You are on page 1of 67

Probability and Statistical Inference 3rd

Edition Magdalena
Niewiadomska-Bugaj
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/probability-and-statistical-inference-3rd-edition-magd
alena-niewiadomska-bugaj/
PROBABILITY AND
STATISTICAL INFERENCE
k

WILEY SERIES IN PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS


Established by Walter A. Shewhart and Samuel S. Wilks

Editors: David J. Balding, Noel A. C. Cressie, Garrett M. Fitzmaurice, Geof H. Givens,


Harvey Goldstein, Geert Molenberghs, David W. Scott, Adrian F. M. Smith, Ruey S. Tsay

Editors Emeriti: J. Stuart Hunter, Iain M. Johnstone, Joseph B. Kadane, Jozef L. Teugels

The Wiley Series in Probability and Statistics is well established and authoritative. It covers
many topics of current research interest in both pure and applied statistics and probability
theory. Written by leading statisticians and institutions, the titles span both state-of-the-art
developments in the field and classical methods.

Reflecting the wide range of current research in statistics, the series encompasses applied,
methodological and theoretical statistics, ranging from applications and new
techniques made possible by advances in computerized practice to rigorous treatment of
theoretical approaches.

This series provides essential and invaluable reading for all statisticians, whether in
academia, industry, government, or research.

A complete list of titles in this series can be found at http://www.wiley.com/go/wsps

k k

k
PROBABILITY AND
STATISTICAL INFERENCE
Third Edition

Magdalena Niewiadomska-Bugaj

Robert Bartoszyński†
This edition first published 2021
© 2021 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in
any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by
law. Advice on how to obtain permission to reuse material from this title is available at http://www.wiley.com/go/
permissions.

The right of Magdalena Niewiadomska-Bugaj and Robert Bartoszyński to be identified as the authors of this
work has been asserted in accordance with law.

Registered Office
John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 111 River Street, Hoboken, NJ 07030, USA

Editorial Office
111 River Street, Hoboken, NJ 07030, USA

For details of our global editorial offices, customer services, and more information about Wiley products visit us
at www.wiley.com.

Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats and by print-on-demand. Some content that
appears in standard print versions of this book may not be available in other formats.

Limit of Liability/Disclaimer of Warranty


While the publisher and authors have used their best efforts in preparing this work, they make no representations
or warranties with respect to the accuracy or completeness of the contents of this work and specifically disclaim
all warranties, including without limitation any implied warranties of merchantability or fitness for a particular
purpose. No warranty may be created or extended by sales representatives, written sales materials or promotional
statements for this work. The fact that an organization, website, or product is referred to in this work as a citation
and/or potential source of further information does not mean that the publisher and authors endorse the
information or services the organization, website, or product may provide or recommendations it may make. This
work is sold with the understanding that the publisher is not engaged in rendering professional services. The
advice and strategies contained herein may not be suitable for your situation. You should consult with a specialist
where appropriate. Further, readers should be aware that websites listed in this work may have changed or
disappeared between when this work was written and when it is read. Neither the publisher nor authors shall be
liable for any loss of profit or any other commercial damages, including but not limited to special, incidental,
consequential, or other damages.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


Names: Niewiadomska-Bugaj, Magdalena, author. | Bartoszyński, Robert,
author.
Title: Probability and statistical inference / Magdalena
Niewiadomska-Bugaj, Robert Bartoszyński.
Description: Third edition. | Hoboken, NJ : Wiley-Interscience, 2021. |
Revised edition of: Probability and statistical inference / Robert
Bartoszyński, Magdalena Niewiadomska-Bugaj. 2nd ed. c2008. | Includes
bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2020021071 (print) | LCCN 2020021072 (ebook) | ISBN
9781119243809 (cloth) | ISBN 9781119243816 (adobe pdf) | ISBN
9781119243823 (epub)
Subjects: LCSH: Probabilities. | Mathematical statistics.
Classification: LCC QA273 .B2584 2021 (print) | LCC QA273 (ebook) | DDC
519.5/4–dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2020021071
LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2020021072

Cover Design: Wiley


Cover Images: (graph) Courtesy of Magdalena Niewiadomska-Bugaj, Colorful abstract long exposure pictures ©
Artur Debat/Getty Images

Set in 10/11.5pt TimesNewRomanMTStd by SPi Global, Chennai, India

10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
To my parents
– MNB
Contents

Preface to Third Edition xi


Preface to Second Edition xiii

About the Companion Website xvi

1 Experiments, Sample Spaces, and Events 1


1.1 Introduction 1
1.2 Sample Space 2
1.3 Algebra of Events 8
1.4 Infinite Operations on Events 13

2 Probability 21
2.1 Introduction 21
2.2 Probability as a Frequency 21
2.3 Axioms of Probability 22
2.4 Consequences of the Axioms 26
2.5 Classical Probability 30
2.6 Necessity of the Axioms 31
2.7 Subjective Probability 35

3 Counting 39
3.1 Introduction 39
3.2 Product Sets, Orderings, and Permutations 39

vii
viii CONTENTS

3.3 Binomial Coefficients 44


3.4 Multinomial Coefficients 56

4 Conditional Probability, Independence, and Markov Chains 59


4.1 Introduction 59
4.2 Conditional Probability 60
4.3 Partitions; Total Probability Formula 65
4.4 Bayes’ Formula 69
4.5 Independence 74
4.6 Exchangeability; Conditional Independence 80
4.7 Markov Chains* 82

5 Random Variables: Univariate Case 93


5.1 Introduction 93
5.2 Distributions of Random Variables 94
5.3 Discrete and Continuous Random Variables 102
5.4 Functions of Random Variables 112
5.5 Survival and Hazard Functions 118

6 Random Variables: Multivariate Case 123


6.1 Bivariate Distributions 123
6.2 Marginal Distributions; Independence 129
6.3 Conditional Distributions 140
6.4 Bivariate Transformations 147
6.5 Multidimensional Distributions 155

7 Expectation 163
7.1 Introduction 163
7.2 Expected Value 164
7.3 Expectation as an Integral 171
7.4 Properties of Expectation 177
7.5 Moments 184
7.6 Variance 191
7.7 Conditional Expectation 202
7.8 Inequalities 206

8 Selected Families of Distributions 211


8.1 Bernoulli Trials and Related Distributions 211
8.2 Hypergeometric Distribution 223
8.3 Poisson Distribution and Poisson Process 228
8.4 Exponential, Gamma, and Related Distributions 240
8.5 Normal Distribution 246
8.6 Beta Distribution 255
CONTENTS ix

9 Random Samples 259


9.1 Statistics and Sampling Distributions 259
9.2 Distributions Related to Normal 261
9.3 Order Statistics 266
9.4 Generating Random Samples 272
9.5 Convergence 276
9.6 Central Limit Theorem 287

10 Introduction to Statistical Inference 295


10.1 Overview 295
10.2 Basic Models 298
10.3 Sampling 299
10.4 Measurement Scales 305

11 Estimation 309
11.1 Introduction 309
11.2 Consistency 313
11.3 Loss, Risk, and Admissibility 316
11.4 Efficiency 321
11.5 Methods of Obtaining Estimators 328
11.6 Sufficiency 345
11.7 Interval Estimation 359

12 Testing Statistical Hypotheses 373


12.1 Introduction 373
12.2 Intuitive Background 377
12.3 Most Powerful Tests 384
12.4 Uniformly Most Powerful Tests 396
12.5 Unbiased Tests 402
12.6 Generalized Likelihood Ratio Tests 405
12.7 Conditional Tests 412
12.8 Tests and Confidence Intervals 415
12.9 Review of Tests for Normal Distributions 416
12.10 Monte Carlo, Bootstrap, and Permutation Tests 424

13 Linear Models 429


13.1 Introduction 429
13.2 Regression of the First and Second Kind 431
13.3 Distributional Assumptions 436
13.4 Linear Regression in the Normal Case 438
13.5 Testing Linearity 444
13.6 Prediction 447
x CONTENTS

13.7 Inverse Regression 449


13.8 BLUE 451
13.9 Regression Toward the Mean 453
13.10 Analysis of Variance 455
13.11 One-Way Layout 455
13.12 Two-Way Layout 458
13.13 ANOVA Models with Interaction 461
13.14 Further Extensions 465

14 Rank Methods 467


14.1 Introduction 467
14.2 Glivenko–Cantelli Theorem 468
14.3 Kolmogorov–Smirnov Tests 471
14.4 One-Sample Rank Tests 478
14.5 Two-Sample Rank Tests 484
14.6 Kruskal–Wallis Test 488

15 Analysis of Categorical Data 491


15.1 Introduction 491
15.2 Chi-Square Tests 492
15.3 Homogeneity and Independence 499
15.4 Consistency and Power 504
15.5 2 × 2 Contingency Tables 509
15.6 r × c Contingency Tables 516

16 Basics of Bayesian Statistics 521


16.1 Introduction 521
16.2 Prior and Posterior Distributions 522
16.3 Bayesian Inference 529
16.4 Final Comments 543

Appendix A Supporting R Code 545

Appendix B Statistical Tables 551

Bibliography 555

Answers to Odd-Numbered Problems 559

Index 571
Preface to Third Edition

You have in front of you the third edition of the “Probability and Statistical Inference,” a
text originally published in 1996. I have been using this book in the classroom since then,
and it has always been interesting to see how it serves the students, how they react to it,
and what could still be done to make it better. These reflections prompted me to prepare a
second edition, published in 2007. But academia is changing quickly; who the students are
is changing, and how we should teach to help them learn is changing as well. This is what
made me consider a third edition. The response from Wiley Publishing was positive and my
work began.
There were three main changes that I saw as necessary. First, adding a chapter on the
basics of Bayesian statistics, as I realized that upper level undergraduate students and grad-
uate students needed an earlier introduction to Bayesian inference. Another change was to
make the book more appropriate for the flipped classroom format. I have experimented with
it for three years now and it is working quite well. The book introduces and illustrates con-
cepts through more than 400 examples. Preparing the material mainly at home gives students
more time in class for questions, discussion, and for problem solving. I have also added
over 70 new problems to make the selection easier for the instructor. A third change was
including an appendix with an R code that would help students complete projects and home-
work assignments. My two-semester class based on this text includes three projects. The first
one –in the fall semester–has students present applications of selected distributions, includ-
ing graphics. Two projects for the spring semester involve resampling methods. The necessary
R code is included in the appendix.
There are many people to whom I owe my thanks. First, I would like to thank Wiley
Editor Jon Gurstelle, who liked the idea of preparing the third edition. After Jon accepted
another job elsewhere, the book and I came under the excellent care of the Editorial Teams of
Mindy Okura-Mokrzycki, Kathleen Santoloci, Linda Christina, and Kimberly Monroe-Hill
who have supported me throughout this process. I would also like to thank Carla Koretsky,
the Dean of the College of Arts and Sciences at Western Michigan University, and WMU
Provost, Sue Stapleton, for granting me a semester-long administrative sabbatical leave that
significantly sped up the progress of the book.
xi
xii PREFACE TO THIRD EDITION

I am indebted to several of my students for their valuable comments. I am also grateful


to my departmental colleagues, especially Hyun Bin Kang and Duy Ngo, who used the text
in class and gave me their valuable feedback. Hyun Bin also helped me with the format-
ting of the R code in the appendix. Finally, I thank my husband, Jerzy, for his support and
encouragement.

MNB

November 2020
Preface to Second Edition

The first edition of this book was published in 1996. Since then, powerful computers have
come into wide use, and it became clear that our text should be revised and material on
computer-intensive methods of statistical inference should be added. To my delight, Steve
Quigley, Executive Editor of John Wiley and Sons, agreed with the idea, and work on the
second edition began.
Unfortunately, Robert Bartoszyński passed away in 1998, so I was left to carry out this
revision by myself. I revised the content by creating a new chapter on random samples, adding
sections on Monte Carlo methods, bootstrap estimators and tests, and permutation tests.
More problems were added, and existing ones were reorganized. Hopefully nothing was lost
of the “spirit” of the book which Robert liked so much and of which he was very proud.
This book is intended for seniors or first-year graduate students in statistics, mathematics,
natural sciences, engineering, and any other major where an intensive exposure to statistics
is necessary. The prerequisite is a calculus sequence that includes multivariate calculus. We
provide the material for a two-semester course that starts with the necessary background in
probability theory, followed by the theory of statistics.
What distinguishes our book from other texts is the way the material is presented and the
aspects that are stressed. To put it succinctly, understanding “why” is prioritized over the skill
of “how to.” Today, in an era of undreamed-of computational facilities, a reflection in an
attempt to understand is not a luxury but a necessity.
Probability theory and statistics are presented as self-contained conceptual structures.
Their value as a means of description and inference about real-life situations lies precisely in
their level of abstraction—the more abstract a concept is, the wider is its applicability. The
methodology of statistics comes out most clearly if it is introduced as an abstract system
illustrated by a variety of real-life applications, not confined to any single domain.
Depending on the level of the course, the instructor can select topics and examples,
both in the theory and in applications. These can range from simple illustrations of
concepts, to introductions of whole theories typically not included in comparable textbooks
(e.g., prediction, extrapolation, and filtration in time series as examples of use of the
concepts of covariance and correlation). Such additional, more advanced, material (e.g.,
xiii
xiv PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION

Chapter 5 on Markov Chains) is marked with asterisks. Other examples are the proof of
the extension theorem (Theorem 6.2.4), showing that the cumulative distribution function
determines the measure on the line; the construction of Lebesgue, Riemann–Stieltjes, and
Lebesgue–Stieltjes integrals; and the explanation of the difference between double integral
and iterated integrals (Section 8.3).
In the material that is seldom included in other textbooks on mathematical statistics, we
stress the consequences of nonuniqueness of a sample space and illustrate, by examples, how
the choice of a sample space can facilitate the formulation of some problems (e.g., issues of
selection or randomized response). We introduce the concept of conditioning with respect to
partition (Section 4.4); we explain the Borel–Kolmogorov paradox by way of the underlying
measurement process that provides information on the occurrence of the condition (Example
7.22); we present the Neyman–Scott theory of outliers (Example 10.4); we give a new version
of the proof of the relation between mean, median, and standard deviation (Theorem 8.7.3);
we show another way of conditioning in the secretary problem (Example 4.10). Among
examples of applications, we discuss the strategies of serves in tennis (Problem 4.2.12), and
a series of problems (3.2.14–3.2.20) concerning combinatorial analysis of voting power. In
Chapter 11, we discuss the renewal paradox, the effects of importance sampling (Example
11.6), and the relevance of measurement theory for statistics (Section 11.6). Chapter 14
provides a discussion of true regression versus linear regression and concentrates mostly on
explaining why certain procedures (in regression analysis and ANOVA) work, rather than
on computational details. In Chapter 15, we provide a taste of rank methods—one line of
research starting with the Glivenko–Cantelli Theorem and leading to Kolmogorov–Smirnov
tests, and the other line leading to Mann-Whitney and Wilcoxon tests. In this chapter, we
also show the traps associated with multiple tests of the same hypothesis (Example 15.3).
Finally, Chapter 16 contains information on partitioning contingency tables—the method
that provides insight into the dependence structure. We also introduce McNemar’s test and
various indices of association for tables with ordered categories.
The backbone of the book is the examples used to illustrate concepts, theorems, and meth-
ods. Some examples raise the possibilities of extensions and generalizations, and some simply
point out the relevant subtleties.
Another feature that distinguishes our book from most other texts is the choice of prob-
lems. Our strategy was to integrate the knowledge students acquired thus far, rather than
to train them in a single skill or concept. The solution to a problem in a given section may
require using knowledge from some preceding sections, that is, reaching back into material
already covered. Most of the problems are intended to make the students aware of facts they
might otherwise overlook. Many of the problems were inspired by our teaching experience
and familiarity with students’ typical errors and misconceptions.
Finally, we hope that our book will be “friendly” for students at all levels. We provide
(hopefully) lucid and convincing explanations and motivations, pointing out the difficulties
and pitfalls of arguments. We also do not want good students to be left alone. The material
in starred chapters, sections, and examples can be skipped in the main part of the course, but
used at will by interested students to complement and enhance their knowledge. The book
can also be a useful reference, or source of examples and problems, for instructors who teach
courses from other texts.
I am indebted to many people without whom this book would not have reached its current
form. First, thank you to many colleagues who contributed to the first edition and whose
names are listed there. Comments of many instructors and students who used the first edition
were influential in this revision. I wish to express my gratitude to Samuel Kotz for referring
me to Stigler’s (1986) article about the “right and lawful rood,” which we previously used in
the book without reference (Example 8.40). My sincere thanks are due to Jung Chao Wang
PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION xv

for his help in creating the R-code for computer-intensive procedures that, together with
additional examples, can be found on the book’s ftp site

ftp://ftp.wiley.com/public/sc tech med/probability statistical.

