,

when the Hadith says that God created Adam in his form, it means that God
maintained Adam in his own original form without any transformation.31 Third, al-

Razi also pointed out that this second meaning implies that Adam was created

without undergoing the natural embriological process, such as through sperm

27 However, we do not concur with Watt’s view that this version of interpretation is an ‘ingenious
way’ of reinterpreting the words put forward by the traditionists (mubadditbiuT) in order to escape
from the controversial implication of anthropomorphism. Watt, “Some Muslim Discussions,” 96. For
this interpretation is duly taken in accordance with the context of the utterance (asbab al-wurud) of
the Hadith as mentioned earlier by Ibn Qutaybah. As a matter of fact, the problem of
anthropomorphism still persist, if other versions of the Hadith such as that with the ending ‘in the
form of the Most Merciful’ (’ala surat al-Rahman ) are taken into consideration.
28 Ibn Qutaybah, for example, disagreed with this interpretation since it will make the saying
superfluous and does not yield any benefit (ma kana ft al-kalam faldatan). “Nobody doubt,” he
argued, “that God will create human beings according to their nature and create other creatures
according to their own respective natures.” Ta *wil, 147.
29 Asas, 98.
30Al-Razi related that when God removed Adam from heaven, together with him being removed were
the serpent and the peacock whose forms were changed by God. Asas, 99.
31 Ibid, 98-99.

178
(nutfah), blood clot (‘alaqah), a morsel of flesh (mudghah) and other process of

biological birth affirmed by the naturalists (al-dahriyyah) and biologists as

something necessary for the formation of a human being. Neither was Adam

created through a long period of time and through the medium of celestial bodies

(al-aflak) as maintained by the philosophers. Fourth, al-Razi alluded to the fact that

the term surah can also convey the meaning of attribute (sifab). Hence, when the

Hadith says that God created Adam in his form, it means that God created him in a

form already perfected with the attributes of a man, such as being knowledgeable,

happy and the like.32

As to the third meaning, namely, that the pronoun ‘his’ refers to the form of
God,33 al-Razi observed that this meaning is possible through the following line of

understanding: first, Adam is imbued with attributes similar to those of God.

According to this interpretation, Adam is distinct from other creatures in terms of

his knowledge which is universal in nature as well as in his capacity of knowing

language. Both of these qualities, according to al-Razi, resemble in some respects

the attributes of God:

Adam is indeed distinguished from other persons and bodies in the


fact that he knows the intelligibles. He is able to derive words and
knowledge (al-hurf wa al-sinaah). These are the noble qualities which
befit the attributes of Allah in some aspects. Hence, the saying of the
prophet ‘Allah has created Adam in His image’ is true according to
this line of interpretation. 34

Al-Razi nevertheless made an important note that this similarity does not

lead to the similarity in terms of divinity (ilahiyyah) between Adam and God. Being

32 Ibid., 100.
33 Although al-Razi prefers the view that the pronoun ‘his’ in the Hadith “God created Adam in his
form refers to Adam, yet in the Hadith in which the addition “surah al-Rahman” (the form of the
Merciful) occurs, the implication of the pronoun ‘his’ must be to God, since it cannot be otherwise.
In other words, any of the versions with the words (the Merciful) made it clear that the form is
God’s.
34 Asas, 100.

179
similar in some remote concomitants (lawazim al-ba(idah) yet different in many

others does not necessitate similarity in terms of divinity:

If it is said that the commonality (musharakah) in the attributes of


perfection (sifdt al-kamal) necessitates the commonality in divinity (al-
ilabiyyah), we say that commonality in some remote concomitants (al-
lawazim al-baldab) with differences in many other aspects, does not
necessitate similarity in divinity.35

Second, as an extension of the first, the ‘form of God’ could also be

interpreted as Adam being created with the attributes of generosity and majesty, the

perfect manifestation of which belong to God. It is also an indication that man is

created fundamentally distinct from other creatures in terms of his attributes. He is

created in the best form, nearer to his Creator. By this, al-Razi was suggesting that

there is a possibility that man, in varying degrees, though not completely, can

imitate God in terms of His attributes as Ion as it does not negate the divine
CfQ

transcendence. To support this view, he quoted the Qur’anic verse, “for Him

belongs the loftiest similitude” (wa lahu al-matbal al-ald) and the Hadith of the

Prophet “adorn your conduct with the decorum that is Godly” (takballaqu bi akblaq

Allah). In his other work, Lawami al-Bayyindt, al-Razi further explained how

this imitation of every name of God can take place in re ardi to man. 38
CfQ

From the above two interpretations, the Hadith which indicates that the

Prophet was displeased with the man who denigrated the face of another man can be

incorporated into this meanin Since Adam is created ‘similar’ to the attributes of
CrQ

God, the denigration of the man’s face which is the place where many of the36 37 38

36 Al-Qur’an, al-Rum 30:27.


37 Asas, 100.
38 Lawami', passim. In this work, following in some respects the work of al-Ghazali, Maqsad al-
Asna fi Sharh Asma’ Allah al-Husna, al-Razi explicates each and every one of the Ninety Nine
Beautiful Names of God followed by the way how the servant of Allah can imitate at his own level
that particular divine Name. For example, the way a servant can be characterized with the Name al-
Quddus (The Holy) is through purifying their soul from the inclination towards the matters related
to bodies (al-jasmaniyyahf and busying himself in acquiring eternal knowledge and a praiseworthy
character (al-akhlaq al-hamidah). While to be characterized with the attribute of al-Malik, a servant
should detach all his needs from other than Allah. Lawami, 182-186.

180
manifestation of his attributes such as seeing, thinking, hearing, should be avoided.

We will further elaborate upon the position of the face in our next sub-topic.

The third interpretation which is based on the view of al-Ghazali is that just

as God is beyond any corporeal implication, Adam is created similar to this ‘form’ in

the sense that his essence, which is his soul, neither inheres in nor connected with

any physical and corporeal being. Its connection with the body is only in terms of

regulation (al-tadbir) or administration (al-tasarruf ).39

It becomes clear from the foregoing explanations regarding the issue of the

‘image of God’ that for al-Razi, to whatever the pronoun ‘his’ in the Hadlth refers,

the principle maintained by him is that it must not, as much as possible, impinge

upon the divine transcendence.

GOD’S FACE

Another anthropomorphic attribute often mentioned by the Qur’an is the Face of

God (Wajh Allah). Among the verses in which this word occur are “But forever

will abide the Face of your Lord,”40 “Everything will perish except His own Face,”41

“...who seek the Face of God,”42 “To Allah belong the East and the West, wherever

you turn, there is Allah’s Face.”43 In a number of Hadiths, the word Face of God

mostly takes place when it refers to the ultimate objective of a Muslim in his acts of

submission towards his Lord, that he submits and strives in God’s path in order to

39 Asas, 100-101. Al-Ghazali mentioned this in his Kitab 'AJaib al-Qalb one of the chapters in his
Ihya’ ‘Ulum al-Din. He explained that the heart and the body are analogous to a king and a kingdom
or a city. As a king, the heart has its army including the physical organs such as the hands and legs,
as well as the spiritual ones such as anger, intellect and desire. Al-Ghazali, Ihya’ ‘Ulum al-Din
(Bayrut: Dar al-Fikr,1991), vol. 3, 6-8.
40 Al-Qur’an, al-Rahman, 55:27.
41 Al-Qur’an, al-Qasas 28:88.
42 Al-Qur’an, al-Rum 30:38-39. The word ‘face’ also occurs in the form “who seek His face” (yuridu
wajhahu) as in al-Kahf 18:28, al-An am 6:52; and in the form “the desire to seek the Face of their
Lord Most High” (ibtigha’ wajh rabbihi) as in al-Layl 92:20.
43 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:115.

181
seek His Face (ibtigha’ wajh Allah). Al-Razi adduced the Hadith which was

mentioned by Ibn Khuzaymah in commenting the verse of the Qur’an, “Say: ‘He has

power to send calamities on you from above, and from beneath your feet, or to cover

you with confusion in party strife giving you a taste of mutual vengeance each from
the other,’”44 following which, the Prophet repeatedly (three times) said, “I seek
45 46

refuge by Your Face” (audhu bi wajhika).

