You are on page 1of 14

The Conceptual Dimension in Art and the Modern Theory of Artistic Value

Author(s): Roger Seamon


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , Spring, 2001, Vol. 59, No. 2
(Spring, 2001), pp. 139-151
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/432220

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/432220?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROGER SEAMON

The Conceptual Dimension in Art


and the Modern Theory of Artistic Value

The impact of Marcel Duchamp's ready- made an artifact into art, but that "some per-
mades on the philosophy of art has been out son or persons acting on behalf of a certain
of all proportion to the interest of the objects social institution (the artworld) has con-
themselves-as indeed it should be for these ferred [upon these things or occurrences] the
ur-instances of what has come to be called status of candidate for appreciation."4
conceptual art. These works and their prog- Thirdly, Arthur Danto proposed what we
eny inspired a radical questioning of tradi- might call the theory theory of art. Danto
tional art theory, and the resulting revolution claims that it is neither appearances worth
consisted of three main theoretical events. contemplating nor an institutional imprima-
First, given that there was nothing especially tur that makes objects into art, but the con-
worth seeing in these art objects, the neces- ceptual itself, i.e., theory: "What in the end
sity of the perceptual to the arts was elimi- makes the difference between a Brillo box
nated and its centrality challenged, thus and a work of art is a certain theory of art."5
making the conventional term for art theory, The identity and value of works of art lie in
aesthetics, a serious misnomer: their meanings, and thus their status as art
objects depends upon interpretations, not
Recent years have seen the rise ... of a "concep- perceptual discrimination:
tual art," many of whose works were nothing
other than "things to think about" and owed The sparkplug as an aesthetic object and the
nothing to any mode of perception ... [whereas] sparkplug as an artwork would have very differ-
other aesthetic objects do depend on sensory ent properties, and it is not clear that the beauty
order.1 of the sparkplug is even relevant to its apprecia-
tion as an artwork. That would be ambiguous
Timothy Binkley, among many others, sees until it became interpreted, as in the parallel case
this as a liberation: "Art in the twentieth cen- of Duchamp's Fountain.6
tury has ... freed itself of aesthetic parame-
ters and sometimes creates directly with Danto's theory returns an identity to art, but
ideas unmediated by aesthetic [that is, per- again minimizes the perceptual. Aesthetics is
ceptual] qualities."2 The anti-aesthetic na- now a misleading word for the theory of art.
ture of such "pieces" had a second influential Pretty good for a shovel, a urinal, and the
consequence, the institutional theory of the like. A skeptic might minimize the whole
arts, which "has been consciously worked business by means of Francis Sparshott's ob-
out with the practices of the artworld in servation that "some aesthetic objects exist
mind-especially developments of the last to be thought about rather than to be per-
seventy-five years, such as dadaism, pop art, ceived,"7 but what we might call Sparshott's
found art, and happenings."3 If a successful paradox, the existence of unperceived aes-
work of art could be nonbeautiful, took no thetic objects, calls for more than that-but
skill to make, and might even be ephemeral, not a theoretical revolution. Conceptual art,
it was not some fine perceptual quality that I shall argue, does not force us to rethink

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 59:2 Spring 2001

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
140 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

completely the nature of art. It can, however, may sound too simple, too neat, and too con-
help us to become self-conscious about the venient, i.e., not "bad" enough to be true, yet
presence of a conceptual dimension in tradi- it is just what I think has happened. I shall
tional works of art,8 a dimension that some pursue this theme after showing that concep-
of the most prominent modern visual art has tual art intensely cultivates a dimension that
strikingly and innovatively cultivated, which, was present in earlier art, most familiarly, but
in turn, has led to radical conclusions about not exclusively, in allegory.
art generally. That has been an overreaction. From the establishment of aesthetics as a
Conceptual art strongly emphasizes what philosophical discipline in the eighteenth
was already present in some art, and the con- century until quite recently, the fine arts
ceptual dimension should, therefore, be un- were identified with the judgment of the
derstood as a permanent possibility and an beautiful, and the beautiful was found in per-
addition, rather than a challenge, to a rough ception. Here is a typical statement:
consensus about the forms of artistic value
that has emerged over the last 250 years.
We may decide in general whether a particular
That is my deflationary proposal.
judgment is genuinely aesthetic by seeing if an af-
The process of overreaction and subse-
firmative answer can be given to the question,
quent normalization has occurred before in
"Does tracing out the relation indicated by the
the history of modern art theory; indeed, it
judgment in question contribute to the direct and
seems to be its "logic." Very briefly and very
immediate sensory experience?" If it does not, if
roughly speaking, mimetic art dominated
it dissipates the aesthetic impact and corrodes its
Renaissance theory as the artists pursued
wholeness by diverting attention from the imme-
what E. H. Gombrich calls the "discovery of
diate givenness, it is not an aesthetic judgment.1
appearances."9
Next, the emphasis on feeling in romantic
art led to expressive theories, and, later, Given this assumption, the relation between
nonrepresentational painting became the medium and meaning in art is that a change
basis and motive for a formalist theory of the (of the right sort) in the former entails a
arts. However, the mimetic, expressive, and change in the latter. That is just what it
formal theories of art were eventually trans- means to grasp something aesthetically.11
formed into what I have called "dimensions," The reason for this is that we expect art to be,
that is, different kinds of aesthetic value to use Nelson Goodman's term, dense:
rather than competing essentialist concep- "Three symptoms of the aesthetic may be
tions of art. The conceptual, I want to argue, syntactic density, semantic density, and syn-
should be thought of in the same way. Thus, tactic repleteness," where density and re-
my mildly inflationary proposal is that the pleteness refer to a symbolic system that
addition of expressive and formal dimen- "provides for infinitely many characters so
sions to the mimetic moved us toward a ordered that between each two there is a
plausible theory of value in art. Adding the third."112 This means, roughly, that we do not,
conceptual broadens and strengthens what I for example, treat the lines in a graph as we
shall call, adapting the well-known phrase of do the identical lines if they signify a range of
Paul 0. Kristeller, the modern theory of ar- hills in a drawing, and this emphasis on per-
tistic value. Although the path has, obviously, ceptual density "call[s] for maximum sensi-
not been nearly as simply sequential (Aris- tivity of discrimination."13 This view of the
totle included a formal dimension in his ac- arts is nicely expressed in the nontrans-
count of tragedy, Kant is the formalist par latability thesis-that concepts are media-in-
excellence, etc.) and conceptually tidy (there different, whereas poetry is what is lost in the
are very different mimetic and expressive translation.
theories) as my summary account makes it, Untranslatability and the need for fine-
there has, nonetheless, been progress toward ness of discrimination are precisely what we
a consensus in the theory of art. That claim do not find in conceptual art, where what