Particular thanks are due to Katarzyna Bugaj for careful proofreading of the entire
manuscript, Łukasz Bugaj for meticulously creating all figures with the Mathematica
software, and Agata Bugaj for her help in compiling the index. Changing all those diapers
has finally paid off.
I wish to express my appreciation to the anonymous reviewers for supporting the book
and providing valuable suggestions, and to Steve Quigley, Executive Editor of John Wiley &
Sons, for all his help and guidance in carrying out the revision.
Finally, I would like to thank my family, especially my husband Jerzy, for their encour-
agement and support during the years this book was being written.

Magdalena Niewiadomska-Bugaj

October 2007
About the Companion Website

This book is accompanied by a companion website:

www.wiley.com/go/probabilityandstatisticalinference3e

The website includes the Instructor’s Solution Manual and will be live in early 2021.

xvi
CHAPTER 1

EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND


EVENTS

1.1 INTRODUCTION

The consequences of making a decision today often depend on what will happen in the future,
at least on the future that is relevant to the decision. The main purpose of using statistical
methods is to help in making better decisions under uncertainty.
Judging from the failures of weather forecasts, to more spectacular prediction failures,
such as bankruptcies of large companies and stock market crashes, it would appear that
statistical methods do not perform very well. However, with a possible exception of weather
forecasting, these examples are, at best, only partially statistical predictions. Moreover,
failures tend to be better remembered than successes. Whatever the case, statistical
methods are at present, and are likely to remain indefinitely, our best and most reliable
prediction tools.
To make decisions under uncertainty, one usually needs to collect some data. Data may
come from past experiences and observations, or may result from some controlled processes,
such as laboratory or field experiments. The data are then used to hypothesize about the
laws (often called mechanisms) that govern the fragment of reality of interest. In our book,
we are interested in laws expressed in probabilistic terms: They specify directly, or allow us
to compute, the chances of some events to occur. Knowledge of these chances is, in most
cases, the best one can get with regard to prediction and decisions.
Probability theory is a domain of pure mathematics and as such, it has its own concep-
tual structure. To enable a variety of applications (typically comprising of all areas of human
endeavor, ranging from biological, medical, social and physical sciences, to engineering,
humanities, business, etc.), such structure must be kept on an abstract level. An application
of probability to the particular situation analyzed requires a number of initial steps in which
the elements of the real situation are interpreted as abstract concepts of probability theory.

Probability and Statistical Inference, Third Edition. Magdalena Niewiadomska-Bugaj and Robert Bartoszyński.
© 2021 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Published 2021 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc.

1
2 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

Such interpretation is often referred to as building a probabilistic model of the situation at


hand. How well this is done is crucial to the success of application.
One of the main concepts here is that of an experiment—a term used in a broad sense. It
means any process that generates data which is influenced, at least in part, by chance.

1.2 SAMPLE SPACE

In analyzing an experiment, one is primarily interested in its outcome—the concept that


is not defined (i.e., a primitive concept) but has to be specified in every particular applica-
tion. This specification may be done in different ways, with the only requirements being that
(1) outcomes exclude one another and (2) they exhaust the set of all logical possibilities.

EXAMPLE 1.1

Consider an experiment consisting of two tosses of a regular die. An outcome is most


naturally represented by a pair of numbers that turn up on the upper faces of the die
so that they form a pair (x, y), with x, y = 1, 2, . . . , 6 (see Table 1.1).

Table 1.1 Outcomes on a pair of dice.


y
1 2 3 4 5 6
1 (1, 1) (1, 2) (1, 3) (1, 4) (1, 5) (1, 6)
2 (2, 1) (2, 2) (2, 3) (2, 4) (2, 5) (2, 6)
x 3 (3, 1) (3, 2) (3, 3) (3, 4) (3, 5) (3, 6)
4 (4, 1) (4, 2) (4, 3) (4, 4) (4, 5) (4, 6)
5 (5, 1) (5, 2) (5, 3) (5, 4) (5, 5) (5, 6)
6 (6, 1) (6, 2) (6, 3) (6, 4) (6, 5) (6, 6)
In the case of an experiment of tossing a die three times, the outcomes will
be triplets (x, y, z), with x, y, and z being integers between 1 and 6.

Since the outcome of an experiment is not known in advance, it is important to deter-


mine the set of all possible outcomes. This set, called the sample space, forms the conceptual
framework for all further considerations of probability.

Definition 1.2.1 The sample space, denoted by S, is the set of all outcomes of an experiment.
The elements of the sample space are called elementary outcomes, or sample points. 

EXAMPLE 1.2

In Example 1.1, the sample space S has 62 = 36 sample points in the case of two tosses,
and 63 = 216 points in the case of three tosses of a die. The first statement can be veri-
fied by a direct counting of the elements of the sample space. Similar verification of the
second claim, although possible in principle, would be cumbersome. In Chapter 3, we
will introduce some methods of determining the sizes of sets without actually counting
sample points.

EXAMPLE 1.3

Suppose that the only available information about the numbers, those that turn up on
the upper faces of the die, is their sum. In such a case as outcomes, we take 11 possible
values of the sum so that
S = {2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 12}.
SAMPLE SPACE 3

For instance, all outcomes on the diagonal of Table 1.1—(6, 1), (5, 2), (4, 3), (3, 4),
(2, 5), and (1, 6)—are represented by the same value 7.

EXAMPLE 1.4

If we are interested in the number of accidents that occur at a given intersection within
a month, the sample space might be taken as the set S = {0, 1, 2, . . . } consisting of all
nonnegative integers. Realistically, there is a practical limit, say 1,000, of the monthly
numbers of accidents at this particular intersection. Although one may think that
it is simpler to take the sample space S = {0, 1, 2, . . . , 1,000}, it turns out that it is
often much simpler to take the infinite sample space if the “practical bound” is not
very precise.

Since outcomes can be specified in various ways (as illustrated by Examples 1.1 and 1.3),
it follows that the same experiment can be described in terms of different sample spaces S.
The choice of a sample space depends on the goal of description. Moreover, certain sample
spaces for the same experiment lead to easier and simpler analysis. The choice of a “better”
sample space requires some skill, which is usually gained through experience. The following
two examples illustrate this point.

EXAMPLE 1.5

Let the experiment consist of recording the lifetime of a piece of equipment, say a light
bulb. An outcome here is the time until the bulb burns out. An outcome typically will
be represented by a number t ≥ 0 (t = 0 if the bulb is not working at the start), and
therefore S is the nonnegative part of the real axis. In practice, t is measured with some
precision (in hours, days, etc.), so one might instead take S = {0, 1, 2, . . . }. Which of
these choices is better depends on the type of subsequent analysis.

EXAMPLE 1.6

Two persons enter a cafeteria and sit at a square table, with one chair on each of its
sides. Suppose we are interested in the event “they sit at a corner” (as opposed to sitting
across from one another). To construct the sample space, we let A and B denote the
two persons, and then take as S the set of outcomes represented by 12 ideograms in
Figure 1.1. One could argue, however, that such a sample space is unnecessarily large.

B A
A B A B
B A

A B
B A B A
A B

A B
A B B A
B A

Figure 1.1 Possible seatings of persons A and B at a square table.


4 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

If we are interested only in the event “they sit at a corner,” then there is no need to
label the persons as A and B. Accordingly, the sample space S may be reduced to the
set of six outcomes depicted in Figure 1.2. But even this sample space can be simplified.
Indeed, one could use the rotational symmetry of the table and argue that once the first
person selects a chair (it does not matter which one), then the sample space consists of
just three chairs remaining for the second person (see Figure 1.3).

x x x
x x
x

x x x x
x x

Figure 1.2 Possible seatings of any two persons at a square table.

Figure 1.3 Possible seatings of one person if the place of the other person is fixed.

Sample spaces can be classified according to the number of sample points they contain.
Finite sample spaces contain finitely many outcomes, and elements of infinitely countable
sample spaces can be arranged into an infinite sequence; other sample spaces are called
uncountable.
The next concept to be introduced is that of an event. Intuitively, an event is anything
about which we can tell whether or not it has occurred, as soon as we know the outcome of
the experiment. This leads to the following definition:

Definition 1.2.2 An event is a subset of the sample space S. 

EXAMPLE 1.7

In Example 1.1 an event such as “the sum equals 7” containing six outcomes
(1, 6), (2, 5), (3, 4), (4, 3), (5, 2), and (6, 1) is a subset of the sample space S. In
Example 1.3, the same event consists of one outcome, 7.

When an experiment is performed, we observe its outcome. In the interpretation devel-


oped in this chapter, this means that we observe a point chosen randomly from the sample
space. If this point belongs to the subset representing the event A, we say that the event A
has occurred.
We will let events be denoted either by letters A, B, C, . . . , possibly with identifiers, such
as A1 , Bk , . . . , or by more descriptive means, such as {X = 1} and {a < Z < b}, where X
SAMPLE SPACE 5

and Z are some numerical attributes of the sample points (formally: random variables, to be
discussed in Chapter 5). Events can also be described through verbal phrases, such as “two
heads in a row occur before the third tail” in the experiment of repeated tosses of a coin.
In all cases considered thus far, we assumed that an outcome (a point in the sample space)
can be observed. To put it more precisely, all sample spaces S considered so far were con-
structed in such a way that their points were observable. Thus, for any event A, we were
always able to tell whether it occurred or not.
The following examples show experiments and corresponding sample spaces with sample
points that are only partially observable:

EXAMPLE 1.8 Selection

Candidates for a certain job are characterized by their level z of skills required for the
job. The actual value of z is not observable, though; what we observe is the candidate’s
score x on a certain test. Thus, the sample point in S is a pair s = (z, x), and only one
coordinate of s, x, is observable.
The objective might be to find selection thresholds z0 and x0 , such that the rule:
“accept all candidates whose score x exceeds x0 ” would lead to maximizing the (unob-
servable) number of persons accepted whose true level of skill z exceeds z0 . Naturally,
to find such a solution, one needs to understand statistical relation between observable
x and unobservable z.

Another example when the points in the sample space are only partially observable con-
cerns studies of incidence of activities about which one may hesitate to respond truthfully,
or even to respond at all. These are typically studies related to sexual habits or preferences,
abortion, law and tax violation, drug use, and so on.

EXAMPLE 1.9 Randomized Response

Let Q be the activity analyzed, and assume that the researcher is interested in the fre-
quency of persons who ever participated in activity Q (for simplicity, we will call them
Q-persons). It ought to be stressed that the objective is not to identify the Q-persons,
but only to find the proportion of such persons in the population.
The direct question reduced to something like “Are you a Q-person?” is not likely to
be answered truthfully, if at all. It is therefore necessary to make the respondent safe,
guaranteeing that their responses will reveal nothing about them as regards Q. This
can be accomplished as follows: The respondent is given a pair of distinguishable dice,
for example, one green and one white. She throws them both at the same time, in such
a way that the experimenter does not know the results of the toss (e.g., the dice are in a
box and only the respondent looks into the box after it is shaken). The instruction is the
following: If the green die shows an odd face (1, 3, or 5), then respond to the question
“Are you a Q-person?” If the green die shows an even face (2, 4, or 6), then respond
to the question, “Does the white die show an ace?” The scheme of this response is
summarized by the flowchart in Figure 1.4.
The interviewer knows the answer “yes” or “no” but does not know whether it is
the answer to the question about Q or the question about the white die. Here a natural
sample space consists of points s = (i, x, y), where x and y are outcomes on green and
white die, respectively, while i is 1 or 0 depending on whether or not the respondent is
a Q-person. We have φ(s) = φ(i, x, y)= “yes” if i = 1 and x = 1, 3, or 5 for any y, or
if x = 2, 4, 6, and y = 1 for any i. In all other cases, φ(s) = “no.”
6 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

Green die

odd even

Are you a White die


Q-person? 1 23456

YES

NO

Figure 1.4 Scheme of a randomized response.

One could wonder what is a possible advantage, if any, of not knowing the question
asked and observing only the answer. This does not make sense if we need to know the
truth about each individual respondent. However, one should remember that we are
only after the overall frequency of Q-persons.
We are in fact “contaminating” the question by making the respondent answer
either a Q-question or some other auxiliary question. But this is a “controlled
contamination”: we know how often (on average) the respondents answer the
auxiliary question, and how often their answer is “yes.” Consequently, as we will
see in Chapter 11, we can still make an inference about the proportion of Q-persons
based on the observed responses.

PROBLEMS

1.2.1 List all sample points in sample spaces for the following experiments: (i) We toss a
balanced coin.1 If heads come up, we toss a die. Otherwise, we toss the coin two more
times. (ii) A coin is tossed until the total of two tails occurs, but no more than four
times (i.e., a coin is tossed until the second tail or fourth toss, whichever comes first).
1.2.2 Alice, Bob, Carl, and Diana enter the elevator on the first floor of a four-story build-
ing. Each of them leaves the elevator on either the second, third, or fourth floor.
(i) Describe the sample space without listing all sample points. (ii) List all sample
points such that Carl and Diana leave the elevator on the third floor. (iii) List all
sample points if Carl and Diana leave the elevator at the same floor.
1.2.3 An urn contains five chips, labeled 1, . . . , 5. Three chips are selected. List all out-
comes included in the event “the second largest number drawn was 3.”
1.2.4 In a game of craps, the player rolls a pair of dice. If he gets a total of 7 or 11, he wins
at once; if the total is 2, 3, or 12, he loses at once. Otherwise, the sum, say x, is his
“point,” and he keeps rolling dice until either he rolls another x (in which case he
wins) or he rolls a 7 in which case he loses. Describe the event “the player wins with
a point of 5.”

1 Unless specifically stated, we will be assuming that all coins and/or dice tossed are fair (balanced).
SAMPLE SPACE 7

1.2.5 The experiment consists of placing six balls in three boxes. List all outcomes in the
sample space if: (i) The balls are indistinguishable, but the boxes are distinguishable.
(Hint: There are 28 different placements.) (ii) Neither the balls nor the boxes are dis-
tinguishable. (iii) Two balls are white and four are red; the boxes are distinguishable.
1.2.6 John and Mary plan to meet each other. Each of them is to arrive at the meeting
place at some time between 5 p.m. and 6 p.m. John is to wait 20 minutes (or until
6 p.m., whichever comes first), and then leave if Mary does not show up. Mary
will wait only 5 minutes (or until 6 p.m., whichever comes first), and then leave if
John does not show up. Letting x and y denote the arrival times of John and Mary,
determine the sample space and describe events (i)–(viii) by drawing pictures, or by
appropriate inequalities for x and y. If you think that the description is impossible,
say so. (i) John arrives before Mary does. (ii) John and Mary meet. (iii) Either Mary
comes first, or they do not meet. (iv) Mary comes first, but they do not meet. (v)
John comes very late. (vi) They arrive less than 15 minutes apart, and they do not
meet. (vii) Mary arrives at 5:15 p.m. and meets John, who is already there. (viii)
They almost miss one another.
Problems 1.2.7–1.2.8 show an importance of the sample space selection.
1.2.7 Let E be the experiment consisting of tossing a coin three times, with H and T stand-
ing for heads and tails, respectively.
(i) The following set of outcomes is an incomplete list of the points of the sample
space S of the experiment E: {HHH, HTT, TTT, HHT, HTH, THH}. Use a tree
diagram to find the missing outcomes.
(ii) An alternative sample space S  for the same experiment E consists of the follow-
ing four outcomes: no heads (0), one head (1), two heads (2), and three heads (3).
Which of the following events can be described as subsets of S but not as subsets of
S  = {0, 1, 2, 3}?
A1 = More than two heads.
A2 = Head on the second toss.
A3 = More tails than heads.
A4 = At least one tail, with head on the last toss.
A5 = At least two faces the same.
A6 = Head and tail alternate.
(iii) Still another sample space S  for the experiment E consists of the four outcomes
(0, 0), (0, 1), (1, 0), and (1, 1). The first coordinate is 1 if the first two tosses show the
same face and 0 otherwise; the second coordinate is 1 if the last two tosses show
the same face, and 0 otherwise. For instance, if we observe HHT, the outcome is
(1, 0). List the outcomes of S that belong to the event A = {(1, 1), (0, 1)} of S  .
(iv) Which of the following events can be represented as subsets of S, but cannot be
represented as subsets of S  ?
B1 = First and third toss show the same face.
B2 = Heads on all tosses.
B3 = All faces the same.
B4 = Each face appears at least once.
B5 = More heads than tails.
1.2.8 Let E be an experiment consisting of tossing a die twice. Let S be the sample space
with sample points (i, j), i, j = 1, 2, . . . , 6, with i and j being the numbers of dots
that appear in the first and second toss, respectively.
8 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

(i) Let S  be the sample space for the experiment E consisting of all possible sums
i + j so that S  = {2, 3, . . . , 12}. Which of the following events can be defined as
subsets of S but not of S  ?
A1 = One face odd, the other even.
A2 = Both faces even.
A3 = Faces different.
A4 = Result on the first toss less than the result on the second.
A5 = Product greater than 10.
A6 = Product greater than 30.
(ii) Let S  be the sample space for the experiment E consisting of all possible absolute
values of the difference |i − j| so that S  = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5}. Which of the following
events can be defined as subsets of S but not of S  ?
B1 = One face shows twice as many dots as the other,
B2 = Faces the same,
B3 = One face shows six times as many dots as the other,
B4 = One face odd, the other even,
B5 = The ratio of the numbers of dots on the faces is different from 1.
1.2.9 Referring to Example 1.9, suppose that we modify it as follows: The respondent
tosses a green die (with the outcome unknown to the interviewer). If the outcome is
odd, he responds to the Q-question; otherwise, he responds to the question “Were
you born in April?” Again, the interviewer observes only the answer “yes” or “no.”
Apart from the obvious difference in the frequency of the answer “yes” to the
auxiliary question (on the average 1 in 12 instead of 1 in 6), are there any essential
differences between this scheme and the scheme in Example 1.9? Explain your
answer.