Al-Razi, first and foremost, denied any possibility that the term 'wajh Allah"

could be understood in the literal sense. It is impossible to comprehend ‘the Face of

God’ as a physical face, as an organ and limb (al-udw wa al-jarihah) as claimed by

the anthropomorphists. Al-Razi put forward a simple, foolproof argument more

towards discrediting the argument of the anthropomorphists. If the Face of God is

to be understood in the physical sense, then when God says elsewhere in the Qur’an

that “everything will perish except His own Face” (kullu shay7 halik ilia wajhabu),

all other limbs will perish including the eyes which is on the face!47 It also implies

that the verse “Wherever you turn, there is Allah’s Face” will mean that the physical

face of God will appear in every section of the world, which is absurd. In addition,

al-Razi challenged the consistency of the anthropomorphists by questioning how

they would construe the meaning of “seeking the Face of God” if the meaning of

face is physical, since they themselves re arded the Face of God as eternal.48
CfQ

44 Such as the Hadith mentioned by al-Razi which says, “Whoever fasts a day for the cause of Allah
in order to seek the Face of God, Allah will keep away his face from Hell for seventy years (kharif -
literally autumn).” Another Hadith, “Those of you who take refuge with Allah, He will protect him,
whosoever among you who seek the Face of God, He will grant him with greatness.” Asas, 131.
45 Al-Qur’an, al-An am 6:65.
46 As to the last part of the Surah (to cover you with confusion in party strife giving you a taste of
mutual vengeance each from the other), the Prophet says, “these two are more easier and lighter.”
Asas, p. 131; Ibn Khuzaymah, 11. This Hadith was narrated by ‘Amru bin Dinar from Jabir. Ibn
Khuzaymah asserted after quoting the above verse that God has affirmed to Himself a face and
attributes to it the attribute of Majesty, Bounty and Honour (dbu al-Jalal wa al-Ikram) and He
affirms (hakama) His face with eternity and denies it from annihilation (halak). Ibid., 10.
47 Al-Razi is here referring to the view of Ibn Saman of the Rafidah who held this view, that it is
only God’s face (as a limb) that will persists. Tafsir, vol. 9, 22.
48 Asus, 133

182
Something eternal, according to al-Razi, cannot be sought especially when the act of

seeking implies that the object that they seek will take place in existence.49

...the Face of Allah according to their view is eternal and everlasting


(qadim azaliy). Something eternal is not sought (la yurad), since that
which is sou ht will mean that what is sou ht is its occurrence in

CfQ

CfQ
existence (yuradu busuluhu ft al-wujud) which is impossible in regard
to something eternal.50

Besides, if the face is considered physical, those who seek the Face of God

will also seek the wrath of God which also appears from the face, while certainly

what they are after is not the wrath of God but rather His pleasure (al-rida).51 52

Due to the above impossibilities and logical inconsistencies, the term ‘wajb’

according to al-Razi, can only be understood as referring to two allegorical meanings:

first as an indirect expression (kindyah) of the essence (al-dbdt) of God; second, as a

sign of God’s pleasure (al-rida). The explication of the former goes as follows: that

the face is the aspect through which the essence and reality of man can be

manifested (al-(adw alladhi bibi yatabaqqaq wujud dhalika al-insan). According to

the custom and tradition of the Arabs, the person who is responsible for social
52
organization is called the ‘the face of the community’ (wajb or wajib al-qawm).

The face, therefore, is the representation of the whole self of a man. Second, the

meaning of man is the manifestation of what transpires from his intellect, senses,

understanding and reflection. The source and substratum of all faculties and

activities is the head of a person, while the outward manifestation (mazhar) of these

faculties is represented by the face. Thus, the word face is the appropriate term for

49 Ibid.
50 Ibid.
51 Ibid. This is a logical argument which follows from the premise that the face of God is the physical.
Al-Razi argued that since from the face not only the signs of pleasure will appear but also the signs
of wrath and anger, hence, to seek the face of God will imply not only seeking His pleasure but also
His anger and wrath.
52 Ibid., 134.

183
representing the essence of man.53 In addition, when the Arab says the face of the

matter (wajb badha al-amr), he means the essence of the matter.54

From the above nuances of meanings, the verses “but forever will abide the

face of your Lord” and “everything will perish except His own Face” are then

understood as indicating that which is the eternal essence of God which abides and

which will not perish.55 Everything other than Allah, since they are originated and

contingent, is receptive of non-existence and destruction. But God, as a Necessary

Existent, and the Creator and Determiner (Murajjib) of all originated things, is not

receptive of destruction and non-existence.56

As to the meaning of pleasure (rida), al-Razi explained that the face

represents the attitude of human being towards something, since when a man is

inclined towards something, he will direct his face towards it, and vice versa. This

indicates that the face is the manifestation of the inclination and hatred in man.57 It

is through this meaning that the verse “To Allah belong the East and the West,

wherever you turn, there is Allah’s face,” and the Hadith, “I seek refuge by the Face

of Allah (bi wajb Allah)” should be interpreted.58

The meanin of rida is supported by the fact that some of these verses refer
CfQ

specifically to man’s submission to God (‘ibadab). 9 For example, the phrase

“wherever you turn, there is Allah’s face” in Surat al-Baqarah (2:115) refers to

directions in prayer (so/dt), while the phrase “seeking the Face of Allah” in Surat al-

Rum refers to seeking the Pleasure of God by almsgiving (zakat).60 It goes without

saying that all these rituals are done in order to seek the pleasures of God.

53 Ibid.
54 Ibid.
55 Ibid. Al-Razi maintained that these verses are mentioned by God for the sake of affirmation (al-
ta kid) and exaggeration (mubalaghah).
56 Tafsir , vol.9, 20-21.
57 Asas, 134.
58 Ibid., 135; Tafsir, vol. 2, 21.
59 Tafsir, vol. 10, 356.
60 Before this phrase, in the same verse it goes, “So give what is due to the kindred, the needy and the
wayfarer”(Al-Qur’an al-Rum 30:38).

184
In al-Tafslr al-Kabir, al-Razi elaborated further the interpretations of the

term wajb in the Qur’an. First, the attachment of the term ‘wajb’ to God is similar

to other attachment of created things to the divine God such as God’s house (bayt

Allah) the purpose of which is to render nobility and honour to such created things

(h/d sabll al-tasbrif). In other words, a creation of God becomes noble when its

name is specifically attached to the name of God, although ultimately it means that

the thing indeed belongs to God. Since all directions including the east and the west

are under the dominion of God, the phrase fa thamma wajb Allah means that ‘the

direction to which you are made to face (aiblah) belongs to God.’ matter of

cz>
fact, this is what is meant by qiblah, namely ‘the direction which has been specified
by God for people to face.61 Second, the term wajb also means aim and intention (al-

qasd wa al-niyyab) as shown by the verse “For me, I have set my face, firmly and

truly towards Him who created the heavens and the earth.”62

In general, the allegorical meanings ascribed by al-Razi for the term “Face of

God” is far from any anthropomorphic implication. < matter of fact, in


co

contradistinction from the view that the verse leads to anthropomorphism,63 al-Razi

regards the phrase “to God belong the East and the West” as the strongest proof in
denying the bodily aspect of God and affirming His transcendence.64 This is due to

the fact that this phrase makes clear that these two directions as well as other

directions are parts of God’s creatures:

...It is clear that these two directions (the East and the West) are in the
dominion of God (mamlukatdn. lahu). This is so since ‘direction’
means something extended (mumtad) in length, width and depth and
everything with this nature is divisible. Every divisible is composite
and compound and everything with these characteristics necessarily

61 Tafsir, vol. 2, 21. Hence what is called qiblah is that direction which Allah has determined and
asked the Muslims to face to in their five daily prayers.
62 Al-Qur’an, al-An'am 6:79.
63 According to al-Razi, the anthropomorphists argued that this verse yields anthropomorphism in
two regards. First, that the verse clearly shows that God has a face and the existence of a face
presupposes the existence of a body. Second, God also attributes Himself as ‘He who possesses
width’ (al-wasi) which is one of the attributes of a body. Tafsir, vol. 2, 21.

185
needs a creator...it is affirmed from this that God is the Creator of all
directions. The Creator is no doubt prior in existence than the
creation. Since God, the Creator before the creation, is beyond any
direction, it is necessary that He remains as such even after the
creation...65

Moreover, if God’s face is corporeal as claimed by the anthropomorphists, His

face will be designated in a certain direction which will contradict the last phrase of
the verse, that “wherever you turn, there is Allah’s face.”66

THE VISION OF ALLAH (RUYAT ALLAH)

Another topic that has a direct implication for our present discussion is the Vision of

God (Ru’yat Allah). It is a theological position which stipulates that God can be

seen by human beings in the Hereafter. Rejected categorically by the Mutazilah

due to its absurdity and serious impingement upon the divine transcendence, it is

defended, however, by the Ashairah and the Maturidiyyah as something important


in the belief of a Muslim.67 While the arguments against this position hinge upon the

impossibility of the Vision of God due to its physical implication, those who support

it depend on the textual proofs from the Qur’an and Hadiths. The later Ashairah,

however, endeavored to describe the nature of this Vision by linking it to a special

kind of Vision granted by God only to select humankind.

What is interesting with regard to this topic is for us to know al-Razi’s

position on this issue. Al-Razi who was an Ash’ari, as we have maintained

throughout the previous chapters, was consistent in rejecting the notion of

physicality with regard to the nature of God. Since the attack leveled by the

65 Ibid.
66 Tafsir, vol. 2, 21. Al-Razi also provided another possible allegorical meaning for the word ‘wajb’ in
this verse namely it refers to intention and objective (al-qasd \va al-niyyab) as implied by another
verse regarding Prophet Ibrahim, “I have set my face, firmly and truly towards Him who created the
heavens and the earth, and never shall I give partners to Allah” (al-An am 6:79).
67 For further reference to the Ashairah and the Mutazilah view on this issue, see Ibanah, 56-65;
Nihayat, 115-118; Arbain, 189-218; Ma'alim, 53-57. A lucid summary on this issue was written by
Fathalla Kholeif in his commentary of al-Razi’s debate in Controversies, 118-130.

186
Mutazilab mostly alleged that the affirmation of the Vision will lead to

anthropomorphism, al-Razi’s position as an Asb‘ari was, therefore, in a dilemma.

How did al-Razi defend the Ashairab position which seems to contradict his very

own principle? Did al-Razi agree with this position and if yes, how did he reconcile

this position with his overall rejection of the notion that God is beyond the physical

and temporal realm?

