You are on page 1of 14

Journal of Business Ethics (2010) 91:3–16 © Springer 2010

DOI 10.1007/s10551-010-0564-4

Virtuous Decision Making for Business


Ethics Chris Provis

ABSTRACT. In recent years, increasing attention has importance of intuition in management decision
been given to virtue ethics in business. Aristotle’s thought making. Bearing that in mind, we may see new force
is often seen as the basis of the virtue ethics tradition. For in some quite old ideas in both Aristotelian and
Aristotle, the idea of phronēsis, or ‘practical wisdom’, lies Confucian virtue ethics traditions, ideas about the
at the foundation of ethics. Confucian ethics has notable close relationship of character and judgment, and
similarities to Aristotelian virtue ethics, and may embody
about ways to enhance individuals’ capacities and
some similar ideas of practical wisdom. This article con-
siders how ideas of moral judgment in these traditions are
dispositions for making good decisions.
consistent with modern ideas about intuition in man- In this opening section, I note the development of
agement decision making. A hypothetical case is consid- literature about Aristotelian and Confucian virtue
ered where the complexity of ethical decision making in a ethics, both generally and in business ethics. The next
group context illustrates the importance of intuitive, section then turns to ‘phronēsis’, a prominent notion
phronēsis-like judgment. It is then noted that both Aris- in Aristotelian virtue ethics. I suggest that the idea
totelian and Confucian virtue ethics include suggestions can be illustrated by the sort of judgment a sporting
about support for moral decision making that are also referee sometimes has to exercise, spanning both
consistent with modern theory. evaluative and factual elements in a single act of
judgment. The next section suggests that such
KEY WORDS: intuition, management decision making, judgment seems very much like some of the sorts of
phronēsis, practical wisdom, virtue ethics, yı̀
intuitive judgment discussed by modern cognitive
psychologists. In the next section, I therefore explore
this suggestion in a hypothetical case similar to the
This article aims to draw together three strands of situation that confronted Roger Boisjoly before the
thought, and thereby to suggest some ideas for fur- tragic Challenger launch decision. The complexity of
ther development about ethical decision making in such a situation seems to require the sort of holistic
business. The first strand of thought is about Aris- decision making that draws intuitively on an agent’s
totelian virtue ethics and Aristotle’s idea of phronēsis. experience and character, along the lines that are very
The second strand of thought is about Confucian much in keeping with ideas of virtue ethics.
virtue ethics. The third line of thought is about If that is correct, then it is worth noting also that
intuition in management decision making. The virtue ethics traditions may have worthwhile points
exposition does not claim to be especially novel in to make about the moral judgment in many such
any of these areas, but to suggest that it may be complex management situations. In getting us to
worthwhile to bring them together. In particular, if focus on development of decision makers’ experi-
our ultimate aim is to foster ethical action in busi- ence and character, these traditions may lead us
ness, then we need to notice modern work about the toward enhanced decision making more effectively
than approaches that focus on the details of specific
decisions. The final section, therefore, notes some of
Chris Provis studied and taught philosophy, then worked for the ideas that are prominent in virtue ethics about
some years in industrial relations and now is Associate Pro- ways to develop and support individuals’ decision
fessor in the School of Management at the University of South making, ideas that seem to be equally plausible
Australia, where he teaches business ethics.
4 Chris Provis

suggestions about ways to foster good intuitive brought out by translating phronēsis as ‘moral wis-
decision making by managers. dom’ rather than ‘practical wisdom’ (see e.g. Byrne,
The suggestions in this article are triggered by the 1997; Hursthouse, 1999, p. 59). In addition, of
expanding literature about virtue ethics in business course, the term phronēsis refers to an activity of
(e.g. Koehn, 1995, 1998; Moore, 2002, 2005a, b; judging, whereas yı̀ refers to what is judged. This
Solomon, 1992a, 1999). The focus is on the notion partly reflects the fact that as a general matter Con-
that is sometimes referred to as ‘practical wisdom’ in fucianism does not place so much emphasis as
translation of Aristotle’s term phronēsis. The idea is Western tradition on issues of individual judgement
prominent in Aristotle’s work, and lies at the core of and knowledge (Hansen, 2004, p. 85).2 However, I
his idea of virtue: shall contend later that the Confucian tradition
equally with the Western virtue ethics tradition has
‘Virtue is a state of character concerned with choice, important ideas about ways to support ethical deci-
lying in a mean, i.e. the mean relatively to us, this
sion making.
being determined by a rational principle, i.e. by that
Translation aside, in what follows I shall suggest
principle by which the man of practical wisdom would
determine it.’ That is Aristotle’s definition of virtue.
that phronēsis and judgments of yı̀ can be usefully
(Ross, 1980, ix, quoting from The Nicomachean Ethics aligned with modern views of management decision
II. vi. 15) making. The idea of ‘appropriateness’, or ‘moral
wisdom’ is one that may build a bridge between
This is therefore a natural area to focus on in general accounts of management decision making
thinking about the extent to which virtue ethics is and specific discussions about ethical decision mak-
applicable to business, since Western virtue ethics ing in business. In doing so, they can add weight to
often looks back to Aristotle as its founder (e.g. the idea that virtue ethics provides a viable basis for
MacIntyre, 1985). ethical decision and action in business. The intention
At the same time, as well as the growing aware- is therefore not primarily to argue in detail for a
ness of the applicability of virtue ethics to business, specific interpretation of Aristotle’s idea of phronēsis
there is also a developing literature about Confu- or of the idea of yı̀, but to suggest an account that
cianism and the ethics of business (e.g. Chan, 2008; seems to me to be consistent with these ideas and is
Lam, 2003). Unsurprisingly, this area of discussion worthwhile in itself.
overlaps with discussion of virtue ethics (e.g. Romar,
2002). Various writers have noted that Confucian
ethics has some important similarities to Aristotelian Phronēsis
virtue ethics (Sim, 2001, 2003, 2007; Slingerland,
2001; Yu, 1998, 2006).1 In considering the role of Phronēsis has been discussed as a significant idea within
judgment in virtue ethics and business, it is natural to virtue ethics by a number of recent writers (see, e.g.
look at the Confucian tradition as well as at the Fowers, 2003; Holt, 2006; Homiak, 1997; Hurst-
Aristotelian virtue ethics tradition. Yu has argued house, 1999; MacIntyre, 2007, p. 154; McDowell,
that Confucius’ idea of yı̀ (義[义]) has important 1979; Nussbaum, 1985; Sherman, 1989; Sorabji,
similarities to Aristotle’s notion of phronēsis: “appro- 1980; Swanton, 2003). However, there has been only
priateness is the rational aspect of Confucius’s con- a little discussion of it in a management context, even
ception of virtue, and it corresponds in many aspects amongst writers who have explored virtue ethics as an
to Aristotle’s concept of practical wisdom (phronēsis)” important approach to business ethics. While it is
(Yu, 2006, p. 335). touched on (see, e.g. Koehn, 1995, pp. 534–535;
There are some issues of translation, both of 1998; Moore, 2005b, p. 250; Solomon, 1992b,
phronēsis and of yı̀. Yu here translates yı̀ as ‘appro- pp. 62–63), the implications have not been fully
priateness’, but it is often translated as ‘rightness’. examined.
The translation of phronēsis as ‘practical wisdom’ may One key idea is that phronēsis should be contrasted
have a connotation of instrumentalism or practical with mechanical calculation and with routine rule-
efficacy which is absent in Aristotle, and the close based decision. In addition, however, phronēsis
relationship between phronēsis and yı̀ may better be embodies an element of evaluation. This is brought
Virtuous Decision Making for Business Ethics 5

