You are on page 1of 17

“ Dynamic Dualism”: Kurth and Riemann on Music Theory and the Mind

daphne tan

This article examines Ernst Kurth’s critical engagement with the ideas of Hugo Riemann and his
eventual reformulation of harmonic dualism in dynamic terms. The principle of “dynamic dualism”
appears most cogently in Musikpsychologie ([1931] 1947). After discussing the broader psychological
movement within which this book emerged, I outline the aims and audience of Musikpsychologie
and provide a detailed discussion of the dynamic dualism Kurth articulates therein. I then return to
the origin of Kurth’s fascination with dualism, namely to Riemann, tracing points of intersection be-
tween the two figures across several decades. I suggest that Kurth’s displeasure with Riemann’s theo-
ries is symptomatic of a broader philosophical disagreement over the explanatory power of music
theory and its relation to psychology at the time.

Keywords: Ernst Kurth, Hugo Riemann, Musikpsychologie, dualism, tonal system, tonal harmony,
the unconscious, psychology, history of theory.

The fact that I frequently mentioned Hugo Riemann in Darstellungssysteme (1913), and lengthy references to Riemann
particular arises from the outstanding significance of this appear in Grundlagen des linearen Kontrapunkts: Bachs melodi-
scholar, which cannot be ignored in any field of musicology.
Therefore if I repeatedly run counter to Riemann’s theory
sche Polyphonie (1917), Romantische Harmonik und ihre Krise in
in this book (especially with regard to the fundamentals of Wagners “ Tristan” ([1920] 1975) and Bruckner (1925). Finally,
harmony) and draw attention to the errors that even this Riemann’s harmonic theory emerges as a major concern in
mighty pioneer has committed in individual instances, then Musikpsychologie ([1931] 1947). Kurth found much to admire
I would like emphatically to avoid the accusation of a lack in the elder scholar’s writings—and as we will see, the senti-
of respect for the lifetime of work, or of failing to recognize
the monumental achievements, for which the field of musi-
ment was mutual—but he ultimately parted ways with
cology has Riemann to thank. Riemann over the activity of musical listening, and more to
—Ernst Kurth the point, over what aspects of listening music theory should
s Ernst Kurth remarks in the epigraph,1 Hugo investigate.

A Riemann was an unavoidable interlocutor, particularly


for a generation of scholars active in the early decades
of the twentieth century. Riemann, perhaps the most prolific
This article focuses on a single issue that connects Kurth and
Riemann: dualism. For modern-day readers, the term “dualism”
will likely call to mind “harmonic dualism,” the nineteenth-
century tradition that took as its starting point Hermann von
and prominent theorist of his day, was someone one had to
contend with if one wanted to write about music theory.2 Helmholtz’s research into the physiology of hearing and vision.3
Kurth, a much younger scholar hoping to make inroads with Recently, harmonic dualism has undergone a revival in North
his own theoretical ideas, was up to the challenge; indeed, he American music theory. Some scholars have turned with
interrogated Riemann’s harmonic and rhythmic theories in ev- renewed interest to historical sources—particularly the works of
ery one of his widely read books. An extended critique of these Moritz Hauptmann, Arthur von Oettingen, and Riemann—
theories is central to Kurth’s habilitation thesis Die and have argued for the usefulness of the dualist perspective.
Voraussetzungen der theoretischen Harmonik und der tonalen Others have formulated new theories that bear the marks of
these sources to varying degrees.4 And many have acknowledged
Core ideas in this paper were first presented at the 2015 meetings of the
the polemics precipitated by dualism, particularly in the hands
Society for Music Theory and the Music Theory Society of New York of Riemann, “its most visible spokesman.”5
State, and in a featured presentation for the Indiana University Graduate
Students Symposium. In developing this project further, I benefitted from 3 See Klumpenhouwer (2002) for an overview.
conversations with several people: my thanks to Robert Wason, Henry 4 See in particular Part II (“Dualism”) of Gollin and Rehding (2011), as
Klumpenhouwer, and Frank Samarotto for their valuable input; and to well as Harrison (1994). For recent sustained discussions about
Poundie Burstein, Sebastian Bisciglia, Jenine Brown, and Sarah Marlowe Hauptmann and Oettingen, see, respectively, Moshaver (2009) and Clark
for their encouragement. Finally, I am grateful to the two anonymous (2001).
reviewers for their generous comments and suggestions. 5 Klumpenhouwer (2011, 195). Harrison (1994, 7) remarks that “the har-
1 Kurth (1917, x); trans. modified from Kim (2003, 327). monic dualists are often ridiculed today for their enormous theoretical
2 As Daniel Harrison notes (1994, 6–7): “[Riemann] is chiefly responsible card houses and for their adamant advocacy of technical ideas hardly sub-
for setting the agenda of turn-of-the-century music theory. And not only stantiated in composed music,” while Klumpenhouwer (2011, 195) has
theory: most central European composers of this century were schooled in written a number of articles that “defend dualism against attacks on its in-
Riemannian doctrine of one type or another.” ternal structural consistency.”