As have been mentioned earlier, the position of affirming the Vision of God is

strongly based on the Qur’anic verses and Prophetic tradition. Among the Qur’anic

verses which affirm the Vision of God is the verse that describes the gleaming faces

of the believers in the Hereafter upon seein their Lord as their reward in Paradise

CfQ
“...and some faces, that Day will beam, looking towards their Lord.”6 Another verse

reads, “To those who do right is a goodly reward and even more (ziyddab).”*
69 When

commenting upon this verse, the Prophet in one Hadith said that ziyadah meant

“seeing God’s face.”70 Some other verses mention the meeting of the true believers

with their Lord (liqa9 rabbibimf which implies the prerequisite of seein Him.71 72

CfQ
The Mu tazilites maintaining that human physical structure is necessary for

sight, generally denied the Vision of God. They took up their position on Qur’anic

verses which appear to deny Vision such as “Eyes cannot reach Him,” His words
to Moses: “You will not see Me,”73 and “It is not fit for man that God should speak

to him except by revelation or from behind a veil...”74 Some Mu tazilites interpreted

the Vision as knowledge which is related to the human intellect or heart, hence we

can see God through our hearts (qulub) which is equated with our knowledge of

8 Al-Qur’an, al-Qiyamah 75:22-3.


69 Al-Qur’an, Yunus 10:27.
70 Ma'alim, 54; Yusof Ali The Meaning of the Holy Qur’an, 487.
71 Maalim, 54-55.
72 Al-Qur’an, al-Anam, 6:103.
73 Al-Qur’an, al-Araf 7:143.
74 Al-Qur’an, al-Shura 42:51.

187
God.75 While others viewed that we will see God in the Hereafter, God will create for

man in the Hereafter the sixth sense through which we will see God.76

On the other hand, the Ashairah, being more faithful to scriptural authority,

affirmed the possibility of the Vision of God. Abu Hassan al-Ash'ari viewed that the
Vision of God, first and foremost, must be believed.77 In al-Ibanah, he said:

We hold that God will be seen in the next world by sight as the full
moon is seen in the night. So shall the faithful see Him, as we are told
in the traditions that come down on the authority of the Prophet of
God: and we believe that the infidels will be veiled from Him. When
the faithful see Him in Paradise as God said, “Yea, they shall be shut
out as by veil from their Lord on that Day”, [al-Qur’an, al-
Mutaffifin, 83:15] and that Moses asked God for the sight of Him in
this world and God manifested Himself to the mountain and turned it
to dust78 and taught Moses by it that He should not see Him in this
world.79

The story of Moses was an oft-quoted proof by the Ashairah in proving the

Vision of God. Al-Shahrastani argued that the fact that Prophet Moses asked to see

God shows that it is a possibility. Likewise, when God, in His reply, made the

condition for the Vision by asking Moses to observe the mountain, it also indicates

that the Vision is possible:

Now did Moses know that God could be seen? Or was he ignorant on
the subject? If he was ignorant, his knowledge of God ill-befitted the
dignity of a Prophet; if he did not know that it was a possibility, then
his knowledge agrees with the fact that his request was for the possible
not for the impossible. The reply, “You shall not see me” equally
points to the possibility, for God does not say “I’m not visible” but He
asserts impotence or lack of vision on the part of the seer...Thus the

75 Maqalat , vol.l, 238. This is the view of Abu al-Hudhayl.


76 Ibid., vol.l, 289. This is the view of Direr and Hafs. According to them, the sixth sense is
different from the senses we have now.
77 Nihdyat, 115-116. He, however, hesitated as to whether it was a special cognition, i.e., connected
only with an existing thing, or a perception virtually the same as knowledge in its connection, i.e. not
affecting, or being affected by, the object of Vision.
78 Al-Qur’an, al-A'raf, 7:139.
79 Ibanah, 51-52.

188
impediment is linked to a possibility and the impediment is referred to
the weakness of the instrument not to the impossibility itself.80

Later Ashairah had advanced more philosophical arguments in support of the

possibility of Vision of God. The common one, as pointed out by al-Razi, is the

argument based on existence that runs as follows: That the common reason of the

visibility of substance and accident, when analyzed, is either origination (al-huduth)

(which implies that both have point of beginning) or existence (al-wujud).

Origination cannot be the cause of visibility since it is regarded as an existence

preceded by non-existence, and non-existence (al-adam) cannot be part of the

principle. Therefore, the only cause of the visibility is existence. Existence is also

what is common to both the visible world (shahid) and the invisible world (gha’ib).

Extending this formula to the case of God, it follows that since God exists, He,
therefore, can be seen.81

Al-Razi, however, disagreed with this argument and regarded it as weak.

Using mostly the argument of the Mutazilah, he raised strong objections to the

rational proofs put forward by the Ashairah. His arguments, inter alia, attacked the

very notion of possibility. Since the arguments put forward by the Ashairah are
based on possibility (which he refers to with the terms imkan and sihhah), 82 it

cannot be a strong basis of argument in affirming the Vision of God. This is because

possibility is an ontological status that is preceded by non-being. The possibility of

Vision, therefore, is a judgment of privation or a non-existent quality (hukm

‘adamiy), not a positive judgment (sifah mawjudah), since it is based on something

absent, something absent cannot be the cause of something that exists. If

something possible can be the cause of something real, argued al-Razi, the world

so Nibayat, 118.
31 Arba'in, 191; Ma'alim, 54; Nibayat, 116.
82 It seems here that what al-Razi meant by sibbab here is equivalent to possible or contingent
(mumkin).
™Arbam, 192

189
would actually have existed when its existence was merely possible, and this entails
, -4- 84
eternity:

If possibility is a positive attribute (sifah mawjudah'y there is no


doubt that the world before its existence, existed in reality (sahib al-
wujud) and if possibility would be the existential attribute, it will
necessitate the eternity of the world.85

As to the argument by the Ashairah regarding the visible nature of

substance and accident, al-Razi viewed that substance and accident do not only share

in common the characteristics of visibility, but also other characteristics such as

being created (makhluqah). If ‘being created’ is re arded as the premise of the

CfQ
argument, it will lead to the conclusion that even God can therefore be created

(makhluqah). In other words, although God shares the attribute of existence

together with substance and accidents, His existence nevertheless cannot be

identified with the existence of the substance and accidents since His existence is

essentially distinct from the other two. This ar ument also reminds us of our
CfQ

previous discussion with regard to the position held by the Karramiyyah in proving

that Allah is in a direction and the counter-argument which al-Razi gave in


rebutting this argument.86 The Karramiyyah also argued based on the premise that

existence is the cause (eillah) of the principle which they held that for every two

existents, one of them must either subsist in the other (halan fi al-akhar) or be
distinct from the other in terms of direction.87 In the same vein, al-Razi refuted this

premise held by the Ashairah and affirmed that it is not existence but rather

origination (huduth) that is the cause of the principle.

The difficulty in employing rational proofs in substantiating the possibility of

the Vision of God led al-Razi to reject the possibility of arguing this position

through rational means. In Arbain, after putting forward a lengthy refutation on

See Chapter Three, 116.

190
the difficulty of the rational arguments supporting the possibility of the Vision of
God, al-Razi concluded, following the position of al-Maturidi,88 that we cannot

affirm the possibility of the Vision of God based on rational proofs.89 The

affirmation has to be based on scriptural authority:

What is preferred, according to us, is to say that it is the textual proofs


that indicate the Vision of God.90

Al-Razi’s disagreement with rational arguments for the possibility of the

Vision of God, nevertheless, does not lead him to the opposite position, namely, the

denial of the Vision of God, as done by the Mutazilah. As a matter of fact, he

disproved all the ar uments of the Mutazilah which are based on the Scripture

under the pretext of their misunderstanding the verses of the Qur’an.9

Al-Razi also maintained his stern position against anthropomorphism by

denying any physical implication of the Vision. For that matter, he employed ta\vil

by resorting to the view that the Vision is a spiritual Vision that God grants

specifically to those deserving the reward by God. He maintained that the Vision

which is alluded to in the verse, “and some faces, that Day will beam, looking

towards their Lord,” means the spiritual Vision (al-ru’yah) and not an ocular Vision

using the pupil of the eye but a special kind of Vision endowed by God to those
Q?
whom He wishes.

Based on the foregoing explanation, we can conclude that for al-Razi,

following the Qur’anic verses and Prophetic traditions that clearly stipulate it, the

88 See Abu Mansur al-Maturidi, Kitab al-Tawbid, ed. Fathalla Kholeif (Bayrut: Dar al-Mahriq, 1970),
77-85
89 Arba'in, 198. It seems that this difficulty was also shared by other later Asbairab. We found, for
example, in Shahrastani’s Nihayat Iqdam the same complication was reported. After having a
lengthy explication of the issue, he concluded, “On the whole it is best to re ard the visio Dei as a
tn

matter of scriptural attestation, in which case the story of Moses is the locus classicus’, but God
knows best what is true.” Nihayat 118.
90 Ma'alim, 54. Al-Razi conceded that in this regard he follows the position of al-Maturidi, who was
also of the view that rational proofs cannot exhaust the possibility of Vision of God and its
occurrence must be based on the textual argument. Al-Razi, al-Arbatn ft Usui al-Din, 198.
91 Arbam, 210-218.
92 Arba'in, 208.