out in the difference between phronēsis and and to identify an act as careless or using excessive
Aristotle’s contrasted notion of technē, the sort of force on that basis.
technical judgment exercised in an art or craft (see At least so far as determining an appeal for caught
Aristotle, 1934, VI, iii, 1, pp. 331–333). I believe behind, the job of the cricket umpire could be lar-
that the core idea is embodied in the difference gely performed by a machine, in the same way that,
between umpiring in cricket and refereeing in soc- in recent years in major tennis tournaments, a
cer. For a little while, I want to concentrate on this machine has been used to determine whether the
example. Not everyone will be familiar with the tennis ball is ‘out’.4 The task of the soccer referee
details of both these sports, but they are widely could not be, because judgments of what is careless
played all over the world, and the distinction or reckless require some general understanding of
emerges reasonably well from a description of what values like human well-being or responsibility. I
is involved. Other sports could also be used to make suggest that one way of putting this point is to say
the same distinction. that the soccer referee must display phronēsis in
In cricket, a batter is out whenever a fielder catches deciding whether to award a free kick, whereas at
the ball after it has been hit, before it touches the least in deciding an appeal for caught behind, the
ground.3 This is true even if the bat has only made task of the cricket umpire seems more akin to technē.
slight contact with the ball, and the ball has continued In a business context, a similar distinction can be
on with only a slight deflection. Members of the applied to decisions required of managers. There are
fielding team may then appeal to the umpire to certainly decisions like those required from the
determine that the batter has been ‘caught behind’. cricket umpire. We might refer to these quite nat-
Because the contact between bat and ball is often very urally as technical decisions. But many management
slight, the umpire sometimes has to make a quite decisions will be value-based decisions that involve
difficult decision in judging whether to uphold the phronēsis-like judgment, a judgment about what is
appeal. The decision relies on perceptions of various appropriate, or right, that is not a purely technical
factual matters, such as whether the bat touched the matter.
ball and whether the wicketkeeper took the ball It is important that this is not a straightforward
cleanly before it hit the ground. If the answer to such distinction, because it often requires value-based
questions is yes, then the required decision is clear: the judgment to see that an issue is not a matter for
batter is out. The umpire’s decision does not require a purely technical decision. In business, unlike cricket,
value-based judgment. Provided certain matters of whether a matter requires a purely technical decision
fact are clear, that is all there is to it. or some value-based judgment often will be unclear
Contrast this with a soccer referee’s decision or contestable. This is an important aspect of
whether to award a free kick or a penalty. In the phronēsis, and a significant point about the role of
rules (or ‘laws’) of soccer, Law 12 states that a free judgment in virtue ethics. Phronēsis revolves around
kick is to be given if a player performs any of several the perception of particular cases as falling under a
actions, such as pushing, charging or jumping at an general heading which has some evaluative or ethical
opponent “in a manner considered by the referee to dimension. The understanding involved in such
be careless, reckless or using excessive force”. Thus, perception requires the agent to possess such virtues
at least part of what is required of the referee is to of character as compassion, forbearance and courage:
make a judgment about what is “careless, reckless or “character is revealed as much in what an agent
using excessive force”. This is to a significant extent perceives as in what is done” (Fowers, 2003, p. 417).
a value-based judgment. This idea of ‘value-based In a management context, this is a first point to note
judgment’ is undefined and imprecise, of course, but about phronēsis: it seems to be involved at the very
crucially here it requires certain experience and outset of any decision-making process, in recognis-
virtues of character from the agent. It requires the ing that there is a decision to be made, or the
referee to have an understanding of what is poten- salience of certain possibilities and choices. This is
tially injurious, of what a player can reasonably be why judgment plays such a central role in Aristotle’s
expected to do in various circumstances, and so on, virtue ethics:
6 Chris Provis

On Aristotle’s view, an ethical theory that begins with of the most important ways in which virtue ethics
the justification of a decision to act begins too far differs from consequentialism. Once again, this is a
down the road. Preliminary to deciding how to act, one point of similarity between Western and Confucian
must acknowledge that the situation requires action. virtue ethics. In assessing yı̀, what is appropriate,
The decision must arise from a reading of the cir- Mencius quite explicitly differed from the Mohist
cumstances. This reading, or reaction, is informed by
opponents of Confucianism: “the Mohists, defend-
ethical considerations expressive of the agent’s virtue.
Perception is thus informed by the virtues. (Sherman,
ing a form of universalistic consequentialism, argued
1989, p. 29) that what is righteous is what benefits everyone as a
whole. Mencius, in contrast, argues against using
Similarly, for Confucians like Mencius, judgment of benefit or utility as a metric for choosing appropriate
what is appropriate emerges from human develop- action” (Van Norden, 2004, p. 150).
ment and the growth of character (Van Norden,
2004; see also Confucius, 1971, Book XV, Chap.
xxxii, p. 303). Virtue is in part an inclination to act Intuition, management and value
well, but in part also an ability developed from
experience, to judge what is right. Recently, a good deal of work has been done on
This understanding of ethical decision making is management decision making, and it is nowadays
at odds with many traditional accounts that that lay widely accepted that good decisions do not neces-
emphasis on decisions in well-defined and clearly sarily require a well-defined decision problem
structured situations where the fact that a decision is addressed through a process of conscious, deliberate
necessary is apparent. Typically, such accounts posit ratiocination. Sadler-Smith and Sparrow note that
a clearly defined set of objectives and a well-defined “the decisions which managers are faced with in
set of alternative courses of action, with outcomes workplace settings are often characterized by prob-
that can be attributed some definite value (e.g. lem structures which are ambiguous, dynamic, data
Thomas, 1972, pp. 31–32). There are at least two poor, and time pressured” (2008, p. 315). It is
ways in which such an approach to management therefore no surprise that attention has been given to
decision making is at odds with an approach that the idea of ‘intuition’ in management decision
emphasises phronēsis. One is the implication that making. Although this idea is not new (see e.g.
decision situations present themselves in clear, Barnard, 1938, p. 302), it has been taken forward by
structured ways. That approach can suggest that we recent work in modern cognitive science, which has
first identify some decisions but not others as drawn together ideas from psychology, biology,
requiring consideration of ethics, in the way that computing and elsewhere to advance our under-
some decisions but not others may require consid- standing of decision making (see e.g. Clark, 2000
eration of industrial awards, or engineering prob- and references therein). Here, the salient point is that
lems. On the contrary, emphasis on the importance “research suggests that intuition may be integral to
of phronēsis implies that successfully completing tasks that involve high
complexity and short time horizons” (Dane and
Such decision making is not limited to the emergence
Pratt, 2007, p. 33).
of an occasional ‘ethical issue’. Rather, deliberation
about how best to act is part of the warp and woof of Dane and Pratt note that the term ‘intuition’ can
everyday life. (Fowers, 2003, p. 417) be used to refer to different things. The nature of
intuition is still a matter of discussion and debate
The second way is the idea that we can separately within modern cognitive psychology. There has
identify goals and values and make decisions aimed at been debate, which still continues, about how best
maximising those values. This approach is of course to model the processes underlying cognition (e.g.
characteristic of modern consequentialism, and has Evans, 2008; Sloman, 2002). However, it seems
been criticised from various directions, not only possible to distinguish between ‘intuition’ and the
from the point of view of virtue ethics, but the sorts of cognitive ‘heuristics’ that we may use to
importance of phronēsis in virtue ethics may be one reach decisions quickly or with little information
Virtuous Decision Making for Business Ethics 7