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Seamon The Conceptual Dimension in Art 141

matters are ideas that are very loosely tied to What Bosanquet means by this is made clear
appearances:14 in a comment on The Divine Comedy:

Malevich's most famous painting remains The Dante is not a great poet because in speaking of a
Black Square-a square of uniform black within a she-wolf he signifies by it at once the temporal
border of white. The original version, first exhib- power of the Pope and the sin of avarice; but be-
ited in 1915, is now displayed in the Tretyakov cause in his intentness upon the issue and the
Gallery; carelessly painted over another painting, meaning, nothing that has a natural significance
its surface deteriorated and is now a cross-section escapes his ear and eye.20
of irregular white lines (a particularly ironic fate
for picture [sic] intended to be the last word in To which he adds the poetic authority of
stark simplicity), but it was always the concept of Robert Browning:
the painting, not its execution, that mattered.'5
If beauty indeed lies in symbolic meaning, and if
In the same vein, Binkley says of Duchamp's symbolic meaning is utterly arbitrary, then we ask
L. H. 0. 0. Q., "When you look at the art- with Fra Lippo Lippi:
work you learn nothing of artistic conse-
quence which you don't already know from "Why for this
the description Duchamp gives," and "the What need of art at all? A skull and bones,
difference [between this kind of art and that Two bits of wood nailed crosswise, or, what's best,
based on perception] can be elucidated by A bell to chime the hours with, does as well." 21
contrasting ideas and appearances."16
Binkley is, of course, arguing against the va- Those bits of wood and that bell are the sorts
lidity of the entire aesthetic tradition, in of things that we find in conceptual art, unin-
which "aesthetic qualities cannot be commu- teresting in themselves but valued for what
nicated except through direct experience of they signify. The question is why an object
them,"117 but one need not accept his conclu- that means is sometimes art, while at other
sions about that to accept his account of con- times it is not. In Danto's formulation, a real
ceptual art as an art that is not grounded in thing becomes art by virtue of interpretation,
appearances. Indeed, that is simply the re- but our interpretation of the cross as a Chris-
ceived view. tian symbol does not make it art, while
If the arbitrary nature of the relationship Duchamp's shovel is somehow transformed.
between concept and artifact is the distinc- The mere fact that an image stands for a con-
tive mark of conceptual art, we can take our cept does not suffice to make it into art. We
cue as to how to proceed from conceptual art are familiar with all sorts of symbolic images,
to the conceptual in art from a passage in from crosses to figures on bathroom doors,
Bernard Bosanquet's History of Aesthetic in that are not art, and Bosanquet assumes that
which he comments upon the arbitrariness Dante's symbolism is, although serious, just
of what he calls symbolism:'8 like those examples. I need, therefore, to
show that there is something about some
Imitation is only a rule of art, and prima facie can symbolism and conceptual art that makes
make nothing beautiful which is not given as them art-like, even though in both instances
beautiful. Symbolism is a mode of interpretation; we are dealing with what appears to be more
and with all its enormous risks of arbitrariness, like a graph than a painting, with something
has the one advantage of absolute universality. If that merely stands for something else. The
all that has a meaning may be beautiful, then there arbitrariness of the relationship between
is nothing in which we may not chance to detect an image and concept is, therefore, not what de-
element of beauty. It is easy to see how hopeful is fines conceptual art; that may be necessary
such an idea, and how rich a prospect it opens, in but it is not sufficient.
comparison with the notion of the beautiful as fi- In an earlier essay I argued that an impor-
nally and unalterably given to perception.19 tant way in which the arts engage us is by

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
142 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

eliciting our capacity to make perceptual in- inadequate, or critical of the artist's obscu-
ferences: rity. Along the same lines, Francis Sparshott
asserts that "beauty occupies the ground be-
I shall call the process ... guided rapid uncon- tween cliche and chaos," with variety pro-
scious reconfiguration (GRUR for short). It is tecting against the former, and unity protect-
guided, because poems, like all works of art, are ing against the latter.26
deliberately made [or found and offered], and our Gap opening (by artists) and closing (by
pleasure lies in getting what the artist is up to. It audiences) takes various forms in the arts.
must be rapid, because art is for pleasure, and For example, in graphic arts and painting
rapid reconfiguration is pleasurable moment by there is a gap to be leaped between our
moment, which is very different from what occurs knowledge that we are looking at a surface
as you read this essay. The activity is unconscious, and our perception of a three-dimensional
in a cognitive not psychoanalytic sense; when we object. We are pleased at making the leap
get a joke or hear a melody, we do so without from surface configuration to object, al-
being aware of the steps in the process. We leap though such mere depiction no longer has
the communicative gap opened by an author by the magic it once did; we demand much more
reconfiguring enough so as to accommodate the sophisticated perceptual leaps. To see
apparently disconnected elements.22 An obvious, Cezanne's color patches as very subtle
if minor, example of this process, which I will call "props" for the making of a full illusion,
imaginative inference, is a joke, where, through a which is the form of make-believe that I
mysterious process, we simply "get it." A major think Cezanne is often engaged in, is to leap
example would be what happens when we look at, a wider gap than in traditional "realistic" art,
say, a Rembrandt self-portrait, where we infer the at least on a formal level.27 Cubism is the
state of the sitter's soul from the appearances, and classic form of this characteristically modern
the more we look the more we see. What is crucial preference. To feel the emotional intensity in
in both cases is that it is the audience that must Hemingway's sparseness or James's circum-
make the inferences, as the artist does not fill in locutions is to make an imaginative leap
the gaps, which means that we cannot say how we from surface reticence to expressive depth. I
got from here to there, from image to concept. do not claim that this is all that goes on in art,
This should be contrasted with argument, where, but that it is pervasive and an important
ideally, we are led by the thinker step by careful source of art's value to us.28 Our success at
step from concept to concept. In arguments a having made the inference is marked by de-
bridge is built rather than a gap leaped. We can light in having successfully gotten what the
see it go up every step of the way, and we try to artist was up to, which, unlike more straight-
find error as we proceed. In art implication and forward forms of communication, demands
imaginative inference dominate.23 We have to get imaginative inference.29
it, and it has to be gettable in a certain way.24 This process is at work in both conceptual
art and the allegories and symbols of tradi-
This thesis is closely related to a traditional tional art. The artists do not tell us what their
and persistent view of value in art. symbols mean, but rely on our making the
proper inference, and however straightfor-
However we analyze the difference between the ward that inference may be, it makes all the
regular and the irregular, we must ultimately be difference that we are not told the meaning
able to account for the most basic fact of aesthetic but must infer it. The difference between
experience, the fact that delight lies somewhere conceptual art and traditional allegories is
between boredom and confusion. If monotony that the images in the latter have, in the first
makes it difficult to attend, a surfeit of novelty instance, what Bosanquet calls "natural sig-
will overload the system and cause us to give up.25 nificance," and which I would call the mi-
metic and expressive implications that we in-
If the gap is too narrow, as in a too obvious tuitively get when we engage with fictions.
pun or plot, we groan with disappointment; if Hamlet says, "Thrift, thrift, Horatio," and we
it is too wide we are stumped and feel either infer that he is deeply upset but is also