191
Vision of God will certainly take place among the believers in the Hereafter. As far

as the rational proofs are concerned, especially those put forward by the Ashairah,

he regarded them as insubstantial since they can only prove the Vision at the level of

possibility. Although he affirmed the actualization of Beatific Vision, al-Razi was

consistent with his principle that this Vision does not imply anthropomorphism.

The Vision must not be in any way physical in nature but spiritual or in a manner

that God will create in accordance to the suitability of the believers. In this way, he

still held to his principle of denying anthropomorphic implications in the meanin of

CfQ
the textual verses. His view also proves that as an Asbairah, he still put great

emphasis on textual proof.

THE AFFIRMATION OF DIRECTION (AL-JIHAH) WITH REGARD TO

GOD

Among the anthropomorphic aspects that compel the mind of the mushabbihab into

holding the corporeal view of God, is the notion of direction (jihab). By affirming

that God is within certain direction, they support their views with rational

principle that for every two existents, one of them must either subsist in the other

(hdlan fi al-akbar) or be distinct from the other. Al-Razi also, as we have dealt with

earlier, has pointed out in great length the weaknesses of this principle.

In the Qur’an, there are several verses that literally imply the notion of

direction and which led the anthropomorphists to ascribe direction to God. Al-Razi

categorized ten kinds of Qur’anic verses brought forward by the anthropomorphists

which, according to them, clearly imply the affirmation of direction with regard to

God:

i) Verses that relate the act of God sittin on the Throne.


CfQ

ii) Verses which contain the term ‘above’ (fawq).

iii) Verses with the term ‘to be high’ (al-uluw).95 93 94

93 Al-Qur’an, Taha.
94 Al-Qur’an, al-An am 6:18, 61; al-Nahl 16:50

192
iv) Verses which contain the term ‘ascend towards Him’ (al-uruj ilaybi)?

v) Verses with the words ‘lowering’ and ‘sending down’ (inzal wa al-

9598
tanzil) 97 9699

vi) Verses which contain the word ‘towards’ (ila) describing God as the
end point of destination (intiba’al-gbayab)9*

vii) Verses with the phrase ‘they are veiled (mabjubun) from God’ which

implies a physical connotation."

viii) Verses which infer that God is in heaven (ft al-sama9).1"

ix) Verses containing the word ‘elevation towards Him’ (al-raf ilaybi)

especially in the case of the Prophet ‘Isa.101 102 103 104

x) Verses which indicate nearness to God (cindiyyab)192

There are also several Hadi ths which indicate similar meanings. Among them

is one related by Abu Hurayrah in which the Prophet says, “Whenever God decrees

creation, He will write something (kitaban) and, it is with him above the Throne (fa

buwa ‘indahu fawq al-‘arsb). [God says] Verily My blessing precedes My wrath

(inna rabmati sabaqat gbadabi)”193 Another Hadlth mentions that the Prophet

affirmed the positive answer of a maid of companion when the latter asked her

whether or not God was in the sky (/z al-sama9). Another textual argument used

by the anthropomorphists is the story of the ascension of the Prophet to heaven

(mi raj) which implies that God is specifically in the direction of above referring to

the verse in the Qur’an “Then He approached and came closer, and was a distance of

95 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:255; al-Saba’ 34:23; al-A‘la 87:1; al-Layl 92:20; al-Ma arij 70:4.
96 Al-Qur’an, al-Ma arij 70:4; al-Fatir 35:10.
97 These words occur more than 100 times in the Qur’an.
98 Al-Qur’an, al-Qiyamah 75:23; al-Sajadah 32:11; al-Hajj 22:48; al-Fajr 89:28.
99 Al-Qur’an, al-Mutaffifin 83:15.
100 Al-Qur’an, al-Mulk 67:17; Al-Qur’an, al-Naml 27:65.
101 Al-Qur’an, Ali ‘Imran 3:55; al-Nisa’ 4:157-8.
102 Al-Qur’an, al-Araf 7:206; al-Qamar 54:55; al-Tahrim 66:ll;Fussilat 41:37; al-Anbiya’ 21:19.
103 Bukhari, Sahib, vol. 7, 127.
104 Asas, 174.

193
but two bow-lengths (qaba qawsayri) or nearer. So did Allah convey the inspiration
to His servant what He meant to convey.”105

In Asas, al-Razi approached this issue from two aspects: first by reaffirming

the rational argument on the divine transcendence (of the direction and body)

against the anthropomorphists’ rational principle that God is localized in a direction.

From this affirmation, he moved on to assert that the rational proof that God is

beyond the notion of body and direction renders it necessary for us to interpret the

verses regarding the anthropomorphic nature of God to other than their literal

meaning. In other words, once the transcendence of God is affirmed through

strong rational principle and scriptural proofs, the meanin must not contradict this

CfQ
principle. For, this would render the Qur’an and the Hadi th contradictory to each

other as well as to reason.

Al-Razi also opined that the safest way for many people in dealing with this

issue was to deny the literal meanings of the verses as held by the early generation

(al-salaf) and refrain from looking for further meanings.106 Nevertheless, as a

mutakallimun who put very much emphasis on a systematic approach to kalam and

also on the consistent and comprehensive understanding of the meaning of the

Qur’an as well as holding to the view that the Qur’an is overall understandable, al-

Razi went on to explain the proper meaning of the anthropomorphic verses. He put

forward a few arguments in refuting the literal meanings of the verses held by the

anthropomorphists regarding direction. His method was to examine the context in

which the verses take place and to detect the contradiction between the literal

meanings with the whole context in which the verses occur. For example, with

regard to the phrase in the Qur’an which says that God is ‘sitting on the Throne,’

the physical sitting or settling on the Throne should be rejected since the contextual

meaning which can be understood from the verses prior and after this particular
>

verse, does not support the alleged meaning. The preceding verse that says,

105 Al-Qur’an, al-Najm 53:8-10.


106 Asas, p. 175.

194
revelation from Him who created the earth and the heavens on high,” 7 clearly

demonstrates that God is not specified by any notion of direction. While the verse

which follows verse 5, says, “To Him belongs what is in the Heavens and on the

earth and all between them, and all beneath the soil,” shows the impossibility of God

being physically settled on the throne, which is in the heavens. If al-sama9 which

literally means that which is in the direction of above (sumuw wa fawqiyyab), and

everything in it belong to God, it is, therefore, impossible for God to be in the same

direction as that which He has created. This situation, according to al-Razi, is


equivalent to saying that “God belongs to God” which is absurd.107 On the other
108 109

hand, the general meaning of both the two verses which precede and follow that

particular verse alludes to the perfection of God’s power and the apex of His

greatness in Divinity (ghdyat uzmatibV). Hence it is implausibe, as far as the overall

understanding of the Qur’an is concerned, that the verse which comes in the middle

conveys a contradictory meanin to the two other verses.


CfQ

His second argument against the physical implication of istiwa’ is that the

implication of understanding ‘istawa as a physical sitting is that God will be

composed of parts:

the part of the one who sits on the Throne which takes place on the
right side of the Throne must be different from the part which takes
place on the left part of the Throne. This will necessarily lead to
compartment and composition in the essence of God, which is
impossible.10

Emphasizing again the purity and transcendence of God, al-Razi added that if

we accepted the physical sitting of God on the Throne, we will be forced to accept

the fact that God can reside physically in other places, which means that God will be

mingling with dirty and impure things (qadhurdt wa al-najasdt). Al-Razi also

argued based on the verse which says that “and the angels will be on its [the

107 Al-Qur’an, Ta ha 20:4.


108 Asos, 176.
109 Ibid., 177.

195
Throne] sides, and eight will that day bear the Throne of your Lord above them,”

saying that if the ‘arsh is the physical place of God, the angels then are construed as

carrying God while God, who preserves and maintains the creations, is not in need of
111 Scripturally, the notion of God sitting physically on a Throne also
them.110

contradicts many other verses which indicate that God is near to human beings and

that God is always with them, such as, “We are nearer to him than His jugular

“It is He who is God in heavens


vein,”112 “He is with you wherever you may be,”113 114

and God on earth.”

Hence, the appropriate meanin of the term ‘istawa cala al-arsh’ according to

CfQ
al-Razi, is the complete mastery, power and possession of God over the Throne.

This meaning, according to al-Razi, is established on the principle of the Arabic

language used by the expert of the language as shown, for example, by the

following poetry:

man has taken possession (istawa) over Iraq,


without the usage of any sword and the spill of any blood115

One may question that if it is the metaphorical meaning that is meant by God

in this verse, God is then ignorant of the proper word to be used in conveying the

message to human beings and this is an imperfection with regard to God. To this

view, al-Razi replied that God reveals the Qur’an based on the custom (urf) and

convention of the people, and the conveying message through allegorical


O

expressions is not something strange to the Arabs. Even in the Qur an there are

numerous verses that comes with such expressions as in the verses, “But it is Allah

who deceives them (khadiuhum) ”116 “The unbelievers plotted against God and Allah

110 Al-Qur’an, al-Haqqah 69:17.


111 Asos, 177.
112 Al-Qur’an, Qaf 50:16.
113 Al-Qur’an, al-Hadid 57:4.
114 Al-Qur’an, al-Zukhruf 43:84.
115 Asas, 178.
116 Al-Qur’an, al-Nisa’ 4:142.

196
too plotted against them,” “Allah makes fun of them.” All these verses do not

convey their literal meaning since this would go against the divine transcendence.

