You are on page 1of 14

Modern Art Theories

Author(s): Christopher Williams


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , Autumn, 1998, Vol. 56, No. 4
(Autumn, 1998), pp. 377-389
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/432128

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CHRISTOPHER WILLIAMS

Modern Art Theories

The ancient doctrine that artworks are imitative theory, bad news for the other, or-as I think
or capture likenesses has been widely denied, most likely-bad news for both.
and by aestheticians who are thought to hold
sharply contrasting views about the nature of
art. Two of these views are of particular interest
to me. The first is formalism, or one of the views The view that modernism (which for my pur-
that can be called formalism, which maintains poses may include postmodernism) is thought to
that artworks qua artworks are void of all repre- threaten may be called the picture conception of
sentational content and consist in mere patterns art. Differing accounts of what makes some-
of line and color that please us on a direct in- thing a picture can be given, but I will take the
spection. The second (and currently much more concept of a picture for granted; what matters
discussed) view is that artworks differ from here is the relation of pictures to art, and whether
mere physical objects by virtue of an invisible there are genuine, tenable alternatives to the pic-
art-making property, namely, an identification ture conception. That the standing credentials of
that an artist makes whereby a physical object the picture conception are unexpectedly strong
acquires a representational content. For the sake is the topic I begin with; and I wish to make
of terminological symmetry, and to distinguish three claims about that conception, and a fourth
it from other positions, I shall call this second about art.
view invisibilism-which should not be taken (i) The picture conception does a quite cred-
to suggest that artworks themselves are invisi- itable job of covering a very large number of ar-
ble, but only that the art-making property can- tifacts we think of as works of visual art. Most
not be discerned in the visible physical object. paintings and sculptures, whether they are tradi-
If we think about the overall history of art, tional or modern, Western or non-Western, are
formalism and invisibilism look counterintu- naturally described as pictures or as having a
itive. But these views were motivated by devel- pictorial character. This observation is espe-
opments in modern art, and these views can cially worth making in connection with modern
look more promising against that background. art, which affords us works by Matisse, Picasso,
They are modern art theories, to use a term that Mir6, Magritte, Kahlo, O'Keeffe, Hockney, and
is calculatedly ambiguous between theories of many, many other undisputed picture makers.
modem art and modern theories of art. I want to Modernism also affords plenty of hard cases,
sort this ambiguity out, to understand the philo- and I shall say more about these later, but their
sophical impact that modern art should have on existence should not obscure the plethora of
our thinking, and to argue that insofar as the tractable cases.
case against the ancient doctrine relies on his- (ii) If we accept the picture conception, we
torical premises the case is far from conclusive. are hardly committed to thinking that any pic-
We shall also see that formalism and invisi- ture whatsoever is an artwork. In this sentence
bilism have more in common than we might "an artwork" can have two meanings, one de-
have supposed. Depending on one's perspective, scriptive and one normative, and it is only the
their common ground can be good news for one normative that I want. However, we should first

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56:4 Fall 1998

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
378 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

distinguish, in a somewhat idealized manner, other light entirely by thinking about corre-
the two meanings. To call something an artwork sponding claims for science.
may be to say that an artifact was made under If we wanted to, we could say that one "the-
the concept of art, however well or poorly it suc- ory of science" holds that the task of science is to
ceeds aesthetically or artistically. Or it may be ascertain, via some theoretical apparatus, causal
to say that an artifact has, or comes to have, the or other regularities that unaided observation
values characteristic of art, however it was does not disclose to us. But why should we want
made. (Any view about art is given the best runto? This "theory" again does not tell us any-
for its money with the second meaning, since thing we did not already know, and we can
that meaning helps to shift attention away from scarcely imagine any rival theories that could
flawed, unsatisfying works and also to weaken take its place without changing the subject. To
any tendency to acquiesce in historically paro- be sure, there are controversies about the ratio-
chial understandings of the artifacts that can fall nality of scientific procedures and the differ-
under the concept of art.) ences between science and pseudoscience, the
Now a child's drawing, on many reckonings, status of theoretical entities, the best way to
is not an artwork in the normative sense, whereas understand theory change, and so forth, but
a painting by Vermeer is. Both are pictures. Yet these controversies concern-or only fruitfully
we need not suppose that the difference between concern2-particular cases in science. They
the Vermeer and the child's drawing is to be arise against a background in which the nature
sought in some additional, extrapictorial ingre- of science itself is fixed, and must be fixed if the
dient that only the Vermeer has; instead we controversies are to be intelligible.
could suppose that the difference merely has to It would be more than surprising to have a
do with its being the kind of picture that it is. bona fide theory of science, and it is not obvious
The Vermeer illuminates some aspect of its sub- why the situation with art should be any differ-
ject (to use a natural idiom) as the child's draw- ent. But someone could insist that the situation
ing does not. And so we might think that a pic- has to be strikingly different because of the way,
ture becomes an artwork when it proves to be for instance, in which our appreciations of vari-
peculiarly revelatory of its subject-perhaps ous artworks relate to each other. Once Cezanne
revelatory in the way that only a picture, as op-is recognized to have artistic merit, our appreci-
posed to a verbal description, can be. Clearly, ation of Duccio need not, and presumably should
more would have to be said about "revelation," not, be discredited.3 Yet oxygen-theory does in-
but it is at least worth remarking that the notion terestingly displace phlogiston-theory. And so,
of artistic beauty (to use an old-fashioned if we are not to be perplexed, it might seem that
idiom) could be explicated by this means. a theoretical apparatus for limning the general
(iii) The picture conception need not-in my shape of art is necessary for our understanding
view, should not-be thought of as a theory of of art, while a theoretical need does not exert the
art (in such expressions as "Plato's imitation same pressure where our understanding of sci-
theory"). For it could-in my view, should-be ence is concerned.
regarded as a basic framework in which we de- This conjecture is mistaken. The problem is
bate about the inclusion or exclusion of individ- that there are two levels of possible perplexity in
ual artifacts rather than as an object of debate in the Cezanne-Duccio pairing, and one level is
its own right. 1 The whole of this essay is needed too abstract for a general question of art to gain
to make all of this large claim plausible, but the a foothold and the other is not abstract enough.
following reflection is a start. If the picture con- The first level is occupied if we ask how an ap-
ception is a "theory," it does not really explain preciation of Cezanne can coexist peacefully
anything at all, but merely registers what is ut- with an appreciation of Duccio.4 The right an-
terly obvious about the majority of artworks that swer is that excellence comes in many varieties,
we know. To label Mrs. Siddons a picture is not that we are equipped to appreciate them all, and
to theorize about the painting, save in a mislead- that there need not be any onus to reduce one
ingly grandiose sense. This reflection is quite kind to any other. This claim would have to be
simple-too simple, one might fear. To show elaborated and defended, but notice that we
that it need not be so, let us put the matter in an-
have left the notion of art well behind us. If the