1.3 ALGEBRA OF EVENTS

Next, we introduce concepts that will allow us to form composite events out of simpler ones.
We begin with the relations of inclusion and equality.

Definition 1.3.1 The event A is contained in the event B, or B contains A, if every sample
point of A is also a sample point of B. Whenever this is true, we will write A ⊂ B, or equiv-
alently, B ⊃ A. 

An alternative terminology here is that A implies (or entails) B.

Definition 1.3.2 Two events A and B are said to be equal, A = B, if A ⊂ B and B ⊂ A. 

It follows that two events are equal if they consist of exactly the same sample points.

EXAMPLE 1.10

Consider two tosses of a coin, and the corresponding sample space S consisting of four
outcomes: HH, HT, TH, and TT. The event A = “heads in the first toss” = {HH, HT}
is contained in the event B = “at least one head” = {HH, HT, TH}. The events “the
results alternate” and “at least one head and one tail” imply one another, and hence
are equal.
ALGEBRA OF EVENTS 9

Definition 1.3.3 The set containing no elements is called the empty set and is denoted by ∅.
The event corresponding to ∅ is called a null (impossible) event. 

EXAMPLE 1.11 *2

The reader may wonder whether it is correct to use the definite article in the definition
above and speak of “the empty set,” since it would appear that there may be many
different empty sets. For instance, the set of all kings of the United States and the set of
all real numbers x such that x2 + 1 = 0 are both empty, but one consists of people and
the other of numbers, so they cannot be equal. This is not so, however, as is shown by
the following formal argument (to appreciate this argument, one needs some training
in logic). Suppose that ∅1 and ∅2 are two empty sets. To prove that they are equal, one
needs to prove that ∅1 ⊂ ∅2 and ∅2 ⊂ ∅1 . Formally, the first inclusion is the implication:
“if s belongs to ∅1 , then s belongs to ∅2 .” This implication is true, because its premise
is false: there is no s that belongs to ∅1 . The same holds for the second implication, so
∅1 = ∅2 .

We now give the definitions of three principal operations on events: complementation,


union, and intersection.

Definition 1.3.4 The set that contains all sample points that are not in the event A will be
called the complement of A and denoted Ac , to be read also as “not A.” 

Definition 1.3.5 The set that contains all sample points belonging either to A or to B (so
possibly to both of them) is called the union of A and B and denoted A ∪ B, to be read as
“A or B.” 

Definition 1.3.6 The set that contains all sample points belonging to both A and B is called
the intersection of A and B and denoted A ∩ B. 

An alternative notation for a complement is A or A, whereas in the case of an intersection,


one often writes AB instead of A ∩ B.
The operations above have the following interpretations in terms of occurrences
of events:
1. Event Ac occurs if event A does not occur.
2. Event A ∪ B occurs when either A or B or both events occur.
3. Event A ∩ B occurs when both A and B occur.

EXAMPLE 1.12

Consider an experiment of tossing a coin three times, with the sample space
consisting of outcomes described as HHH, HHT, and so on. Let A and B be
the events “heads and tails alternate” and “heads on the last toss,” respectively.
The event Ac occurs if either heads or tails occur at least twice in a row so that
Ac = {HHH, HHT, THH, HTT, TTT, TTH}, while B c is “tails on the last
toss,” hence, B c = {HHT, THT, HTT, TTT}. The union A ∪ B is the event
“either the results alternate or it is heads on the last toss,” meaning A ∪ B =
{HTH, THT, HHH, THH, TTH}. Observe that while A has two outcomes and B has

2 Asterisks denote more advanced material, as explained in the Preface to the Second Edition.
10 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

four outcomes, their union has only five outcomes, since the outcome HTH appears
in both events. This common part is the intersection A ∩ B.

Some formulas can be simplified by introducing the operation of the difference of two
events.

Definition 1.3.7 The difference, A \ B, of events A and B contains all sample points that
belong to A but not to B
A \ B = A ∩ Bc.
The symmetric difference, A ÷ B, contains sample points that belong to A or to B, but not
to both of them:
A ÷ B = (A ∩ B c ) ∪ (Ac ∩ B) = (A ∪ B)\(A ∩ B). 

EXAMPLE 1.13

In Example 1.12, the difference B c \A is described as “at least two identical outcomes
in a row and tails on the last toss,” which means the event {HHT, HTT, TTT}.

Next, we introduce the following important concept:

Definition 1.3.8 If A ∩ B = ∅, then the events A and B are called disjoint, or mutually
exclusive. 

EXAMPLE 1.14

Based on Example 1.12, we know that the following two events are disjoint: C = “more
heads than tails” and the intersection A ∩ B c = “the results alternate, ending with
tails.”

Example 1.14 shows that to determine whether or not events are disjoint, it is not neces-
sary to list the outcomes in both events and check whether there exist common outcomes.
Apart from the fact that such listing is not feasible when sample spaces are large, it is often
simpler to employ logical reasoning. In the case above, if the results alternate and end with
tails, then the outcome must be THT. Since there are more tails than heads, C does not occur.
The definitions of union and intersection can be extended to the case of a finite and even
infinite number of events (to be discussed in the Section 1.4). Thus,

n
A1 ∪ A2 ∪ · · · ∪ An = Ai (1.1)
i=1

is the event that contains the sample points belonging to A1 or A2 or . . . or An . Conse-


quently, (1.1) is the event “at least one Ai occurs.” Similarly,

n
A1 ∩ A2 ∩ · · · ∩ An = Ai (1.2)
i=1

is the event that contains the sample points belonging to A1 and A2 and . . . and An . Conse-
quently, the event (1.2) is “all Ai ’s occur.”

EXAMPLE 1.15

Suppose that n shots are fired at a target, and let Ai , i = 1, 2, . . . , n denote the event
“the target is hit on the ith shot.” Then, the union A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An is the event “the
ALGEBRA OF EVENTS 11

target is hit” (at least once). Its complement (A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An )c is the event “the target
is missed” (on every shot), which is the same as the intersection Ac1 ∩ · · · ∩ Acn .

A perceptive reader may note that the unions A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An and intersections


A1 ∩ · · · ∩ An do not require an extension of the definition of union and intersection for
two events. Indeed, we could consider unions such as

A1 ∪ (A2 ∪ (· · · (An−2 ∪ (An−1 ∪ An )) · · · )),

where the union of only two events is formed in each set of parentheses. The property
of associativity (below) shows that parentheses can be omitted so that the expression
A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An is unambiguous. The same argument applies to intersections.
The operations on events defined in this section obey some laws. The most important ones
are listed below.
Idempotence:
A ∪ A = A, A ∩ A = A.

Double complementation:
(Ac )c = A.

Absorption:
A∪B =B ⇐⇒ A∩B =A ⇐⇒ A ⊂ B. (1.3)

In particular,

A ∪ ∅ = A, A ∪ S = S, A ∩ ∅ = ∅, A ∩ S = A,

which in view of (1.3) means that ∅ ⊂ A ⊂ S.

Commutativity:
A ∪ B = B ∪ A, A ∩ B = B ∩ A.

Associativity:

A ∪ (B ∪ C) = (A ∪ B) ∪ C, A ∩ (B ∩ C) = (A ∩ B) ∩ C.

Distributivity:

A ∩ (B ∪ C) = (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ C), A ∪ (B ∩ C) = (A ∪ B) ∩ (A ∪ C).

De Morgan’s Laws:

(A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An )c = Ac1 ∩ · · · ∩ Acn ,


(A1 ∩ · · · ∩ An )c = Ac1 ∪ · · · ∪ Acn . (1.4)

It is often helpful to use Venn diagrams for studying relations between composite events
in the same sample space. The sample space S is there represented by a rectangle, while its
subsets represent events (see Figure 1.5).
The complement of event A is represented in Figure 1.5a, the union and intersection of
the events A and B are represented in Figure 1.5b and c, respectively.
Venn diagrams can also be used to check the validity of formulas. For example, consider
the first De Morgan’s law (1.4) for the case of two events:

(A ∪ B)c = Ac ∩ B c . (1.5)
12 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

A
A B A B
(a) (b) (c)

Figure 1.5 Complement, union, and intersection.

A
B

Figure 1.6 The first De Morgan’s law.

Venn diagrams made separately for the left-hand side and the right-hand side of (1.5) (see
Figure 1.6) indicate that both regions are the same. Although a picture does not constitute
a proof, it may provide convincing evidence that the statement is true, and sometimes may
even suggest a method of proving the statement.

PROBLEMS
For the problems below, remember that a statement (expressed as a sentence or formula) is
true if it is true under all circumstances, and it is false if there is at least one case where it
does not hold.

1.3.1 Answer true or false. Justify your answer. (i) If A and B are distinct events (i.e., A = B)
such that A and B c are disjoint, then Ac and B are also disjoint. (ii) If A and B are
disjoint, then Ac and B c are also disjoint. (iii) If A and B are disjoint, and also B and
C are disjoint, then A and C are disjoint. (iv) If A and B are both contained in C,
then C c ⊂ Ac ∩ B c . (v) If A is contained in B, C is contained in D, and B is disjoint
from D, then A is disjoint from C. (vi) If A ∪ B c = B c , then B ⊂ Ac .
1.3.2 In the statements below A, B, C, and D are events. Find those statements or formulas
that are true. (i) If A ∩ B = A ∩ C, then B = C. (ii) A ∪ (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ B c ) = A.
(iii) A ∪ (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ B c ) = B. (iv) If A \ B = C, then A = B ∪ C. (v) (A ∪ B) ∩
(C ∪ D) = (A ∩ C) ∪ (A ∩ D) ∪ (B ∩ C) ∪ (B ∩ D). (vi) (A ∩ B) ∪ (C ∩ D) = (A ∪
C) ∩ (A ∪ D) ∩ (B ∪ C) ∩ (B ∪ D). (vii) (Ac ∪ B c ∪ C c )c = Ac ∩ B c ∩ C c . (viii) If
A ⊂ B, and B ∩ C = ∅, then C c ∩ A ∩ B c = ∅. (ix) If A ∩ B, A ∩ C and B ∩ C are
not empty, then A ∩ B ∩ C is not empty. (x) Show that (A ÷ B) ÷ C = A ÷ (B ÷ C).
1.3.3 Find X if: (i) A ÷ X = ∅. (ii) A ÷ X = A. (iii) A ÷ X = S. (iv) A ÷ X = B.
1.3.4 In a group of 1,000 students of a certain college, 60 take French, 417 take calculus,
and 509 take statistics. Moreover, 20 take French and calculus, 17 take French and
statistics, and 147 take statistics and calculus. However, 196 students do not take any
INFINITE OPERATIONS ON EVENTS 13

of these three subjects. Determine the number of students who take French, calculus,
and statistics.
1.3.5 Let A, B, and C be three events. Match, where possible, events D1 through D10 with
events E1 through E11 . Matching means that the events are exactly the same; that is,
if one occurs, so must the other and conversely (see the Definition 1.3.2). (Hint: Draw
a Venn diagram for each event D1 , . . . , D10 , do the same for events E1 , . . . , E11 , and
then compare the diagrams.)
Among events A, B, C:
D1 = two or more occur. D2 = exactly one occurs.
D3 = only A occurs. D4 = all occur.
D5 = none occurs. D6 = at most one occurs.
D7 = at least one occurs. D8 = exactly two occur.
D9 = no more than two occur. D10 = B occurs.
E1 = A ∪ B ∪ C.
E2 = (A ∩ B c ∩ C c ) ∪ (Ac ∩ B ∩ C c ) ∪ (Ac ∩ B c ∩ C).
E3 = (A ∩ B)c ∩ (A ∩ C)c ∩ (B ∩ C)c .
E4 = (A ∪ B ∪ C)c .
E5 = Ac ∩ B c ∩ C c .
E6 = A ∩ B ∩ C.
E7 = B.
E8 = A ∩ B c ∩ C c .
E9 = (A ∩ B ∩ C c ) ∪ (A ∩ B c ∩ C) ∪ (Ac ∩ B ∩ C).
E10 = (A ∩ B ∩ C)c .
E11 = (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ C) ∪ (B ∩ C).
1.3.6 A standard deck of cards is dealt among players N, S, E, and W . Let Nk , k = 1, 2, 3, 4
be the event “N has at least k aces,” and let Sk , Ek , and Wk be defined similarly. For
each of the events below, determine the number of aces that N has. (i) N1 ∩ S1 ∩ E1 ∩
W1 . (ii) E2 ∩ (W2 ∪ S2 ). (iii) N3 \ N4 . (iv) S3 ∩ W1 . (v) S1c ∩ W1c ∩ E1c . (vi) N2 ∩ E2 .
1.3.7 Five burglars, A, B, C, D, and E, divide the loot, consisting of five identical gold bars
and four identical diamonds. Let Ajk be the event that A got at least j gold bars and
at most k diamonds. Let Bjk , Cjk denote analogous events for burglars B, C (e.g.,
B21 is the event that B got 2, 3, 4, or 5 gold bars and 0 or 1 diamond). Determine the
number x of gold bars and the number y of diamonds received by E if the following
events occur (if determination of x and/or y is impossible, give the range of values):
(i) (A20 ∪ B20 ∪ C20 ) ∩ D30 . (ii) E12
c
. (iii) A23 ∩ B13 ∩ C13 ∩ D13 . (iv) A23 ∪ B13 ∪
C13 ∪ D13 .
1.3.8 Let Anc be defined inductively by A0c = A, A(n+1)c = (Anc )c . Find Amc ∩ Anc and
Amc ∪ Anc for m, n > 0.