As to the reason why it is the Throne which is specifically mentioned in the verse as

the object of divine possession and not other creations, al-Razi asserted that it is due

to the fact that among the originated existence (al-mawjuddt al-muhdathah\ the

Throne is the greatest creation, and God administers all matters in the world through

the Throne as He created all creation based on the creation in the Throne.119
117 118

With re ard to the verses which contain directional connotations such as


CfQ

“/hwq” and “mw,” al-Razi remarked that these terms do not refer to direction but

rather to the power and domination of God over His creation. This is apparent in the

case of the term ‘fawq' when in the same verse, it is also linked to other similar

attributes such as al-Qahhar which is evident in the verse “He is the Omnipotent

over His worshippers (fawqa ‘tbadih?).”120 In addition, if they refer to the direction,

it will not necessarily be a praiseworthy position for God since in this case, what

makes God praiseworthy is not His essence and attributes but his directional

position.121 122 123

GOD’S HAND

The term hand of God is used sometimes in its singular form, yad (one hand) as in

the verse “Say, all bounties are in the Hand of Allah, He granted them to whom He

pleases,” “The Hand of Allah is over their hands,” and in some other verses it is

mentioned with “two hands” such as “Allah said, “O Iblis! what prevents you from
prostrating yourself to one whom I have created with My [two] hands,”124 and “Nay,

117 Al-Qur’an, Ali ‘Imran 3:54.


118 Al-Qur’an, al-Baqarah 2:15.
119 Asas, 179.
120 Al-Qur’an, al-An am 6:61.
121 Asas, 180-181.
122 Al-Qur’an, Al-‘Imran 3:73.
123 Al-Qur’an, al-Fath 57:29.
124 Al-Qur’an, al-Sad 38:75.

197
both His hands are widely outstretched, He gives and spends as He pleases.”125 This

different occurrence, nevertheless, is to al-Razi, does not make any change in his

interpretation of the verses. For both are not indicative of a physical organ of God.

Rather, they refer to other meanings, which are more appropriate to the divine

qualities of God.

Al-Razi assigned three meanings to the term hand: first, it refers to the

meaning of power (qudrab). Linguistically, when it is said that “the hand of the king

is over the hand of the people,” it means that his power is predominant over his

citizens. The meaning of ‘hand’ perfectly indicates the meanin of power and it is

CfQ
further supported by the expression that “this state is in the hand of this leader,”

which means that the leader has power over the state even if he himself does not

possess physical hand!1 Second, the term ‘hand’ conveys the meaning of bounty

(nimab) since hand is the efficient means by which bounties are granted. But in

this case, the semantic relation between the term ‘hand’ and the meaning of bounty,

to al-Razi, is in the form of a relation between the cause and the effect (al-sabab

'ala al-musabbab). In other words, the meaning of bounty, as something that is

granted by the hand is also inherent in the meaning of hand. The third meanin of

CfQ
hand is more mechanical and linguistic, namely, as a relation of words that function

as an affirmation in the Qur’anic verse “...spend something in charity before your


private consultation” (fa qaddimu bayna yaday naiwakum sadaqab).127 In this

verse, there is no indication of the meanin of hand involved since it only serves as a
CfQ

linguistic tool.

Based on the above linguistic preliminaries, al-Razi further assigned these

meanings to various verses in the Qur’an in which the term ‘hand’ occur. In the

verse “The Hand of Allah is over their hands,”128 the meaning of hand here is power,

that the omnipotence of God predominates over the power of His creatures. As for

125 Al-Qur’an, al-Ma’idah 5:64.


126Asds, 141.
127 Al-Qur’an, al-Mujadalah 58:12.
128 Al-Qur’an, al-Fath 48:10.

198
the verse regarding the Jews who claim that the hand of God is tied up (yadullah
i 17Q
maghlulan), the meanin of hand in this verse refers to bounty while the whole

CfQ
verse means the Jews believed that the bounties of God are withheld from them.1

This is also congruent with the following phrase in the same verse which is

indicative of the granting of bounties to creatures, “Nay, both His hands are widely

outstretched, He gives and spends (of His bounty) as He pleases.”

Al-Razi also refuted the views of scholars who assigned the meaning of ‘two

hands’ as ‘two attributes which subsist in the divine essence from which a noble and

distinguished creation (referring to Adam) had been created.’131


129This
130 refers to the

verse “Allah said, ‘O Iblis! What prevents you from prostrating yourself to one
whom I have created with My [two] hands.”132 They based their argument on the

fact that it is due to the creation by the two attributes of God that has made Adam

noble person and become the reason for the angels to prostrate before him.

Disagreeing with al-Razi, they questioned that if the two hands were interpreted to

mean power, then why is it that other creations which were also created by God by

His power were similarly not commanded by God to be prostrated to by the

an els?133 Al-Razi replied that if it is because of being created by two hands that
CfQ

Adam had been conferred with more nobility, hence the creation of beasts (bahalm)

and cattle (an dm.) would be nobler than Adam since it is mentioned in the Qur’an
that they were created by many hands [of God]134 “See they that it is We who have

created for them - among other things which our hands have fashioned- cattle,

which is under their dominion?”135 The number of hands, according to al-Razi, is not

indicative of any numerical representation, rather it refers to the abundance of divine

129 Al-Qur’an, al-Ma’idah 5:64.


130 Asas, 142.
131 Ibid.
132 Al-Qur’an, Sad 38:75.
133 They also questioned that the term “two hands” cannot mean power since the term has the
connotation of two things while power only means one. Asas, 143.
134 Ibid.
135 Al-Qur’an, Yasin 36:71.

199
providence which has been given to God’s creation. ‘Hand’ also is a metaphorical
expression of something that is done by someone or somebody.136

CONCLUSION: AL-RAZI’S GENERAL METHOD IN TREATING THE


ANTHROPOMORPHIC VERSES

From the foregoing discussion, we can observe some important methods employed

by al-Razi in dealing with anthropomorphic verses:

i) Since divine transcendence occupies an important place in al-Razi’s

interpretation of the anthropomorphic verses, al-Razi consistently applied

tawil with re ard to those expressions whose literal meanings appear to


CfQ

contradict the principle of divine transcendence which have already been

established based on reason and other clear verses of the Qur’an. Whatever

alternative meanin that he assigned to the anthropomorphic expressions


CfQ

must be in line with the denial of their apparent meaning which are contrary

to the divine transcendence. This is also in accordance to his systematic

approach in interpreting the Qur’an which emphasizes consistency and

coherence between the meaning of all the Qur’anic verses.

ii) As a linguist, al-Razi’s inclination to discuss the problem from the linguistic

point of view is apparent. For example, he manifested an independent mind

in exhausting each and every meaning of a word without necessarily being

confined to the classical interpretation of the word or a verse. By exhausting

both ordinary and terminological meanings word used in the Arabic


O

language, he widened the semantic field of a word before assigning proper

meaning to it.

His mastery of Arabic literature also assisted him in analyzing the proper

usage of given word, evidenced, among others, by the fact that many

136 Asas, 144.

200
time he cited pieces of evidence (shawahid) from pre-Islamic Arabic poetry

to corroborate his explanation of a word. For example, in affirming the

allegorical meaning of the word istiwa’ in the Qur’an as istila’ (complete

mastery and power) and to show that this meanin is an established one

CfQ
within the Arabic language, he cited classical Arabic poetry: “man has taken

possession (istiwaj over Iraq, without the usage of any sword and the spill of

any blood.”137

iv) Although al-Razi was not strict in assigning various meanings to certain

words, he nevertheless did not stretch the meanin to the extent it

CfQ
contradicted the normal usage of Arabic language. He often regarded the

‘normal usage of the word’ as something canonical in determining a certain

meaning of a word. For example, in the case of the temi ‘face of God’ (wajh

Allah), al-Razi chose the meaning ‘the essence of God’ based on the normal

usage of the Arabic language which usually used the term wajh to refer to

the most important aspect of a matter, such as wajh al-qawm, which refers

to the head of the community and wajh al-amr which refers to the essence

In another case which is not mentioned in this chapter,


of a matter.138 139

namely that regarding the verse ‘laysa ka mithlihi shay/ where al-Razi

rejected the interpretation of some mufassirun who viewed this verse as

having a double meaning due to the repetitious words ‘fcu’ and ‘mithlj hence

interpreted the phrase as “nothing likes unto His likeness,” as if it affirms

the existence of God’s resemblance (mithl). Al-Razi’s rejected this

interpretation based on the fact that it is not a common usage of the Arabic

language. This kind of linguistic structure is used as a kind of rhetoric

(mubalaghah), but the Arabs, according to al-Razi used this kind of phrase

to refer to the ‘person’ not the resemblance.

137 Asas, 178.


138 See page 184-185 in this chapter.
139 Ta fsir, vol.9, 584.

201
v) Al-Razi often used simple rational arguments in disproving the impossibility

and inconsistency of the anthropomorphists’ literal interpretations. This is

supported by the explanation of the context of the verses. Although this

method is also associated with the Mutazilah, a few exceptions in al-Razi’s

explanations such as in the case of the Vision of God where he aligned

himself to the scriptural authority although no rational evidence satisfied him

in affirming the actualization of the Vision, have rendered him different from

the method of the Mutazilah.

202
CONCLUSION

From the foregoing study of al-Razi’s view on divine transcendence and

anthropomorphism, it has become clear that al-Razi, like al-Ghazali before him,

believed that divine transcendence should be upheld in an absolute sense, as

established by the Qur’an and the principle of reason. For that matter the

understanding of the anthropomorphic expressions in the Qur’an and Hadiths

must be in accordance with this unswerving principle of divine transcendence.