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Seamon The Conceptual Dimension in Art 143

deeply witty and uses his wit to keep his by dropping the allegory, for in the opinion
"cool." We also infer that Shakespeare of Bosanquet and other romantic theorists
would have us admire this stance, even as we who excluded allegory from the aesthetic
recognize that it cannot be Hamlet's final re- that might just make it better as art. No,
sponse to the events in Elsinore. If Hamlet dropping the allegory, as is done with chil-
was taken by the original audience as a sym- dren's versions of Gulliver's Travels, prevents
bol of Elizabeth's courtiers who were re- us from making imaginative inferences, and
volted by her sexual shenanigans but pre- making such inferences is, on the theory ad-
tended to be above the battle and merely vanced above, a distinctive reason for our
made snide remarks, we would then have a desire to encounter art.30
conceptual dimension added to the "natural Contrary to Bosanquet, then, the relation-
significance." The symbolic meaning needs ship between an image and a concept is as
to be inferred no less than the mimetic and art-like as his "natural significance." The
expressive meanings, and it is, therefore, an next step is to show that the process of imagi-
intrinsic dimension of the art. native inference we find in allegory is char-
We need to contrast this with the case acteristically found in conceptual art. Con-
where we are not interested in the natural ceptual art is, I claim, often a sort of
significance and where the symbolic mean- mini-allegory, a metaphor, although the im-
ing is not inferred but given, in other words, plied meanings are, relative to traditional
where the allegory is merely illustrative, not symbolism, indeterminate, though not
a stimulus to inference. For example, we can wholly so.31 This is nicely illustrated in the
safely presume that Plato's purpose in the following comment on what I take to be a
cave allegory is not to engage us in the activ- typical work of contemporary conceptual
ity of "making believe" or to get us to infer art:
the symbolic meaning, but to illustrate an
idea, which he explicitly spells out for us.
For all its assertive size it remains primly reticent
Therefore, we do not make inferences about
about just what it has in mind. Is the giant dress a
natural significance ("What is the mood of
symbol of oppressive girlishness, the kind of
the people in the cave?" is not a serious
looming Memories of Mom that many a feminist
question) or conceptual meaning, for the lat-
must feel when she contemplates what to wear to
ter is given to us. There is, of course, art in
her next soir6e? Or is it a kind of big-girl celebra-
Plato's tale; we admire the aptness of his par-
tion of the power of the petticoat, insisting that,
able and the beauty of the language, and
with enough chutzpah, frills can be rescued from a
there is, no doubt, some space for interpreta-
submissive past and turned into a power outfit for
tion. It is not a pure graph, to go back to
the nineties?32
Goodman's example. However, like the
graph it is in principle dispensable and not
merely replaceable, like Duchamp's shovel. What makes this work conceptual is that, in
A corollary of what I have been arguing contrast to, for example, a nude sculpture,
about the nature of the conceptual dimen- where we are not puzzled by the choice of
sion in art is that the game of drawing con- object, it is not clear what the purpose of the
ceptual implications contributes, when suc- work is, and our "natural" impulse at that
cessful of course, to the value of works of art. point is to search for a conceptual meaning
Consider Orwell's Animal Farm. If we were that will make sense of its very existence.
to find out that Orwell had not intended the The contemporary preference for openness
allegory (that it was just a children's story and uncertainty, which conceptual art first
about unfairness), we ought to say, "Well, he helped to develop and now exploits, should
damn well should have," for the story not not obscure the fact that the same allegorical
only becomes much more incisive and adult process that we find in Dante and Orwell is
as a political parable, but we now can, at each at work here, only more playfully and tenta-
moment, get the allegorical implications. It is tively. Today we like uncertainty and resist
not that one simply misunderstands the work closure, and it is the ability of conceptual art

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
144 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