1
2 music theory spectrum 0 (2020)

Yet the endurance of dualism as a theoretical conceit in the the chordal root (B) and third (D]), and the leaping tenor
generation after Riemann has been less frequently acknowl- voice “feigns a real chordal progression”; the sonority on beat
edged.6 Missing, for instance, is an account of dualism’s sec- three is only “apparently” a new chord. At the same time, the
ond life in the writings of Ernst Kurth. Within a suspended G]4 in the piano provides initial support for the
comprehensive study of tonal-harmony-as-experienced, Kurth voice but lingers longer, resolving only in the final eighth note
reformulates Riemann’s harmonic dualism into a principle of of the measure. Conversely, the retained chord-tone B4 in the
“dynamic dualism.” Like most of Kurth’s ideas, the broad vocal part sounds against the low C\3 in the piano left-hand.
strokes of dynamic dualism appear in Voraussetzungen, his ear- In m. 19, the soaring vocal part anticipates the piano
liest publication, but it is in Musikpsychologie, his very last, that right-hand, grating against the G]4 and elevating the tension
they are articulated most cogently. There are, of course, nu- effect. A change occurs in mm. 20–21 as ascending suspension
merous definitions of dualism, and it would be an interesting figures complicate the underlying tonic harmony. Indeed,
task to determine which one fits Kurth best.7 But my main Kurth calls attention to the accented “suspension formation” in
goal here is more circumscribed: to demonstrate that dynamic m. 21, which appears in the “outer form” of a common-tone
dualism was the result of Kurth’s sustained engagement with diminished-seventh chord. We hear a similar suspension for-
Riemann’s theories over several decades, and that in respond- mation twice more on the downbeats of mm. 22–23; here “the
ing to Riemann’s polemics head-on, Kurth refined his own simplified spelling” (die vereinfachte Orthographie) of a first-
perspective on the tonal system, and more broadly, on the rela- inversion Em7 chord belies the inherent neighbor-note ten-
tionship between music theory and the mind. sions within (i.e., the G\2 in the bass is actually F 2 that Ü
It might come as a surprise that Kurth was interested in Ü
resolves to G]2, the E4 in the alto is D 4 that resolves to E]4,
such a systematizing enterprise at all, since he is best known to and the D\5 in the soprano resolves to C]5). The voice clings to
English-language audiences for his close analyses of the music the unresolved D\5, paying no heed to the resolution tone C]3
of Bach, Wagner, and Bruckner.8 Indeed, before going fur- in the piano. All of this comes to a head as the secondary domi-
ther, it would be useful to revisit one such analytical passage: nant (C]7) resolves—fleetingly—to the supertonic in m. 24.
bearing in mind Kurth’s analytical prerogatives will help us un- What is most notable in Kurth’s account is not the
derstand why he found Riemann’s theoretical writings both “surprisingly simple” (überraschend schlicht) underlying progres-
compelling and inadequate. sion of V7 –I–V7=II–II,11 but that the chromatic alterations to
Example 1 contains an excerpt from Hugo Wolf’s “An den this diatonic progression engender an “overpowering network
Schlaf,” which Kurth analyzes in Romantische Harmonik.9 of forces” that “fully permeates [the progression] with tension
While modern-day scholars have focused on larger-scale har- effects.” He calls attention to the growing intensity of the pas-
monic trajectories, motives, and tonal plans, Kurth limits his sage as a whole: tension processes that originate within the first
observations to the local level.10 He interprets m. 18 as a dom- measure accumulate in subsequent measures, bolstered by in-
inant seventh in E major, but one that is “withheld” through- creasing amplitude in the “outer dynamics.” Like any analytical
out, made unrecognizable through a confluence of “tension interpretation, his says as much about his theoretical preroga-
formations” (Spannungsbildungen). From the first half to the tives as it does about the music, and I am struck by his concern
second half of the measure, “neighbor-note distortions” alter for the interaction of performers and for the push and pull
among individual voices. He presents a compelling case for
6 Robert Wason (1985, 117–18) notes that Riemann’s new “evidence” in
how dynamic tensions prevail, and indeed define, the
1905 resuscitated the dualism debate. I will explore this evidence further Romantic style. With his ardent commitment to chromatic
below. music of the long nineteenth century, Kurth pushed back on
7 For a sample of these definitions, see Mooney (1996, 42ff.), Rehding the widely held belief in his day that the music of Haydn,
(2003, 31), Riley (2004, 5), and Klumpenhouwer (2011, 196–99). Mozart, and Beethoven represented the pinnacle of musical
Riemann, of course, provides several definitions of his own; here is one development. In this immediate way, then, Kurth diverged
from the fifth edition of his Musik-Lexikon (1900): dualism is, “broadly
ideologically from Riemann, a theorist who, in the words of
speaking, the assumption of a twofold basis of harmony, [that is] the ma-
jor consonance ([reckoned] from the principal tone upwards) and the mi-
Scott Burnham, perpetuated this belief through “the formula-
nor consonance ([reckoned] from the principal tone downwards)”; tion of a theory of music which covertly embodied as its funda-
translated in Rehding (2003, 188). As Harrison (1994, 265) notes, mental assumption the ideological premise that the underlying
Riemann talks explicitly about chords, but it is the duality of keys that he syntax of the Viennese Classical style could serve as the univer-
champions. sal basis of music.”12
8 The pioneering efforts of Lee A. Rothfarb, especially his publications
from 1988 and 1991, first brought Kurth to the attention of a wider
English-language audience. Important forerunners are Hsu (1966) and 11 Indeed, as Wason (1985, 53) notes, the idea that “every chromatic struc-
McCreless (1983). ture, without exception, is reducible to a diatonic one” is “implicit to most
9 Kurth ([1920] 1975, 199–201). I consulted the 1975 reprint of the third Viennese systems of harmony of the first half of the nineteenth century.”
edition; this analytical vignette does not appear in the original edition. See, for instance, his comparison of this idea in the theories of Emanuel
Rothfarb (1991, 114–16) also presents a translation. Aloys Förster and Simon Sechter.
10 See, for instance, Stein (1985) and Taycher (2012). 12 Burnham (1992, 13).
kurth and riemann on music theory and the mind 3