Our examination of his refutation of the Musbabbihab’s views also demonstrates

that al-Razi extensively utilized the logical and philosophical method which

became one of the important hallmarks of the later Asharite mutakallimun. in

explicating the theological views as well as refuting the views of their adversaries.

This is in line with what has been observed by Ibn Khaldun who himself wrote

Lubab al-Muhassal, summary of al-Razi s theological masterpiece, Muljassal,

that al-Razi was the first among the later scholars (muta ’akhkbirm) who

successfully combined the problems of philosophy with those of kalam.1


2 3With

this new approach, al-Razi was also deemed as offering a more systematic

theology. It is also important to note that through al-Razi’s forceful refutations

of anthropomorphism, more elaborative arguments concerning the subject of

God’s otherness or differentness (mukhalafab) were included by later Ash'arite


mutakallimun in their expositions on the Islamic creed4 such as the detailed

discussion on the impossibility of divine essence being subjected to corporeal and

bodily qualities such as the characteristics of substance and accident (jawbar wa

arad): that God cannot be in a space and direction, and that God cannot be seen,

touched, smelled and so on. Al-Razi’s Kitab Asas al-Taqdis, in this case, which

1 Ed. Rafiq al-cAjam (Bayrut: Dar al-Mashriq, 1995).


2 Muqaddimah, 466.
3 Fazlur Rahman, Islam (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979), 96.
4 “Some Muslim Discussions”, 87.

203
was specifically written to refute the literalist position of the two main sects of

the musbabbibab, namely the Karramiyyab and the extreme Hartabilab, has

served as a repository of rational and textual arguments for the later Asharite

mutakallimun in expounding their arguments against the anthropomorphists.

This is evident from the writings of al-Razi’s Asb arf successors such as al-

Taftazani and al-Iji, who utilized several important principles that were

originated and formulated by al-Razi in their exposition of the principle of


kalam.5 We have also demonstrated in our study that al-Razi, through his Kitab

Asas al-Taqdfs, has identified and deliberated at length, as he always did in his

other works, all his adversaries’ arguments before putting forward his own

arguments. While this work benefited the later Asb arf mutakallimun, it also

invited criticism from their theological adversaries, notably by later Hanbalite

scholars such as Ibn Taymiyyah in his work Ta’sis al-Radd ‘ ala Asas al-Taqdfs.

Our study also reveals that al-Razi’s priority in understanding the

scripture is on the internal consistency of the whole message of religion revealed

by God to humankind. There must not be any contradiction in God’s message

especially with those principle which were already established rationally and

scripturally. The Qur’an as a clear book (kitabun mubfri) which was revealed by

the Wise God (al-Hakim) must also be clear to human reason. In the case of the

ambiguous verses (mutasbabibat), they must be understood through the

guidance of the clear and established principles of reason and other verses with

established meanings (muhkamat). Hence, after having made clear the specific

criteria of mudkamat and mutasbabibat of the Qur’an, al-Razi maintained that if

there are any contradictions between the literal meaning of any verses of the

Qur’an or Hadith with established rational principles and other established

verses, the literal meanings must, first and foremost, be denied. More so when

5 Heer, “Priority of Reason”, 181-183.

204
the literal meaning is detrimental to the principle of divine transcendence. What

follows after that, according to al-Razi, is either that we leave the meanings to

God, as done by the salaf, or we interpret them to come to a more acceptable

meanin within the bounds of the established verses, linguistic applicability and
CfQ
sound reason. This is basically the principle underlying al-Razi’s treatment of

anthropomorphic verses.

Al-Razi was often judged by his critics as being influenced by the

Mu tazilah.6 This representation becomes clearer when he proposed ta \vil, the

allegorical interpretation, which has been the distinctive characteristic of the

Mu tazilah method in the interpretation of the Scripture, as being the proper

solution for dealing with anthropomorphic verses. Without denying the

parallelism of much of his arguments with those of the Mu tazilah, we, however,

have shown in our study that al-Razi was still an Ash arI and was consistent in

using the epistemological framework of Ash arI kalam in dealing with the

anthropomorphic issue. In Chapter Two, it has been established that al-Razi was

in disagreement with the Mu tazilah on the issue of the nature of the divine

attributes and their relation to the divine essence. While concurring with the

Mu tazilah on the necessity of ta \vH when dealing with those verses which

contradict rational principles, he outlined some exceptions to give greater room to

the priority of revelation as we have shown in the particular case of the Beatific

Vision in Chapter Five.

Throughout our study, the problem of the relation between reason and

revelation is also clarified. In contrast to the Western religious tradition in which

reason and revelation are on opposite sides, the Islamic tradition resolves the issue

by identifying the role of reason as the true interpreter of the scripture. The

exaltation of God’s Words and the understandability of the Scripture must not be

at the expense of reason. As shown by al-Razi, the consistency of the scriptural

6 Ignaz Goldziher, ‘Aus der Theologie das Fakhr al-Din al-Razi’, Der Islam, iii (1912) quoted in Watt,
Islamic Philosophy, 95; Theology, xv.

205
message can be established by adhering to established rational principles while

emphasizing the most important aspect of God, namely, His transcendence as an

important message of the Qur’an as the Word of God.

The method employed by al-Razi in dealing with anthropomorphic verses

can offer solutions for overcoming extremism in dealing with the Scripture,

problem which prevails even in our present day between two extreme positions:

strict adherence to the literal meaning of the text, on the one hand, and the

liberal method of interpreting the meaning of the text, on the other. The former

can be seen from the present-day emergence of the Wahhabf-Salaff group which

traces their origin to the Hanbalites, while the latter, indubitably, is gaining

momentum in the present age with the emergence of “post-modernist” Muslim

thinkers with their ‘deconstruction’ hermeneutical method employed in

interpreting the Qur’an, in emulation of the Biblical tradition of the Christian

West. We believe that al-Razi’s approach is a good antidote for both extremes.

206
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Abrahamov, B. (1992). Fakhr al-Din al-Razi on God’s knowledge of the


particulars. ORIENS (33),133-155.

Abrahamov, B. (1992). Ibn Taymiyya on the agreement of reason with tradition.


The Muslim World, LXXXII (3-4), 256-273.

Abrahamov, B. (1995). The Bi-la Kayfa doctrine and its foundations in Islamic
theology. ARABICA, Journal of Arabic and Islamic Studies, Tome XLII
(3): 365-379.

Abrahamov, B. (1996). Anthropomorphism and interpretation of the Qur’an in


the theology of al-Qasim Ibn Ibrahim. Leiden: E.J.Brill.

Abrahamov, B. (2002). Fakhr a-Din al-Razi on the knowability of God’s essence


and attributes. ARABICA, Journal of Arabic and Islamic Studies, Tome
XLIX, Fascicule (2), 204-230.

Abu Ya'la, n.d. Tabaqat al-Hanabilah. (vols 1-2). Bayrut: Dar al-Ma rifah.

Abu Zahrah, Muhammad. (1989). Tarikh al-mazahib al-Islamiyyah. Al-Qahirah:


Dar al-Fikr al-Arabi.

Adler, M. J. (ed.). (1952). The great ideas, A syntopicon of great books of the
Western World. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc.

Adler, M. J. (1980). How to think about God: a guide for 20th century pagan.
New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.

Al-Amidi, Sayf al-Din. (1971). Ghayat al-maram fl ilm al-kalam. Ed. Hassan
Mahmud 'Abd Latif. Al-Qahirah: Lujnah Ihya’ al-Turath al-Islami.

Anawati, G. C. (1983). Fakhr al-Din al-Razi. In The Encyclopedia of Islam. New


edition, (vol. 2., 751-755).

Arberry, A. J. (1957). Revelation and reason in Islam. London: George Allan &
Unwin.

207
Al-Asfahani, al-Raghib. (1992). Risalah fi zikr al-wahid wa al-ahad. Ed. 'Umar
al-Sarisi. Amman: Jami'at al-Isra’.

Al-Ash'ari, Abu Hasan (1940). al-Ibanah an usul al-diyanah. (W. C. Klein,


Trans.). New Haven: American Oriental Society.

Al-Ash'ari, Abu Hasan. (1990). Maqalat al-Islamiyyih wa ikhtilif al-musallih.


(vols. 1-2). Ed. Muhy al-Din 'Abd al-Hamid. Bayrut: Maktabah al-
'Asriyyah.

Al-Attas, Syed Muhammad Naquib. (1986). A commentary on the fujjat al-


siddiq of Nur al-Dih al-RanOT Kuala Lumpur: Ministry of Culture.

Al-Azmeh, Aziz. (1988). Orthodoxy and Hanbalite fideism. Arabica: Revue


D’Etudes Arabes, XXXV (3), 253-266

Al-Baghdadi, Abu Mansur. (1935). Al-Farq bayna al-firaq. (K. C. Seelye, Trans.)
New York: AMS Press. Part Two, (A. S. Halkin, Trans.). Tel Aviv:
Palestine Publishing.

Al-Baghdadi, Abu Mansur. (1981). Usui al-din. Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-
Ilmiyyah.

Bajuri, Ibrahim. (1826). Hashiyah ala matn al-Sanusiyyah. Bangkok: Maktabah


Muhammad al-Nahdi.