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Williams Modern Art Theories 379

peaceful coexistence of Cezanne and Duccio is a most elementary recognitions of particular in-
problem, much the same problem arises for our stances. Yet perceivers are able to identify art-
admiration of Pericles and Lincoln as statesmen. works. The old story about the grapes that
Yet a theory of statesmanly virtue is not needed Zeuxis sculpted and the birds took to be real is a
in order to make our understanding of that phe- most meager resource for philosophy: birds, and
nomenon, the joint admiration, satisfactory.5 people, do not usually mistake a sculpture for
The second level of perplexity is occupied if we food, and when they do, they are usually fools or
ask how it is that we (can) admire Cezanne, on the juveniles, not innocently gulled adults, because
assumption that we already admire Duccio, or vice artworks generally look quite different from
versa. Here the solution is to find an obliging critic, other, nonart objects in which perceivers have
someone with the knack of describing Cezanne's an interest. The occasional trompe l'oeil detail
work in such a way as to help make the scales fall in a work does not disturb this conclusion, in
from our resistant eyes. The critic's offices may be part because wholesale illusionism must be un-
in vain-a familiar point-but the point to make common in art if the concept of art is to be use-
here is that criticism is the only means we have ful, in part because illusion extends to only a
for doing anything about perplexity at this level. portion of any work.
And criticism of particular artworks is not the This last point can be expanded. It is some-
same as general theorizing about art, unless we times suggested that Renaissance artists aspired
just beg all the relevant questions. to create illusions by depicting objects in linear
I suspect that only if we conflate these two perspective. If true, this claim would help to
levels will we think that the Cezanne-Duccio make the nature of art seem problematic, if only
pairing creates a need for an authentic theory of on the picture conception. However, it is not
art, and I shall try to strengthen incredulity re- true. Suppose we say that there is indeed an il-
garding this need as we go along. Let us just lusion of the third dimension in the ideal-limit
note now that if a ground-floor theory of art is Renaissance painting, the Albertian window: it
as vacuous as a ground-floor theory of science, is simply a fallacy to infer from the illusion of
then the aspect-revealing picture conception depth to an illusion about the objects depicted in
would seem to be the most promising candidate that depth, and there is no reason to think that
for being the analogue of the regularity-reveal- the depicted objects would take us in. Hence
ing theory conception of science.6 there is no problem arising from considerations
(iv) My fourth claim requires a little stage of illusion with art on the picture conception.
setting. We shall have trouble accepting both the Nor does art become more problematic in the
claim that the picture conception is not a theory twentieth century (and this position can be held
and the claim that no theory of art is needed at even if we do not accept the picture conception).
the ground floor if we think that our cognitive Only a few would confuse a Rothko with an
relationship encounters special hardships be- accidentally painted canvas that a centrifuge
cause the nature of art is intrinsically problem- might produce. Much of the reason is that the
atic. The claim is that there are no special hard- probabilities are extremely low that a random
ships of this sort. process would yield Rothko's subtleties. We
The nature of art would be problematic at the may worry that the mere (and logically undis-
base, and insolubly so, if we assigned to art in- missable) possibility of a "centrifuge Rothko" is
compatible characterizations, as we do with the enough to problematize the nature of art spe-
protagonist of the barber paradox, who was said cially; but this would be a hasty judgment, be-
to shave all and only those men who did not cause if the example reveals anything it reveals
shave themselves. But nobody has suggested that unlikely contingencies can always occur.
that art is like this, and in any event those clam- And so a worry here would just be the far more
orous for theory want a manageable problem, general one about epistemological skepticism.
one that a theory could treat. Now we would Again, art has been left behind: the skeptical
have some justification for their pessimistic as- worry has here an illustration picturesquely in-
sessment and hope for the proposed cure if the volving art, but an illustration to the same effect
nature of art were such that we were unable to could be made with anything else. Hence there
identify artworks by sight, unable to make the is no special problem.