1.4 INFINITE OPERATIONS ON EVENTS

As already mentioned, the operations of union and intersection can be extended to infinitely
many events. Let A1 , A2 , . . . be an infinite sequence of events. Then,

 ∞

A1 ∪ A2 ∪ · · · = Ai and A1 ∩ A2 ∩ · · · = Ai
i=1 i=1

are events “at least one Ai occurs” and “all Ai ’s occur,” respectively.
14 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

If at least one event Ai occurs, then there is one that occurs first. This remark leads to the
following useful decomposition of a union of events into a union of disjoint events:


Ai = A1 ∪ (Ac1 ∩ A2 ) ∪ (Ac1 ∩ Ac2 ∩ A3 ) ∪ · · · , (1.6)
i=1

where Ac1 ∩ · · · ∩ Ack−1 ∩ Ak is the event “Ak is the first event in the sequence that occurs.”
For an infinite sequence A1 , A2 , . . . one can define two events:
∞ 
 ∞
lim sup An = Ai (1.7)
k=1 i=k

and ∞ 


lim inf An = Ai , (1.8)
k=1 i=k

these being, respectively, the event that “infinitely many Ai ’s occur” and the event that “all
except finitely many Ai ’s occur.” Here the inner union in the event (1.7) is the event “at least
one event Ai with i ≥ k will occur”; call this event Bk . The intersection over k means that
the event Bk occurs for every k. No matter how large k we take, there will be at least one
event Ai with i ≥ k that will occur. But this is possible only if infinitely many Ai s occur.
For the event lim inf An , the argument is similar. The intersection Ak ∩ Ak+1 ∩ · · · = Ck
occurs if all events Ai with i ≥ k occur. The union C1 ∪ C2 ∪ · · · means that at least one of
the events Ck will occur, and that means that all Ai will occur, except possibly finitely many.
If all events (except possibly finitely many) occur, then infinitely many of them must
occur, so that lim sup An ⊃ lim inf An . If lim sup An ⊂ lim inf An , then (see the definition
of equality of events) we say that the sequence {An } converges, and lim sup An = lim inf An .
The most important class of convergent sequences of events consists of monotone
sequences, when A1 ⊂ A2 ⊂ · · · (increasing sequence) or when A1 ⊃ A2 ⊃ · · · (decreasing
sequence). We have the following theorem:

Theorem 1.4.1 If the sequence A1 , A2 , . . . is increasing, then




lim An = An ,
n=1

and in case of a decreasing sequence, we have




lim An = An .
n=1
∞
Proof : If the sequence is increasing, then the inner 
union ( i=1 Ai ) in lim sup An remains

the same independently of k so that lim sup An = i=1 Ai . On the other hand, the inner

intersection in lim inf An equals Ak so that lim inf An = k=1 Ak , which is the same as
lim sup An , as was to be shown. A similar argument holds for decreasing sequences. 

The following two examples illustrate the concept of convergence of events.

EXAMPLE 1.16

Let B(r) and C(r) be the sets of points on the plane (x, y) satisfying the conditions
x2 + y 2 < r2 and x2 + y 2 ≤ r2 , respectively. IfAn = B(1 + 1/n), then {An } is a

decreasing sequence, and therefore lim An = n=1 B(1 + 1/n). Since x2 + y 2 <
INFINITE OPERATIONS ON EVENTS 15

∞
(1 + 1/n)2 for all n if and only if x2 + y 2 ≤ 1, we have n=1 B(1 + 1/n) = C(1).
∞ hand, if An = C(1 − 1/n), then {An } is an increasing sequence, and
On the other
lim An = n=1 C(1 − 1/n) = B(1). We leave a justification of the last equality to the
reader.

EXAMPLE 1.17

Let An = B(1 + 1/n) for n odd and An = B(1/3 − 1/2n) for n even. The sequence
{An } is now B(2), B(1/12), B(4/3), B(5/24), . . . , so it is not monotone. We have here
lim sup An = C(1), since every point (x, y) with x2 + y 2 ≤ 1 belongs to infinitely many
An . On the other hand, lim inf An = B(1/3). For x2 + y 2 < 1/9, we have x2 + y 2 <
(1/3 − 1/2n)2 if n is large enough (and also x2 + y 2 < 1 + 1/n for all n). However, if
x2 + y 2 ≥ 1/3, then (x, y) does not belong to any An with even n. Thus, lim sup An =
lim inf An , and the sequence {An } does not converge.

Infinite operations on events play a very important role in the development of the theory,
especially in determining limiting probabilities.
The definitions below will prepare the ground for the considerations in the following
chapters. In Chapter 2, we will introduce probability as a number assigned to an event. For-
mally, we will be considering numerical functions defined on events, that is, on subsets of the
sample space S. As long as S is finite or countably infinite, we can take the class of all subsets
of S as the domain of definition of probability. In case of infinite but not countable S (e.g.,
where S is an interval, the real line, or a plane), it may not be possible to define probability
on the class of all subsets of S. Although the explanation lies beyond the scope of this book,
we will show how the difficulties can be avoided by suitable restriction of the class of subsets
of S that are taken as events. We begin with the concept of closure under some operation.

Definition 1.4.1 We say that the class A of subsets of S is closed under a given operation if
the sets resulting from performing this operation on elements of A are also elements of A. 
Complementation Ac , finite union A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An , infinite union A1 ∪ A2 ∪ · · ·, limits
of sequences lim An , are few examples of such operations.

EXAMPLE 1.18

Let S = {0, 1, 2, . . . }, and let A consist of all subsets of S that are finite. A is
closed under finite unions and all intersections, finite or not. Indeed, if A1 , . . . , An
are finite sets, then A = A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An is also finite. Similarly, if A1 , A2 , . . . are
finite, then ∩i Ai ⊂ A1 , and hence ∩i Ai is also finite. However, A is not closed under
complementation: if A is finite (A ∈ A), then Ac is not finite, and hence Ac ∈ / A. On
the other hand, if A is the class of all subsets of S that contain some fixed element,
say 0, then A is closed under all intersections and unions, but it is not closed under
complementation.

The following concepts have an important role in the theory of probability.

Definition 1.4.2 A nonempty class A of subsets of S that is closed under complementation


and all finite operations (i.e., finite union, finite intersection) is called a field. If A is closed
under complementation and all countable operations, it is called a σ-field. Finally, if A is
closed under monotone passage to the limit,3 it is called a monotone class. 
3 In view of the fact proved earlier that all monotone sequences converge, this condition means that (a) if A1 ⊂
A2 ⊂ · · · is an increasing sequence of sets in A, then ∪i Ai ∈ A, and (b) if A1 ⊃ A2 ⊃ · · · is a decreasing sequence
of sets in A, then ∩i Ai ∈ A.
16 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

Let us observe that Definition 1.4.2 can be formulated in a more efficient way. For A to
be a field, it suffices to require that if A, B ∈ A, then Ac ∈ A and A ∩ B ∈ A (or Ac ∈ A
and A ∪ B ∈ A). Any of these two conditions implies (by induction and De Morgan’s laws)
the closure of A under all finite operations. Consequently, forA to be a σ-field, it suffices

∞require that whenever A1 , A2 , . . . ∈ A, then Ai ∈ A and i=1 Ai ∈ A (or Ai ∈ A and
c c
to
n=1 Ai ∈ A); this follows again from De Morgan’s laws.
4

It is important to realize that closure under countable operations is stronger than closure
under any finite operations. This means that there exist classes of sets that are fields but not
σ-fields. This is illustrated by the following example:

EXAMPLE 1.19

Let S = {1, 2, 3, . . . }, and let A be the class of all subsets A of S such that either A
or Ac is finite. Then A is a field but not a σ-field. First, if A ∈ A, then Ac ∈ A because
the definition of A is symmetric with respect to complementation. Next, if A and B
are both in A, so is their union. If A and B are both finite, then A ∪ B is finite and
hence belongs to A. On the other hand, if either Ac or B c (or both) are finite, then
(A ∪ B)c = Ac ∩ B c is also finite because it is contained in Ac and also in B c .
Thus, A is a field. However, A is not a σ-field. Let An bethe set consisting only of

the element n (i.e., An = {n}). Clearly, An ∈ A. Take now n=1 A2n = {2, 4, 6, . . . }.
This is a countable union of sets in A that is not in A since the set of all even numbers
is not finite, nor does it have a finite complement.

Typically, it is easy to determine that a class of sets is a field, while direct verification that
it is a σ-field can be difficult. On the other hand, it is sometimes easy to verify that a class of
sets is a monotone class.

Theorem 1.4.2 A σ-field is a monotone class. Conversely, a field that is a monotone class is a
σ-field.

Proof : To prove this theorem, assume first that A is a σ-field, and let ∞A1 , A2 , . . . be a mono-
tone sequence of elements of A.  If A1 ⊂ A2 ⊂ · · · , then lim An = n=1 An ∈ A, whereas if

A1 ⊃ A2 ⊃ · · · , then lim An = n=1 An ∈ A. So A is a monotone class. On the other hand,
let A be a monotone class and a field, and let A1 , A2 , . . . be an arbitrary sequence of elements
of A. Put Bn = A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An . Then since A is a field, and also B1 ⊂ B2 ⊂ · · · , Bn∈ A for

∞n. Further, since A is a monotone class, lim Bn ∈ A. However, lim Bn = n=1 Bn
every
= n=1 An , so A is a σ-field, as asserted. 

The last in this series of concepts is that of the minimal field (or σ-field, or monotone
class) containing a given set or collection of sets. We begin with some examples.

EXAMPLE 1.20

Let S be any set. On one extreme, the class consisting of two sets, ∅ and S, is closed
under any operation so that A = {∅, S} is a field, a σ-field, and a monotone class. On
the other extreme, the class of all subsets of S is also closed under any operations, finite
or not, and hence is a field, a σ-field, and a monotone class. These two classes of subsets
of S form the smallest and the largest fields (σ-field, monotone class).

4 For various relations among classes of sets defined through closure properties under operations, for example, see

Chow and Teicher (1997) and Chung (2001).


INFINITE OPERATIONS ON EVENTS 17

For any event A, it is easy to check that the class A, consisting of the four events
{∅, A, Ac , S}, is closed under any operations: unions, intersections, and complements
of members of A are again members of A. This class is an example of a field (σ-field,
monotone class) that contains the events A and Ac , and it is the smallest such field
(σ-field, monotone class).
On the other hand, the class A, consisting of events {∅, A, S}, is a monotone
class, but neither a field nor σ-field. If A and B are two events, then the smallest field
A containing A and B must contain also the sets Ac , B c , the intersections A ∩ B,
A ∩ B c , Ac ∩ B, Ac ∩ B c , as well as their unions A ∪ B, A ∪ B c , Ac ∪ B, and Ac ∪ B c .
The closure property implies that unions such as (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∪ B c ), must also
belong to A.

We are now ready to present the final step.

Theorem 1.4.3 For any nonempty class K of subsets of S, there exists a unique smallest field
(σ-field, monotone class) containing all sets in K. It is called the field (σ-field, monotone class)
generated by K.

Proof : We will prove the assertion for fields. Observe first that if A1 and A2 are fields, then
their intersection A1 ∩ A2 (i.e., the class of sets that belong to both A1 and A2 ) is also a field.
For instance, if A, B ∈ Ai (i = 1, 2), then A ∪ B ∈ Ai because each Ai is a field, and conse-
quently A ∪ B ∈ A1 ∩ A2 . A similar argument holds for intersections and complements.
Note that if A1 and A2 contain the class K, then the intersection A1 ∩ A2 also contains
K. The property extends to any intersection of fields containing K (not only the intersections
of two such fields).
Now, let C be the intersection of all fields containing K. We claim that C is the minimal
unique field containing K. We have to show that (1) C exists, (2) C is a field containing K,
(3) C is unique, and (4) C is minimal.
For property (1) it is enough to show that there exists at least one field containing K. We
may take here the class of all subsets of S: it is a field (as well as a σ-field and monotone
class), and it contains all sets in K. Property (2) follows from the fact that the intersection of
fields containing K is a field containing K. Property (3) (i.e., uniqueness of C) follows from
the fact that the result of the operation of intersection is unique.
Finally, suppose that there exists a field C  containing K such that C  ⊂ C. Then C  must
appear as one of the factors in the intersection defining C so that C ⊂ C  . Consequently,
C  = C. This completes the proof for the case of fields. The proofs for σ-fields and monotone
classes are exactly the same, since an intersection of σ-fields (or monotone classes) containing
K is again a σ-field (monotone class) containing K. 

One may find it disturbing that Theorem 1.4.3 asserts the existence and uniqueness
of some objects without giving a clue as to how to practically find them. In fact, the
nonconstructive character of the theorem, combined with its generality, is instead a great
help. As we will see in Chapter 2, the natural objects of our interest (the domains of
definition of probability) will be σ-fields of events. Beyond the trivial situations of finite
or countably infinite sample spaces S, where one can always consider the maximal σ-field
consisting of all subsets of S, one is forced to restrict consideration to classes of events
that form σ-fields generated by some “simple” events. The events in these σ-fields are
typically of a very rich structure, and one seldom has useful criteria for distinguishing
events (elements of the σ-field in question) from “nonevents,” that is, subsets of S to which
probabilities are not assigned. However, as shown by the two examples below, the smallest
σ-field generated by some class is richer than the smallest field generated by the same
class.
18 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

EXAMPLE 1.21

A point moves randomly on the plane, and its location is recorded at some time t. The
outcome of this experiment is the pair (x, y) of coordinates of the observed location of
the point (e.g., imagine here the location of a particle of dust in a liquid, tossed about
by random hits from molecules of the medium, and performing Brownian motion;
or imagine a location of a previously marked bird at the time of its capture in a bird
migration study or the ages of both husband and wife at the time one of them dies).
In any study of this kind (regardless of its ultimate purpose), the “natural” sample
space S is a plane or part of the plane, (the positive quadrant, etc.). The “simple”
events here are of the form a < x ≤ b, c < x ≤ d, that is, rectangles with sides parallel
to the axes. The reason for distinguishing these events as “simple” is that, as will be
explained in later chapters, it is often easy to assign probabilities to these events. The
reason for the particular configuration of strict and nonstrict inequalities (i.e., north
and east side included, south and west side excluded) will also become apparent from
the analysis below. To simplify the language, we will call such events Rectangles,
and use a capital letter to signify the specific assumption about which sides are
included and which are not. Naturally, we will allow for infinite Rectangles, such as
{a < x ≤ ∞, −∞ < y ≤ b}.
It is easy to determine the field generated by all Rectangles: These are events that
result from finite operations on Rectangles. Clearly, the complement of a Rectangle
is a union of at most eight disjoint (infinite) Rectangles (see Figure 1.7), whereas the
intersection of Rectangles is again a Rectangle (or is empty). Since unions are reduced
to intersections of complements by De Morgan’s laws, every element of the smallest
field containing all Rectangles is the union of a finite number of disjoint Rectangles. On
the other hand, there exist events that do not belong to this field of events. As a simple
example, one might be interested in the event that the point (x, y) lies within distance
r from some fixed point (from the initial location of the particle, the point of release
of the bird, etc.). This event is a circle on the plane, and hence a subset of S, which is
not decomposable into a finite number of Rectangles. On the other hand, a circle does
belong to the σ-field spanned by Rectangles: it is representable as a countable union of
Rectangles, or equivalently, as an infinite intersection of sets built up of Rectangles.

B7 B6 B5

B8 A B4

B1 B2 B3

Figure 1.7 Complement of a Rectangle.

Similarly, in this example there are other events, which are not in the field generated
by Rectangles and which could be considered, such as triangles, rectangles with sides
not parallel to the axes, and ellipses.
PROBLEMS 19

EXAMPLE 1.22

Take an experiment consisting of tossing a coin infinitely many times. The “natural”
sample space S is the space of all infinite sequences x = (ξ1 , ξ2 , . . . ), where ξi = 0
or 1 (or any other two distinct symbols representing heads and tails). The “simple”
events here are of the form “heads on the nth toss,” that is, sets of all infinite sequences
x = (ξ1 , ξ2 , . . . ) with the nth coordinate ξn satisfying ξn = 0. The events in the field
generated by the simple events are of the form “heads on tosses k1 , . . . , kn and tails
on tosses r1 , . . . , rm ,” with both m and n finite and the outcomes of all other tosses
remaining unspecified.
An event that does not belong to this field, but does belong to the σ-field generated
by the simple events, is the event that “as the number of tosses increases, the frequency
of heads approaches a limit.” Clearly, to determine whether or not this event occurs, it
does not suffice to know any finite number of coordinates ξn .
To generalize this example, replace the outcome of the coin tosses by the result
of some experiment repeated infinitely many times. This way the coordinate ξn
carries more information than it does for the outcome of nth coin toss. The “simple”
events are now of the form of sets of sequences x = (ξ1 , ξ1 , . . . ) with ξi ∈ Ai for
i = 1, . . . , n, while the ξi ’s for i > n are unconstrained. Here A1 , . . . , An are events
that occur at the first n times of observations. The “simple” events described above,
of an obvious interest and importance both in applications and in building the
theory, are called “cylinder” events. The smallest σ-field containing all cylinder events
comprises all events that may be of interest, including those that are obtained through
limits of sequences of cylinder events.