(Betsch, 2008, p. 8; Glöckner, 2008). Betsch gives customers or others, or equally some benefit or other
this definition: consideration, including quite general perceptions of
what is ‘appropriate’ or ‘right’.
Intuition is a process of thinking. The input to this The significance of affect in such cognitive pro-
process is mostly provided by knowledge stored in
cesses has itself been an area of exploration. Haidt
long-term memory that has been primarily acquired
emphasises that “the contrast of intuition and rea-
via associative learning. The input is processed auto-
matically and without conscious awareness. The out- soning is not the contrast of emotion and cognition”
put of the process is a feeling that can serve as a basis (2001, p. 818). Emotions can play a significant
for judgments and decisions. (Betsch, 2008, p. 4) positive role in intuitive cognitive processes, for
example by directing attention one way rather than
It is compatible with this that such intuition can be another (Epstein, 2008, p. 33; Sadler-Smith and
complemented by conscious, deliberate reflection Sparrow, 2008, p. 313; Slovic et al., 2002). One
(Betsch, 2008, p. 7). implication may be to reinforce the suggestion that
The role of experience is crucial. Betsch suggests in many decision-making situations it is unrealistic to
that “intuition can yield highly accurate judgments draw a line between facts and values for separate
and decisions if the prior sample of experiences is treatment. Emotions and values are not the same,
representative for the current task” (2008, p. 6), but they are closely linked. It is somehow odd to
while Epstein comments that although intuition is experience emotional responses to things that one
often a form of pattern recognition, “the defining does not value, either positively or negatively, and
attribute of intuition is the tacit information that is odd not to experience some affective response to
acquired by automatically learning from experience” things that one does value (Provis, 1981).
(Epstein, 2008, p. 31; see also Hogarth, 2008, p. 95). Many management decisions are not best achieved
He goes onto contend that “in problems that are too or modelled by separating facts and values as part of
complex or that are structured in a manner that the decision-making process. Often we can best refer
makes it impossible to objectively analyze their to the correct decision by using the English term,
components, holistic, experiential judgments may ‘appropriate’, the term that Yu uses when translating
provide the only possible approach” (Epstein, 2008, yı̀ in the Analects. The term ‘appropriate’ is one of
p. 33). those terms that spans the distinction between fact
Dane and Pratt reserve the term ‘intuition’ for and value. To say that it would be appropriate to take
“affectively charged judgments that arise through an umbrella on my walk is partly to say that I have
rapid, nonconscious, and holistic associations” some beliefs about the possibility of rain, and partly to
(2007, p. 40). If we accept that characterisation, then say that I do not wish to get wet. There, we might
it seems plausible to suggest that phronēsis may be identify a relatively well-defined set of factual state-
considered as a form of intuitive decision making, ments and another relatively well-defined set of value
which incorporates general, value-related consider- statements that we can see together go together with
ations in judgments about specific circumstances. It the judgment of appropriateness. However, there
is plausible to suggest that phronēsis is ‘holistic’, in the does not seem to be any general presumption that
sense that it maps stimuli onto complex cognitive every judgment of appropriateness has to be based on
structures, “recognising features or patterns … rather two complementary well-defined sets of statements,
than making connections through logical consider- one set about values and another about facts. When a
ations” (Dane and Pratt, 2007, p. 37), and the fact manager correctly judges that a particular course of
that such judgments are “affectively charged” is also action is appropriate, that does not necessarily mean
significant. The affective charge can be associated that it is possible to separately identify well-defined
with value-based considerations. In the analogous sets of values and facts that are the basis for the
case of the soccer referee, the referee’s judgment is judgment. It is partly because the decisions faced by
one that embodies an appreciation of bodily harm managers often do not have the clear structure that
that a player is likely to suffer. In a business situation, would be required for separation of factual and
the affective base for managers’ judgment may be the evaluative elements, that they may best be modelled
harm that is liable to be suffered by employees, by using ideas like intuition or phronēsis, rather than
8 Chris Provis

by referring only to a process of following rules or considered for a new product, which most people at
calculating outcomes. the meeting are supporting, but she is concerned
The fact that intuitive judgments sometimes allow about a potential weakness that may pose a danger to
rapid decisions to be made under conditions of time users. She can point to some general data about
pressure has made them of special interest to scholars strength of materials, which support her misgivings.
of management. However, as noted by Dane and However, most people at the meeting seemed to
Pratt, it is not only time pressure but also complexity think that she is being alarmist, and point to the
that can make it important to call on intuition. So far extensive history of the use of similar materials
as ethics is concerned, it may be the complexity of that has not seen any problems. The meeting was
judgments that is more salient than time pressure. adjourned, and will continue tomorrow. Jean has to
That complexity is partly the intermingling of factual consider how firmly to press her opposition to the
and evaluative elements. To explore this point, it proposal. What should she do tomorrow, when the
will be useful to consider an example of a kind of discussion continues about the proposal for the new
situation that a manager may confront, where deci- product? This morning, she had a distinct feeling
sion making would be hard to model in some that she was on the outer, and that if she persists in
orthodox terms, and then go further in considering opposition to the project she will harm her reputa-
the applicability of a notion like phronēsis. tion, while the project will go ahead anyway.
This case resembles the Challenger disaster. That
case has been discussed and analysed at great length
(see e.g. Allinson, 1998; Elliot et al., 1993; Vaughan,
Jean and the new product 1996). The issues are to do with estimates of risk,
organisational communication, care for danger, and
To explore how phronēsis-like intuition may figure in the like. Some of the issues are difficult: When does
everyday management decision making, consider a failure to recognise the danger become reckless, and
hypothetical case in which one individual’s decision immoral? For Jean, the issue is immediately practical,
is the focus, but the individual’s decision revolves even though it still has difficult theoretical elements.
around communication in a group situation. Such There are intertwined issues of risk assessment and
cases are very important in modern organisations, how firmly to maintain her position. She has to
although not much discussed in traditional virtue evaluate risk, both with regard to the probabilities of
ethics. events occurring, and the significance of the harm
Imagine that Jean is a middle-ranking project they would involve, and at the same time she has to
officer and team leader in the fictional Endeavour work out ways of approaching the forthcoming
Organisation. Sometimes, Jean has to attend meet- discussions, with possibilities of carrying the day, and
ings where she and other members of Endeavour implications if she does not.
have to determine organisational policy on a par- In many social situations, we are confronted with
ticular issue. She sometimes goes into those meetings a similar interplay, where we have to make some
with a point of view, but finds it difficult to maintain estimate about the facts of the situation, at the same
her initial stance as she hears others with different time as we have to work out how to communicate
ideas. On occasion, she finds herself influenced by our estimate and its implications, bearing in mind
the course of the discussion and is convinced by the not only the probabilistic assessment we have made
ideas others are putting forward, without being quite of the facts but the ethical concerns that are tied to it,
sure why. On other occasions, she assents to the and the attitudes and positions of others in the sit-
general opinion, even though she has private reser- uation.
vations. Sometimes, one or two others at such a If we were to reason about things in a step-
meeting will join with her, and together they will by-step way, then we might try to separate out those
maintain a minority viewpoint, and sometimes even different sorts of considerations, and deal with them
convince the majority to change their own view. one by one. First, what are the probabilities that x, y
This morning, Jean had to attend a meeting about and z will be the case? Second, what are the ethical
production strategies. There is a proposal being issues tied to x, y, and z? To what extent does x
Virtuous Decision Making for Business Ethics 9