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
380 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Still, confusions between modernist works and will, of Cezanne or Warhol, and that accepting
mere physical things can occur, but as with the these artifacts as artworks at the time makes our
grapes of Zeuxis, they can be easily explained standing conception of art uncouth.9
through the perceiver's inexperience or impa- Unusual artworks can certainly prompt retail
tience (a more significant factor for modernist changes in our thinking about art. Cezanne may
than for traditional art), or again, in the rela- lead us to question whether a picture might show
tively rare and exceptional instance through more by containing less detail than a convention-
the playful idiosyncrasies of a particular work. ally realistic picture does; Warhol, how much
The newness in appearance of modernist work mechanicality the art-making process can as-
may mean that the necessary experience for the similate and still yield an artwork. But such
perceiver takes longer to come by, but that may changes as these need not dislodge the picture
be all. As with more traditional art, the phenom- conception. So how exactly could the experi-
enon of isolated confusions hardly forces us to ments or faits accomplis of the avant-garde have
conclude that this art, or our conceptual relation- the wholesale revisionary implications that ei-
ship to it, poses peculiar internal difficulties. ther formalism or invisibilism envisage? In this
Perhaps it will be said that this reply fails to section and the next I want to consider spelled-
show due appreciation for the context of intro- out attempts to answer this question.
duction for modernist works. When modernist One way of interpreting wholesale revision-
works made their debut, according to this objec- ism is crude on the face of it, but its very crudity
tion, they were so new and strange that recogni- makes it a useful starting point. We may think
tion of them was not easy. So (to continue) it is of this attempted answer as the revolutionary in-
one thing to recognize that Rothko's pieces are terpretation of the avant-garde, and it says that
artworks after the community has digested their the nature of art is simply transformed by what
achievement, but quite another to be present at avant-garde artists do (or have done). To sim-
the creation, and to grasp them as artworks at plify things, we could say that artists made pic-
that time. To counterreply, it is quite unclear tures before 1910, and that their pictures were
why we should attach so much importance to artworks too, but that after 1910, and for what-
the first viewers' perplexed responses as to sup- ever reason, artists made formal patterns in-
pose that a theory of art must be addressed, as it stead, which in the new dispensation qualify as
were, to them. But let us suppose, for the sake of artworks and uniquely qualify. 10 Thus, a Rothko
argument, that it should be so addressed, and go appearing before 1910 might in hindsight be re-
on to ask how a theory could help those viewers garded as prescient, but it would not be an art-
and how we are to understand the help. work, and for the same reason that a Vermeer
appearing afterwards would be a mere historical
II souvenir but not an artwork either. A similar
revolutionary narrative could then be told about
The formalist Clive Bell, writing in 1914, at- the displacement of formalism in (to simplify
tempted to vindicate the work of Cezanne be- once more) 1960. This last remark reveals that it
fore a world that was still largely unreceptive to is possible, on the revolutionary interpretation,
that work, and propounded a theory of art for both formalism and invisibilism to be true
within which a more comprehending reception theories at different times. I I As theories of mod-
for Cezanne and other postimpressionists could ern art, they become, for one art-historical mo-
be effortlessly secured.7 Half a century later, in ment, applicable theories of art in general.
1964, the invisibilist Arthur Danto attempted The revolutionary interpretation is unappeal-
something similar when philosophers (presumed ing because it divides the history of art into
to be baffled) invited him to make sense of discrete, conceptually unrelated segments, and it
Warhol, a more advanced (or more adventurous) is not at all clear how we can tell anything
modernist.8 The provocative idea animating grander than a bare causal story about the rela-
these projects is that our thinking about art-not tions between the segments. This result is unap-
individual works but art itself-should change pealing from a less speculative perspective as
profoundly, somehow, because of the experi- well, because of a related difficulty that con-
ments, or faits accomplis, call them what we fronts us in whatever post-revolutionary space

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Williams Modern Art Theories 381

we occupy as spectators. For it is not clear that tion has its point only if those spectators felt in
pre-revolutionary art can be art for us, can be some inarticulate way that the mystifying arti-
anything more than an historical souvenir itself, facts were artworks after all, albeit ones which
unless it coincidentally makes sense under the they were unable to appreciate. (Their denials
terms of the new dispensation. And yet our ex- are charitably construed as exaggerated admis-
perience of art suggests that subsequent artistic sions of a natural frustration.) The irritation
developments frequently deepen our apprecia- passed, if it passed at all, by viewing and re-
tion of past achievements, and this is contrary to viewing the works, perhaps accompanied by
what the revolutionary interpretation would lead pointers, which sympathetic others supplied, on
us to expect. These objections seem decisive. how to look at the works.
The revolutionary interpretation nevertheless Now let us suppose that the painting is felt not
acquires an air of greater plausibility, but only to be art. We then have a problem characterizing
an air, if we suppose, as Danto did, that there is the puzzlement that we have: the painting is not
an analogy between recalcitrant observational a puzzling artwork (by hypothesis), but we do
phenomena, which (new) scientific theories ex- have to be puzzled by it nonetheless in order to
plain, and recalcitrantly avant-garde works, which justify the importation of the enlightening the-
(new) theories of art explain. But the analogy is ory. So we will have to say that the painting is
confused. A theory of art tells us what the gen- aesthetically puzzling in some way, where "aes-
eral character of art is, whereas a scientific the- thetically" does not carry the more restricted
ory merely explains the particular phenomena implications of "artistically." But there are no art-
that fall within the purview of the theory. To independent aesthetic anomalies that theories of
think, on the basis of the analogy, that an avant- art can target and remove. We never find our-
garde work could trigger a revision in our con- selves in a predicament where we would say,
ception of art would thus be akin to thinking "This artifact is aesthetically puzzling-would
that the switch from the Ptolemaic to the Coper- it be less so if we thought of it as an artwork, if
nican theory of the solar system could trigger a we revised our conception of art so that it un-
corresponding revision in our conception of problematically instantiated the concept?" And
what science does. To have a proper analogy even if we thought we were in this predicament,
with a scientific theory we require not a theory the justification of any theory intended to ac-
of art but an "artistic theory," which ostensibly commodate the artifact would be unabashedly
shows how a puzzling C6zanne painting, for ex- circular.
ample, need not puzzle us. There are no artistic I am not suggesting that there are absolutely
theories,12 nor any reason to think a theory of no independent aesthetic perplexities: we might
art could be called upon to do its job. be pleased, for example, by the appearance of a
The force of this claim can be brought out by certain object, despite its odd colors or the re-
means of a dilemma. Either the puzzling paint- pellent materials of which it is composed, and
ing is already felt to be an artwork indepen- our pleasure may, in that light, mystify us. But
dently of a theory or it is not. If the painting is surely the solution here lies just in getting ac-
already felt to be an artwork, then a theory is customed to the object (that is, to the organic
useless, since we wanted the theory to make the whole that comprises separately displeasing
painting intelligible as an instantiation of the parts), not in supplying a theory. For insofar as
concept. On this horn of the dilemma, the puz- an aesthetic puzzle is genuinely independent of
zlement we have can be expressed as follows: the art concept, a theory of art will pass the puz-
"How, given that this artifact is felt to be art or zle by.
to be assessable as art, do we understand it?" The dilemma shows that neither formalism at
This is a reasonable question, one which we can an earlier time nor invisibilism at the present is
imagine people asking, but one whose answer supported by avant-garde gestures, understood
requires criticism, once again, not theory. The in a revolutionary fashion. The dilemma also
first spectators of early modernist works felt shows that a transcendental claim about art is
consternation in front of what they saw and similarly unfounded, namely, that an artwork is
many of them were prepared to deny, at the time, an artwork in virtue of a theory of art. This the-
that what they saw was art. But the consterna- ory-dependence thesis, as we may call it, seems