PROBLEMS

Let B1 , B2 , . . . be a countable partition of S; that is, Bi ∩ Bj = ∅ for all i = j, and


1.4.1 
i Bi = S. Let An = Bn ∪ Bn+1 ∪ · · ·. Find lim An .

1.4.2 Assume that John will live forever. He plays a certain game each day. Let Ai be the
event that he wins the game on the ith day. (i) Let B be the event that John will win
every game starting on January 1, 2035. Label the following statements as true or false:
(a) B = lim inf An . (b) B ⊂ lim inf An . (c) B ⊃ lim sup An . (d) B = lim sup An .
(ii) Assume now that John starts playing on a Monday. Match the following events
C1 through C9 with events D1 through D11 :
C1 = John loses infinitely many games.
C2 = When John loses on a Thursday, he wins on the following Sunday.
C3 = John never wins on three consecutive days.
C4 = John wins every Wednesday.
C5 = John wins on infinitely many Wednesdays.
C6 = John wins on a Wednesday.
C7 = John never wins on a weekend.
C8 = John wins infinitely many games and loses infinitely many games.
C9 = If John wins on some day, he never loses on the next day.
∞ ∞
D1 = j=0 [A7j+4 ∪ A7(j+1) ], D2 = j=0 A7j+3 ,
∞ ∞ ∞
D3 = j=0 [Ac7j+6 ∩ Ac7(j+1) ], D4 = n=1 k=n Ack ,
∞ ∞ ∞
D5 = i=1 [Aci ∪ Aci+1 ∪ Aci+2 ], D6 = n=1 k=n A7k+3 ,
 c ∞

D7 = j=0 [A7j+6 ∪ A7(j+1) ] , D8 = j=0 A7j+3 ,
20 EXPERIMENTS, SAMPLE SPACES, AND EVENTS

∞  n ∞  ∞ c
n=0 [ i=1 Ai ] ∩ i=0 [Ai ∩ Ai+1 ∩ Ai+2 ] ,
c
D9 = k=n+1 Ak , D10 =
∞ ∞  
∞ ∞
D11 = [ n=1 k=n Ack ] ∩ j=1 m=j Am .

1.4.3 Let A1 , . . . , An be distinct subsets of S. (i) Find the maximum number of sets (includ-
ing S and ∅) of the smallest field containing A1 , . . . , An . (ii) Find the maximum
number of sets in this field if An−1 ⊂ An . (iii) Answer (ii) if A1 ⊂ A2 ⊂ · · · ⊂ An .
(iv) Answer (ii) if A1 = · · · = An = ∅. (v) Answer (i)–(iv) for a σ-field.
1.4.4 For 0 < α < 1, let I(α) = {x : 1 − α < x < 1 + α}. Consider a sequence α1 , α2 , . . .
of numbers satisfying 0 < αn < 1 for all n, and let An = I(αn ). (i) Find lim sup An
and lim inf An . (ii) Find conditions, expressed in terms of αn , under which
lim An exists, and find this limit. (iii) Define J(α) = {x : 1 − α ≤ x ≤ 1 + α} and
Bn = J(αn ). Answer questions (i) and (ii) for sequence {Bn }.
1.4.5 Let S = {0, 1, 2, . . . } be the set of all integers. For A ⊂ S, let fn (A) be the number of
elements in the intersection A ∩ {0, 1, . . . , n}. Let A be the class of all sets A for which
the limit
f (A)
q(A) = lim n
n→∞ n
exists. Show that A is not a field. [Hint: Let A1 = {1, 3, 5, . . . } and A2 ={ all odd
integers between 22n and 22n+1 and all even integers between 22n+1 and 22n+2 for
n = 0, 1, . . . }. Show that both A1 and A2 are in A but A1 ∩ A2 ∈ / A.]
1.4.6 Let S = (−∞, +∞). Show that the class of all finite unions of intervals of the form
[a, b], (a, b), [a, b), and (a, b], with possibly infinite a or b (intervals of the form [a, ∞),
etc.) forms a field.
CHAPTER 2

PROBABILITY

2.1 INTRODUCTION

The concept of probability has been an object of debate among philosophers, logicians,
mathematicians, statisticians, physicists, and psychologists for the last couple of centuries,
and this debate is not likely to be over in the foreseeable future. As advocated by Bertrand
Russell in his essay on skepticism, when experts disagree, the layman would do best by
refraining from forming a strong opinion. Accordingly, we will not enter into the discus-
sion about the nature of probability; rather, we will start from the issues and principles that
are commonly agreed upon.
Probability is a number associated with an event that is intended to represent its
“likelihood,” “chance of occurring,” “degree of certainty,” and so on. Probabilities can
be obtained in several ways, the most common being (1) the frequency (or objective)
interpretation, (2) the classical (sometimes called logical) interpretation, and (3) the
subjective or personal interpretation of probability.

2.2 PROBABILITY AS A FREQUENCY

According to the common interpretation, probability is the “long-run” relative frequency of


an event. The idea connecting probability and frequency is (and had been for a long time)
very well grounded in everyday intuition. For instance, loaded dice were on several occasions
found in the graves of ancient Romans. That indicates that they were aware of the possibility
of modifying long-run frequencies of outcomes, and perhaps making some profit in such
a way.
Today, the intuition regarding relationship between probabilities and frequencies is even
more firmly established. For instance, the phrases “there is 3% chance that an orange picked

Probability and Statistical Inference, Third Edition. Magdalena Niewiadomska-Bugaj and Robert Bartoszyński.
© 2021 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Published 2021 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc.

21
22 PROBABILITY

at random from this shipment will be rotten” and “the fraction of rotten oranges in this
shipment is a 3%” appear almost synonymous. But on closer reflection, one realizes that the
first phrase refers to the probability of an event “randomly selected orange will be rotten,”
while the second phrase refers to the population of oranges.
The precise nature of the relation between probability and frequency is hard to formu-
late. But the usual explanation is as follows: Consider an experiment that can be repeated
under identical conditions, potentially an infinite number of times. In each of these repeti-
tions, some event, say A, may occur or not. Let N (A) be the number of occurrences of A in
the first N repetitions. The frequency principle states that the ratio N (A)/N approximates
the probability P (A) of event A, with the accuracy of the approximation increasing as N
increases.
Let us observe that this principle serves as a basis for estimating probabilities of various
events in the real world, especially those probabilities that might not be attainable by any
other means (e.g., the probability of heads in tossing a biased coin).
We start this chapter by putting a formal framework (axiom system) on a probability
regarded as a function on the class of all events. That is, we impose some general conditions
on a set of individual probabilities. This axiom system, due to Kolmogorov (1933), will be
followed by the derivation of some of its immediate consequences. The latter will allow us
to compute probabilities of some composite events given the probabilities of some other
(“simpler”) events.

2.3 AXIOMS OF PROBABILITY

Let S be the sample space, namely the set of all outcomes of an experiment. Formally, prob-
ability, to be denoted by P , is a function defined on the class of all events,1 satisfying the
following conditions (usually referred to as axioms):
Axiom 1 (Nonnegativity):
P (A) ≥ 0 for every event A.
Axiom 2 (Norming):
P (S) = 1.
Axiom 3 (Countable Additivity):


P (A1 ∪ A2 ∪ · · · ) = P (Ai )
i=1

for every sequence of pairwise disjoint events A1 , A2 , . . . , (such that Ai ∩ Aj = ∅


for all i = j). 
If the sample space S is finite or countable, one can define a probability function
 P as fol-
lows: Let f be a nonnegative function defined on S, satisfying the condition s∈S f (s) = 1.
Then, P may be defined for every subset A of S as P (A) = s∈A f (s). One can easily check
that P satisfies all three axioms. 
Indeed, P (A) ≥ 0 because f is nonnegative, and P (S) = s∈S f (s) = 1. Finally, let
A1 , A2 , . . . be a sequence of disjoint subsets of S. Then,
 
P (A1 ) + P (A2 ) + · · · = f (s) + f (s) + · · ·
s∈A1 s∈A2
∞ 
 
= f (s) = P Ai .
s∈A1 ∪A2 ∪··· i=1

1 The nature of the class of all events will be (to a certain extent) explicated in Section 2.6. See also Section 1.4.
AXIOMS OF PROBABILITY 23

Passing from the first to the second line is allowed because A1 , A2 , . . . are disjoint, so each
term appears only once. The sum in the second line is well defined (i.e., it does not depend
on the order of summation because the terms are nonnegative).
 if S is not countable, one usually needs to replace summation by integration,
However,
P (A) = A f (s) ds. This imposes some conditions on functions f and on the class of events
A. For a detailed discussion, the reader is referred to more advanced probability texts (e.g.,
Chung, 2001).

EXAMPLE 2.1 Geometric Probability

One of the first examples of an uncountable sample space is associated with “the ran-
dom choice of a point from a set.” This phrase is usually taken to mean the following:
a point is selected at random from a certain set S in a finite-dimensional space (line,
plane, etc.), where S has finite measure (length, area, etc.), denoted generally by |S|.
The choice is such that if A (A ⊂ S) has measure |A|, then the probability of the chosen
point falling into A is proportional to |A|. Identifying S with the sample space, we can
then write P (A) = |A|/|S|.
To better see this, suppose that in shooting at a circular target S, one is certain to
score a hit, and that the point where one hits S is assumed to be chosen at random in
the way described above. What is the probability that the point of hit is farther from
the center than half of the radius of the target?
From Figure 2.1, it is clear that the point of hit must lie somewhere in the shaded
annulus A. Its area is |A| = πR2 − π(R/2)2 so that P (A) = |A|/πR2 = 3/4. Of course,
the assumption under which this solution is obtained is not very realistic: typically sets
closer to the center are more likely to be hit than sets of the same area located closer
to the perimeter.

R/2 R

Figure 2.1 Hitting a target.

The concept of “random choice” from an uncountable set is sometimes ambiguous. This
is illustrated by the next example.

EXAMPLE 2.2 Bertrand’s Paradox

A chord is chosen at random in a circle. What is the probability that the length of the
chord will exceed the length of the side of an equilateral triangle inscribed in the circle?
24 PROBABILITY

This problem was originally posed in 1888 by Joseph Bertrand, a French mathe-
matician, who provided three solutions, all valid, but yielding inconsistent results.

SOLUTION 1. The chord is uniquely determined by the angle α (see Figure 2.2).
These angles are chosen at random from the interval (0, π). It is clear that the length
of the chord exceeds the side of the equilateral triangle if α lies between π/3 and 2π/3,
so the answer to the question is 1/3.

Figure 2.2 First solution of Bertrand’s problem.

SOLUTION 2. Let us draw a diameter QQ (see Figure 2.3) perpendicular to the
chord P . Then, the length of the chord exceeds the side of the equilateral triangle
if it intersects the line QQ between points B and B  . Elementary calculations give
|BB  | = |QQ |/2, so the answer is 1/2.

Figure 2.3 Second solution of Bertrand’s problem.

SOLUTION 3. The location of the chord is uniquely determined by the location of


its center (except when the center coincides with the center of the circle, which is an
event with probability zero). For the chord to be longer than the side of the equilateral
triangle inscribed in the circle, its center must fall somewhere inside the shaded circle
in Figure 2.4. Again, by elementary calculations, we obtain probability 1/4.
AXIOMS OF PROBABILITY 25

Figure 2.4 Third solution of Bertrand’s problem.

The discovery of Bertrand’s paradox was one of the impulses that made researchers in
probability and statistics acutely aware of the need to clarify the foundations of the theory,
and ultimately led to the publication of Kolmogorov’s book (1933). In the particular instance
of the Bertrand “paradoxes,” they are explained simply by the fact that each of the solutions
refers to a different sampling scheme: (1) choosing a point on the circumference and then
choosing the angle between the chord and the tangent at the point selected, (2) choosing
a diameter perpendicular to the chord and then selecting the point of intersection of the
chord with this diameter, and (3) choosing a center of the chord. Random choice according
to one of these schemes is not equivalent to a random choice according to the other two
schemes.
To see why it is so, we will show that the first and second scheme are not equivalent. The
analogous arguments for the other two possible pairs of schemes are left as an exercise.

EXAMPLE 2.3

Imagine different devices (physical mechanisms, computer programs, etc.) built for
sampling random chords. One scheme chooses a point on the circumference, and
then the angle α between the chord and the tangent to the circle at the point chosen
(Figure 2.2). The second scheme chooses first the direction of the diameter and
then the point B on the diameter, at which the chord perpendicular to this diameter
intersects it (Figure 2.3). From Figure 2.5, it is seen that the angle AOB is α, and

0
α y = cosα
1
B C
α
A

Figure 2.5 Explanation of Bertrand’s paradox.


26 PROBABILITY

therefore y = |OB| = cos α. Thus, dy = (sin α) dα, which means that equal changes
of α do not produce equal changes of y. In fact, these changes are smaller when α is
small. Consequently, a device that chooses angles α at random will tend to produce
more intersections of the diameter that are farther from the center (i.e., more chords
will be shorter).

PROBLEMS

2.3.1 Label all statements below as true or false. (i) If A is more likely to occur than
Ac , then P (A) > 0.5. (ii) If A occurs whenever B does, then P (B) ≤ P (A).
(iii) If P (A) ≤ P (B), then whenever B occurs, A does also. (iv) If P (A) = 0.75, then
A must occur three times out of every four. (v) The sum of probabilities of disjoint
events A and B cannot exceed 1. (vi) If A and B are not disjoint, the sum of their prob-
abilities exceeds 1. (vii) If P (A ∩ B), P (A ∩ C), and P (B ∩ C) are all positive, then
P (A ∩ B ∩ C) is also positive. (viii) If sample spaces for two experiments are identical,
then the probability of the same event A must be the same for both experiments.
2.3.2 A bathroom floor is covered by square tiles with side length a. You drop a coin with
diameter b, where b < a. Find: (i) The probability that the coin will rest entirely within
one tile. (ii) The probability that the coin will partially cover four different tiles.
2.3.3 Show that first and third, as well as second and third, schemes of sampling chords (see
Bertrand’s paradox) are not equivalent.

2.4 CONSEQUENCES OF THE AXIOMS

The simplest consequences of the axioms of probability are as follows:

1. The probability of the impossible event is zero:

P (∅) = 0. (2.1)

This follows from the fact 1 = P (S) = P (S ∪ ∅ ∪ ∅ ∪ · · · ) = P (S) + P (∅) + P (∅) +


· · · , which is possible only if P (∅) = 0. It is important to realize that the converse is not
true: the condition P (A) = 0 does not imply that A = ∅. This is shown by the following
example:

EXAMPLE 2.4

Consider an experiment consisting of tossing a coin infinitely many times. The out-
comes may be represented as infinite sequences of the form HHTHTTHT . . . so that
the sample space S contains infinitely many of such sequences. The event “heads
only,” that is, the set consisting of just one sequence HHHH . . . , is not empty.
However, the chance of such an outcome is, at least intuitively, zero: tails should
come up sooner or later.

2. Probability is finitely additive:

P (A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An ) = P (A1 ) + · · · + (An )

for any n = 1, 2, . . . , if the events Ai are pairwise disjoint.


CONSEQUENCES OF THE AXIOMS 27

In an infinite sequence A1 , . . . , An , ∅, ∅, . . . , events are pairwise disjoint only if


A1 , . . . , An are, so Axiom 3 applies. Therefore, using (2.1), we have
P (A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An ∪ ∅ ∪ · · · ) = P (A1 ) + · · · + P (An ) + P (∅) + · · ·
= P (A1 ) + · · · + P (An ),
while the left-hand side is P (A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An ).
3. Monotonicity: If A ⊂ B then P (A) ≤ P (B). This follows from the fact that
B = A ∪ (B ∩ Ac ). The events on the right-hand side are disjoint, so we have
P (B) = P (A) + P (B ∩ Ac ) ≥ P (A) by Axiom 1. Since A ⊂ S for every event A, we
have 0 ≤ P (A) ≤ 1.
4. Probability is countably subadditive:
∞ 

P An ≤ P (A1 ) + P (A2 ) + · · · , (2.2)
n=1

for every sequence of events A1 , A2 , . . . . This follows from representation (1.6) as a union
of disjoint events, and then from monotonicity. We have
∞ 

P An = P (A1 ) + P (Ac1 ∩ A2 ) + P (Ac1 ∩ Ac2 ∩ A3 ) + · · ·
n=1

≤ P (A1 ) + P (A2 ) + P (A3 ) + · · · .