to elicit that interpretive activity that consti- conceptual art is, normally, very interesting
tutes its main artistic value.33 conceptually, that is, as a way of doing philos-
Allegory is not the only way in which we ophy by other means, just as the Pound poem
are encouraged to make imaginative infer- is not especially valuable as poetics. Harold
ences, both in conceptual and traditional art. Rosenberg, for example, claims, "The func-
Duchamp's shovel and Warhol's Brillo tion of art in our time is not to please the
Boxes are not so much (if at all) symbols as senses but to provide a fundamental investi-
gestures; i.e., they are understood to be say- gation of art and reality."34 Although some
ing something by implication, although, once works of art, and not just conceptual ones,
again in contrast with traditional art, the im- may stimulate such investigations, they can-
plications are much more open. Whereas not seriously develop an argument.35 Con-
there is considerable freedom to draw one's ceptual art is, normally, more like wit than
own moral from traditional narratives, as "investigation." Thus, when Arthur Danto
long as one remains, so to speak, in the ball- says that when Andy Warhol exhibited a
park, gestures in conceptual art are, initially, "painting-by-numbers painting" he was
much more enigmatic; i.e., the gap is greater "making a statement about anyone being
between image and meaning. Let me give an able to be an artist," we do not take Warhol's
example from early modern poetry, Ezra statement itself very seriously.36 Indeed, it is
Pound's "Papyrus," which is more conceptu- either banal or false. If Warhol means that
ally puzzling than most traditional art but most people can learn that putting paint on
less so than many postmodern works: canvas makes a work of art and are physi-
cally capable of doing so, then the statement
Spring ...... is banal. If he means that all such efforts are
Too long ...... equally good, it is false. He is, somewhat dis-
Gongula ...... ingenuously, making a rhetorical thrust at
the notion of genius, but no argument or "in-
We need, first, to make the leap between the vestigation" is involved. The artistic element
title and the ellipses by inferring that papy- in the Warhol gesture consists of him doing
rus manuscripts are often in bad condition something that elicits Danto's inferential ca-
and their contents therefore fragmentary. It pacities. Danto makes the leap from dumb
is clever of Pound to have presented us with painting to the idea implied, and that is what
the problem of inferring why the poem is so makes the transaction arty. Warhol is witty
truncated. But we also need to make the leap and Danto gets it.
between what is obviously a very thin love Conceptual art is, to pick up the main
poem (so why publish it?) and Pound's the- thread, a member of the family of artistic cri-
ory that fragments can be expressive, which teria-joining mimesis, expression, and
justifies it. We must infer that he is not set- form-by virtue of its capacity to create op-
ting this work beside Sappho, Catullus, portunities for imaginative inference in a
Dante, Shakespeare, etc., but instead, if we symbolic mode. Thus when Arthur Danto
have the proper theory, we can infer that it is says that "the structure of artworks is, or is
an illustration of his thesis about the expres- very close to the structure of metaphors," he
sive power of the fragment. The poem is a lit- defines all art in terms of the dimension of
tle bit mimetic and expressive, but mostly artistic value that conceptual art cultivates,
conceptual, not as allegory but as an illustra- i.e., the conceptual.37 Danto takes the
tion of a thesis. That Pound is successful enthymeme as a model of what happens
"proves" the thesis, but the poem is good not when we understand a metaphor, and the
because the thesis is true or deep, but be- enthymeme "involves a complex interrela-
cause the words offer a challenge to the tion between the framer and the reader of
imagination to make some plausible infer- the enthymeme. The latter must himself fill
ences that will close the gap opened by its the gap deliberately left open by the for-
puzzling nature. mer."38 Exactly, but the gaps exist in the mi-
A brief digression: I reject the idea that metic, expressive, and formal dimensions, as

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Seamon The Conceptual Dimension in Art 145

well as the conceptual, and so the conceptual Given the fact that works of art tend to be
must take its place with them in the modern stronger in one dimension than another, crit-
theory of artistic value. ical comments usually focus on just one or
As I said earlier, what has happened is that two. Here are three examples that empha-
the dominance of mimesis as the definitive size, respectively, mimesis, expression, and
purpose of art has been challenged by ex- form:
pressive, formalist, and now conceptual theo-
ries. In each case, the challenger tries to dom- He was an astonishing man, was Carle Vernet. His
inate the field but ends up being (justifiably) collected works are a world, a little Comedie
added to what has preceded.39 This means Humaine of their own; for trivial prints, sketches
that the conceptual, as I have understood it of the crowd and the street, and caricatures, often
here, should be added to the mimetic, the ex- constitute the most faithful mirror of life.... Each
pressive, and the formal-the axiological pose and gesture has the accent of truth; each
triad we already have-as a dimension of ar- head and physiognomy is endowed with an au-
tistic value.40 Recognizing the conceptual as thentic style for which many of us can vouch when
an aspect of much art broadens and thus we think of the guests who used to enjoy our fa-
strengthens our sense of what art is. By add- ther's hospitality in the days of our childhood.43
ing the conceptual to the original triad we (i)
acknowledge what has usually been a In Randall Jarrell's comment on some
bastard child in the family of artistic values; poems of Robert Frost, expression is in the
(ii) have our attention drawn to the common foreground:
process of imaginative inference; and (iii)
avoid the revenge of the once-rejected con- Many of these poems are extraordinarily subtle
ceptual sibling on the entire family.41 The and strange, poems which express an attitude that,
theoretical implications of conceptual art at its most extreme, makes pessimism seem a
should neither undermine nor colonize the hopeful evasion; they begin with a flat and terri-
theory of artistic value, but help to take us ble reproduction of the evil in the world and end
closer to a full account. by saying: It's so; and there's nothing you can do
I cannot repeat the case for the centrality about it; and if there were, would you ever do it?44
of the mimetic, expressive, and formal in
both the appraisal and the theory of the arts, Finally, here is a comment of Henry James
but I do want to at least suggest how perva- on the formal incoherence of a painting:
sive they are. Here is a passage from a recent
review of two books on Renaissance art: Though an ambitious picture, this struck us as a
not especially felicitous one; it is a singular con-
In the center of the most beautiful painting by gregation of pieces rapportees. One has a curious
Corregio in the Louvre there is a knot of flesh as sense of having seen the separate parts before, in
intricate and lively as a swimming octopus. It con- some happier association. The eagle and the flag
sists of the left hand of the Virgin Mary delicately (which are rather awkwardly and heavily con-
supporting the slightly smaller right hand of Saint trived) possess, indeed, the merit of originality;
Catherine, while the much smaller hand of the in- but the other things have each an irritating air of
fant Christ tenderly picks out the Saint's ring fin- being a kind of disordered memory of something
ger. This is a miniature example of an effect at else. The young woman's body, her arms, her head,
which Corregio excelled: actions inspired by a the landscape behind her, the sky, are very old
sentiment of breathless intensity are somehow friends; but somehow, on this occasion they are
endowed with angelic grace and with a formal not looking their best. It describes Mr. Gray's pic-
complexity which is delightfully difficult to disen- ture not unjustly, we think, to say it is a superficial
tangle.42 pastiche of Titian.45

The mimetic, expressive, and formal are not As I cannot quote critic after critic to prove
easily disentangled in this description, but this point (how many would it take?), I can
the three dimensions are clearly present. only ask the reader to pick at random some