involve harm to others? To what extent does y judgment, one which combines general ethical
involve keeping a promise? To what extent is z considerations with an assessment of what, probably,
unfair to others? Third, even when I have then come the effects will be of the new product. For the sake
to a view about what it will be best for us to do, how of analysis, it may be possible to separate some
do I approach others? In fact, though, we often do assessment of facts from ethical implications, but the
not reason in that step-by-step way. We make a judgment she eventually has to make is like the
single, unitary judgment which integrates an soccer referee’s, combining factual and evaluative
understanding of the facts with some evaluative elements.
stance: in short, we display phronēsis. Our judgment For example, the layers of complexity include the
involves an inextricably evaluative element. Our fact that Jean has to decide how far to press her view.
situation is similar to that of the soccer referee, who In this respect, her situation is very much like Roger
has to come to a conclusion about what probably Boisjoly, the engineer at Morton Thiokol who has
occurred, but in addition, simultaneously, has to become the most well-known for voicing concerns
judge whether the conduct was careless, and so on. about the Challenger launch, and who had specific
We have a situation that illustrates the point made by fears about the effect of low temperature on the
Sadler-Smith and Sparrow that: O-ring seals, which in the event did fail, causing the
disaster. Boisjoly tried hard to persuade others, but
While models and computers may be good at aggre- was not heeded (Elliot et al., 1993, pp. 96–97).
gating and analyzing data, intuition (since it derives Perhaps there is some requirement on Jean to act as
from integrative pattern recognition and holistic Boisjoly did. Assuming that her judgment is unal-
judgments) may be the only avenue open to managers tered about the risk, then it seems that she has an
to weigh, aggregate, and make sense of intangibles
obligation to try to convince others of it. The
involved in judgments where there are ‘deeper core
problem will be how to deal with the group pres-
values that underlie a decision’. (Sadler-Smith and
Sparrow, 2008, p. 317; quoting Schoemaker and sures that dispose others to agree with the majority.
Russo, 1993, p. 28) There are limits to what she can do, and perhaps
how far she should press her concern depends on the
Do we need to accept that a manager’s intuitive details of her assessment. But is it just a matter of Jean
judgment in this kind of situation is best modelled as weighing up consequences, considering her estimate
a single unitary act, which combines both a per- of the likely harm if the new product goes ahead, her
ceptual and an evaluative dimension? The onus of judgment of how likely she is to get the proposal
proof at least seems to be on a theorist who wishes to abandoned, against the harm to her reputation and
champion separate acts of factual perception and career if she maintains her opposition?
moral evaluation. Such an approach seems likely to This might be one sense of the English phrase
be motivated by a particular understanding about ‘practical wisdom’, and it even figures in some
ethics and decision-making. It seems to rest on a translations of phronēsis as ‘prudence’.5 However,
positivist, Hume-type view that fact and value are that does not seem to be what we would expect of a
distinct, and must be dealt with independently. That person who is virtuous in the sense espoused by
general view has been widely criticised (see, e.g. virtue ethics, if we are imagining a person who puts
Anscombe, 1958). reputation and career ahead of other considerations.
It is both the decision time-frame and its com- In English, ‘practical’ can have the connotation of
plexity that suggest that a soccer referee’s judgment subordinating ethical concerns to others of more
is likely to be a single act of intuition. In Jean’s case, pressing importance, but that would be problematic
it is more especially the deep complexity of her as an approach to advocate from an ethical point of
situation that suggests that her eventual judgment view, and may not be a reasonable translation of
about what to do will be a single act of intuition. Aristotle.
Given the complexity and multi-layered nature of Without undue emphasis on self-interest, a con-
group decision making and organisational commu- sequentialist view might also suggest that account of
nication, it seems plausible to suggest that Jean, in Jean’s situation, seeing just the need to weigh pos-
her meeting, will have to make a single, unitary sible outcomes. Such an account might require Jean
10 Chris Provis