5. Complementation:
P (Ac ) = 1 − P (A). (2.3)
This follows from Axiom 2, by the fact that A and Ac are disjoint and A ∪ Ac = S.
6. Probability of a union of events:
P (A ∪ B) = P (A) + P (B) − P (A ∩ B). (2.4)
Indeed, since A ∪ B = A ∪ (Ac ∩ B), then P (A ∪ B) = P (A) + P (Ac ∩ B). On the
other hand, B = (A ∩ B) ∪ (Ac ∩ B), and hence, P (B) = P (A ∩ B) + P (Ac ∩ B).
Solving for P (Ac ∩ B) in one equation and substituting into the other, we obtain (2.4).
A more intuitive argument may be made by using Venn diagrams (see Figure 2.6). In the
sum P (A) + P (B), each sample point from the intersection A ∩ B is included twice, so to
obtain the probability of the union A ∪ B, we must subtract the probability P (A ∩ B).

A
B

Figure 2.6 Union of two events.


EXAMPLE 2.5

Suppose that P (A) = 0.4, P (B c ) = 0.6, P (Ac ∩ B) = 0.1. Find P (A ∪ B c ).

SOLUTION. The best strategy for solving this kind of problem is finding the
probabilities of all the intersections (in this case, A ∩ B, A ∩ B c , Ac ∩ B, Ac ∩ B c ).
28 PROBABILITY

The probability P (Ac ∩ B) = 0.1 is given. Next, (A ∩ B) ∪ (Ac ∩ B) = B, and the


events on the left are disjoint. So P (A ∩ B) + P (Ac ∩ B) = P (B) = 1 − P (B c ),
which means that P (A ∩ B) + 0.1 = 1 − 0.6, and hence, P (A ∩ B) = 0.3. Then, using
A = (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ B c ), we have 0.4 = P (A) = P (A ∩ B) + P (A ∩ B c ) = 0.3 +
P (A ∩ B c ); hence, P (A ∩ B c ) = 0.1. similarly P (Ac ∩ B c ) = 0.5. Applying formula
(2.3), we have P (A ∪ B c ) = P (A) + P (B c ) − P (A ∩ B c ) = 0.4 + 0.6 − 0.1 = 0.9.
For the case of three events: A, B, and C, the same argument based on Venn dia-
grams gives the formula
P (A ∪ B ∪ C) = P (A) + P (B) + P (C)
−P (A ∩ B) − P (A ∩ C) − P (B ∩ C)
+P (A ∩ B ∩ C). (2.5)
It can be checked at Figure 2.7 that the formula (2.5) includes each part of the union
A ∪ B ∪ C exactly once.

Figure 2.7 Union of three events.

Formula (2.5) may be generalized to the case of the union of any finite number of events.

Theorem 2.4.1 For any events A1 , . . . , An



n 
P (A1 ∪ · · · ∪ An ) = P (Ai ) − P (Ai1 ∩ Ai2 )
i=1 1≤i1 <i2 ≤n

+ P (Ai1 ∩ Ai2 ∩ Ai3 ) + · · ·
1≤i1 <i2 <i3 ≤n

+ (−1)n+1 P (A1 ∩ · · · ∩ An ). (2.6)

Proof : We will proceed by induction. The theorem is true for n = 1. Assume now that for-
mula (2.6) holds, and write
n+1  n   
  n
P Ai = P Ai + P An+1 \ Ai .
1 1 1

Since    

n 
n
P (An+1 ) = P An+1 ∩ Ai +P An+1 \ Ai ,
1 1
CONSEQUENCES OF THE AXIOMS 29

we have n+1    
 
n 
n
P Ai =P Ai + P (An+1 ) − P (Ai ∩ An+1 ) .
1 1 1

n n
Applying formula (2.6) to P ( 1 Ai ) and to P 1 (Ai ∩ An+1 ) , and then combining the
corresponding terms, we obtain (2.6) with n replaced by n + 1. 

PROBLEMS

2.4.1 Let events A, B, and C be such that A contains B and is disjoint from C. Moreover,
A is twice as likely as B, three times as likely as C, and half as likely as its complement
Ac . Find P (B ∪ C).
2.4.2 Events A, B, and C are such that A ∩ B = A ∩ C = ∅ while B ∩ C is not
empty. Determine P (A ∪ B ∪ C) as a function of x if P (A) = P (B) = P (C) =
3P (B ∩ C) = x.
2.4.3 Find P (A ∪ B c ) for events A and B such that P (A) = P (B) = 1/2, and
P (Ac ∩ B c ) = 1/3.
2.4.4 To make the formula P [(Ac ∩ B c )c ] = 2 − P (Ac ) − P (B c ) − x valid, x must equal:
(1) P (A ∪ B). (2) P (A ∩ B). (3) P (Ac ∪ B c ). (4) None of the above.
2.4.5 Three events A, B, and C are such that C is contained in the intersection
Ac ∩ B, P (A) = 0.6, P (A ∩ B) = 0.3, and P (C) = P (Ac ∩ B c ) = 0.1. Find: (i)
P (B). (ii) The probability that exactly two of the events A, B, C will occur. (iii) The
probability that exactly one of the events A, B, C will occur.
2.4.6 Let A, B, C, D, and E be five events such that P (A) = P (B) = · · · = P (E) = k and
P (A ∩ B) = P (A ∩ C) = · · · = P (D ∩ E) = p. Moreover, at least one of the events
A, . . . , E must occur, and the intersection of any three events among A, B, . . . , E is
empty. (i) Find p if k = 0.3. (ii) Omit the assumption that at least one of the events
must occur and determine all possible values of k if it is known that p = 0.01.
2.4.7 If events A1 , . . . A101 are such that P (A1 ) = · · · = P (A101 ) = 0.01, P (A1 ∩ A2 ) =
P (A1 ∩ A3 ) = · · · = P (A100 ∩ A101 ) = r, while every triple intersection is empty,
find the smallest possible value of the probability of intersection r.
2.4.8 Before the era of cell phones (a time that most of today’s students do not remember),
people often used public phones that operated after a coin was inserted. These phones
were sometimes faulty and either took a coin without giving a connection or gave
the connection but also returned the coin. (i) A faulty public phone returns the coin
with probability 60%, it gives you the number you dial with probability 20%, and
it takes your coin and does not give you the required connection with probability
30%. Find the probability that you will talk with the number you dial for free. (ii) A
certain public phone is such that it returns the coin with probability a, connects you
with the number you dial with probability b, and it gives you the connection for free
with probability c. Let us agree to say that the phone is individually honest if it takes
your money if and only if it provides you with the required connection, and that it is
socially honest if it takes, on average, as many coins as it gives correct connections (but
perhaps from different customers). Find conditions for a, b, and c under which the
phone is individually honest. (iii) Find conditions under which the phone is socially
honest.
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
nearly the whole ocean assumed the appearance and agitation of boiling
water.

Throughout our passage, we remarked, that whenever the wind hauled to


the southward of southeast, it increased in force. It occurred so frequently as
to be a subject of general remark.

On the 20th of September, in latitude seven degrees fifty minutes south,


and longitude one hundred and twenty degrees thirty minutes west, we saw a
comet for the first time, thirty or forty degrees above the horizon, and
bearing from us east by north. At day-light, on the morning of September
26th, several of the southernmost of the Marqueses were in sight. They were
all mountainous, but covered with vegetation, and as we drew near presented
a pleasing contrast to the sterile and gloomy Gallapagos. We stood along the
shore of La Dominica, admiring the beautiful little valleys that were
presented to our view in quick succession, where villages of palm-thatched
huts, surrounded by clumps of tall cocoa-nut and wide-spreading bread fruit
trees, formed scenes of rural quiet calculated to fill the imagination with the
most agreeable conceptions of the happy condition of their inhabitants. At
length we came to a small bay where the valley was more populous than any
we had seen before, and the captain, to our great satisfaction, hauled up for it
and stood close in towards the island. We lowered a boat, and providing
ourselves with a few trifles for presents, pulled into the bay within a few
yards of the shore. The beach was already thronged with people of all ages,
male and female, who invited us to land by the most significant gestures,
whilst many of them were singing and dancing to express their joy. The
surrounding rocks and hills were covered with groups of females, gaily
decked off with their neat head-dresses of the white Tapa cloth and many-
coloured robes, which were floating in the wind, half concealing and half
exposing their fantastically painted limbs. When they saw that we would not
land, the men and boys dashed into the water with whatever they had to offer
us, and swam off to the boat. A chief, who had a dry wreath of cocoa-nut
around his brows, came off with them; and, upon being invited, got into the
boat, where he remained until our departure, apparently giving orders from
time to time to those who were passing and repassing from the shore to the
boat. In a few minutes, they had presented us with a considerable quantity of
cocoa-nuts, bananas, and papayas, for which we gave them in return a few
trifling articles, the most valuable of which were glass beads. The chief had
his eyes constantly fixed upon our fire-arms, and finally gave us to
understand, by motions, that a pistol would be acceptable to him. With this
intimation we could not comply; but he bore the refusal with great good
nature, and for some time after our store of little presents was exhausted, his
people continued to bring us off fruit without the expectation of any return.
When they found that we were serious in our refusal to land, the women
came from the hills and assembled on the rocks close to us, where, in a
nearer view, they could display their persons to more advantage, and charm
us with the melody of their voices. There they all joined in songs, keeping
time by clapping their hands, stopping occasionally to receive the applause
of the men and to invite us on shore. Several of them, male and female,
swam off to the boat; and when we were about to depart, insisted so strongly
upon going on board with us that we had to use some violence to get clear of
them.

We continued on in the afternoon, soon passing La Dominica, and at


sundown made Rooahooga ahead. The weather being squally and the island
only fifteen miles from us, we lay by for the night. At daylight, we found
ourselves a few miles distant from the middle of the south side of the island,
where a bay presented itself, which, at a distance, promised to afford
anchorage. On a nearer approach, however, its appearance changed, and as
there were but few signs of inhabitants, we ran along toward the west end of
the island. This part of it had not much appearance of fertility, although we
saw a few large trees. It is high, broken, and indented with a number of small
bays, none of which are large enough to form a harbour. In rounding the
southwest point of the island we had sudden and violent gusts of wind.
Invisible Bay is situated a little to the westward of this point, and although it
has somewhat the appearance of a harbour, and presents to view a beautiful
sand beach, we saw no indications of inhabitants. About ten miles to the
north, we anchored in twenty fathoms water, having rocky bottom, and an
inaccessible rocky shore where the surf breaks violently. The captain and
several officers went back to Invisible Bay in one of the boats, and in a cave
close to the shore they found five or six natives, who at their approach, fled
to the hills, making signs for our people to depart. In the cave, they found a
few fishing-nets. They tried to prevail upon the natives to come near, but
their demonstrations of friendship were answered only by motions
expressive of hostility. The landing was difficult, as the shore was rocky, and
a considerable surf broke upon it, although the bay was tolerably protected
by a projecting point. Soon after meridian, we got under way and shaped our
course for Nooaheeva, which was plainly in sight from Rooahooga. We
stood along, with a fine breeze and clear weather, and at three, P.M., rounded
the north-eastern extremity of Nooaheeva, when a spacious harbour, called
Comptroller's Bay, opened to our view. It is about three miles deep, and at its
inner extremity are two projecting points that extend out for more than a
mile, and form three small harbours. We were no sooner observed by the
natives on shore, than they put off in a number of large canoes and pulled
with great rapidity towards us. The wind was light and baffling, and we
advanced slowly into the harbour. In a few minutes, we were surrounded by
canoes, containing from six to eight men each. They belonged to different
tribes, which they attempted to explain to us with great earnestness of speech
and gesture, but as we had no one on board who knew much of the language,
we were greatly at a loss to comprehend their meaning. They had not
followed us long when two of the canoes came along side, one on each
quarter, and the men crawled up the side and perched themselves upon the
hammocks, like so many monkeys, where they called out in a loud voice,
addressing themselves alternately to us and to the natives on the side of the
vessel opposite to them,—one party exclaiming "Mattee, mattee, Typee!"
and the other "Mattee, mattee,[4] Happah!" and occasionally using angry
gestures with the exclamation. This was too expressive for us not to
understand. They belonged to different tribes, the Typee, and Happah; and
were mutually trying to prejudice us against the tribe to which they did not
belong, in order to induce us to anchor in their own bay. Both the bays were
beautiful, but as the Happahs' was the most populous and nearest to us, we
gave it the preference; and a little before sunset anchored in twenty fathoms
water within a cable's length of the shore. The Typees no sooner saw that we
were standing in for the Happah Bay, than they hurried into their canoe and
paddled off for their village as fast as they could. The Happah valley was a
romantic spot. A plain, a league or two in circumference, stretched back to
the mountains in a semicircular form, presenting in front a clear white sand
beach about a mile long. The plain was covered with cocoa-nuts, with bread-
fruit interspersed, and near enough to form a continued shade without
presenting the appearance of a dense forest. Scattered about every where
through these trees were the palm-thatched habitations of the natives. In the
rear of the plain, the mountains rose precipitously, forming an insuperable
barrier against the incursions of other tribes. The land rose gently to the left,
but it was almost barren and added nothing to the beauty of the landscape.
On the extreme right, a considerable mountain and a point projecting far out
into the bay, separated the Happahs from the tribes that lived beyond them in
that direction. Nothing could equal the apparent joy of the natives when they
saw us anchored in front of their village. The whole tribe, which probably
did not exceed five hundred, flocked down to the beach, expressing their
satisfaction by dancing and singing. Hundreds of them dashed into the water
and swam off to us, so that we had not time to furl sails and clear the deck
before the vessel was crowded with people. To show them that we had the
means of making successful resistance against any hostile intention they
might adopt, we paraded our musketeers upon the deck and practised them, a
ceremony that appeared to afford the natives very great amusement. We
allowed them to remain on board until the dusk of evening, when the number
being so great as to make the vessel uncomfortable, and apprehending that in
the course of the night they might appropriate to themselves many things
that they would find about the deck, and which could not conveniently be
spared, we sent most of them on shore. The chiefs and a few others who
expressed a great desire to remain, were permitted to pass the night with us.

On the following day, I took a few presents with me and went over to the
Typee valley, to visit that tribe, celebrated as the most warlike of Nooaheeva.
As soon as the boat was perceived, the people came running towards the
beach in every direction, and before she reached the shore we were
surrounded by great numbers, who plunged into the water and swam off to
us. As many as we could conveniently accommodate were permitted to get
into the boat, where they treated me so unceremoniously that I did not think
it prudent to land. Amongst those who paid me a visit was a chief of the
tribe. He was a man about thirty years of age, well-featured and of fine
proportions. His deportment was grave and dignified, but like the rest of our
new acquaintances, who swam off to us, he was quite naked except a slight
covering about his loins. The common people treated him with great
deference, and never intruded upon that part of the boat where he was
seated. He made us understand that he wished to obtain muskets and powder,
for the purchase of which he had caused five or six large hogs to be brought
down, that were tied and laying on the shore. I offered him whatever else I
had that I thought would induce him to part with them; but he obstinately
refused any other consideration than muskets and powder. Large quantities
of cocoa-nuts, bananas, and papayas were thrown into the boat by the people
who were swimming around us, and when we had been lying there an hour,
we had as many in the boat as we could conveniently carry. I had a variety of
presents, such as beads, buttons, &c., all of which the common people were
very anxious to obtain; but the chief would take nothing from me of less
consequence than fire-arms or gunpowder. I offered him flints and musket
balls, which, although of great value amongst the natives, he would not
receive. He invited me frequently, with great earnestness of manner, to land,
until he found, by my repeated refusals, that I was determined to remain in
my boat.

The bay of the Typees was rather smaller than that of the Happah tribe.
They live principally upon the side of a mountain that rises gently from the
shore. The number of the tribe appeared to be about the same as that of the
Happahs. Their houses are situated in circular chains of villages, rising one
above the other, from the base to near the top of the mountain, where it
terminates in rude and uninhabitable cliffs. Groves and clumps of cocoa-nut,
and bread-fruit trees are every where interspersed with the dwellings, and the
mind of the observer being impressed with the idea of their usefulness to the
natives, gives a double effect to the beautiful landscape adorned by their
waving tops and broad green leaves. We had several occasions to remark the
inveterate dislike that the Typees and Happahs entertained towards each
other.