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
146 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

serious reviews (not interpretive essays) and anything), both literally and metaphorically, what
see if the critic does not focus, with varying it expresses, and what formal features it empha-
emphasis given the work, on the standard sizes.50
triad.
The triad is as pervasive in the philosophy Finally, in The Mirror and the Lamp, the de-
of art as it is in criticism. The case for the cen- finitive account of the shift from the classical
trality of and intimate relationship between to the romantic theory of the arts, Meyer
mimesis, expression, and form has been Abrams organizes art theory from antiquity
made very well and at length, explicitly by to the nineteenth century in terms of four
Iredell Jenkins in Art and the Human Enter- basic orientations: the mimetic, the expres-
prise, who notes that there have been many sive, the objective (my formal), and the prag-
contenders for the title of what art is, but matic.51 Abrams's typology is based on a dia-
gram, with the work of art at the center
in the course of these disputes, three concepts surrounded by artist, world, and audience,
have emerged as leading candidates for the role and these correspond to the objective (for-
of first principle, or basic category of aesthetic mal), the artist (expressive), the world (mi-
theory: these are the notions of imitation, expres- metic), and the audience (pragmatic).52 This
sion, and form. Each of these doctrines has served suggests that the theorists discussed by
as a theme on which numerous variations have Abrams, i.e., just about everyone from antiq-
been played ... but the categories of imitation, ex- uity to 1830, work unself-consciously within
pression, and form have maintained their pri- these fundamental categories.
macy.46 Perhaps the most persuasive evidence for
the significance of the triad is that when a
In Sparshott's The Theory of the Arts, which work is weak in one dimension, we often feel
is our summa aesthetica, the expressive and the need to fill in the dimension that is miss-
formal dimensions are derived from and ing. Faced with a work of art we expect cer-
based on a mimetic foundation. The triad is tain kinds of value and try to make up for
also common in introductions to aesthetics. perceived deficiencies. "Music alone," to use
When George Dickie outlines "Present-Day Peter Kivy's phrase, offers a good example.
Theories of Art" in Aesthetics: An Introduc- Composers often cite experiences that their
tion he begins with "A Modern Beauty The- music is about, listeners find metaphorical
ory of Art," which focuses on Clive Bell's meanings (often by analogy to contending
formalism, and then discusses imitation and and cooperating forces and voices), and the-
expression theories.47 Imitation, expression, orists work hard to find something mimed
and form are also the basis for Anne Shep- (usually feelings or emotions), thereby add-
herd's primer, Aesthetics: An Introduction to ing an (inner) mimetic dimension to a formal
the Philosophy of Art,48 and the triad makes and expressive art. A recent issue of The
an appearance in Robert Stecker's recent Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism con-
book Artworks: tains another such effort, James 0. Young's
"The Cognitive Value of Music."53
Sometimes we enjoy artworks for the expressive The same principle is at work in criticism
properties we perceive in them. Sometimes we of the decorative arts, where it is common to
enjoy artworks because they represent things in look for and "find" mimetic and conceptual
fascinating ways. Sometimes we enjoy artworks meaning. In a chapter entitled "Designs as
for the patterns we perceive in their organiza- Signs" in The Sense of Order, E. H. Gom-
tion.49 brich writes:

In an essay on "Style and Significance in Art From the observation that decorative motifs can
History," Jenefer Robinson says, have a symbolic meaning, it was only too tempt-
ing a step to conclude that all motifs were origi-
As I use the phrase, the term "aesthetic signifi- nally conceived as symbols-though their mean-
cance" encompasses what the work represents (if ing had been lost in the course of history. If that

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Seamon The Conceptual Dimension in Art 147

conclusion was justified a rich harvest beckoned artistic value might seem complacent-a
to the historian who deciphered the symbolism of word of the worldly wise to the innocently
far distant ages.54 astounded-and reductive of an obviously
significant change in the history and theory
To which we might add contemporary less of art, I shall end by saying why I think the
historically-minded interpreters who take change is, in fact, very significant. The appeal
artworks as signs of the personal, political, or of conceptual art and its theory is part of a
collective unconscious. It is most often the major change in the world of art, and the
mimetic and conceptual that is added to for- world generally. The change I have in mind is
mal arts, but the New Critics found underly- the preference for meaning over value, or
ing formal structures (often based on alle- the according of value to making meaning
gorical readings of abstracted images) in rather than artifacts.58 The decline of con-
literary works whose obvious appeal is mi- cern for artistic skill, however broadly con-
metic and expressive. Apropos of this point, ceived, and the rise of theory and interpreta-
Northrop Frye shrewdly notes, tion is a sign of this shift within the
philosophical community. We tend not to
The commenting critic is often prejudiced against ask, as people once did, "How is it done?" or
allegory without knowing the real reason, which is "Is it good?" but rather, "Is it art?" and
that continuous allegory prescribes the direction "What does it mean?" That last question,
of his commentary, and so restricts its freedom.55 often understood as an utterance of the un-
initiated, is emblematic of our general condi-
Interpreters dislike the conceptual dimen- tion. We produce numerous handbooks on
sion, since they want to make their own (cre- how to interpret rather than how to make.
ative, not cooperative) contributions. Posit- Speaking emblematically, Brooks's and War-
ing deep meanings makes gaps between ren's handbook of interpretation, Under-
image and concept, and interpretation fills standing Poetry, replaces Aristotle's Poetics,
them with "inferences" (really, in this case, which is concerned with making not mean-
inventions). ing. When meaning overshadows making as
Allegorical interpretation has been the the source of value, the artists go "thinky"
conceptual companion of narrative since an- and the interpreters become prominent
tiquity, but it is applicable to any art.56 The -which is just what has happened. Thus
academic version of the triumph of the con- Robert Stecker speaks of our emphasis on
ceptual in our century is the proliferation of "interpretation-centered value" and says
interpretation, which adds a symbolic di- that "especially in our soon-to-be-concluded
mension to whatever it encounters, and the century, literature has come to be valued
relation of this to my main theme is sug- precisely in virtue of the fact that it invites,
gested by Frye's observation that "it is not indeed, requires interpretation."59 Gerald
often realized that all commentary is allegor- Graff has made a related point about the im-
ical interpretation, an attaching of ideas to plications of interpretation as the goal of ac-
the structure of poetic imagery."57 In other ademic criticism: "The very stockpiling of
words, interpreters normally attach a con- competing explications came to seem a
ceptual dimension to works that are them- prima facie proof of a work's complexity and
selves aesthetic, i.e., perceptual, and whose therefore its value."60 This, of course, applies
value has been independently established on to conceptual art with appropriate ven-
that ground, thus filling in a missing band in geance, and for a large segment of the col-
the spectrum of artistic evaluation. Critics lege-educated population works of art (and
thus acknowledge by implication the central- not just, or perhaps now even primarily,
ity of the mimetic, expressive, formal, and works of fine art) have displaced the Bible as
conceptual dimensions of art. We should, I the main focus of hermeneutic attention.
conclude, join them. Stecker follows the observation just quoted
Since my domestication of the conceptual with the statement that "this is puzzling" and
by integrating it into the modern theory of explains it by saying that such a view "invites