Bajuri, Ibrahim, n.d. Shard jawbarat al-tawdid, Bayrut: Mu’assasah Anas bin
Malik.

Baydawi, 'Abd Allah. (2002). Tawalical-anwar min matalUal-anzar. Along with


Mahmud Isfahani’s commentary Ma tali cal-anzar, Shard tawali cal-anwar.
(vols. 1-2). (E. E. Calverley & J. W. Pollock, Trans.) Brill: Leiden.

Bello, I. A. (1989). The medieval controversy between philosophy and orthodoxy:


ijmacand ta \vil in the conflict between al-Ghazall and Ibn Rushd. Leiden:
E.J. Brill.

Bosworth, C.E. (1978). Karramiyyah. In The Encyclopaedia of Islam. New


Edition, (vol. 4, 667-669).

Ceylan, Yasin. (1996). Theology and tafsir in the major works of Fakhr al-Dih
al-Razi. Kuala Lumpur: ISTAC.

208
Craig, W. L. (2000). The Kalam cosmological argument. Eugene: Wipf and Stock
Publishers.

Daghim, Samih. (1998). Maws u at mustalahat ilm al-kalam al-Islamf. (vols. 1-


2). Bayrut: Maktabah Lubnan Nashirun.

Daghim, Samih. (2001). Maws u at mustalahat al-Imam Fakhr al-Dirt al-Razi.


Bayrut: Maktabah Lubnan Nashirun.

Al-Dhahabl, al-Husayn. (1986). al-Tafsir wa al-mufassirun, Al-Qahirah: Dar al-


Kutub al-Hadithah.

Dhanani, Alnoor. (1994). The physical theory of kalam. Leiden: E.J.Brill.

Ess, J. V. (2000). Tashblh wa Tanzlh. In The Encyclopaedia of Islam. New


Edition, (vol.10, 341-344).

Fakhry, Majid. (1983). A history of Islamic philosophy. (2nd edn.). New York:
Columbia University Press.

Al-Farabi, Abu Nasr. (1985). Mabadi’ ar a’ahi al-madihah al-fadlah. (R. Walzer,
Trans.) Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Al-Faruqi, Ismail Raji. (1998). Islam and other faiths. Ed. Ataullah Siddiqi.
Leicester: The Islamic Foundation and The International Institute of
Islamic Thought (HIT).

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1963). Tahafut al-falasifah. (Sabih Ahmad Kamali,


Trans.). Lahore: Pakistan Philosophical Congress.

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1980). al-Mankhul min ta liqat al-usul. (2nd edn.). Ed.
Muhammad Hassan Haitu, Dimashq: Dar al-Fikr.

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1986). Munazarah fi al-radd ala al-Nasara. Ed. 'Abd
al-Majid al-Najjar. Bayrut: Dar al-Gharb al-Islami.

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1988). al-Arba mfiusul al-din. Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub
al-'Ilmiyyah.

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1988). Maarij al-quds fI madarij marifat al-nafs.


Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah.

209
Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1991). Ihya’ ilium al-dih (8 vols.). Bayrut: Dar al-Fikr.

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1991). Mishkat al-anwar. (W.H.T. Gairdner, Trans.).


Reprint. Lahore: Sh. Muhammad Ashraf.

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid.(1992). Maqsad al-asna fishard asma’ Allah al-fusna.


(D. Burrell & N. Daher, Trans.). Cambridge: The Islamic Text Society,

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1994). al-Iqtisad fi al-i tiqad. ‘Abd Rahman Abu Zayd,
Trans.). New Delhi: Kitab Bhavan.

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (1994). Iljam al aw am an ilm al-kalam, in Majmuat


rasa’ll al-Imam al-Ghazall. Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah.

Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid. (2002). Fay sal al-tafiiqah. (S.A. Jackson, Trans.).
Oxford University Press.

Gilson, E. (1941).God and philosophy. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Gilson, E. (1969). The idea of God and the difficulties of atheism. In The great
ideas today 1969. Ed. R.M. Hutchins & M.J. Adler. Chicago: Encyclopedia
Brittanica Inc.

Gimaret, D. (2000). Tawhid. In The Encyclopaedia of Islam. New Edition.


(vol.10, 389).

Heer, N. (1993). The priority of reason in the interpretation of scripture: Ibn


Taymiyah and the mutakallimun. In Literary heritage of classical Islam.
Ed. Mustansir Mir. Princeton: The Darwin Press, Inc.

Ibn Abi Usaybi'ah. (1882). Uyun al-anba’ fi tabaqat al-atibba’. Al-Qahirah:


Matba‘ah Wahbiyyah.

Ibn Faris. (1999). Mujam maqayis al-lughah. Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-
‘Ilmiyyah.

Ibn Hajar, n.d. al-Durar al-kaminah fi al-ayan al-mi‘at al-thaminah. Bayrut:


Dar al-Jil.

Ibn Hanbal, Abdullah b. Ahmad. (1985). Al-Sunnah. Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-
Ilmiyyah.

210
Ibn Hazm. (1985). al-Fasl ff al-milal wa al-ahwa’ wa al-nihal, (vols. 1-5).
Bayrut: Dar al-JIl.

Ibn al-Jawzi, Abu al-Faraj 'Abd al-Rahman. (2000). Dafu sbubah al-tashbih bi
akuffi al-tanzih. Ed. Hassan Saqqaf. Reprint. Amman: Dar al-Imam al-
Nawawi.

Ibn al-Jawzi, Abu al-Faraj 'Abd al-Rahman. (2002). Kitab akhbar al-sifat. (M.
Swartz, Trans.). Leiden: Brill.

Ibn Kathir. (2000). Tafsir al-Qur’an al-AzLn (vols.1-5) Bayrut: Dar Ihya’ al-
Turath al-'Arabi.

Ibn Khaldun, n.d. Muqaddimah. Bayrut: Mu’assasat al-'Alami li al-Matbu'ah.

Ibn Khallikan. (1843). Wafayat al-ayan. (M. D. Slane, Trans.). London: Johnson
Reprint Corporation.

Ibn Khuzaymah, Muhammad bin Ishaq. (1983). Kitab al-Tawhfd wa ithbat sifat
al-rabb. Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah.

Ibn Manzur, (1990). Lis an al-drab (vols.1-15). Bayrut: Dar al-Sadir.

Ibn Qudamah, (1985). Tahrim al-nazar fikutub ahi al-kalam. (George Makdisi,
Trans.). Cambridge: E.J.W Gibb Memorial.

Ibn Qutaybah. n.d. Ta\vil mukhtalif al-Jiadith. Bayrut:‘Alam al-Kutub.

Ibn Sina. (1973). Danish nama-i ala’L (P. Morewedge, Trans.). London: Routlege
& Kegan Paul.

Ibn Taymiyyah. (1985). Muwafaqat sahih al-manqul li sarih al-maqU. Bayrut:


Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah.

Ibn Taymiyyah. (1998). Kitab al-asma’ wa al-sifat. (vols.1-2) Bayrut: Dar al-
Kutub al-'Ilmiyyah.

Al-Isfahani, al-Raghib. (1992). Mufradat alfaz al-Quran. Ed. Safwan 'Adnan


Dawudi Dimashq: Dar al-Qalam.

211
Al-Jabbar, ‘Abd. (1965). Sahrh usd al-khamsah. Ed. ‘Abd. Karim ‘Uthman. Al-
Qahirah: Maktabah Wahbah.

Al-Jurjani, ‘All Muhammad. (1991). al-Tarifat. Al-Qahirah: Dar al-Kitab al-


Misri.

Al-Juwayni, ‘Abd Malik ibn ‘Abd Allah. (1969). al-Shamil fiusd al-dih. Ed. ‘All
Sami Nashshar, Faysal Badirun & Shuhir Mukhtar. Iskandariyyah:
Mansha’ah al-Ma‘arif.

Al-Juwayni, ‘Abd Malik ibn ‘Abd Allah. (2000). Kitab al-irshad. (P. E. Walker,
Trans.). Reading: Garnet Publishing.

Kafrawi, Shalahudin. (1999). Fakhr al-Din al-Razi’s sources of ta’wil: between


revelation and reason. Islamic Quarterly, XLIII (3), 187-199.

Al-Kawthari, Muhammad Zahid. (1994). Maqalat al-Kawthari. Al-Qahirah: al-


Maktabah al-Azhariyyah li al-Turath.

Kholeif, Fathalla. (1969). Fakhr al-Dih al-Razi. Al-Qahirah: Dar al-Maarif.

Kholeif, Fathalla. (1984). A Study on Fakhr al-Dirt al-Razi and his controversies
in Transoxiana. Bayrut: Dar al Mashriq.

Kinberg, L. (1988). Muhkamat and mutashabihat (Koran 3/7): implication


Koranic pair of terms in medieval gesis. ARABICA, XXXV (2),143-
172.

Laoust, H. (1979). Ahmad b. Hanbal. In The Encyclopaedia of Islam. New


Edition, (vol.l, 272-277).

Ma’sumi, M. Saghir Hasan. (1970). Imam RazTs ‘ ilm al-akhlaq. English


translation of his Kitab al-nafs wa al-ruh wa shard quwabuma with
introduction and commentary. Islamabad: Islamic Research Institute.

Al-Maturidi, Abu Mansur. (1970). Kitab al-Tawhid. Ed. Fathalla Kholeif.


Bayrut: Dar al-Mashriq.