to take into account the long-run effects of what she Here, the implication is that Jean might not only
does, the impact on such cases in the future, for have to weigh up consequences. At least in some
example, and other such factors, but ultimately it cases, she might have to ‘honour’ her values, rather
will see the decision in terms of consequences. Is than basing her decision on an estimate of likely
there any other way of seeing it? Werhane (1999, outcomes. It may be that the exercise of phronēsis
Chap. 3) has discussed the Challenger case in detail in does sometimes require ‘honouring’ values, rather
the context of ‘moral imagination’, commenting than maximising them. It may be that when we see
especially on the way in which participants’ ‘mental what is appropriate (yı̀), then we do not calculate
models’ may have limited the way in which they saw outcomes but see patterns in events, and intuitively
the situation. One notable point brought out by her compare the pattern that will emerge if we act in one
discussion is the difference amongst different par- way, with the pattern that will emerge if we act in
ticipants in their various risk assessments. She another. We are affected by such factors as our
emphasises the general availability of different ways intuitive forecast of what sort of person we will
of seeing things in such complex organisational sit- subsequently seem to be in our own eyes, if we act
uations, different ‘perspectives’, as she puts it. Here, in one way rather than another. We have no firm
we can note that such perspectives might go beyond criterion to refer to. Calculating outcomes may be
different assessments of risk, not necessarily seeing it impossible, in practice (Elster, 1989, Chap. 4). At
in terms of consequences, at all. best, we can see a number of considerations. How
Such a possibility is identified by Philip Pettit in serious is the issue? In the issue, how prominent is
his prominent defences of consequentialism (Pettit, the value? How clear are the consequences? Whose
1991, 1997, 2000). He notes that whatever moral interests are at stake in the possible outcomes? These
values we have, there are two approaches toward all seem as though they may be relevant. It is pre-
them: an approach that considers that ethics requires cisely the fact that there is not a usable general rule
us to do just what will promote those values, and an that makes necessary some intuitive, holistic, virtue-
alternative approach that considers that it may be based judgment.
appropriate to ‘honour’ such values, even if that may In Jean’s case, it is the complexity of the cir-
contribute nothing toward promoting them. With- cumstances and factors relevant to the decision that
out being able to look at details of Pettit’s arguments make it plausible to suggest that it should be mod-
here, we may take it that Jean could honour her elled as an intuitive process. In the case of the soccer
values by standing out against the proposal for the referee, it is both the complexity and the time
new product, even if she had no assurance that doing involved that suggests the same conclusion. The
so would be of any use. Can we resolve the question referee sees that a player has acted carelessly or used
whether Jean ought to do that? excessive force, and that perception carries on its face
Such cases are not unreal. Pettit notes as an the implication that a free kick is appropriate. Both
example the tension between pacifists who adopt a complexity and time pressure create needs for rapid,
course in the belief that it will promote peace, and holistic judgment (cf. Cohen, 2004, p. 49). Such
others who eschew war whatever the outcome judgment is discussed in modern literature under the
(Pettit, 1997, p. 126). Another instance might be the title of ‘intuition’, but it seems to be very similar to
case in the news not so long ago of a climber Aristotelian phronēsis or Confucian judgment of yı̀.
encountered by others on Mount Everest. The From an ethical point of view, it can be set over
climber was in difficulties. The others did not try to against judgments that are based on calculation of
assist, because, as one of them said, “there was outcomes or following clearly delineated moral
nothing they could do for him”.6 Subsequently, Sir rules. The complexity of many real situations where
Edmund Hillary said “On our expedition 50 years moral decisions are needed means that a holistic
ago, [we] would have never considered leaving a judgment is required of the sort envisaged in these
man like that”.7 The difference might reflect that virtue traditions. This is one major respect in which
same question of whether to ‘honour’ values, even if virtue ethics differs from consequentialism and rule-
doing so has no effect on outcomes. oriented deontology.
Virtuous Decision Making for Business Ethics 11

Developing virtuous judgment way, we may develop ability to recognise patterns,


without necessarily learning a rule of any traditional
This leaves us with the question how Jean will view form, or acquiring any ability to measure and cal-
her decision subsequently. Can she be sure that she culate. When we are considering intuition-based
acted correctly? Was there a right decision in the ethical judgments in business, an implication seems
circumstances? We have now reached a point where to be that intuitive judgment may be developed by
criticism is sometimes levelled at virtue ethics. It can getting individuals to consider cases and examples.
seem as though we are saying that virtuous intuition Taking the point further, we may accept that in
is needed to make moral decisions, rather than cal- ethics as in other areas,
culation or reference to clear rules, but not saying
any more about that virtuous intuition. It may seem organizations that wish to facilitate effective intuiting
need to concentrate on promoting ongoing and
to be defined only by reference to what it is not,
deliberate practice in kind learning environments.
without any substantial information about what it is,
They may also encourage managers to be mindful of
how to attain it, or how to evaluate it. their environments in order to facilitate implicit
In fact, however, there are positive directions to learning. By remaining alert and viewing problems
pursue for substantive comment about such virtuous from multiple perspectives, ‘mindful’ managers may
intuition. We have already noted the substantial form new cognitive categories and distinctions (Dane
literature that has grown up about phronēsis. Now- and Pratt, 2007, p. 49).
adays, that is complemented by modern writing
about intuition in decision making. A number of Those comments not only are consistent with
developments and conclusions in that area can have Werhane’s emphasis on the importance of devel-
specific application to intuition in moral decision oping ‘moral imagination’ as a basis for decision
making (see in particular Haidt, 2001). Such study making, but they are also reminiscent of teaching in
further extends virtue traditions’ long-established major virtue ethics traditions. Both Aristotle and the
emphasis on development of good decision-making Confucian traditions give some emphasis to experi-
powers in individuals. The Confucian focusses on ence as a primary source of developing practical
the jūnzı̆, and the Aristotelian focusses on the wisdom. Aristotle suggests that
phronimos, both orienting themselves toward the
while young men become geometricians and mathe-
decision-maker rather than the decision process. That maticians and wise in matters like these, it is thought
emphasis on individuals’ decision-making capacities that a young man of practical wisdom cannot be found.
suggests that development of good decision making The cause is that such wisdom is concerned not only
involves development of individuals rather than with universals but with particulars, which become
refinement of techniques of decision analysis. familiar from experience, but a young man has no
Such an emphasis is consistent with research on experience, for it is length of time that gives experi-
intuition to the extent that such research suggests ence. (Aristotle, 1980, VI, viii, p. 148, and see also VI,
that successful intuition-based decision making is xi, p. 153; and see Hursthouse, 1999, pp. 59–60)
developed through personal experience. We have
Without doubt, though, experience alone can be
already noted comments by Betsch (2008) and
over valued as a basis for developing good decision
Epstein (2008), which illustrate the point: “For
making (Phillips et al., 2004, p. 306). Bazerman
many cognitive scientists, the most plausible source
notes the inadequacy of experience as a corrective
of intuition is past experience… [T]his account
for certain kinds of shortcomings of judgment
conceives intuition as knowledge accumulated
(Bazerman, 2006, pp. 191–193). It may be that the
unconsciously through experience with numerous
sort of intuition involved in moral judgments is best
cases” (Smith, 2008, p. 459). Modern accounts of
developed through experience complemented by
how learning may occur in neural networks,
other processes such as reflection (Clark, 2000;
through repeated synaptic adjustment, suggest that
Haidt, 2001, pp. 828–829) and coaching (Phillips et
repeated exposure to instances of one kind and an-
al., 2004, pp. 308–309). The fact that experience
other allow such networks to recognise patterns in
alone is not sufficient for development of moral
phenomena (Churchland, 1995, Chap. 3). In that
12 Chris Provis