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
148 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

us to be creative, to participate in creating fine art historically (Levinson) and historically-func-


tionally (Stecker), and to nondefine it narratively
(completing) a work."161 True, but that is not
(Carroll), are motivated by the challenge of conceptual
new. We often forget that students once art only insofar as each is meant to replace theories gen-
made poems, not interpretations, as part of erated by the avant-garde. See Jerrold Levinson, "De-
their education. Students who are asked to fining Art Historically," in Music, Arts, and Metaphysics:
interpret poems-rather than write imita- Essays in Philosophical Aesthetics (Cornell University
Press, 1990), Robert Stecker, "Historical Functional-
tions of them-are being silently inducted
ism," in Artworks: Definition, Meaning, Value (Pennsyl-
into the now-dominant view that art means vania State University Press, 1997), and Noel Carroll,
rather than that artists make.62 That, in turn, "Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art," The
strongly influences what artists then do; thus Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (1993):
313-326. Here, as so often in this paper, I must paint
we get the very intellectual fine art of our
with a very broad brush. Danto, like others I shall refer
day, in which the conceptual dimension is so to, is emblematic of what he is commonly taken to mean.
strongly emphasized. The relationship of the In fact Danto's theory is now mimetic (i.e., referential),
ascent of the conceptual to social reality bor- since he claims that works of art are about things, al-
ders on what is now a commonplace, that though not (necessarily) by means of representations.
This thesis was already implicit in The Transfiguration
knowledge and ideas are today the distinc-
of the Commonplace and is explicit in After the End of
tive and increasingly important forms of cap- Art. For commentary on this see Noel Carroll, "Danto's
ital. The radical implications for theory that New Definition of Art and the Problem of Art The-
derived from conceptual art were the ories," The British Journal of Aesthetics 37 (1997):
artworld expression of a tendency that per- 386-392.
6. Arthur Danto, "From Aesthetics to Art Criticism
vades our culture, and while I have ques-
and Back," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
tioned whether conceptual art ought to 54 (1996): 106.
make us rethink aesthetics, I do not underes-7. Sparshott, The Theory of the Arts, p. 199.
timate its import. I might also add that the 8. That art theory makes self-conscious what was im-
thread that I claim ties together the tetrad of plicit in earlier practices is one of the themes of Harold
Osborne's Aesthetics and Art Theory (New York: E. P.
mimesis, expression, form, and the concep- Dutton, 1970), p. 23 et passim. Osborne's candidate for
tual, the notion of imaginative inference, it- the aesthetic is formalism, but, as I point out below, the
self emphasizes-but only emphasizes-the thesis applies to mimesis and expression as well.
cognitive in art and so, like conceptual art 9. E. H. Gombrich, Art and Illusion (Princeton Uni-
versity Press, 1960), p. 299.
and its theory, bears the mark of its time.63
10. Lewis Beck White, "Judgments of Meaning in
Art," in Contemporary Aesthetics, ed. Matthew Lipman
ROGER SEAMON (Boston: Allyn and Bacon, 1973), p. 184. Originally pub-
lished in The Journal of Philosophy 41 (1944): 169-178.
Department of English
11. It is sometimes claimed that poetry offers a
University of British Columbia counterexample to aesthetic, or perceptual, theories of
Vancouver, British Columbia V6T 1W5 art. However, Sparshott makes the point that "it is as in-
Canada telligible structures that literary works exist; but, as
seemed not to be the case with the chess problem, the
exact order of the intelligible components as perceived
INTERNET: rseamon@interchange.ubc.ca is of the essence of the form" (The Theory of the Arts, p.
199). In other words, in contrast to poems, "chess prob-
1. Francis Sparshott, The Theory of the Arts (Prince- lems, like mathematical proofs, have an order that in no
ton University Press, 1982), p. 199. way depends on any sensory medium or any
2. Timothy Binkley, "Piece: Contra Aesthetics," in spatiotemporal order in which they may be set out"
Philosophy Looks at the Arts: Contemporary Readings (ibid.).
in Aesthetics, 3rd ed., ed. Joseph Margolis (Temple 12. Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art: An Ap-
Universiy Press, 1987), p. 81. The essay originally ap- proach to the Theory of Symbols (Indianapolis:
peared in The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 Bobbs-Merrill, 1968), pp. 252 and 136.
13. Ibid., p. 136.
(1977): 265-277.
3. George Dickie, Aesthetics: An Introduction (India- 14. I say "loosely" because not any appearances will
napolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1971), p. 105. do. For example, Duchamp's choice of a urinal turned
out to be unhappily ambiguous: "Even members of
4. Ibid., p. 101. This is an early formulation of a theory
that became much more sophisticated. Duchamp's immediate circle, like Walter Arensberg,
5. "The Artworld," in Art and Its Significance:An An- thought Duchamp was drawing attention to the white
thology of Aesthetic Theory, 3rd ed., ed. Stephen David gleaming beauty of the urinal. But in 1962 Duchamp
Ross (SUNY Press, 1994), p. 479. Recent efforts to de- wrote to Hans Richter: 'When I discovered ready-

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Seamon The Conceptual Dimension in Art 149