example 1. Analysis of Wolf, “ An den Schlaf,” Mörike-Lieder, mm. 17–34

Kurth’s analytical treatises were immensely popular in his time, the climax of an increasingly contentious debate within aca-
as their many reprintings attest, and present-day readers who give demic philosophy over the status of experimental psychology, a
themselves over to his idiosyncratic prose style will be richly subspecialty of the discipline. Experimental psychology, which
rewarded. Yet as Carl Dahlhaus suggests, a full understanding of borrowed its methods from the natural sciences (especially
any one of these treatises is only possible in the context of Kurth’s physiology), had gained an ever-stronger foothold in German-
entire output. And until recently, Musikpsychologie— speaking universities since the turn of the century, as demon-
“chronologically the endpoint, but methodologically the starting strated by the rapid establishment of psychological institutes,
point of [Kurth’s] entire enterprise”—has received limited schol- academic journals, and societies for experimental research.14
arly consideration.13 Taking Dahlhaus’s cue, we will begin our ex- Moreover, between 1890 and 1910 an increasing number of
ploration of dynamic dualism at the chronological end, with full professorships in philosophy were held by experimental
Kurth’s final articulation of this principle in Musikpsychologie. psychologists. Alarmed at this latter trend in particular, more
The remainder of this article is in three parts. The first con- than a hundred philosophers in Germany, Austria, and
siders the aims and audience of Musikpsychologie within the Switzerland signed a petition in 1913 demanding that no fur-
context of a broader psychological movement. This is followed ther philosophy chairs be awarded to psychologists.15
by a detailed examination of the principle of dynamic dualism This discord among philosophers was interrupted, however,
within that book. From there I return to the origin of Kurth’s by the First World War. Psychology became a useful military
fascination with dualism, namely to Riemann, tracing points instrument in wartime, and its proven utility sparked the post-
of intersection between the two figures across several decades. war enthusiasm for “applied” psychology within and outside
A dedicated comparison of their philosophies and theoretical the academy.16 The intellectual separation of this new applied
ideas undoubtedly deserves a fuller study than I offer here.
Nevertheless, I suggest that the starting point for such a com- 14 Among the newly formed psychological institutes, Wilhelm Wundt’s in
parison is an investigation into the differing ways they pre- Leipzig (est. 1879) and Carl Stumpf’s in Berlin (est. 1894) were the most
sented their approaches as psychological. influential. Among the newly formed journals were Zeitschrift für
Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane (est. 1890) and the Archiv für
die gesamte Psychologie (est. 1903). Finally, the Society for Experimental
psychology, MUSIKPSYCHOLOGIE, and music theory Psychology was founded in 1904, later renamed the German Society for
Psychology in 1929, in an attempt at greater inclusivity.
15 For full accounts of this event, see Ash ([1995] 1998, 47) and Kusch
Psychology as a field of study experienced a sea change from (1995, 190–94).
1913 to 1931, the period corresponding to Kurth’s most sig- 16 Also known as “military psychotechnics,” military psychology produced
nificant professional activities. The first of these years marks aptitude tests for pilots, drivers of military vehicles, and machinery opera-
tors. It also conducted research into the reaction times of soldiers, the psy-
13 Dahlhaus (1973). The most comprehensive English-language treatments chological processes during the firing of handguns, the effectiveness of
of Musikpsychologie appear in Kim (2003), Tan (2013), Tan (2015), and camouflage, and many other issues; see Kusch (1995, 222) for a compre-
Tan (2017). An important German-language source is Rösler (1997). hensive list of these projects. After the war, applied psychology dealt with
4 music theory spectrum 0 (2020)