wisdom is also to be found in virtue ethics traditions. p. 121), but it is also very much a picture within the
The point seems implicit in Aristotle (Nussbaum, virtue ethics tradition.
1986, pp. 306–308). Steinberger notes that for At the same time, other related points to be found
Aristotle phronēsis seems to involve not only aretē – in modern literature about intuition-based moral
which may be translated as ‘virtue’ – but also nous: decision making are redolent of virtue traditions. For
mind, or intelligence (Steinberger, 1993, p. 120). example, they note the importance of social inter-
The point is also quite clear in the Confucian tra- action in developing intuition. Clark comments that
dition. Lai notes “the centrality of practice” in the “even if it is true that individual moral understanding
Confucian tradition (Lai, 2006, p. 111), but also typically far surpasses anything that a few words can
points out that there is no suggestion that practice capture, it is also true that moral reasoning and
alone is enough. She argues that “the significance of decision-making is quintessentially a communal and
Confucian ethical thought lies in its attention to the collaborative affair” (2000, Clark’s emphasis). Haidt
cultivation of reasoning skills and sensitivity in moral suggests that aspects of intuitive moral decision
deliberation” (2006, p. 109), even though “in making can be enhanced by the involvement of
Confucian thought, the primacy of practice con- suitably-chosen others:
textualises the entire cultivation process” (2006,
p. 117). It is quite possible that in areas like moral By seeking out discourse partners who are respected
decision making our intuition and judgment may be for their wisdom and open-mindedness, and by talking
improved by reflection on experience, and it is this about the evidence, justifications, and mitigating fac-
tors involved in a potential moral violation, people can
combination of thought and experience that is called
help trigger a variety of conflicting intuitions in each
for in the Confucian tradition: “Learning without
other. If more conflicting intuitions are triggered, the
thought is labour lost; thought without learning is final judgment is likely to be more nuanced and ulti-
perilous” (Confucius, 1971, Book II, Chap. xv, mately more reasonable. (Haidt, 2001, p. 829)
p. 150). Although Confucian teaching sometimes
seems to emphasise the importance of practice over If, on the one hand, this reminds us of Werhane’s
theory, and even though Confucians like Mencius account of the importance of getting ourselves to see
stress “the context-sensitivity of virtuous actions” things from different points of view, then on the
(Van Norden, 2004, p. 172), they accept the other hand, it also reminds us of both Confucian and
importance of deliberation and reflection that turn Aristotelian advice about the support of others: “The
on reasons and principles (Cua, 1989; Shun, 1989; superior man on grounds of culture meets with his
2004, p. 190). In Jean’s case, considered above, she friends, and by their friendship helps his virtue”
can take into account of general principles like moral (Confucius, 1971, Book XII, Chap. xxiv, p. 262),
principles of beneficence and respect, not assuming and “those in the prime of life [friendship] stimulates
that they specify correct actions in a precise way, but to noble actions – ‘two going together’ – for with
reflecting subsequently on the decision she made, friends men are more able both to think and to act”
trying to see it from different points of view and (Aristotle, 1980, VIII, i, p. 192). The general point
considering whether, with hindsight, she might have that development of individual decision-makers is
chosen differently. best enhanced in a social context is supported by
The general picture that emerges on this account various pieces of research (see e.g. Garcı́a-Retamero
is that good ethical decision making is often intui- et al., 2006; Takezawa et al., 2006).
tive, that such intuition is developed through Certainly, there are differences between the
experience, but experience needs or benefits from Western and Confucian virtue ethics traditions, and
training and reflection (cf. also Smith, 2008, p. 461). the Confucian tradition lays more emphasis on
Overall, however, what is at the centre of the the importance of judgment as a social process
picture is development of the individual decision- (Kupperman, 2004, pp. 113–114). That seems to be
maker rather than of superior decision-making the other side of the coin from the fact noted early in
routines and processes that are generally applicable. this article that the Confucian tradition places less
This is an idea that is consistent with modern emphasis on matters of individual judgment, and
research in cognitive science (Gigerenzer, 2006, associated with the Confucian emphasis on ideas of
Virtuous Decision Making for Business Ethics 13

social harmony that are much less noticeable in the importance of intuitive judgment in situations of
Western thought (Ihara, 2004; Kupperman, 2004; high complexity. Management decisions are very
Rosemont, 2004). A more detailed account could often made in situations of high complexity where
explore these and other differences. Here, however, social and other factors are interwoven. Often it is
the general point is that each tradition does not practicable to separate out factual and evaluative
acknowledge the importance of social support for matters or weigh the consequences of different
good intuitive decision making. alternatives. Sometimes, it will just be necessary to
From a management point of view, this confirms make an intuitive judgment, and perhaps to honour
the often-recognised importance of peer support and some values one is committed to.
organisational culture in supporting ethical action. The emphasis that this account puts on intuition
Again, a more detailed account could explore that in ethical decision making leads to derivative
point in more detail, including close reference to the emphasis on development of capacity by individual
types of social experience and example that can decision-makers, rather than analysis of decision
improve intuitive ethical judgement, and the processes. Once again, traditional virtue ethics
organisational processes, structures and inititatives accounts are consistent with some modern accounts
that are implied, such as the importance of ‘com- of how good intuitive decision making is developed.
munities of practice’ for knowledge and under- In particular, they suggest the importance of expe-
standing within organisations (see e.g. Wenger and rience coupled with reflection, and social support.
Snyder, 2000). There are other points also that may Modern research can extend and deepen our
be drawn from the literature on intuition-based understanding of managers’ ethical decision making,
decision making. Thus, for example, Dane and Pratt but that understanding may have foundations in very
suggest that organisations “need to reduce the rate of old virtue ethics traditions.
member turnover in order to foster the development
of more effective intuitive decision making among
members” (2007, p. 49), and that transfer of exper- Notes
tise may best be effected by having experienced,
1
good decision-makers work together with novices. MacIntyre (1991) has argued against comparison of
Such points once again resonate with a virtue ethics the Confucian and Aristotelian traditions, but his view
emphasis on decision-makers rather than abstract has been widely questioned (see Sim, 2007).
2
decision processes. The term zhı̀ (志) used in Confucian ethics (for
example, as one of Mencius’ four ‘sprouts of virtue’:
Van Norden, 2004, p. 149) is sometimes translated as
‘wisdom’, but seems to have more of a volitional sense
Conclusion than the sort of cognitive sense that phronēsis has and
which figures in the discussion of this article (Shun,
The general picture presented here is that often 2004, p. 186).
when we make decisions, we do not utilise an ability 3
With a few qualifications that are not relevant here,
to follow rules, or to calculate outcomes, but rec- such as the ball having been properly delivered to the
ognise a pattern in our circumstances, and see that batter and the fielder being within the field of play.
4
some action or other is ‘appropriate’ in such cir- And indeed a ‘snickometer’ has started to figure in
cumstances. On this view, ethical decision making cricket television replays as a way for the audience to
and management decision making are often matters check the umpire’s judgment.
5
of pattern recognition, and the virtue ethics tradi- See, e.g. Rackham’s Loeb Library translation (Aris-
totle, 1934, II, vi, 15, p. 95). Perhaps this English con-
tions born of Aristotle and Confucius give better
notation is the reason why Hursthouse (1999) tends to
accounts of such decision making than some modern use ‘moral wisdom’ more often than ‘practical wisdom’.
analytical accounts that have their roots in the he- 6
‘Climber’s Everest Decision Agony’, BBC News 23
donic calculus of Bentham and other consequen- May 2006, http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/england/tees/
tialist approaches. 5010348.stm, accessed 2 September 2006.
This picture is consistent with modern accounts 7
‘Death on the Mountain’, ABC Radio National,
of management decision making which emphasise The Sports Factor, 2 June 2006, http://www.abc.net.au/
14 Chris Provis