mades I thought to discourage aesthetics.... I threw the nize the distinction between poems and arguments con-
bottle rack and the urinal in their faces as a challenge ducted in images. The latter are amazingly
and now they admire them for their aesthetic beauty."' opaque-until explained, at which point the images dis-
(The passage is from Danto, "From Aesthetics to Art appear and the ideas remain. It is disheartening to tell
Criticism and Back," pp. 106-107.) But is it not the case the writer that this is not poetry at all. Contrast that with
that the appearance of artworks can change quite drasti- the student who plays with sounds and meanings and
cally without seriously impairing our sense of their na- has a rhythmic knack.
ture and value? I cannot go into detail on this issue. The 25. E. H. Gombrich, The Sense of Order: A Study in
main point here is that even when the appearance the Psychology of Decorative Art (Cornell University
changes, as for example in the case of the Parthenon, we Press, 1979), p. 9.
are still interested in the appearances, not the relation- 26. Sparshott, The Theory of the Arts, p. 122. George
ship between some object and a concept. They loved the Steiner says in Errata (London: Weidenfeld and
color and formal perfection, we appreciate the stark Nicolson, 1997), p. 20, that "any motion of meaning in
fragments. human utterance or expression will occur ... between
15. Richard M. Price. Review of Kazimir Malevich convention and anarchy, between cliche and creation,"
and the Art of Geometry (museum exhibit), The British which would mean that the unity in variety formula, of
Journal of Aesthetics 38 (October 1998): 430. which these notions are a variation, is not special to art.
16. Binkley, "Piece Contra Ethics," p. 82. The difference might be that in philosophy, for example,
17. Ibid., p. 86. one must be original, but not too original, in relationship
18. I shall adopt this term to refer very broadly to all to what went before. Philosophers are engaged in a dia-
cases in which there is on one side an image and on the logue or conversation. In most art, however, the unity
other a concept. Allegory is a form of symbolism, and and variety is largely internal to the work, for while
critics often use the term metaphor as the equivalent of some artworks are explicitly responses to earlier ones
symbol; thus, "the sea in Hart Crane's poetry is a meta- (the most common example would be parody), most are
phor for eternity." not.
19. Bernard Bosanquet, History of Aesthetic (New 27. See Kendall Walton, Mimesis as Make-Believe:
York: Meridian Books, 1957), p. 143 (emphasis added). On the Foundations of the Representational Arts (Har-
First edition published 1932. Bosanquet does not mean vard University Press, 1990) for this modern version of
that the motif must be beautiful, but that the work must the play theory of art. As Walton's theory is primarily
be judged on the basis of appearances. Art is less than cognitive, it fits well with my notion of imaginative in-
skin deep. ference. Here is another example of the leap, although
20. Ibid., p. 159. The current prejudice in favor of now it is from illusion to the "reality" of which the illu-
meaning and against "mere" naturalism is clearly ex- sion is made: "Not only is nothing in her [Cindy
pressed by David Carrier in his essay on "Naturalism Sherman's] pictures what it seems to be at an overex-
and Allegory in Flemish Painting," The Journal of Aes- cited first glance; it is always patently something else. In
thetics and Art Criticism 45 (1987): 239: "Allegorical in- her Old Master portraits, initially ravishing 'lace,' 'silk,'
terpretations make paintings seem more deeply mean- 'brocade,' and other sumptuous materials quickly con-
ingful than do earlier naturalistic descriptions." They do fess to being so many shoddy, Fourteenth Street
not, however, make paintings seem more meaningful to schmattes. They could not fool anyone. And yet at the
Bosanquet and Browning. outset they gull us all. Such is the might of fully imag-
21. Ibid., p. 158. ined fiction. We seize upon the illusion, however attenu-
22. Roger Seamon, "Guided Rapid Unconscious Re- ated. Then comes the echt Sherman moment, when the
configuration in Poetry and Art," Philosophy and Liter- illusion collapses. We are left foundering in the back-
ature 20 (1996): 415. I might want to drop the "rapid," wash of our suddenly absurd credulity. Now what?"
but that does not alter the basic point. In fact, the notion (Peter Schjeldahl, "Valley of the Dolls: Cindy
of rapidity connects such gap-leaping to the idea of Sherman's Return to Form," The New Yorker [June 7,
'seeing as," which also seems to involve pace; if one 1999], p. 95.)
needs to have something explained, the zest is more or 28. What are other sources? For example, we want
less gone. But I do want to emphasize here that in the the content in mimetic works to be about what concerns
encounter with any even mildly complex work, one will us, and we want the artist's attitude to that to be appro-
not get it all at once. The term inference puts the whole priate-if that is not too pale a word for what is often
thing into slow motion. crucial to our appraisal. The artist who writes about
23. The distinction is clearly not absolute; imaginative death seriously takes a big chance for correspondingly
inference occurs in outside art, and logic can play a part big returns. There is, however, always something happily
in works of art, especially poetry. There is, of course, an imaginative in good art, which is why the Holocaust is
indefinite number of ways in which an artwork can be problematic as a subject. Tragedy is, one might say, one
valued, and it is not only in art that imaginative infer- solution to the problem of how to make art out of what
ence is elicited. The most common form is perhaps is terrible. As an admirer of the recent movie Life Is
irony, and that obviously is a pervasive part of commu- Beautiful, I would say that in it Roberto Benigni does
nication. My argument is only that imaginative infer- for the Holocaust what "Cinderella" does for stepmoth-
ence seems to be concentrated in the arts. ers, i.e., uses fantasy to acknowledge the terrors through
24. Anyone who has read the complexly metaphori- imagined overcoming. Bruno Bettelheim's The Uses of
cal arguments that young poets often write will recog- Enchantment: The Meaning and Importance of