psychology from the psychology of yesteryear was defined by a What is here regarded as music psychology is neither a tone
further removal from “pure” philosophical problems.17 A new psychology nor an aesthetics of music; thus this is not an
investigation of artistic production, but rather of psychical
crisis thus ensued, now among researchers in experimental psy- functions that form the very basis of musical hearing in
chology. Taking a cue from their philosophy colleagues, they general, and consequently of any aesthetics, theory, stylis-
petitioned in 1929–1930 for more professorships—not to re- tics, and other areas of music research. . . . For this reason
place, but to work alongside, philosophy.18 the contents are governed by the interaction of two areas,
During this turbulent period of disciplinary readjustment, sev- music and psychology. [The goal of this study is] to locate
the connection to psychology for all phenomena that are
eral new schools of experimental psychology flourished. Most no-
subject to tonal laws, and therefore to assemble, above all,
table are those affiliated with the far-reaching movement known material on the frontier of both sciences [music and
as “Gestalt psychology,” loosely characterized by the rejection of psychology].22
elementalism, “the assumption that sensory ‘elements’ are the basic
constituents of mental life.”19 In his seminal text on the subject, Kurth declares music psychology to be no less than the foun-
Mitchell G. Ash writes that “the period from 1920 to 1933 dation of every area of music research, thus recalling the posi-
marked the high point . . . of Gestalt psychology’s theoretical de- tion taken by Wundt (from the experimental side) and
velopment, its research productivity and its impact on German Wilhelm Dilthey (from the “pure” philosophical side) that psy-
science and culture”; it also achieved international prominence chology formed the basis of all human sciences
during this time.20 The Berlin school in particular, so-called be- (Geisteswissenschaften).23 He also singles out two preexisting
cause its founders Wolfgang Köhler, Kurt Koffka, and Max research areas, tone psychology and the aesthetics of music,
Wertheimer were trained under philosopher Carl Stumpf at the whose concerns he deems only superficially similar.
University of Berlin, is generally regarded as the school of Gestalt Contemporaneous readers would have been familiar with
theory. But it cannot be ignored that other rival holistic schools— the term “Tonpsychologie” from Stumpf’s two-volume mag-
for instance, the Graz school, led by Alexius Meinong and num opus of this name; indeed it would be entirely reasonable
Christian von Ehrenfels, and the Leipzig school of to assume from Kurth’s reference that Musikpsychologie is a
Ganzheitspsychologie, led by Felix Krueger—laid claim to establish- not-so-veiled response to Stumpf, just as Stumpf’s
ing similar concepts, and further, that individuals sought to high- “Tonpsychologie” could be read as a response to Hermann von
light insufficiencies in the Berlin school’s holism.21 Helmholtz’s “Tonempfindungen.”24 Kurth does interrogate
It was against this complex backdrop of events that Stumpf’s concept of fusion at length in the third section of his
Kurth’s ideas on the psychology of music developed, emerg- book, and as seen in the above quote, he also adapts Stumpf’s
ing in their most synthesized and detailed form in
Musikpsychologie. Beginning in the foreword and throughout
the first section of this book, Kurth establishes the parameters
of his research agenda, situating it within the realm of music 22 “Was hier als Musikpsychologie betrachtet wird, ist weder eine
research (Musikwissenschaft) as well as within pre- and post- €
Tonpsychologie noch eine Asthetik der Musik; daher auch keine
war academic psychology. Let us examine both aspects of this Untersuchung des künstlerischen Schaffens, sondern jener psychischen
disciplinary positioning, beginning with the highly suggestive Funktionen, die erst dem musikalischen Hören überhaupt zugrunde