rn/sportsfactor/stories/2006/1651512.htm#, accessed 2 Clark, A.: 2000, ‘Word and Action: Reconciling Rules
September 2006. and Know-How in Moral Cognition’, in R. Campbell
and B. Hunter (eds.), Moral Epistemology Naturalized
(University of Calgary Press, Calgary). Canadian Journal
of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 26, 267–289.
Acknowledgments Cohen, S.: 2004, The Nature of Moral Reasoning (Oxford
University Press, Melbourne).
This is a revised version of an article presented at the Confucius: 1971, Confucian Analects, the Great Learning and the
2008 World Business Ethics Forum, which was itself a Doctrine of the Mean, trans. J. Legge (Dover, New York).
much-revised version of a article presented at the 2008 First published by Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1893.
conference of the Australian Association of Professional Cua, A. S.: 1989, ‘The Status of Principles in Confucian
and Applied Ethics. The author is grateful to partici- Ethics’, Journal of Chinese Philosophy 16(3–4), 273–296.
pants in discussion on those occasions, and to Howard Dane, E. and M. G. Pratt: 2007, ‘Exploring Intuition and
Harris for many relevant conversations. Its Role in Managerial Decision Making’, Academy of
Management Review 32(1), 33–54.
Elliot, N., E. Katz and R. Lynch: 1993, ‘The Challenger
Tragedy: A Case Study on Organizational Commu-
References nication and Professional Ethics’, Business & Professional
Ethics Journal 12(2), 91–108.
Allinson, R. E.: 1998, Review of D. Vaughan, The Elster, J.: 1989, Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences
Challenger Launch Decision: Risky Technology, Culture and (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge).
Deviance at NASA (Chicago, University of Chicago Epstein, S.: 2008, ‘Intuition from the Perspective of
Press, 1996), Business Ethics Quarterly 8(4), 743–756. Cognitive-Experiential Self-Theory’, in H. Plessner,
Anscombe, G. E. M.: 1958, ‘Modern Moral Philosophy,’ C. Betsch and T. Betsch (eds.), Intuition in Judgment
Philosophy 33, 1–19. Reprinted in R. Crisp and M. and Decision Making (Psychology Press, New York),
Slote (eds.): 1997, Virtue Ethics (Oxford University pp. 23–37.
Press, Oxford), pp. 26–44. Evans, J. S. B. T.: 2008, ‘Dual-Processing Accounts of
Aristotle: 1934, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. H. Rackham Reasoning, Judgment, and Social Cognition’, Annual
(Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA). Review of Psychology 59, 255–278.
Aristotle: 1980, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. D. Ross Fowers, B. J.: 2003, ‘Reason and Human Finitude: In
(Oxford University Press, Oxford). Revised edition Praise of Practical Wisdom’, American Behavioral Scientist
edited by J. L. Ackrill and J. O. Urmson. 47(4), 415–426.
Barnard, C. I.: 1938, The Functions of the Executive Garcı́a-Retamero, R., M. Takezawa and G. Gigerenzer:
(Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA). Thirtieth 2006, ‘How to Learn Good Cue Orders: When Social
Anniversary edition 1968. Learning Benefits Simple Heuristics’, in R. Sun and
Bazerman, M. H.: 2006, Judgment in Managerial Decision N. Miyake (eds.), Proceedings of the 28th Annual
Making, 6th Edition (John Wiley & Sons, New York). Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (Erlbaum,
Betsch, T.: 2008, ‘The Nature of Intuition and Its Neglect Mahwah, NJ), pp. 1352–1357.
in Research on Judgment and Decision Making’, in Gigerenzer, G.: 2006, ‘Bounded and Rational’, in R. J.
H. Plessner, C. Betsch and T. Betsch (eds.), Intuition Stainton (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science
in Judgment and Decision Making (Psychology Press, (Blackwell, Oxford), pp. 115–133.
New York), pp. 3–22. Glöckner, A.: 2008, ‘Does Intuition Beat Fast and Frugal
Byrne, P. H.: 1997, ‘Phronēsis and Commonsense Judg- Heuristics? A Systematic Empirical Analysis’, in
ment: Aristotle and Lonergan on Moral Wisdom’, in H. Plessner, C. Betsch and T. Betsch (eds.), Intuition in
M. Baur (ed.), Virtues and Virtue Theories: Proceedings of Judgment and Decision Making (Psychology Press, New
the American Catholic Philosophical Association, Vol. 71, York), pp. 309–325.
pp. 163–177. Haidt, J.: 2001, ‘The Emotional Dog and Its Rational
Chan, G. K. Y.: 2008, ‘The Relevance and Value of Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judg-
Confucianism in Contemporary Business Ethics’, ment’, Psychological Review 108(4), 814–834.
Journal of Business Ethics 77(3), 347–360. Hansen, C.: 2004, ‘The Normative Impact of Compar-
Churchland, P. M.: 1995, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of ative Ethics: Human Rights’, in K.-L. Shun and D. B.
the Soul (MIT Press, Cambridge, MA). Wong (eds.), Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of
Virtuous Decision Making for Business Ethics 15