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
382 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

an obvious truth-even a platitude-if we inco- be extraneous, and, what is more, that element
herently accept the analogy between scientific will always have been extraneous (for if it was
theories and theories of art while trying to pre- not always so, the explicative interpretation
serve the thought that there are no independent simply collapses into the revolutionary).
aesthetic anomalies for theories of art to treat. To be sure, we pay a certain price for our
The thesis then looks irresistible: just as there greater sophistication. We can no longer regard
would be no scientific statements about obser- formalism and invisibilism as being, or having
vational phenomena were it not for scientific been, true in consecutive temporal periods, as
theories, so too (it seems) there would be no art- we could before, because the two theories iden-
works without theories of art.13 Yet the thesis is tify different art-making properties, which are
anything but obvious, and it is a good deal the same properties that make objects artworks
bolder than a mere mind-dependence thesis in all periods. So we now have modem theories
about art. It is difficult to tell what the evidence
of art instead of theories of modem art. We thus
for the theory-dependence thesis is, since we raise the standard of proof considerably for the
have to assume the truth of the revolutionary in- theories, since they are more easily defended if
terpretation of modernism in order to get any we suppose that they only became true after
empirical support for it from recent history. And rationally unignorable historical achievements
this assumption, in turn, shows that we cannot made them so. Still, one of the theories-at most
argue for the revolutionary versions of formal- one-might be true for all that, and it will be all
ism or invisibilism by appealing to the thesis. the more impressive for having satisfied the
higher standard of proof.
III Another aspect of the price we pay emerges if
we think about how we must view historical pe-
The revolutionary interpretation is not the only riods that lie prior to the arrival of the true the-
strategy we could adopt for characterizing the ory (and almost all periods are prior, since on
revisionary impact of modernism. Rather than both of our theories the truth arrives very late).
saying that modernism represents a break in art We have to think that the practice and the un-
history, we could say that modernism discloses derstanding of art were systematically discon-
the underlying characteristics that art had had, nected from each other in the pre-enlightened
latently and unselfconsciously, all along. This dispensation, the aestheticians among our an-
result is better, since we avoid the embarrassing cestors (and they were not alone) were vainly
consequence that the artworld just changed the looking for a Northwest Passage when they
subject in 1910 (or 1960). We can call this strat- characterized-that is, thought they were (accu-
egy the explicative interpretation. rately) characterizing-what artists were doing
Those who have been philosophically im- in picture-making terms. Perhaps such an egre-
pressed by the fact of modernism eventually gious disconnection did occur; at least it could
come to terms with it in this more sophisticated occur. But then it is worth remarking that if this
way, which allows us to view the overall history view of the past is correct, the idea that the na-
of art as reflecting a progressively more encom-ture of art is constituted by decisions, stipula-
passing conception of what that history is about. tions, or theoretical pronouncements rapidly
If Cezanne made art, then his paintings reveal loses coherence, since the relevant thoughts or
what is artistically significant about the Old actions of pre-enlightened artists and aestheti-
Masters; if Warhol made art, we thereby learn cians can hardly be regarded as constitutive of
what makes Brueghel's paintings qualify as those artists' works. And thus the explicative in-
well.14 The difference between the new works terpretation actually subverts, rather than rein-
and the old lies in, and only in, the unusual forces, the transcendental theory-dependence
transparency that the new works, as instances ofthesis (as well as its empirical counterpart, the
art, exemplify: with modernism there are fewer institutional theory of art).
extraneous-artistically irrelevant-elements to If, as the picture conception suggests, the un-
distract us. The upshot, so far as formalism and derlying essence of art did not become fully ex-
invisibilism are concerned, is that the picturing plicit only in the recent past, there will also be a
element found in the older works will turn out todisconnection between understanding and prac-

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Williams Modern Art Theories 383

tice. The avant-garde did think that the artist's mon denominator and the hidden parameter are,
task was, in Ezra Pound's slogan, to make it to speak loosely, features that are present in the
new, and it could be argued that this imperative artifacts under review, the issue is whether these
partly meant that the acknowledged task was items have the significance that these theories
not to make pictures. If modernism did not bring demand of them.
about the desuetude of the picture conception,
then (again) it could be argued that the avant- IV