liegen, somit auch jeglicher Asthetik, Theorie, Stilistik und weiteren
opening sentences of the foreword:
Gebieten der Musikforschung. . . . Der Stoff unterliegt damit der
Wechselbeziehung zweier Gebiete, der Musik und der Psychologie. Von
allen tongesetzlichen Ph€anomenen war die Verbindung zur Psychologie
such issues as “the psychology of advertising, forensic psychology, the psy- zu suchen, somit vornehmlich an der Grenze beider Wissenschaften ein
chology of accidents, and aptitude tests for train conductors, insurance Material aufzuschichten” (Kurth 1931 [1947], x). All translations of
agents, prison guards, dentists and surgeons” (Kusch 1995, 260). Musikpsychologie within this article are my own.
17 As Mitchell G. Ash notes, moreover, “By [1929], a plethora of alternative 23 A doyen of experimental psychology, Wundt maintained throughout his
psychologies had arisen to deal with the problems of modern youth, sexu- career that experimentation could only access parts of mental life and thus
ality, character, or personality diagnosis and therapy—practical social needed to remain rooted in philosophy. Dilthey, in a paper entitled “Ideen
problems [that were broad and difficult] to grasp with standard laboratory über eine beschreibende und zergliedernde Psychologie” (1894), criticized
methods” ([1995] 1998, 204). “explanatory or constructive psychology” (based on experimentation) for
18 See Kusch (1995, 261) and Ash ([1995] 1998, 204). the insufficiency of its scope and methods, proposing instead a broader
19 Ash ([1995] 1998, 1). “descriptive or analytic psychology”; the latter could include experimenta-
20 Ash ([1995] 1998, 203). The American reception of Gestalt psychology, tion as well as other forms of analysis and comparison, such as examining
and in turn, the Gestalt critique of American behavioralism, lies outside artworks to study forms of mental activity. See Kusch (1995, 162–69). In
the scope of the present article; see Robinson (1995, Chapter 12) for an addition to influencing Krüger, as mentioned in n. 21, Dilthey had a di-
account. rect hand in Stumpf’s appointment to the University of Berlin. In turn,
21 Influenced by the philosopher Wilhelm Dilthey, Krüger attacked the Stumpf’s students, the Gestalt theorists, would later portray their ideas as
Berlin school for neglecting the role of feeling and will in his 1923 address consonant with Dilthey’s; see Ash ([1995] 1998, 31–33, 296). Kurth
to the Kongreß für experimentelle Psychologie (Leipzig), “Der refers to the 1894 paper and others by Dilthey in Musikpsychologie; see
Strukturbegriff in der Psychologie”; Kurth ([1931] 1947, 27) refers to this Kurth ([1931] 1947, 27n.1).
source in his discussion of Gestalt psychology. 24 See, for instance, de la Motte-Haber (1986–87).
kurth and riemann on music theory and the mind 5

concept of “psychical functions.”25 A close reading of embraces both experimental research and non-experimental,
Musikpsychologie in its entirety, however, reveals that Kurth psychologically oriented philosophy. He justifies this position
employs “tone psychology” more loosely: as a catchall for a in the foreword as well:
mindset and methodology of which Stumpf’s work is
representative—but so too Helmholtz’s and, as we will see The academic discipline of psychology can tackle many
issues from quite different perspectives, especially with its
later, Riemann’s before 1914. Tone psychology, in Kurth’s es- current variety of methods, and it may also, in general, tend
timation, was closely adjacent to physiology, as both assumed to explain things differently, but even then, the set of prob-
one-to-one, measurable correspondences between stimulus lems remains never fully exhausted. Just as with many
and response. In Musikpsychologie, Kurth notes that “tone psy- things, for music there will never be a single valid psychol-
chology treats the interplay of stimulus and reaction,” while ig- ogy but always only ever-changing insights from different
perspectives, as it corresponds to the mental life in its intan-
noring that “opposite to it, there stands an ‘action,’ the gible, ever-moving multiplicity.29
prevailing of that psychical activity that first captures, forms,
and reorganizes the stimulus”; by focusing on stimulus reac- So it is that we encounter in Section 1 a long list of intellectual
tions alone, tone psychology can only address “the sensory area figures with a shared concern for “holistic experience”
of music” (Sinnesgebeit der Musik) rather than music itself.26 (Ganzheitserlebnis). The experimental psychologist-
Alongside this emphasis on psychical activity, “wholeness” philosophers Ehrenfels, Stumpf, Meinong, and Krueger are
arises as a central point in Kurth’s distinction between tone among the names, to be sure, but they stand alongside philos-
psychology and music psychology. He writes, ophers like Dilthey and Henri Bergson.30 Throughout
Musikpsychologie, moreover, Kurth draws connections among
Tone psychology is more aligned with single impressions
contemporaneous psychological ideas and various strands of
(tone, interval, chord, rhythmic unit, etc.), music psychol-
ogy more with the flowing whole, in that it examines the philosophical thought that exalt the immediacy of experience
individual impressions from this [whole]. The physiologist and the power of the unconsciousness.31
says: our sense of hearing is necessary in order to experience Kurth’s intended readership for Musikpsychologie is as broad
sound waves—whereas the music psychologist from his as his scholarly sources. Having designed the book for musi-
standpoint is permitted to say: the sound waves bring forth cians with an interest in psychology, while also seeking to
only the sensory stimulus in which we experience the pro-
cesses of music.27 make a contribution to the area of psychology itself, he ex-
pressly reformulated technical terms and omitted music nota-
Thus when Kurth asserts at the outset of Musikpsychologie tion. “In short,” he writes, “it seemed necessary to stick to an
that his goal is to “locate the connection to psychology for all account that should be understandable in both fields, even by
phenomena that are subject to tonal laws,” he views his project amateurs.”32 Based on the book’s reception, this approach was
as specifically consonant with the ongoing Gestalt move- only partly successful. While some reviewers heralded
ment.28 At the same time, Kurth’s notion of psychology Musikpsychologie as a significant refinement and consolidation
of psychological ideas that were already present in Kurth’s