Self, Autonomy and Community (Cambridge University Moore, G.: 2005, ‘Corporate Character: Modern Virtue
Press, Cambridge), pp. 72–99. Ethics and the Virtuous Corporation’, Business Ethics
Hogarth, R. M.: 2008, ‘On the Learning of Intuition’, in Quarterly 15(4), 659–685.
H. Plessner, C. Betsch and T. Betsch (eds.), Intuition in Moore, G.: 2005, ‘Humanizing Business: A Modern
Judgment and Decision Making (Psychology Press, New Virtue Ethics Approach’, Business Ethics Quarterly 15
York), pp. 91–105. (2), 237–255.
Holt, R.: 2006, ‘Principals and Practice: Rhetoric and the Nussbaum, M.: 1985, ‘The Discernment of Perception:
Moral Character of Managers’, Human Relations 59 An Aristotelian Conception of Private and Public
(12), 1659–1680. Rationality’, in J. Cleary (ed.), Proceedings of the Boston
Homiak, M. L.: 1997, ‘Aristotle on the Soul’s Conflicts: Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. i (Univer-
Toward an Understanding of Virtue Ethics’, in A. sity Press of America, Lanham), pp. 151–201.
Reath, B. Herman and C. M. Korsgaard (eds.), Nussbaum, M.: 1986, The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge
Reclaiming the History of Ethics: Essays for John Rawls University Press, Cambridge).
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), pp. 7–35. Pettit, P.: 1991, ‘Consequentialism’, in P. Singer (ed.),
Hursthouse, R.: 1999, On Virtue Ethics (Oxford Uni- A Companion to Ethics (Blackwell, Oxford), pp. 230–
versity Press, Oxford). 240.
Ihara, C. K.: 2004, ‘Are Individual Rights Necessary? A Pettit, P.: 1997, ‘The Consequentialist Perspective’, in
Confucian Perspective’, in K.-L. Shun and D. B. Wong M. Baron, P. Pettit and M. Slote (eds.), Three Methods
(eds.), Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, of Ethics: A Debate (Blackwell, Oxford), pp. 92–174.
Autonomy and Community (Cambridge University Press, Pettit, P.: 2000, ‘Non-Consequentialism and Universal-
Cambridge), pp. 11–30. izability’, Philosophical Quarterly 50, 175–190.
Koehn, D.: 1995, ‘A Role for Virtue Ethics in the Phillips, J. K., G. Klein and W. R. Sieck: 2004,
Analysis of Business Practice’, Business Ethics Quarterly ‘Expertise in Judgment and Decision Making: A
5(3), 533–539. Case for Training Intuitive Decision Skills’, in
Koehn, D.: 1998, ‘Virtue Ethics, the Firm and Moral D. J. Koehler and N. Harvey (eds.), Blackwell
Psychology’, Business Ethics Quarterly 8(3), 497–513. Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making (Blackwell,
Kupperman, J. J.: 2004, ‘Tradition and Community in Oxford), pp. 62–88.
the Formation of Character and Self’, in K.-L. Shun Provis, C.: 1981, ‘Reason and Emotion’, Canadian Journal
and D. B. Wong (eds.), Confucian Ethics: A Comparative of Philosophy 11(3), 439–456.
Study of Self, Autonomy and Community (Cambridge Romar, E. J.: 2002, ‘Virtue is Good Business: Confu-
University Press, Cambridge), pp. 103–123. cianism as a Practical Business Ethic’, Journal of Business
Lai, K.: 2006, Learning from Chinese Philosophies (Ashgate, Ethics 38(1/2), 119–131.
Aldershot). Rosemont, H. Jr.: 2004, ‘Whose Democracy? Which
Lam, K.-C. J.: 2003, ‘Confucian Business Ethics and the Rights? A Confucian Critique of Modern Western
Economy’, Journal of Business Ethics 43(1–2), 153–162. Liberalism’, in K.-L. Shun and D. B. Wong (eds.),
MacIntyre, A.: 1985, After Virtue, 2nd Edition (Duck- Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy
worth, London). and Community (Cambridge University Press, Cam-
MacIntyre, A.: 1991, ‘Incommensurability, Truth, and the bridge), pp. 49–71.
Conversation Between Confucians and Aristotelians Ross, D.: 1980, ‘Introduction’, in J. L. Ackrill and J. O.
About the Virtues’, in E. Deutsch (ed.), Culture and Urmson (eds.), Aristotle: The Nicomachean Ethics (Oxford
Modernity: East–West Philosophic Perspectives (University University Press, Oxford), pp. v–xxiv. Originally
of Hawaii Press, Honolulu), pp. 104–122. published 1925.
MacIntyre, A.: 2007, After Virtue, 3rd Edition (Duck- Sadler-Smith, E. and P. R. Sparrow: 2008, ‘Intuition in
worth, London). Organizational Decision Making’, in G. P. Hodgkin-
McDowell, J.: 1979, ‘Virtue and Reason,’ The Monist son and W. H. Starbuck (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of
62, 331–350. Reprinted in Crisp, R. and Slote, M. Organizational Decision Making (Oxford University
(eds.): 1997, Virtue Ethics (Oxford University Press, Press, Oxford), pp. 305–324.
Oxford). Schoemaker, P. J. H. and J. E. Russo: 1993, ‘A Pyramid
Moore, G.: 2002, ‘On the Implications of the Practice- of Decision Approaches,’ California Management Review
Institution Distinction: MacIntyre and the Application Fall, 9–31.
of Modern Virtue Ethics to Business’, Business Ethics Sherman, N.: 1989, The Fabric of Character: Aristotle’s
Quarterly 12(1), 19–32. Theory of Virtue (Clarendon Press, Oxford).
16 Chris Provis

Shun, K.-L.: 1989, ‘Moral Reasons in Confucian Ethics’, Sorabji, R.: 1980, ‘Aristotle on the Role of Intellect in
Journal of Chinese Philosophy 16(3–4), 317–343. Virtue’, in A. O. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics
Shun, K.-L.: 2004, ‘Conception of the Person in Early (University of California Press, Berkeley), pp. 201–219.
Confucian Thought’, in K.-L. Shun and D. B. Wong Steinberger, P. J.: 1993, The Concept of Political Judgment
(eds.), Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, (University of Chicago Press, Chicago).
Autonomy and Community (Cambridge University Swanton, C.: 2003, Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View (Oxford
Press, Cambridge), pp. 183–199. University Press, Oxford).
Sim, M.: 2001, ‘Aristotle in the Reconstruction of Takezawa, M., M. Gummerum and M. Keller: 2006, ‘A
Confucian Ethics’, International Philosophical Quarterly Stage for the Rational Tail of the Emotional Dog:
41(4), 453–468. Roles of Moral Reasoning in Group Decision Mak-
Sim, M.: 2003, ‘The Moral Self in Confucius and Aristotle’, ing’, Journal of Economic Psychology 27(1), 117–139.
International Philosophical Quarterly 43(4), 439–462. Thomas, H.: 1972, Decision Theory and the Manager
Sim, M.: 2007, Remastering Morals with Aristotle and (Pitman, London).
Confucius (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Van Norden, B. W.: 2004, ‘The Virtue of Righteousness
Slingerland, E.: 2001, ‘Virtue Ethics, the Analects, and the in Mencius’, in K.-L. Shun and D. B. Wong (eds.),
Problem of Commensurability’, Journal of Religious Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy
Ethics 29(1), 97–125. and Community (Cambridge University Press, Cam-
Sloman, S. A.: 2002, ‘Two Systems of Reasoning’, in bridge), pp. 148–182.
T. Gilovich, D. Griffin and D. Kahneman (eds.), Vaughan, D.: 1996, The Challenger Launch Decision
Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment (University of Chicago Press, Chicago).
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), pp. 379– Wenger, E. C. and W. M. Snyder: 2000, ‘Communities
396. of Practice: The Organizational Frontier’, Harvard
Slovic, P., M. Finucane, E. Peters and D. G. MacGregor: Business Review 78(1), 139–145.
2002, ‘The Affect Heuristic’, in T. Gilovich, Werhane, P. H.: 1999, Moral Imagination and Management
D. Griffin and D. Kahneman (eds.), Heuristics and Decision-Making (Oxford University Press, New York).
Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment (Cambridge Yu, J.: 1998, ‘Virtue: Confucius and Aristotle’, Philosophy
University Press, Cambridge), pp. 397–420. East & West 48(2), 323–347.
Smith, G. F.: 2008, ‘Teaching Decision Making’, in Yu, J.: 2006, ‘Yi: Practical Wisdom in Confucius’s Ana-
G. P. Hodgkinson and W. H. Starbuck (eds.), The lects’, Journal of Chinese Philosophy 33(3), 335–348.
Oxford Handbook of Organizational Decision Making
(Oxford University Press, Oxford), pp. 455–474. School of Management,
Solomon, R. C.: 1992, ‘Corporate Roles, Personal Vir- University of South Australia,
tues: An Aristotelean Approach to Business Ethics’, North Terrace, Adelaide, SA 5000, Australia
Business Ethics Quarterly 2(3), 317–339. E-mail: chris.provis@unisa.edu.au
Solomon, R. C.: 1992, Ethics and Excellence (Oxford
University Press, New York).
Solomon, R. C.: 1999, ‘Business Ethics and Virtue’, in
R. E. Frederick (ed.), A Companion to Business Ethics
(Blackwell, Oxford), pp. 30–37.

You might also like