garde partly did not know what it was up to. I


believe that this argument is sound, but the con- Either formalism or invisibilism holds out the
clusion does not help the revisionary projects. prospect of a deep and exciting discovery about
There are two reasons why it does not help. art. From a naive standpoint, we would have
The first is that it is easy to overmagnify the thought that artworks had content and that the
newness in the avant-garde imperative, since content was accessible to perception. The picture
artists can make art new merely by making new conception affirms both halves of this thought.
sorts of pictures (as most modernists uncontro- Yet formalism denies the first half, invisibilism
versially did), and so the occurrences of "partly" the second. How do we tell which of these three
in the argument above are nontrivial. The sec- views is actually true?
ond is that avant-garde statements about art are Because we cannot complacently invoke the
notoriously ill considered, owing in part to un- verdicts of art history to do our work for us, the
settledness in the artistic practices, and there- question is more difficult than it appears. It
fore some disconnection here should hardly seems to me that we shall only be in a position to
come as a surprise. Many statements in mod- answer it by asking, to begin with, which view
ernist manifestos are just foolish-we should do harmonizes best with our prereflective experi-
well to remember the futurists' solemn call for a ence of art and, then, by asking whether any re-
ten-year suppression of the nude in painting- flective adjustments that a theory subsequently
and general statements about the nature of art invites us to make impoverish that experience.
are plainly liable to create mischief for the un- There are difficulties, too, about what counts as
wary.15 If we bear these points in mind, the the impoverishment (or enrichment) of aestheti-
threat of a disconnection should be less worri- cally pleasurable episodes, or about the extent to
some for modernist practitioners than for pre- which pleasure even shapes the experience of
modern. In any event, if we have to accept a art, but I assume that we can get around these by
measure of disconnectedness (as seems unavoid- using the following standard that ought to be
able), modernism affords the better-the more modest: insofar as the experience of art involves
localized-site. receptivity to a concretely structured phenome-
If we regard the explicative interpretation as non, a theory that attenuates the receptivity or
the right one for our purposes, and I think it is, concreteness will impoverish that experience.
we are ready to consider the claims of formal- Theories of art, by common agreement, can-
ism and invisibilism directly. Surveying the uni- not go proxy for art criticism, but recognition of
verse of art (Old Masters and modernists, but this fact should not blind us to the reality that
also cathedrals and carpets), formalism looks theories, sincerely endorsed, should neverthe-
for the lowest common denominator, and finds less modify our perception of aspects of works
it: configured surfaces are what the diverse ob- as a class. In the case of formalism, which I con-
jects in the universe have in common. Invisibil- sider first, we are at least implicitly encouraged
ism, on the other hand, looks for what, by its to attend selectively to contentless patterns and
lights, is a visually hidden parameter: an inten- to regard the remaining features of the artifact
tional fact concerning an artistic identification. as so much aesthetic dross. Some might think
(The two sets of explananda are not perfectly the effort required for this selective attention is
coextensive, since an invisibilist might not ac- heroic (Bell apparently thought so), but we
cept the carpet as an artwork, because it might might rather think that it is a quixotic, ascetic
lack the right intentional ancestry. However, the exercise, because the reasons for undertaking
two sets should match fairly closely, and so this the exercise are comprehensible only from the
complication is minor.) Since the lowest com- formalist perspective, and also-and I think

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Junon Thu, 01 Jan 1976 12:34:56 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
384 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

more importantly-because people simply do Danto's purpose, which is to illustrate the notion
not perceive pictures in a content-free way. of an unsuccessful artistic identification. But
Danto, in an extremely telling critique of for- we should say something much stronger: that
malism, has noticed that it leaves us with a very my interpretation shows that no identification
thin vocabulary for appreciating the saliences of need be unsuccessful if we are ingenious enough
a work. 16 For example, the Mona Lisa is not, on to partner the perceivable object with an exotic
formal grounds, so different from Duchamp's conceit. Because ingenuity has no upper bound,
LHOOQ-that is, not different enough to ac- and because (according to invisibilism) the per-
count for the aesthetic differences between the ceivable object is a physical object that has no
works. Although Danto himself puts the matter content of its own that can help to shape certain
differently, acceptance of formalism should de- interpretations rather than others, invisibilism
sensitize us to the differences that are not re- can sustain the stronger inference.
ducible to those that are formally describable. If we make this last admission, we are ready
Thus, for reasons such as these, our experience to admit more. The availability, in principle, of
becomes impoverished, and so we are better off an exotic conceit does not show that the distinc-
without formalism. tion between successful and unsuccessful iden-
This conclusion is probably news from no- tifications cannot be drawn for Danto, but rather
where. But what is interesting, and what Danto that success rests entirely on the explanatory
has not noticed, is that a complementary critique scripts that the artist or her admiring (but more
applies to a consistent invisibilism. Whereas articulate) critic volunteers. And this is to say
formalism attempts to reduce the experience of that there is no space at all for the idea that the
art to unconceptualized sensations, invisibilism conceptual component of a work may be intrin-
attempts a reduction in the opposite direction, to sically a part of what we see.
conceptualizations that are only incidentally re- Without that idea, if we complain that my in-
lated to sensations. One of Danto's hypothetical terpretation of Old Man is forced, labored, arti-
artworks will make this point clearer, a failure ficial, or crucially depends on a mere conceit,
(on his view) that he does not discuss in great invisibilism has seemingly no other resources
detail, but which I want to examine more closely. with which to identify the complaint than to say
An artist paints a white canvas bisected by a that we must be requesting a more highly con-
horizontal black line, and she calls her work Old ceptualized script. The feeling that there is not
Man Planting Spring Cactuses. According to enough perceptual continuity between the can-
Danto, the identification is unsuccessful, not in vas and the content is not an intelligible reason
the sense that the result is humdrum art but in for thinking the interpretation forced, any more
the sense that the result is not even intelligible as than it would be in the case of another of Danto's
art. The piece fails, given certain cognitive con- examples, a monochromatic red square titled Is-
straints on imagination, because Danto "can see raelites Crossing the Red Sea. If the Israelites
no identification that might sustain that inter- can pass over and the Egyptians drown without
pretation."'7 Presumably Danto is not just con- a discernible trace, surely the old man can van-
fessing to an imaginative weakness on his part, ishingly plant his cactus on the horizon. And if
one which better imaginers would not share; in- we consistently disallow explanatory appeals to
stead, the problem seems to be that perception the perceivable object-if we generalize from
cannot be structured as the title demands. Yet it what we are doing in these two examples-the
is not clear why the problem is not merely psy- basis for adjudicating between more and less
chological. Suppose we say that Old Man does successful partnerings of script and object be-
make sense, as follows: the line is the horizon at comes increasingly rarefied and intellectual.
which the old man stands, insignificantly small, The invisibilist may have a vestigial but pre-
planting his cactus in an empty desert. In the potent attachment to the picturing conception
spirit of Danto's whimsical vignettes, we might (as may the formalist), and that attachment can
then feel that the work, far from being a failure, help explain a readiness to reject Old Man and to
displays a stunning existential pathos. accept yet another example, the look-alike New-
Now we could say that my interpretation of ton's Third Law, which represents the path of an
Old Man shows that the example is a bad one for isolated particle moving inertially through space.