25 See Tan (2013, 62–79 and 154–75) for a discussion of Kurth’s critique of
Stumpf and his concept of fusion. In contrast to “Erscheinungen,” which
are sensory data (and the memory of these), Stumpf (1907, 4–5) defines
“psychische Funktionen” as immediately given mental activities (Akte), 29 “Die Fachpsychologie kann, besonders bei ihrer heutigen
states (Zust€ande), and experiences (Erlebnisse) that include “the noticing of Methodenvielfalt, vieles noch von ganz andern Seiten her anpacken, mag
phenomena and their relations, the synthesis of phenomena into com- auch manches grunds€atzlich noch anders erkl€aren, aber selbst dann bleibt
plexes, the formation of concepts, [the acts of] grasping and judging, the der Problemkreis nie ganz zu erschöpfen. Sowenig wie sonst wird es auch
emotions, the desiring, and willing.” Compare Kurth ([1931] 1947, 43): für die Musik nie eine alleingültige Psychologie geben, sondern immer
“It arises particularly in musical phenomena that the unconscious psychical nur wechselnde Einblicke aus verschiedenen Betrachtungsweisen, wie es
functions are already, in many ways, conditions for appearances dem seelischen Leben in seiner ungreifbaren, stets bewegten Vielfalt
(Erscheinungen) of conscious cognition (bewußten Erkennen).” entspricht” (Kurth [1931] 1947, xi–xii).
26 Kurth ([1931] 1947, 51; emphasis original). 30 Kurth ([1931] 1947, 26).
27 “[D]ie Tonpsychologie ist mehr auf die Einzeleindrücke (Ton, Intervall, 31 We read, for instance that “Schopenhauer and Feuerbach, and above all
Akkord, rhythmische Einheit usw.) gerichtet, die Musikpsychologie mehr Dilthey and Bergson—in contrast to rationalistic psychology, which drew
auf das fließende Ganze, so dass sie die Einzeleindrücke schon von diesem its conclusions from the representational contents of the imagination—
aus betrachtet. Der Physiologe sagt: unser Gehörssinn ist nötig, um emphasized more the immediacy of experience that happens beyond the
Schallwellen zu erfahren—w€ahrend der Musikpsychologe von seinem imaginable.” (“Schopenhauer und Feuerbach, dann vor allem Dilthey und
Standpunkt sagen darf: die Schallwellen verursachen nur die Bergson, betonten gegenüber der rationalistischen Psychologie, die ihre
Sinnesreizung, in der wir die Vorg€ange der Musik erfahren” (Kurth Schlüsse aus den gegenst€andlichen Vorstellungsinhalten zog, mehr die
[1931] 1947, 51). For a more sustained discussion of Kurth’s distinction Unmittelbarkeit des Erlebens, das sich jenseits des Vorstellbaren abspielt”)
between Tonpsychologie and Musikpsychologie, see Tan (2013, 62–79). (Kurth [1931] 1947, 53).
28 Tan (2015) investigates this topic, highlighting the particular influence of 32 “Kurz, es schien geboten, eine Darstellung einzuhalten, die auf beiden
Krueger. A recent examination of intersections between the Berlin school Gebieten auch für Dilettanten verst€andlich sein soll” (Kurth [1931] 1947,
and Kurth’s Grundlagen, can be found in Probst (2018, Chapter 4). x–xi; emphasis original).
6 music theory spectrum 0 (2020)

prior books,33 others with a narrower, postwar understanding in music-theoretical work. For “when tackled properly,” Kurth
of “psychology” were unconvinced by his adoption of the writes, music theory is “not a dry de[-]composition but instead
term;34 for these reviewers, the book challenged the very limits contains the most intrinsic secrets.”38
of this word, especially within the current climate of disciplin- Anticipating the criticism that his project is an unnecessary
ary transformation. overcomplication of rudimentary ideas that are familiar to any
At this point, it is worth returning to my opening assertion practicing musician, Kurth writes:
that Kurth’s attempts to promote his music-theoretical ideas
brought him into contact with Riemann. For if one were to For that reason, the difficulty often lies in [the fact] that
well-known concepts must be considered without presup-
judge the contents of Musikpsychologie by its cover and fore- position if possible; what music theory simply accepts as
word alone, one might be surprised to encounter traditional givens are for music psychology only the starting points
theoretical topics in later portions of the book: the entire third with which it must entrench itself in its own
section is dedicated to tonal harmony and the fourth section to territory. . . . But these riddles that present themselves ev-
form.35 Yet this preoccupation with music theory is actually erywhere in the basic concepts of practical music theory are
not only the starting points for the philosophical-
because of rather than despite Kurth’s psychological outlook. speculative interpretation of music but, above all, the
Indeed throughout his oeuvre, Kurth maintains that accepted boundaries where the empirical-psychological processes be-
musical “laws,” established through theoretical research and gin to reveal themselves. Here we are searching for those
music pedagogy, have yet-unknown psychological roots; more- basic phenomena of theory only to recognize the psychical
over, locating these roots—these psychical functions— functions that are involved in them.39
contributes to other areas of intellectual inquiry, including the Thus Kurth argues that a shift in perspective can lead to new
newest forms of psychological research. This argument again understandings of well-known concepts. Conversely, music
coheres with Wundt’s suggestion that psychology is the foun- theories fall short when they inadequately acknowledge their
dation for Geisteswissenschaften, and in turn, that humanistic limitations and when they fail to recognize the “circle of
fields could provide data for psychological analysis.36 In mystery” (R€atselring) that inescapably surrounds them.
Musikpsychologie, Kurth observes, “it has been insufficiently Returning to “An den Schlaf” (Ex. 1), Kurth’s analysis can be
recognized that the principal starting points for an empirical understood as an attempt to lead the reader toward psycholog-
psychology of music become apparent in the theory [of music], ical processes that are present in the act of listening but that
or more properly: are hidden within it.”37 He notes that con- cannot be captured through symbolic notation alone. His prose
temporary scholars have searched “more eagerly than ever” for invokes feelings of instability, of the ebb and flow of accumu-
musical laws. Yet in doing so, they inadvertently reveal psycho- lating and abating tensions, in a particular passage of music.
logical principles that are entangled with the “special condi- The third section of Musikpsychologie furthers this cause with a
tions of sounding matter.” This relationship between sounding discussion of psychological processes that are latent within a
matter and its transformation through cognition, between general system of tonal harmony.40 Kurth underscores that
physical and psychological conditions, emerges most strongly