On the morning after our arrival, the sailing-master went on shore in the
Happah valley to obtain an altitude of the sun by the artificial horizon He
was shy of the natives, as we all were at first, and apprehending that some of
them might approach him with a hostile intention, while his back was turned
towards them, and having heard that they held in great reverence a place said
to be Tabooed, or consecrated, he made a circle round his place observation,
and told the natives, who had followed him in great numbers, that the space
within the circle was Tabooed. They stared at him in silence and stood back
from it; but by and by, when he was intently engaged in getting his altitude,
one of the natives, supposing that he was employed in some plan (to him
incomprehensible) to destroy the Typees, as he turned the face of his sextant
in that direction, crawled up gently behind the sailing-master, without being
perceived by him, and suddenly tapping him two or three times on the
shoulder, exclaimed with great energy, "Mattee, mattee, Typee!" It may
readily be supposed that his imagination, which was very much excited
before, was not soothed by this salutation. He turned upon the native,
expressing in look and manner his consternation and displeasure, which was
only met by the delighted Indian with a repetition of "Mattee, mattee,
Typee!"

On the morning of the 25th, I went on shore, in company with several of


the officers, to indulge our curiosity and ramble about the valley. We were
soon surrounded by a group of natives, who followed us wherever we went.
Our first object was to visit the chief of the valley, whose residence we
found at the distance of two or three hundred yards from the shore. It was a
plain, oblong hut, thirty by twenty feet. Its simple structure was such as is
first suggested to the untutored mind—a few poles laid over crotches, upon
which was framed a triangular roof, and the whole thatched with palm or
cocoa-nut leaves. When we entered this regal hut we found the chief seated
near one end of it, who barely condescended to notice us as we approached
to make our salutations. We were not prepared for so rude a reception and
felt somewhat mortified to find a chief of his distinguished rank so totally
destitute of courtesy. We thought at least that he would have risen from his
sitting posture, and expected more from him than our after experience taught
us we had a right to look for from people in a state of nature. The only
furniture in the hut was a few coarse mats. At one side of it five muskets,
highly polished, were arranged one above the other, over which hung two
kegs of powder sewed up in canvass, and near them a few long spears and a
war conch, ornamented with human hair. We made ourselves as much at
home as if we had received a more cordial welcome, and indulged our
curiosity in examining whatever we saw, when suddenly the chief rose and
his silence and gravity were at once explained. We had remarked that he had
an uncommonly large black robe thrown over him, but without the least
suspicion that it covered any one else than himself. He suddenly threw it
aside as we came near him and there stood his wife, a girl about eighteen
years of age, who had just finished making her toilet. He pointed to her with
a look of satisfaction, and uttered "Motake," a word we afterwards learned,
signified very good, or very well. Although she was naturally a pretty girl,
she had made herself a hideous looking object. She had smeared her face all
over with a coarse yellow paint, upon which was drawn streaks of black and
green, than which nothing could have appeared more disgusting. She
assumed a manner and look of affectation, such as may often have been
observed in some self-approving beauty, who, conscious of her charms, feels
that she is an object of admiration to all around her. When I expressed my
disapprobation of her style of ornament, she stared at me with a look of
surprise, which seemed to ask what I was saying. I soon gave both her and
the chief to understand, by signs; after which they seemed not so well
pleased with themselves or each other; and when I saw her again in the
evening she was without any ornament, and looked all the better for it.
While here, two grotesque figures came in and walked up to me with an
austere look. They had a profusion of cock's feathers bound circularly round
their brows, broad gorgets of wood ornamented with red berries round their
necks, shell bracelets and ornaments of polished shell or bone tied above
their ancles. Each held in his hand a fan of palmetto. After standing a few
moments, keeping their eyes fixed upon me, they began jumping up and
down and fanning themselves, applying both hands to the fan. My first
feeling was surprise, mingled with curiosity, to know the cause of their
strange appearance; but when they had several times repeated their exercise,
the scene was altogether so ridiculous that I could not refrain from laughing.
They soon afterwards, without even noticing the chief, turned and walked
off. After leaving the hut of the chief, I visited a number of others, all of
which were nearly alike. In one of them I saw two drums, the only
instruments of music that I met with. The largest of them was a hollow log,
from three to four feet long, and about a foot and a half in diameter, covered
at both ends with shark skin. I asked the owner to play upon it, to which he
readily consented, seeming highly flattered with the invitation. He
accompanied his voice by thumping his hands and elbows on the drum-head;
but the music that he made was intolerable. He beat, however, in very good
time, and had evidently a high opinion of his performance.

In the course of our ramble, one of the officers told an Indian, who had
joined us, by signs, that he wanted some cocoa-nuts. The good-natured
fellow acquiesced without the least hesitation, and to our great astonishment,
ran up a tree standing near us, with the activity of a squirrel. The tree was
forty or fifty feet high, having but a slight inclination, yet the climbing
seemed to occasion him scarcely any exertion. They do not press their
bodies against the tree and hitch themselves up as is customary with us,
which, in their naked condition, they could not do without injury. They press
the bottoms of their feet against the tree, and clinging to it with their hands
one above the other, ascend upon all-fours. It did not strike us with less
surprise when he had thrown the cocoa-nuts down, to see with what facility
he stripped off the hard husks without the aid of any thing but his teeth. For
such a thing to have been accomplished by one of us would be found
impossible. We afterwards remarked the same practise in other places, and at
other islands. It was general except with the old men, who, unless they were
very robust, used a sharp-pointed stick of hard wood to remove the husk.

They could not understand our practice of shaking hands. When we


extended a hand to one of them as a mark of friendly salutation, they looked
as though they would question what was meant by it; and from their manner
seemed to think that our object was to feel their skin, which they would
always reciprocate by raising up our sleeves and examining very minutely.

On the morning of the 29th of September, which was the last of our
remaining in Comptroller's Bay, I made another excursion to the Typee Bay,
taking with me the chief of the Happahs, who was very anxious to go. I
wondered at this, as the tribes evinced so much dislike to each other; but
afterwards saw, in my intercourse with the natives of the South Sea Islands,
that uncivilized men are capable of as much duplicity towards each other as
the educated and refined. When we had arrived within a hundred yards of the
shore we were met by the chief with whom I had formed an acquaintance on
the preceding day. He saluted the chief of the Happahs in a way that
indicated a former acquaintance, but with a look and manner somewhat
formal. The Typee chief immediately spoke to some one near him, who ran
off and in a few minutes returned with a calabash filled with a preparation of
the bread-fruit, upon which was poured a quantity of milk expressed from a
cocoa-nut. This was offered by the Typee to the Happah chief, and I was also
invited to partake of it. I tasted and found it very palatable. The two chiefs
seated themselves in the stern of the boat, and made a hearty breakfast, using
their fingers instead of spoons. Neither of them seemed very communicative,
as only a few words passed between them at this interview. There was also
in the boat a young woman belonging to the chief's family, for whom
breakfast was brought in the shell of a cocoa-nut, and which was a
preparation of the cocoa-nut and bread-fruit, sour and disagreeable to the
taste. This, I was informed, is the food upon which the women almost
entirely subsist, they being Tabooed from eating whatever is held in high
estimation by the men. When the chiefs had finished their repast, the Typee
pointed to his hogs, which he had again caused to be brought down upon the
beach, saying that he wanted powder or guns for them, but unfortunately I
had neither of these valuable articles with which to make an exchange with
him, and he would consider nothing else as an equivalent. He sent for
several old muskets that were very much out of order, and proposed to go on
board with me and have them repaired, making me understand by signs, that
he would in return present me with hogs. His anxiety was so great upon this
subject, that I found it difficult to put a stop to his solicitations. In the mean
time, however, I saw the schooner underway, and dismissing my Typee
friends, pulled away for the Happah Bay. When I had approached within half
a mile of the Happah village, the schooner was almost out of the harbour,
and the chief observing that I was anxious to get on board, proposed jumping
into the water and swimming home, to which I readily consented. He then
stripped himself of his neck and ear ornaments, which consisted of two
white pieces of polished shell and a carved image of bone, and presenting
them to me as a token of his regard, plunged into the water, leaving me free
to pursue my way to the vessel without the trouble of landing him. Most of
the ornaments worn by these people, are of bone or shells, finely polished or
rudely carved. They attach a number of them to a piece of cocoa-nut twine,
and wear them around their necks, or wrists, or ancles, as may be most
agreeable to the taste and fancy of the individuals. A more expensive and
difficult ornament to obtain is a gorget. It is a piece of wood, semi-circular,
about three inches wide, carved to fit the neck, covered with a beautiful red
and black berry, and stuck on with a gum that oozes from the tree of the
bread-fruit. On the hill that rises to the left of the valley, we planted a variety
of seeds of fruit, vegetables and grain, but the natives of the valley are so
totally ignorant of every thing that relates to agriculture, that it is not
probable they will ever derive any advantage from them. Whilst we were in
Happah Bay, the weather was clear and delightful. The temperature so
regular that no change was felt in the transition from day to night.

On the 30th of September, we stood out of Comptroller's Bay, and ran


down for Massachusetts' Bay, a place made familiar to our countrymen by
Commodore Porter's long and interesting visit. The two points that form the
harbours of Comptroller's and Massachusetts' Bays, are about seven miles
distant from each other. At one, P.M., we were clear of the projecting
southern point of Comptroller's Bay, and at three, P.M., anchored in eight
fathoms water, within half a mile of the hill at the bottom of the bay, called
Porter's Monument. Before we came to anchor, the water was covered with
canoes, and people of both sexes and all ages swimming towards us, and as
soon as the vessel lost her head way, they were crawling up on all sides like
so many rats. They were not less delighted with our arrival than were the
Happahs. Hundreds were collected on the shore, and all expressing their
satisfaction by songs and dances. Amongst our first visitors, were two
English sailors who had deserted from whale ships, and been long enough
resident on the island to converse in the language of the natives. With them
came also a native of Nooaheeva, and a native of Otaheite, both of whom
had served a considerable time in whale ships, and could converse in broken
English. We were therefore in no want of interpreters, and it seemed at once
to introduce us to the confidence and friendship of our new acquaintances.

The harbour of Massachusetts' Bay is spacious and affords good


anchorage for ships of the largest class. The only part of it, however, where
landing is not attended with difficulty and some danger, is the east side,
where there is a fine sand beach from a quarter to half a mile long, at one
extremity of which empties a small rivulet of pure and excellent water into
the bay. Landing may be effected at the watering-place beyond Porter's
Monument, where there is a more considerable stream of fresh water, but it
is always difficult, and when the surf is high, cannot fail to be dangerous. At
this place we watered the Dolphin; but had to swim the casks to and from the
shore, and altogether, it was a laborious undertaking. Along the east and
north part of the bay there is a long reef that makes at a short distance from
the shore, upon which a heavy surf is always breaking. In entering the bay,
the whole habitable part of this section of the island is presented at one view,
and forms a most grand and beautiful landscape. It is nearly semi-circular,
and rises like an amphitheatre, in fruitful and populous circular ranges of
hills, until at the distance of several miles, it terminates in a circumference of
high and gloomy mountains, the tops of which resemble a massive wall. This
rude and barren circle of mountain contrasts finely with the fertile ranges
below, covered with their forests of cocoa-nut and bread-fruit trees, and huts
and villages every where scattered about through hill and dale. Nor is the
extreme elevation without its interest and beauty. A number of little cataracts
reflecting the rays of the sun and looking like sheets of liquid silver, break in
upon the gloom of the sterile rock, adding brilliancy as they descend to the
lively prospect below. After a shower, not less than fifty of these splendid
falls of water may be seen, some of which are but just perceptible through
the intervening space between hills and trees, producing an effect peculiarly
agreeable. What is called Porter's Monument, is a round hill from fifty to an
hundred feet high, situated at the east extremity of the bay. It was here that
Commodore Porter had his Fort, not a vestige of which is now remaining. It
is overrun with a wild luxuriant growth of vines and grass, and no trace of a
footstep can be found. On one side of the hill, near its base, was stretched a
bark line, which was attended by a man who calls himself Opotee, and who
declares the hill beyond it to be tabooed. Upon one occasion, as I was
approaching it, some natives called out "Taboo, Taboo!" but Opotee
immediately expressed his willingness that I should pass, as I was a
countryman of his namesake, Opotee. To the north of Porter's Monument,
and back from the sand beach, where was the navy-yard, all is now
overgrown with bushes and trees, some of which have attained to a
considerable size. Like the monument, there is no indication of its ever
having been occupied for any human purpose,

On the first of October, the day after our arrival, I went on shore, taking
with me a great variety of seeds, for the purpose of planting them where it
was most probable they would be taken care of and come to maturity. The
natives flocked round me in great numbers. There was not less than a
hundred boys with the crowd of men and women that followed me. They
were highly delighted when they discovered my object, which was explained
to them by John Luxon, the native of Nooaheeva, who spoke English.
Whenever we came to a rough or muddy place, which was frequently the
case, the boys and men, notwithstanding my remonstrances, would mount
me on their shoulders and carry me over, with loud shouting. I could easily
perceive that this was a frolic with those who engaged in it, and done out of
levity and the caprice of the moment; but I could not but feel that they had
been first stimulated to it by the favourable impression they had conceived
of my design. I planted some things in unfrequented places where I found a
clear spot, but most of the seeds and fruit-pits, in the enclosures of the
natives. John Luxon was a man of some rank as a chief, and possessed
considerable property. To one of his enclosures that was large and seemed to
have been attended with unusual care, I devoted most of my attention. There,
aided by several of the natives, who laboured with great assiduity, I prepared
the ground and made quite an extensive plantation of orange, lemon,
cheromaya, peach, apricot, water-melons, pumpkins, potatoes, onions,
beans, corn, and a variety of other fruits and grain, from Peru. He expressed
himself in terms of the warmest gratitude, and I have no doubt that the
natives have already experienced the most important benefits from the
memento I left them of the Dolphin's visit to their Island.

In the course of my days' occupation, I was several times driven into


Luxon's house by the frequent showers that came over. I no sooner entered,
than the natives flocked after me, and in a few minutes the hut would be
crowded. The little boys and girls here shewed me the same officious
attention that I received in making my way to the village, but expressed in a
different manner. As many as could approach would surround me with their
fans, keeping them going until the rain ceased, and I was again enabled to
resume my work. This was a kind of civility, peculiarly agreeable, as the
weather was oppressively warm; but I could not fail to discover that my little
attendants were all candidates for my friendly notice and bestowed their
civility with the expectation of some reward. I had a few trifles about me,
but not enough to give to all, and felt at a loss in what way I should make my
presents, fearing that the least favoured would be mortified and displeased. It
seemed however to make no difference. It was all "motake"[5] with them.
All seemed satisfied. On my return to the beach, I found it thronged with
men, women, and children. All the beauty and fashion of Massachusetts' Bay
had assembled in honour of our arrival, decked out in their finest tappas, and
gayest colours. The females were dressed in the best style of their island,
with neat turbans of tappa-cloth, white, or ornamented with colours, a white
robe of the same material thrown loosely over them, tastefully knotted on
one shoulder, concealing half the bosom, and a wrapper round the waist that
reached below the knee. They were arranged in groups of a dozen each,
singing merrily and clapping their hands in time to the music of their voices.
A little way from them the men were seated in the same manner and
similarly occupied. The ladies, to improve their charms, had used an
abundant quantity of cocoa-nut oil, which filled the air with its nauseous
perfumes for an hundred yards round. Many of them had more highly
anointed themselves with yellow paint, which, with the cocoa-nut oil, was
running from them in streams. Some had decorated themselves with
necklaces of a golden yellow fruit which bears a strong resemblance to a
pine-apple, and emits a powerful offensive smell. At a distance, with their
variegated robes flying in the wind, their appearance was altogether
agreeable, and upon a near approach the scene was animated beyond
description. The dusk of evening was the signal for their dispersion, when
some went one way and some another. On the second of October, I wandered
back upon the hills, and had all the boys with me that followed me on the
preceding day.