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Williams Modern Art Theories 385

With Third Law we may feel that, in an admit- V

tedly borderline sense, we see the content, but


not so with Old Man. But again, this feeling can- Even if formalism and invisibilism are inade-
not be a reason here. Such pictorial qualities as quate, it may still seem that the picture concep-
artworks have are only incidental to the works, tion has to be in worse straits. I wish to discuss
since the representational notion on which in- some sources of this feeling, and to show, pro-
visibilism insists in the case of a Brueghel paint- grammatically, that the feeling is mistaken. One
ing is the same notion as that which character- category of sources consists of conceptual ob-
izes the whole host of Danto's hypothetical jections to the picture conception; another con-
minimalist pieces, and representation for them sists of empirically hard cases in the history of
is not fundamentally pictorial. modern art.
The invisibilist reconception of art on non- (i) There are a number of easily stated con-
perceptual lines has an untoward effect on our ceptual objections, and they are just as easily
experience. We should expect the spectator who disarmed. One of these-that being a picture is
internalizes invisibilism to resist forming any at most a necessary condition for being an art-
impression of a work until after he consults the work since not all pictures are artworks-I dealt
title and other pertinent explanatory material, with in section I. Another is that the picture con-
just as formalism encourages resistance to our ception would commit us, impossibly, to the
natural content-perceiving proclivities. As be- making of comparisons between the picturing
fore, people simply do not look at art this way, and pictured items in order to determine aes-
and enjoining them to change their perceptual thetic excellence, but this objection presupposes
habits involves considerable strain. To the extent a confusion between our recognition of a pic-
that habits are affected, the experience reduces ture's content (which is something that occurs
to the unpacking of conceits, and it is difficult to without our making comparisons) and our un-
see how-nonfacetiously and in fact-we should derstanding of it (which could not take place un-
find our black-and-white canvases moving, if we less we had some independent familiarity with
mean what we usually mean by that accolade. (I the kind of item pictured).18 Still another objec-
do not want to deny that some of these works tion is expressed in the epigram (which appar-
might be moving, but we should first have to be- ently impresses some philosophers) that art
come disengaged from the theory.) One could does not duplicate the world because a single in-
bravely argue that a reconceived experience could stance of the world is already enough. Although
be better than what we prereflectively have; it copies of things do have a point in the economy
would certainly be different. But the argument of human life, which the epigram bypasses, the
would indeed have to be made, and apart from epigram also fails to register the fact that many
the invisibilist perspective we have no motiva- pictures-surrealist ones, to name a notable
tion to make it. class of examples-are not narrowly duplica-
There are, in sum, no good historical reasons tive at all. In the background, however, there
for denying the picture conception of art. How- lurks a somewhat different objection, to which
ever, if we do misconstrue the history, there is more attention needs to be paid.
also no further reason to think that the choice This objection is less easy to state. The rough
between the two theories is inevitable and ex- idea is that if artists did have a picturing agenda,
haustive, that if formalism is unpalatable we the standard of aesthetic excellence would then
must settle for invisibilism, or vice versa. Only be set by how well the picture approximated the
if we assume that we do not authentically see the appearance of the pictured item. There are two
contents of artworks does it make much sense to versions of the idea: if artists made pictures,
suppose that we apprehend either mere lines and they would in the limit either make artifacts that
colors or else something that is inaccessible to are indistinguishable from other things (hence
ordinary perception. But any mysteries concern- redundant) or else pictures that are maximally
ing the perception of contents are equally mys- realistic, like photographs (and hence redundant
teries for the perception of other objects, and so after the nineteenth century, because of photog-
we ought not to make that assumption merely in raphy). For our purposes it does not matter
the course of attempting to make sense of art. which version we work with, since the central

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
386 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

thought, common to the versions, seems to be problem that the dilemma of the mimetic artist
that perfect self-effacement is internal to, a reg- was later intended to reveal, Danto likened the
ulative ideal for, the concept of a picture, and in postimpressionist artwork to a brilliantly coun-
such a way that individual pictures can be as- terfeited dollar bill inscribed with "Not Legal
sessed as approximations to the ideal. Tender," and the existence of such an artifact is
Once the central thought is stated explicitly, it supposed to indicate a break with mimesis.20
is difficult to see why we should think that it is But if the inscription is meant to be analogous to
even remotely plausible. We may imagine that the blotchiness of Mont Sainte-Victoire, the fal-
there is some plausibility if we are specially in- lacy is evident. Similarly, when Bell sought to
terested in self-effacing pictures. However, main- confirm his negative claims about the place of
taining this impression involves mistaking the representation in art, he appealed to the aesthetic
special purpose of a picture for what pictures significance of so-called primitive art, whose
must be if they are to have purposes simpliciter. virtues rest, as we learn on closer inspection, not
Cezanne's blotchy rendering of Mont Sainte- on an avoidance of representation as such but on
Victoire or Munch's wavy rendering of a screamer what Bell calls "accurate" or "exact" representa-
are no less pictures, and no less satisfying as tion.21 But we cannot shore up the negative
artistic pictures, for having blotchy or wavy el- claims by such an appeal unless we surrepti-
ements that real mountains or screamers (or tiously introduce the conceptual consideration.
photographs of them) lack. And there is no rea- As these examples suggest, it can be difficult
son to think that a person who makes a picture in fact to find pure historical or pure conceptual
must regard a nonpicture or a photograph as the anti-picture arguments. It is easy to blur the two,
terminus of her efforts, as if she were to fail in to begin by supposing that the modernist of our
her mission to the extent that she made anything choice did not appear to make pictures; but then,
but either of these two things. A picture maker come to think of it, if the artist had wanted to,
will want to get the picture right, but there are the project would have been pointless anyway.
many kinds of rightness, and not all, and not Still, we should take care not to blur them. The
many, of them can be accommodated within a hybrid argument offers only illusory solidity:
self-effacing picture (or in any other single pic- once its elements are distinguished the argu-
torial vehicle). ment collapses.
Notwithstanding the implausibility of the self- Some artworks by Kandinsky, Malevich, Mon-
effacement ideal, we sometimes encounter co- drian, members of the New York School, and
vert endorsement of it. In his most systematic others are extremely abstract. At first sight it
exposition of his theory, Danto relies on a seems either that they must be damaging coun-
wholly conceptual argument to discredit the pic- terexamples to the picture conception or that re-
ture conception, and that argument presupposes garding them as artworks must be impossible.
the self-effacement ideal. He asks us to consider Because the attempt to deny that these paintings
the paradoxical plight of the mimetic artist: are works of art is plainly an act of desperation,
mimesis must either fail when it succeeds (by at- the first disjunct begins to look inescapable.
taining self-effacement) or succeed when it fails Yet a strong argument can be made that these
(by retaining non-self-effacing elements).19 But works are not true counterexamples. A number
this paradox (which Danto misleadingly casts of abstractions with which we are familiar do
as a practical dilemma for the artist) cannot even have quasi-pictorial resonances, such as Pol-
be framed unless we normatively require that a lock's Lavender Mist and Rothko's signature
particular picture efface itself. And that require- stacked rectangles, which have discernible af-
ment is the merest imposition: being an artwork, finities with the luminous (as well as numinous)
being a picture, and having non-self-effacing clouds of Friedrich.22 Even Morris Louis's series
elements are in no sense an inconsistent or re- of Unfurleds can be seen naturally as belonging
flectively unstable triad. marginally to the landscape tradition.23 And a
The weakness of the conceptual considera- Mondrian may furnish a convincing image of
tion is concealed, however, if it plays an auxil- rational purity and simplicity (not usually con-
iary role in the historical anti-picture argument. sidered a visible object, but which might none-
In the semi-historicized presentation of the theless be given a visible form). Such works are