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
150 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Fairy-Tales develops this theme, and Norman Holland value, on the other hand, is not assessed solely on the
generalizes it to all literature in The Dynamics of Liter- basis of the visual, internal properties of the picture"
ary Response, still, in my view, one of the best theories of ("The Artistic and the Aesthetic Value of Art," The
literature, although Holland himself has since rejected British Journal of Aesthetics 21 [1981]: 338). While cer-
it. tain works of conceptual art were innovative, and thus
29. That expresses a strong prejudice. Some people have Kulka's "artistic" value, almost all do not. They are
seem quite happily indifferent to getting what was in- simply new occasions for imaginative inference in the
tended, as long as they get something. I would argue that conceptual dimension, and thus take their place beside
they are not on intimate terms with the art. But that is other "normal" works that do not possess Kulka's artis-
another issue. tic value. Conceptual art is now a form of normal art.
30. To use the fashionable term, there is a synergy be- The problem for artists and the source of confusion for
tween natural significance and allegorical meaning. The theorists is that conceptual art is-or seems to
former "thickens" the latter, and the latter connects the be-avant-garde art, and such art ought to be radically
former to reality and thus gives it the "weight" of refer- innovative each time, an impossible imperative. Varia-
ence. tion within a convention is all that can be expected, even
31. I discuss below other ways that conceptual art when greater claims are made, but of course there is al-
leads to imaginative inference. ways the unexpected.
32. Blake Gopnik, "Clothes Come out of the Closet" 41. Pursuing the metaphor, I would say that mimesis
[review of Giant Pink Party Frock], The Globe and Mail is the parthenogenetic parent that now must accept its
(September 27, 1998): C7. place alongside its progeny, although they should ac-
33. A wonderful passage from Rabelais reminds us knowledge who came first and gave birth.
that without serious content the game of allegorical in- 42. Nicholas Penny, "Why is Christ Playing with the
terpretation will not work. At the very end of Book I, "A Magdalene's Hair?" London Review of Books (1998):
Prophetic Riddle" is found inscribed in the foundations 18.
of an abbey, and Gargantua offers a serious interpreta- 43. Charles Baudelaire, The Mirror of Art: Critical
tion, to which a monk replies: "You can read all the alle- Studies by Charles Baudelaire, ed. and trans. Jonathan
gorical and serious meanings into it that you like, and Mayne (Garden City, NJ: Doubleday Anchor Books,
dream on about it, you and all the world, as much as 1956), p. 154.
ever you will. For my part, I don't think there is any 44. Randall Jarrell, Poetry and the Age (New York:
other sense concealed in it than the description of a Vintage Books, 1959), pp. 27-28.
game of tennis wrapped up in strange language," which 45. Henry James, The Painter's Eye: Notes and Essays
he proceeds, hilariously, to set forth. (The Histories of on the Pictorial Arts, ed. John L. Sweeney (London:
Gargantua and Pantagruel, trans. J. M. Cohen Rupert Hart-Davis, 1956), p. 94.
[Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1955], p. 163.) 46. Iredell Jenkins, "Aesthetic Education and Moral
34. Harold Rosenberg, The De-Definition of Art Refinement," The Journal of Aesthetic Education 2
(New York: Collier, 1972), p. 35. (1968): 23.
35. There are, of course, works like Tom Stoppard's 47. Dickie, Aesthetics: An Introduction, pp. 69-94.
Professional Foul, which are primarily arguments in the 48. Anne Shepherd, Aesthetics: An Introduction to the
usual sense, but they are quite rare. Philosophy of Art (New York: Oxford University Press,
36. Danto, "From Aesthetics to Art Criticism and 1987).
Back," pp. 110-111. There is a parallel between the ba- 49. Stecker, Artworks, p. 36.
nality or falsity of Warhol's thesis and the commonplace 50. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40
themes that are implied in literary works and even, (1981). Note also that Robinson's "metaphorically" is at
many argue, in music. (See, for example, Graham the least very close to what I am calling the conceptual
McFee, "Meaning and the Art-Status of 'Music Alone'," dimension of works of art, i.e., a conceptual meaning
The British Journal of Aesthetics 37 [1997]: 31-46.) that we must infer.
These themes are, in themselves, of little interest. What 51. The pragmatic refers to the effects of art, and that
is important is the leap the audience makes between ob- mostly includes what is often placed under the expres-
ject and theme. That death takes us all is about as banal sive. It does not refer primarily to art with a social pur-
as a thought can be, but to make the inference, seem- pose.
ingly for the first time, drives the point home anew. 52. The triad has recently made three more appear-
37. Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, ances, first in James W. Manns's Aesthetics (London:
p. 173. Sharpe, 1998), which was reviewed by Rende Lorraine
38. Ibid., p. 170. in the winter 1999 issue of the ASA Newsletter 18 (no.3).
39. Something like this story is found in the opening Lorraine writes: "Aesthetics is composed of chapters on
paragraphs of Carroll's "Historical Narratives and the ontology, representation,form, expression, intention, and
Philosophy of Art." taste" (p. 4, emphasis added). The other topics are not
40. I need to distinguish my effort to add the concep- sources of value in art but philosophical issues raised by
tual to the set of values in art from Thomas Kulka's ad- the arts. The triad comes up again in a review of Alan
dition of what he calls the "artistic" to the "aesthetic." Goldman's Aesthetic Value: "Our ordinary concept of
Kulka argues that "aesthetic value can be considered as art, we are reminded, is evaluative. To call something a
something which pertains to the visual qualities of the work of art is to suggest it is worth contemplation. Re-
picture" (338), whereas "the artistic, or art-historical cent institutional and historical theories of art ignore

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Seamon The Conceptual Dimension in Art 151

this value component. The author is surely right about yond the Word-Image Opposition (Cambridge: Cam-
this. Traditional theories, e.g., representation, expression, bridge University Press, 1991). The practice was
and formalism, defined art in terms of aesthetic value, ubiquitous, although always contested, in antiquity,
but did not always explain why their defining features where the Greek term for it was allegoresis.
were valuable" (B. H. Tilghman, The Journal of Aesthet- 57. Frye, Anatomy of Criticism, p. 89.
ics and Art Criticism 57 [1999]: 81, emphasis added). 58. Philip Roth's recent novel American Pastoral is, in
And in a review of another recent introduction, M. E. part, a requiem for a culture of making. The hero and
Sharpe's Aesthetics, Gordon Graham writes: "The book the hero's father, admirable types, are glove manufac-
begins with a short discussion of the difficulties attend- turers, and the making and appreciation of gloves is lov-
ing the definition of art ... and then proceeds to an in- ingly described. The rebellious daughter is, in contrast,
formed and thoughtful examination of three large and caught up in meanings, many meanings and not nice
recurrent themes-representation, form, and expres- ones.
sion" (The British Journal of Aesthetics 39 [1999]: 59. Stecker, Artworks, p. 302.
204-205, emphasis added). 60. Professing Literature: An Institutional History
53. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (University of Chicago Press, 1988), p. 228.
(1999): 41-54. 61. Ibid., p. 303.
54. The Sense of Order: A Study in the Psychology of 62. MacLeish's "A poem should not mean but be" is
Decorative Art (Cornell University Press, 1979), p. 218. very confusing. For the idea that poems just "are," and
Note the similarity between Gombrich's and do not wear their meaning (their purpose) on their face,
Bosanquet's skeptical attitudes to the "richness" of is precisely what leads to the need for interpretation.
symbolism. Gombrich, however, is talking about aca- 63. I would like to thank those who commented on
demic extravagances, whereas Bosanquet is missing a earlier versions of this essay at meetings of the Cana-
pleasure. dian Society for Aesthetics and the Pacific Division of
55. Northrop Frye, Anatomy of Criticism: Four Essays the American Society for Aesthetics. I am especially
(Princeton University Press, 1957), p. 90. grateful to the reviewer for this journal, whose criticisms
56. For an egregious contemporary example of sym- were right on the mark.
bolic reading, see Mieke Bal, Reading Rembrandt: Be-

This content downloaded from


45.5.167.198 on Fri, 19 Apr 2024 03:44:14 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like