33 See, for instance, the largely positive reviews by Alfred Lorenz (1930), 38 “Die heutige Geistesforschung, und zwar l€angst nicht nur die
Hans Mersmann (1931), and Theodor W. Adorno (1933). In a letter to Musikwissenschaft selbst, sucht wißbegieriger als je nach den Gesetzen
Kurth following the publication of Musikpsychologie, Guido Adler, his for- der Musik; damit werden aber größerenteils psychologische Gesetze frei-
mer advisor at the University of Vienna, commends the book’s psychologi- gelegt, die sich allerdings mit den besonderen Bedingungen der
cal direction as well as its relevance to existing areas of Musikwissenschaft: Tonmaterie auseinandersetzen und an sie gebunden sind. Aber nirgends
“My own psychological work and studies have been at a standstill for al- tritt auch die besondere Eigenart der Tonmaterie samt ihrer
most three decades, and so for the time being, I do not venture to tell you Umgestaltbarkeit selbst deutlicher hervor als in der Theorie; sie ist, richtig
my opinion in a strictly scientific manner; I can say now, however, that angepackt, keine trockene Zersetzung, sondern schließt die eigentlichsten
the conquest of new territory in your book, with such attentive reference Geheimnisse ein” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 63).
to the constantly growing [psychological] literature, truly satisfies me, as 39 “Darum beruht die Schwierigkeit oft gerade darin, daß altbekannte
does the inclusion of style in the psychological field of research and that Begriffe eine möglichst voraussetzungslose Betrachtung erfahren müssen;
you are nowhere in opposition to my positions about style and style crit- was die Musiklehre schlechtweg als Gegebenheiten hinnimmt, bildet für
icism.” (Guido Adler to Ernst Kurth, 29 April 1931, A1.14, die Musikpsychologie erst Ansatzpunkte, bei denen sie sich in ihr eigenes
Volltextbriefe zum Inventar Nachlass Kurth, Institut für Gebiet eingraben muß. . . . Jene R€atsel aber, die sich überall an den
Musikwissenschaft, Universit€at Bern.) Ausgangsbegriffen der gangbaren Musiklehre eröffnen, bilden nicht bloß
34 See, for instance, the more critical reviews by Kurt Herbst (1931) and die Ausgangspunkte für die philosophisch-spekulative Deutung der
Albert Wellek (1931). Musik, sondern vor allem die Grenzen, an denen sich die empirisch-
35 See Tan (2017) for a discussion of Kurth’s conception of musical form psychologischen Vorg€ange zu enthüllen beginnen. Wir suchen jene
within Bruckner and Musikpsychologie. Grunderscheinungen der Theorie hier nur auf, um die psychischen
36 Ash ([1995] 1998, 23). Funktionen zu erkennen, die an ihnen beteiligt sind” (Kurth [1931] 1947,
37 “Zu wenig ist erkannt worden, daß die haupts€achlichsten Ansatzpunkte 63–64).
für eine empirische Psychologie der Musik in der Theorie offenbar werden, 40 Each of the three chapters highlights an experiential aspect: chord fusion,
oder richtiger: in ihr verborgen liegen” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 62; emphasis or why we sense simultaneous tones as harmonious (Chapter 1: “Der
original). Zusammenklang”); chord tension, or why we feel tension when hearing
kurth and riemann on music theory and the mind 7

while music theorists have taken great pains to explain tonality of changing colors.45 In highlighting the bifocal construction
as a logical, balanced system, music psychology unveils another of each theoretical concept (up/down, major/minor, sharp/
system that is not immediately apparent to the ear or eye: “The flat), he calls attention to their attendant tensions, their
implications now are different for psychology than they are for “dynamic dualism.” Collectively, Kurth’s three layers of dy-
theory. As only needs to be briefly indicated here, theory chains namic dualism provide a framework for understanding why it
itself to the system of major and minor tonalities, which is in es- is that similarly constructed chords and progressions can be
sence also a system of dynamic strivings.”41 perceived and felt differently, often radically so.