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Williams Modern Art Theories 387

not straightforwardly pictures, but they do sus- to the unschooled spectator. The reason is that if
tain picture-like perceptions, particularly over the spectator attends diligently to the artistic
time, as the story of art absorbs them. Perhaps identification, or confines her attention scrupu-
every work that claims enduring interest will lously to the formal pattern, there ought to be
sustain at least these perceptions, and such a available to her a pretty definite answer to the
finding should not surprise us if the picturing question of whether something is an artwork or
conception is as entrenched as I have maintained. not. This feature of these theories does not sit
A redoubtable abstraction that continues to happily with the historical fact that many kinds
move and captivate spectators, they know not of art-jazz and blues, cinema, the European
how, may merely be awaiting the right critic novel-reveal their art-making properties to the
who is able to find apt descriptions for what the next generation. (Here I am using "art" in a
spectators sense that they see.24 broader way, of course, than I have used it else-
These cases are certainly hard, but they indi- where in this essay.) And this feature is closely
rectly point up a hardness that art has always related to the theorists' confident assertions that
had. Describing the content of a Chardin still the representational or sensuous elements of a
life does not pose the difficulty that describing a work are irrelevant to our understanding. These
Kandinsky does, and yet describing how the still claims concerning irrelevance moreover dis-
life illuminates its subject does. Because de- close what is arguably a serious additional ob-
scribing the importance of a work's content may jection to the modern art theories.
not be ultimately separable from describing the It would be remarkable, too remarkable, if we
content itself, it is possible that modernism as a could know in advance what perceivable ele-
whole has made explicit a deep property of art ments were or were not relevant to a grasp of
after all-the awkwardness and even tentative- what a work of art is finally about. We-both
ness that we feel when we try to put our experi- ourselves over time and a genuinely plural set of
ence into words-but this office is a far cry spectators-need to do some protracted looking
from the office of making explicit a revisionary and receptive ruminating instead, without pre-
understanding of art as such. established criteria of interpretative relevance,
It is worth remarking that Danto deals in a inasmuch as relevance is always decided by our
similar way with hard cases, which his own engagement with the peculiarities of particular
view constrains him to locate somewhat differ- works themselves. Formalism and invisibilism
ently. For him the difficulties lie with the artist offer us a shortcut where no shortcut is really
who says of her work, "This is an ordinary arti- practicable or desirable. Since pictorial contents
fact and nothing more," or "This is paint and and pictorial significance do not, and perhaps
nothing more."25 His policy is to say that the re- cannot, become apparent all at once, the picture
fusal to make an artistic identification can be an conception is better able to coexist with the facts
identification in the right circumstances, which of history and our own experience than the the-
seem to be necessarily exceptional. There is a ories that would succeed it.26
good thought in this maneuver, but we may le-
gitimately wonder why this maneuver is deployed CHRISTOPHER WILLIAMS

only now, on behalf of invisibilism, whereas a Department of Philosophy


counsel of greater conservatism would have University of Nevada-Reno
urged an earlier deployment, on behalf of the Reno, Nevada 89557-0056
picture conception. Had it been deployed then,
we would have said that an artist's refusal to
make a picture would-or rather could-yield a INTERNET: CTW@UNR.EDU

special kind of picture-like painting. (On this


more conservative approach, the importance of
the artist's decision would be desirably lessened 1. This formulation is meant to echo a claim P. F. Straw-
son made about our commitment to interpersonal attitudes:
also.)
"This commitment is part of the general framework of
Even so, the main drift of invisibilism, and
human life, not something that can come up for review as
formalism as well, is in effect to deny that hard particular cases can come up for review within this general
cases are really hard, except provisionally and framework." "Freedom and Resentment," in Free Will, ed.