They renewed their frolic of carrying me, and whenever I seated myself,
came round me as many as could approach, each with a green leaf for a fan.
I entered unceremoniously a number of the huts, where I almost always
found one or more men, in nearly every instance, extended on their backs,
their heads resting on a log laid along on one side of the hut, and their heels
on another, about four feet from the first. They would never rise to receive
me, but utter "motake," when I was perceived by them, and make motions
for me to do as they did, offering me at the same time a fan, one of which
they were using almost constantly. In the course of my ramble, I met with a
little girl, twelve or fourteen years old, who was very pretty, attended by a
servant, the only instance in which I remarked such a thing on the island.
She was evidently walking out to make a visit, and had just arrived at the
house of her destination when I met her. I put some beads round her neck,
which seemed to delight her very much; but an old man present, whose hut
she was about to visit, assumed an angry look, and seemed to threaten by his
manner. He changed his conduct, however, when I made him a trifling
present, and the little girl, taking my hand, led me to her father's hut. He was
a chief of some consequence, as was indicated by the possession of two or
three casks of powder, and six muskets. These he took down, and displayed
very ostentatiously, and wanted to know if I had not others to dispose of. His
conduct was altogether kind and hospitable, in acknowledgment for which I
made him a present at my departure. Whenever I wanted cocoa-nuts to
quench my thirst, I had only to signify it to one of the men that was
following me about, and he would supply me from the nearest tree. With one
fellow I was very much amused. He carried his arms full of cocoa-nuts
following me about nearly all day, and when I returned to the vessel I
presented him with a musket ball, with which he was perfectly satisfied, said
it was "motake," and went away. When I returned to the beach in the
evening, I found the natives, male and female, assembled in as great
numbers as on the day previous, and amusing themselves in the same way.
The females were again in their finest attire, and at a distance might any
where else have been mistaken for an assemblage of fashionable belles. We
were apprehensive that our men, a number of whom were at work on shore,
would have been very much annoyed by the intrusion of the natives. This,
however, was not the case. When they commenced their work in the
morning a circle was made, comprehending the whole space we wished them
to occupy, which we told the natives was tabooed, and there was not an
instance of their passing it. The next day they held quite a fair on the beach.
Amongst other things, they had for trade large quantities of cocoa-nuts and
bread-fruit. The former they exchanged for small pieces of tobacco; but a
piece of iron hoop, fashioned into a tool or instrument of husbandry, was
demanded for the latter. They were all day on the beach, cooking and eating
their bread-fruit and cocoa-nuts. In the evening, the boys and men amused us
with playing soldiers, by ranging themselves in a line with sticks for
muskets. One of our officers took a particular pleasure in making grimaces,
and talking a gibberish to the natives in imitation of their manner of
speaking. It was very offensive to them; but they respected us too much to
betray their displeasure. Upon one occasion, however, he amused himself in
this way with the boys, about a hundred of whom were assembled, when I
encouraged them to retaliate on him, by clucking like a hen. They soon
discovered that it was disagreeable to him, and assembled round him like so
many little furies, clucking with all their might. It seemed to delight them to
have an opportunity of revenging themselves upon him, which they did most
amply, for they did not let him rest a moment until he went on board, which
was soon afterwards, highly displeased with me for conspiring with the
Indians against him. We were often amused with the strange and ridiculous
taste of the natives in the article of dress.

They were all desirous of obtaining clothes, and a number of old


garments were given them, or exchanged for curiosities by the officers and
crew. When obtained, whether they fitted or not, the Indians immediately put
them on, and scarcely ever more than one garment at a time. Thus, half
naked and half attired, a native would walk about with exceeding gravity,
admiring himself, and believing that every one else was equally pleased with
his genteel appearance.

Whenever they seated themselves to sing, a person was selected to


occupy a conspicuous station, and perform a dance round the circle, slowly,
and in the most graceful native style, striking at the same time the hollow of
his left arm with his right hand, in time with the music of their voices. This
distinction was always conferred upon some one who had obtained an old
jacket or tattered shirt. If he had on a jacket, it was sure to be buttoned
closely round him, with the two or three remaining buttons, and the sleeves,
if not torn off, would probably not reach more than half the length of his
arms. Thus attired, he would perform his evolutions round the circle slowly,
and with a most serious air, stopping occasionally to receive the applause of
the singers, who bestowed it upon him with great enthusiasm. Soon after
daylight, one morning I was on the beach, and my curiosity led me to a
place, where a number of females were busily employed in collecting
something from the rocks. When I approached them they discontinued their
occupation, and would have fled, but I called them back, and prevailed upon
them to renew their occupation. Each of them was provided with a green
leaf, in which she was gathering from the rocks a species of fine green sea
moss and small snails. What they preserved in the leaf was intended for their
families at home. They ate freely of them, and said it was "motake." The
moss was tender, but to me had no other taste than that of salt water, with
which it was covered at high tide. The snails were not larger than a pea,
covered with a hard shell, and when broken, heated the tongue like pepper.
The moss, when gathered, had a most disgusting appearance. I was told by
the Englishmen, residing here, that the natives esteem it a very great
delicacy. One of the females had an infant with her a few months old, which
she was teaching to swim by holding it in a pool of water, and occasionally
letting it go. The infant would make a slight effort, when let go by the
mother, and, no doubt, was taught to swim almost as soon as it could walk.
On the third of October, in walking through the habitable part of the valley, I
was every where met by females, who addressed me with a smile, and finely
modulated tone of voice, "Coare ta whyhene?"[6] The father of one of these,
good naturedly conducted me to the hut of a chief, highest in blood of any in
the valley. He was a man upwards of fifty, and apparently more civilized
than any of the natives I had seen before. He told the interpreter to say, that
he felt pleasure in seeing me at his hut. It was about forty by twenty feet, and
constructed in the same way as that occupied by the Happah chief, differing
in no respect from those of the common people, except in dimensions. His
rank and importance was displayed in the possession of six muskets, and two
casks of powder that hung directly fronting the door, and which the chief
took occasion to point out to me soon after I entered. To him they were a
treasure, and, in fact, the wealth and consequence of every individual
seemed to be estimated by this standard alone. The powder was covered over
with canvass, and the muskets highly polished. On one side of the hut were
two logs, about three feet apart, and between them a coarse mat, for the
convenience of laying down on, one log being intended for the head, and the
other for the feet. Whilst I was here, a number of visitors came in, and,
walking directly to the logs, without noticing any one, threw themselves
down between them, their heads on one, and feet on the other, where they
lay, fanning themselves, and looking at us, without saying a word, except
once or twice, when they saw me looking at them, I was saluted with
"motake." In the middle of the hut was the coffin of the chief's father, who
had died about six months previous. It was the trunk of a large bread-fruit
tree, six or eight feet long, highly polished, and the lid so ingeniously fitted,
that the place of contact could not be seen but by the closest examination. He
told me that his father had been a great warrior, and the friend of Opotee.[7]
Before his door was a swivel, and a number of shot, that he said he had
obtained from Opotee. He prized them very highly, although they could not
be of the least use to him, except as they served to gratify his vanity. When I
expressed a desire to know the manner in which they prepared the paint,
used by the females, he directed his son to get some of the root, and grind it
between two stones, mixing a little water with it, the only process required. I
gave the chief's wife (who was an old woman) some beads, and a cotton
handkerchief, with which she was so delighted, that she threw both her arms
around my neck, and embraced me most affectionately. She was painted all
over, quite yellow, and so thoroughly smeared my clothes, that I paid dearly
for this expression of her regard. At parting, the chief presented me with a
hog (the only one we obtained at the Marquesas), some sticks of the tappa
tree, and offered whatever was acceptable to me, about his house. We also
exchanged names, and I promised again to visit him, but had no opportunity
afterwards. His son accompanied me on board, carrying the presents his
father had made me, and all the way calling me "Kappe," the name of his
father, and himself, by my name.

In the evening, when I returned to the vessel, she was crowded with
natives, the work of the day being completed. The men and women were in
different circles, singing their songs. That of the women, resembled the
croaking of a great many frogs. The quick and lively motion of their hands,
accompanying the various modulations of the voice, exhibited a great
activity, and command of muscle, and was far more pleasing than their
music. There was one amongst the females, who possessed great powers of
voice, in the utterance of strange sounds, in which none of the rest could
accompany her. The performance seemed to distress her very much, and was
certainly very disagreeable; yet the natives would all stop occasionally, to
listen to her, and, when she was done, exclaimed, with seeming surprise,
"motake!"

On the 4th of October, I took a boat, prepared with arms, and providing
myself with a few presents, ran down for Lewis' Bay, to ascertain the depth
of water at the entrance of the harbour, what difficulties might probably
attend our running in with the schooner, and whether it afforded any better
prospect than the other places we had visited, of obtaining a supply of hogs.
The distance was only six miles, and, with a fine breeze, we were at the
entrance of the harbour in little more than an hour. It was very narrow,
formed by two high points of land, and the depth of water abundantly
sufficient for ships of the largest class. A heavy and broken swell made the
entrance appear difficult: and, without a fair wind, it is so confined, that it
would be hazardous to attempt it; but the gorge being once passed, you enter
a large smooth basin, where there is scarcely a ripple, the land rising high all
around it, and the points locking with each other. In the basin we found good
anchorage, in from four to nine fathoms water, and a clay bottom. Lewis'
Bay is divided into two parts by a projecting point of rocks. I first landed in
that which fronts the entrance, or rather went into the edge of the surf. A
great many people, of all ages, came swimming off through the surf, and in a
few moments the boat was full of them, and of fruit of various kinds. They
were anxious for me to land, but I saw there would be great difficulty in my
getting off again, in the event of any misunderstanding with them, which
was not altogether impossible. I did not remain long, but, dismissing the
natives who had crawled into the boat, or were hanging on the gunwale,
pulled round the point of rocks to the other landing. When first I went into
this part of the harbour, I could perceive only two or three persons, who
were afraid to come near us. They gradually relaxed in their timidity,
however, and kept nearing us a little, until we at last prevailed upon them to
get into the boat. As soon as they saw our muskets, which they thought were
intended for trade; but which were only for our protection, they ran away,
saying, they would bring us hogs directly. In the mean time the news of our
arrival spread, far and wide, over the valley, and the people came running
from every direction, with whatever they could most readily possess
themselves of, for trade. Every body wanted muskets, and a chief had seven
or eight hogs brought to the beach, all of which he offered for one gun. After
spending an hour or two here, on the most friendly terms with the natives, I
prepared to depart, and missed one of my shoes, that I had thrown off wet.
Search was made in the boat, without finding it, when it was remarked, that
a native had been seen crawling in the water for a considerable distance to a
rock near the shore, where he deposited something, and returned. Upon
examination, we found the shoe wrapped up in a piece of tappa cloth, the
Indian having stolen it, without reflecting that the possession of one shoe,
without the other, was of no value to him, or perhaps not caring whether it
was or not, so that he gratified his propensity to steal. When I returned a
short distance, and held the shoe up to show the natives that I had recovered
it, they set up a loud laugh, which I interpreted into applause, of the
ingenious exploit of their countryman. The valley of Lewis' Bay is not to be
compared to either of the other places we visited on the island, for beauty or
fertility. It is, however, quite populous, and the scenery is grand and
picturesque. The land gradually rises from a small plain below, like the
valley occupied by the Typees, in a succession of hills, and terminates in a
perpendicular high ledge of rocks. In returning from Lewis' to
Massachusetts' Bay, the wind was ahead, and we pulled close in with the
shore, which, for nearly the whole distance, rises abruptly, from the ocean, to
the height of six or seven hundred feet. Numerous falls, which were only
perceptible in heavy mist, before they reached the water, were leaping from
the top, whilst the sea beat the sides with unceasing fury, throwing its spray
to the height of more than a hundred feet. Whilst we were tugging at our
oars, contemplating this magnificent scene, the sea suddenly became
unusually agitated, and threatened, at every instant, to swallow up the boat.
We pulled directly from the shore, and for half an hour our situation was
very critical, after which the sea became regular. A phenomenon, so
remarkable, baffled all our speculation, and we were entirely at a loss to
determine respecting its cause. On our arrival on board, we learned that the
vessel had narrowly escaped being driven on shore in a squall It was not the
fault of the anchorage, but in consequence of the baffling winds which had
several times driven the vessel over her anchor, whereby it was fouled by the
cable, and tripped with the violence of the squall.

The natives, as usual, were assembled on the shore near us, amusing
themselves in their customary way, by singing and dancing. The females,
having learned from some of the Dolphin's crew, that it was not in good taste
to use cocoa-nut oil, and paint, in such profusion, left it off, as well as the
golden yellow fruit, which had also been highly disapproved of. It improved
their appearance, and they seemed to be sensible of the superior estimation
in which they were held. These wild ladies, in truth, who, on our first arrival,
came swimming round, like so many mermaids, grew very fastidious in the
short time we remained at their island. After the first day or two, they
requested to be allowed to go on board, in our boats, and then, seeing some
of the officers carried through the surf by the seamen, nothing less would
please them, when they did us the honour of a visit, but to be gallanted on
board with the same ceremony. Our sailors gallantly condescended to gratify
two or three of them; but, instead of taking them to the boat, they most
uncourteously let them fall into the first heavy roller they encountered,
leaving them to the choice of swimming to the boat, or back to the shore
again, after which none ever asked to be carried. With regard to their
superstitions or worship, we could learn but little. John Luxon told me, that
he was tabooed by his father, who was a chief, and that no common man
dared to pass over his head. He was usually dressed in a sailor's shirt and
trowsers, and an old hat. He came off regularly every morning, and ate with
us three time a day, taking his seat at the table, without the least ceremony,
and never waiting to be asked.

One day, some one had, designedly or accidentally, thrown some bread
in John's hat, which he did not perceive when he took it up, and put it on.
When he felt the bread upon his head, he threw his hat off instantly, and,
with a look of the utmost horror, exclaimed, "who put dat dare? Me Taboo
here!" (putting his hand on his head) "To-morrow me sick, me die!" This, he
repeated over a number of times, and with great earnestness of manner tried
to find out who had put the bread in his hat, insisting upon it, that, on the
morrow, he should sicken and die. The morrow, however, came, and John
was alive and well, and was heartily laughed at for his foolish superstition,
when he came on board as usual to spend the day with us. I do not believe
that John had the same implicit faith in taboo afterwards. I tried to find out
from him what was meant by his being tabooed, but he spoke English so
badly, and seemed to understand so little of the matter himself, that I was not
much the wiser for his explanation. We were told here, that, a few years
since, the missionaries at the Society Islands, moved by the benevolent
purpose of converting the Marquesas islanders to Christianity, sent one of
their number to reside at Massachusetts' Bay. The missionary landed
amongst his charge, by whom he was received with characteristic kindness
and hospitality. No other notice was taken of him, however, than would have
been bestowed upon the most poor and ignorant mariner, seeking an asylum
amongst them. He was permitted to fix upon his place of residence, and live
in such way as pleased him best. He soon commenced preaching the
doctrines of his faith. The natives listened to him, wondering at all he said,
but not less at his singular manner of life,—to them unexampled, in all their
acquaintance with the whites,—and, certainly, unparalleled amongst
themselves. They had always seen the white men, who visited their islands,
take liberties with their females, and mingle with them in all their pleasures,
whilst this man, who called himself a messenger from the Great Spirit, lived
a life of celibacy, retired from all that, to them, was amusing or agreeable.
When a free interchange of opinion had taken place amongst them,
respecting him, they came to the conclusion, that he was differently made
and constituted from all other men they had ever seen, and curiosity being
raised to the highest pitch, they, with a levity peculiar to savages, determined
to subject him to a scrutiny. The missionary, alarmed at a disposition that
evinced so little respect for his character and personal rights, took his
departure by the first opportunity, since which no attempt has been made to
convert the natives of the Marquesas to Christianity.

The men of the Marquesas, were, in general, quite naked. But few
ornaments were worn by either sex. The women frequently had no other
ornament than a small flower, stuck through a slit in their ears. Some of the
men wore polished whale's teeth round their necks, and some shell bracelets,
but they were not in common use. A few were tattooed all over, and others
but slightly. The mode of their tattooing seemed to be altogether a matter of
fancy. Some had indulged the most whimsical taste, in having indelibly
pricked into their flesh, fish, birds, and beasts, of all kinds known to them.
Others were tattooed black, even to the inner part of their lips. It is an art in
high estimation amongst them. There are men, who pursue it as a regular
business, and are in great favour with their countrymen, for their skilful
performance. The women tattoo more tastefully than the men. Their feet and
legs, half-way to the knee, are usually covered with figures, wrought with
great neatness, and the right hand and arm, half-way to the elbow, is often
similarly ornamented. Both men and women commonly wear their hair
short, and when instances to the contrary are met with, the persons
invariably have a disgusting appearance, their hair hanging in long and
disagreeable looking matted locks.

You might also like