MacDonald, D. B. (1985). Muslim theology, jurisprudence and constitutional


theory. London: Darf Publishers Limited.

212
McAuliffe, J. D. (1990). Fakhr al-Din al-Razi on God as al-khaliq. In God and
creation: an ecumenical symposium. Ed. D. B. Burrell & B. McGinn.
Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.

McCarthy, R. J. (1953).Tbe theology of Ash drl. Beirut. Imprimarie Catholique.

Michot, Yahya J. (2003). A Mamluk theologian’s commentary on Avicenna’s


risalah adhawiyya: being a translation of a part of the Dar’ al-ta arud of
Ibn Taymiyya, with introduction, annotation, and appendices. Journal of
Islamic Studies. 2 parts. 14 (2),149-203 & 14 (3), 309-363.

Mukhtar, Suhayr. (1971). Al-Tajsim ‘inda al-Muslimih: madhhab al-


Karramiyyah. al-Qahirah: al-Qahirah University.

Muslim. (1998). Sahih bi shard al-Nawawf (vols. 1-18). Bayrut: Dar al-Marifah.

Nashshar, All Sami. (1947). Manahij al-bahth inda mufakkirf al-Islam. Egypt:
Dar al-Fikr al-Arabi.

Nasr, Seyyed Hossein & Leaman, Oliver. (1996). History of Islamic philosophy
(vols. 1-2). London: Routledge.

Netton, I. R. (1989). Allah transcendent: studies in the structure and semiotics of


Islamic philosophy, theology and cosmology. Surrey: Curzon Press.

Peters, J.R.T.M. (1976). God’s created speech. Leiden: E.J. Brill.

Pines, S. (1997). Studies in Islamic atomism. (M. Schwarz, Trans.). Jurusalem:


The Magnes Press.

Al-Qastalani, Abu c Abbas. (1990). Irshad al-sarili sharh sahih al-Bukharf(vols.


1-15). Bayrut: Dar al-Fikr.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1905). Muhassal afkar al-mutaqaddimih wa al-


mutakhkhirin min al-ulama’ wa al-hukama’ wa al-mutakallimin. Al-
Qahirah: Matba'ah Husainiyyah.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1934). Kitab al-arba m fi usuL al-din. Hyderabad:


Matba'ah Majlis Da’irah al-Macarif al-Usmani.

213
Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1976). Law ami‘ al-bayyin at shark asm a’ Allah Ta ala
wa-sifat. Ed. Taha ‘Abd. Rauf Sa‘ad. Al-Qahirah: Maktabah al-Kulliyyat
al-Azhariyyah.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1978). I iiqadat ftraq al-Muslimih wa al-Mushrikin. Al-


Qahirah: Maktabah al-Kulliyyat al-Azhariyyah.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1984). Ma alim fl usul al-dm. Annot. Taha Abd. Ra’uf
Sa‘id. Bayrut: Dar al-Kitab al-‘Arabi.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1985). Nihayat al-gaz fi dir ayat al-ijaz. Ed. Bakri Sheikh
Amin. Bayrut: Dar al-Ilm li al-Malayin.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1987). al-Matalib aliyah min al-ilm al-ilahi (vols. 1-9).
Ed. Ahmad al-Hijazi al-Saqa. Bayrut: Dar al-Kitab al-‘Arabi.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1989). Mabahith al-mashriqiyyah fT al ilm al-ilahiyyat


wa al-tabfiyyat (vols. 1-2). Qum: Maktabah Bidar.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1990). al-Masall al-khams in fi usul al-dih. Ed. Ahmad
Hijazi al-Saqa. Bayrut: Dar al-Jil.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1992). al-Maksul fi ilm al-usul. Ed. Taha Jabir al-
‘Alwani (vols. 1-6). Bayrut: Mu’assasah al-Risalah.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1993). Asas al-taqdfs. Ed. Ahmad Hijazi al-Saqa. Bayrut:
Dar al-Jil.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1994). Shark uyun al-kikmah (vols. 1-3) Tehran:
Mu’assasah al-Sadiq li al-Taba‘ah wa al-Nashr.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. (1997). al-Tafsir al-kabL. Reprint, (vols. 1-32) Bayrut:
Dar Ihya’ al-Turath al-‘Arabi.

Mudasir Rosder. (1989). Asas tauhid: pertumbuhan dan huraiannya. Kuala


Lumpur: Dewan Bahasa dan Pustaka.

Al-Samiri, Jabir Zayd. (1995). al-Sifat al-khabariyyah bayna al-mut babbit in wa


al-mu’awwilfn. Khartoum: Dar al-Sudani li al-Kutub.

Shafi'i, Hassan Mahmud. (1991). al-Madkhal ila dirasat ilm al-kalam. Al-
Qahirah: Maktabah Wahbah.

214
Al-Shahrastani, Muhammad 'Abd al-Karim. (1934). Nihayat al-iqdam fi ilm al-
kalam. (A. Guillaume, Trans.). London: Oxford University Press.

Al-Shahrastani, Muhammad 'Abd al-Karim. (1984). al-Milal wa al-nihal: the


section on Muslim sects. (A. K. Kazi & J. A. G. Flynn, Trans.). London:
Kegan Paul International.

Sharif, M. M. (ed.). (1963). A history of Muslim philosophy (vols. 1-2).


Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz.

Shehadi, Fadlou. (1964). Al-Ghaz all unique and unknowable God. Leiden: E.J.
Brill.

Smith, M. (1938). Al-Ghazali’s al-Risalah al-laduniyyah. Journal of the Royal


Asiatic Society (April), 177-200, 353-374.

Ssekamanya, Siraje. (2000). Al-Ghazali and Ibn Taymiyyah on the legitimacy


and status of 'ilm al-kalam. Ph.D. Dissertation., Kuala Lumpur: ISTAC.

Strothman, R. (1987). Tashbih. In First Encyclopedia of Islam (vol. 8, 685-687).

Street, T. (1997). Concerning the life and works of Fakhr al-Din al-Razi. In
Islam: essays on scripture, thought and society: a festschrift in honour of
Anthony H. Johns. Ed. Peter G. Riddell & Tony Street. Leiden: Brill.

Subhi, Ahmad Muhammad. (1985). Fi ilm al-kalam: dirasat falsafiyyah li ara’


firaq al-Islamiyyahfiusul al-dih. Bayrut: Dar al-Nahdah al-'Arabiyyah.

Al-Subki, Taqi al-Din. n.d. al-Sayf al-thaqil fi al-radd ala Ibn al-Zafil. Al-
Qahirah: Maktabah Zahrah.

Suhayr Mukhtar. (1971). al-TajsFn ‘inda al-Muslimih: madhhab al-


Karramiyyah. Al-Qahirah: Al-Qahirah University.

Swinburne, R. (1996). Is there a God?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Al-Taftazzani, Sa'd al-Din. (1950). Sharh alaqa*id al-Nasafi (E. E. Elder,


Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press.

Al-Taftazzani, Sa'd al-Din. (1989). Sharh al-maqasid (vols.1-6). Ed. Abd.


Rahman 'Umayrah. Bayrut: 'Alam al-Kutub.

215
Al-Tahanawi, Muhammad ‘All. (1998). Kashshaf istilah al-funun. Bayrut: Dar
al-Kutub al-Ilmiyyah.

Tibawi, A.L. (1965). Al-Ghazali’s tract on dogmatic theology: translation of al-


Ghazali’s “Risalah qudsiyyah.” Islamic Quarterly (9), 65-122.

Tritton, A.S. (1947). Muslim theology. London: Luzac & Company Ltd.

Al-Uraybi, Muhammad. (1992). al-Muntalaqat al-fikriyyah inda al-Imam al-


Fakhr al-Razf. Bayrut: Darul Fikr al-Lubnani.

Watt, W. M. (1985). Islamic philosophy and theology: an extended survey.


Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

Watt, W. M. (1990). Some Muslim discussions on anthropomorphism. In Early


Islam. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

Watt, W. M. (1994). Islamic creeds; a selection. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University


Press.

Watt, W. M. (1998). The formative period of Islamic thought. Oxford: OneWorld.

Watt, W. M. Djahmiyyah, In New Encyclopedia of Islam (vol.2, 388).

Williams, W. (2002). Aspects of the creed of Imam Ahmad Ibn Hanbal: a study
of anthropomorphism in early Islamic discourse. International fournal
Middle East Studies, (34), 441-463.

Wolfson, H. A. (1973). Studies in the history of philosophy and religion, vol.l. Ed.
Isadore Twersky, George H. Williams. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.

Wolfson, H. A. (1976). The philosophy of kalam. Harvard: Harvard University


Press.

Al-Zabidi, Murtada. (n.d.), Ithaf al-sadat al-muttaqlh bi shard ihya’ ulum al-
din, 14 vols. Bayrut: Dar al-Kutub al-Ilmiyyah.

Al-Zabidi, Murtada. (n.d.). Taj al-ar us. Ed. cAbd. Karim al-'Azabawi. Kuwait:
Mu’assasah al-Kuwait li al-Taqaddum al-'Ilmi.

216
Zaghlul, Muhammad Said. (1989). Maws u at atraf al-Hadith al-Nabawf al-
Sharif\ (vols.1-11). Bayrut: Dar al-Fikr.

Zarkan, Salih. (1963). Fakbr al-Dfn al-Razf wa ara’uhu al-kalamiyyab wa al-


falsafiyyah. Egypt: Darul Fikr.

217

You might also like