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
388 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Gary Watson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), 12. In Making TheorylConstructing Art (University of
p. 70. I do think the two areas are interestingly parallel. Chicago Press, 1993), Daniel Herwitz sometimes uses the
2. The difference between science and pseudoscience (the word "theory" to cover what avant-garde artists and critics
"demarcation problem") might be regarded as having raised say about modernist works, and here "theory" might appear
a general question about the nature of science. So posed, the to be equivalent to "artistic theory." If so, this usage is very
question did not have good answers. However, we can ex- loose. But Herwitz does not think that such "theories" really
plain why certain practices in certain contexts are scientifi- explain works, and so he in effect denies their existence too.
cally irrational; and debates about these explanations do not 13. Danto endorses the thesis: "It would, I should think,
have to bring the general issue into play at all. never have occurred to the painters of Lascaux that they
3. Technical achievements in art are a different matter. To were producing art on those walls. Not unless there were neo-
adapt E. H. Gombrich's well-known observation, our admi- lithic aestheticians." "The Artworld," p. 431. No argument
ration for the realism of Giotto may be driven out by an ac- is given for this claim-unless the historical procession of
quaintance with the Wheaties box. theories of art (IT [the imitation theory], RT, Danto's theory)
4. That appreciation enters into the characterization is im- is its surrogate, but then taking the procession in this way in-
portant: it has no analogue in science, and its absence there volves the incoherent commitment I just mentioned.
points up differences between feeling and intellect (rather 14. In "Modernist Painting," in Modernism with a
than a differential need of theory). Vengeance, vol. 4 of The Collected Essays and Criticism, ed.
5. We might want to know which virtues are the states- John O'Brian (University of Chicago Press, 1993), pp. 85-
man's virtues, and drawing up the catalogue may then count 93, Clement Greenberg hints at such a line of thought for
as a theory. We are embarked on a different inquiry, how- pre-pop modernism, as did Bell. However, Greenberg spoils
ever, and one that takes our admiration for Pericles and Lin- his version of the line when he writes, "Whereas one tends
coln, and our pretheoretical ability to identify (at least) par- to see what is in an Old Master before one sees the picture
adigmatic instances of admirable statesmen, largely for itself, one sees a Modernist picture as a picture first" (p. 87),
granted. which makes it sound as though there were more of a differ-
6. Most promising, that is, if the candidate has to equip us ence between the Old Master and the modernist than just a
with some explanation of why we value the artifacts we call difference in explicitness-and the making of the claim re-
artworks. I agree with those philosophers who find the in- quires a sharp (and dubious) distinction between seeing a
stitutional theory of art defective on related grounds. picture and seeing what is in it. (We should also notice the
7. Clive Bell, Art (New York: Capricorn Books, 1958). persistence of the picture conception in Greenberg's lan-
Apart from the familiar part I, chap. 1 ("The Aesthetic Hy- guage, which must merely enshrine primitive thinking if that
pothesis"), this book is generally unread, but another perti- conception is wrong.) See Danto, "The Artworld," sec. I,
nent portion is part IV, chap. 1 ("The Debt to C6zanne"). and Transfiguration, chap. 5, for other intimations of the ex-
8. Arthur Danto, in the original statement of his position plicative line of thought.
in "The Artworld," reprinted in Philosophy of the Visual 15. The futurists' call is found in Theories of Modern Art,
Arts, ed. Philip Alperson (New York: Oxford University ed. Herschel Chipp (University of California Press, 1968),
Press, 1992), pp. 426-433, is unequivocally an invisibilist. p. 293. Chipp's instructive collection offers a wealth of
How matters stand in The Transfiguration of the Common- artists' quite unsubstantiated statements about art. And crit-
place (Harvard University Press, 1981) is cloudier; in chap- ics are often not much better. Greenberg, for example,
ters 6 and 7 Danto aligns the art-making properties of a thought that surrealism was less advanced, less serious, than
work with certain expressive, rhetorical, and stylistic quali- the kinds of art he favored. Defense of Greenberg's large
ties whose relationship to artistic identification is at least claim would seemingly call for an extensive philosophical
unclear and at most nonexistent, and which suggest that a investigation, which we do not find. For a helpful discussion
second theory is in the making rather than a development of of this example, see Danto, After the End of Art (Princeton
invisibilism. For simplicity, I will ignore this complication University Press, 1997), p. 9. (Danto gives us very good rea-
in the later work, and will treat Danto as a straightforward son to be suspicious of large claims made by critics, but cu-
invisibilist. riously seems to take such claims at face value, and even at
9. It is possible that the individual works that allegedly more than face value.)
help to usher in a changed conception of art will have a dis- 16. Danto, Transfiguration, pp. 30-31 and all of chap. 4.
tinctive significance. Thus, one might argue that in the case 17. Danto, Transfiguration, p. 130. I am not querying here
of Warhol's Brillo Box, "art becomes its own philosophy" the role that Danto thinks titles play, that of supplying a di-
(whatever that might mean exactly). My concern will be rection for interpretation, but I would query it elsewhere.
with changes in the general conception. Also without demur here, I acquiesce in Danto's practice of
10. The choice of date is pleasantly due to Virginia using "interpretation" for the action that the artist or specta-
Woolf's quip that "in or about December, 1910, human char- tor performs on a mere physical object.
acter changed." "Mr. Bennett and Mrs. Brown," in Collected 18. This objection is found in Collingwood's Principles
Essays (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1967), vol. I, p. 320. of Art (Oxford: Clarendon, 1938), p. 44. Collingwood is
Rather than associating the changes with postimpression- rightly amused at the stockbroker who would collect por-
ism, Woolf looks to Shaw, Samuel Butler, and the greater traits only if he could check the painting against the sitter,
liberties taken by Georgian cooks. but would we be able to assess a portrait aesthetically if we
11. In "The Artworld" this may have been the line that did not know what a face was or lived in a faceless world?
Danto took. Formalism (which he called the RT, or the real- 19. Danto, Transfiguration, p. 26.
ity theory) is not presented as having been false in the period 20. Danto, "The Artworld," p. 427.
between postimpressionism and pop art. 21. Bell, pp. 25-26.

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Williams Modern Art Theories 389

22. As Robert Rosenblum contends in Modern Painting 24. We should not forget, however, that quasi-pictorial
and the Northern Romantic Tradition: Friedrich to Rothko resonances are not the same as Danto's officially nonpicto-
(New York: Harper and Row, 1975). rial notion of representational aboutness. We see pictures
23. Robert Hughes treats Louis this way in The Shock of and quasi-pictures.
the New (New York: McGraw Hill, 1992), chap. 3. Some 25. Danto, Transfiguration, pp. 2-3, 131-135.
might object that Hughes's book, adapted from a television 26. 1 wish to thank Muhammad Ali Khalidi, Anita Silvers,
series and aimed at students or curious philistines, is a bad Annette Baier, Stephanie Semler, and several anonymous
source of support. I think, on the contrary, that such books readers for many helpful comments.
provide the very best support, since they must stick as
closely as possible to the experiential roots of what makes
art interesting to us.

This content downloaded from


124.77.213.2 on Sat, 12 Jun 2021 14:36:29 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like