dynamic dualism and its three layers of 1. LEADING-TONE STRIVING IN THE SCALE: THE SENSATION OF
development42 MOTION

Though accounts of the tonal system often begin with root Kurth implies that since the sensation of motion is psychologi-
motion by fifth, Kurth’s music-psychological theory empha- cally primary among experiences, the scale is ontologically pri-
sizes instead the distinctive experiential power of the leading mary within a dynamic theoretical system. He elaborates:
tone: “the leading tone is the initiating point where the psy- In general, it is not the theory of individual chords but
chological-dynamic processes interpenetrate most intensely, rather only the theory of chordal motions that constitutes
while the roots represent the pivotal points of the physically harmony. They are of such variety, however, that to grasp
given relationships.”43 His theory hinges, moreover, on a them, one must first refer back to the simplest fundamental
leading-tone effect (Leittonwirkung) that expresses itself in motion. And this lies in the connection of two octave-
related tones—in the scale, through whose dynamic dispo-
three different contexts: as a pure sensation of motion; as sition each chordal tension is determined.46
“color” within a chord; and as an evanescent resolution
within an ongoing progression. Crucially, in the course of Beginning with the major scale, Kurth emphasizes that multi-
musical listening, and as a given context develops, the ple ways of hearing and of experiencing motion therein are
leading-tone effect accumulates in layers of development available. He writes, “The unity of tones is not decisive, and
(Entwicklungsschichten); the longer one listens, the greater the the ‘structure’ of the scale is not external. Rather, it is the op-
possibility that one will acquire a “double, triple, etc. posite: with tonal motion, just as in the case of the single tone
leading-tone effect.”44 These effects are readily showcased in and the chord, one confronts the psychological phenomenon
an elaborate context such as a Wolf Lied, but in that multiple [scalar] tendencies can crisscross and pass
Musikpsychologie Kurth employs further illustrative tools to through one another.”47 As Example 2(a) shows, it is possible
isolate them for discussion. That is, he attributes an abstract to perceive the major scale as two tetrachords with identical
“fundamental form” to each: (1) the scale, with its upward- intervallic content, giving rise to a repeating pattern of felt mo-
and downward-striving leading tones, embodies the sensation tion: “The progression of two whole tones and a semitone
of motion; (2) the chord, and particularly the distinction be- (C–D–E–F) repeats itself (G–A–B–C), and with it, [repeats]
tween major and minor, captures the sensation of color; and the simple dynamic of leading-tone intensification toward goal
(3) the circle of keys, with the possibility of moving in tones of motion.”48 The fourth and fifth scale degrees play
sharpwise and flatwise directions, engenders the impression
45 In Voraussetzungen, Kurth’s descriptions of the scale and chord closely re-
semble those in Musikpsychologie; see Chapters 3 (“The Sensation of
simultaneous tones (Chapter 2: “Die Dynamisierung des Klanges”); and Motion and Harmonic Energy”) and 8 (“The Modes as Opposing Forms
chord movement, or what underlying principles govern our responses to with Regard to Harmonic Energy: The Explanation of Minor”), respec-
chord successions (Chapter 3: “Die Klangbewegung”). tively. In the earlier work, however, he does not yet situate these theoreti-
41 “Für die Psychologie sind nun die Folgerungen daraus noch andere als für cal constructs within an overarching dynamic system.
die Theorie. Für diese kettet sich, wie hier nur kurz angedeutet zu werden €
46 “Uberhaupt macht noch nicht die Lehre von den einzelnen Kl€angen die
braucht, hieran das System der Dur- und Moltonarten, das im Grunde Harmonik aus, sondern erst die von den Klangbewegungen. Sie sind aber
ebenfalls ein System dynamischer Strömungen ist” (Kurth [1931] 1947, von solcher Vielfalt, daß man zu ihrer Erfassung zun€achst auf die ein-
209; emphasis mine.) fachste Grundbewegung zurückgreifen muß. Und diese liegt in der
42 This is the heading of Musikpsychologie, Section 3, Chapter 3, Subsection Verbindung zweier Oktavtöne, der Skala, durch deren dynamische
2 (“Der dynamische Dualismus und seine drei Entwicklungsschichten”). Lagerung jede Akkordspannung mitbedingt ist” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 205;
In this subsection, Kurth lists the three layers (three times, in fact) but my emphasis).
does not discuss them in order. One also needs to read Subsection 1 47 “Die Zusammengehörigkeit der Töne ist keine eindeutige, die ‘Struktur’
(“The Fundamental Motion”) to fully understand the three layers, particu- der Skala keine €außerliche; im Gegenteil: wie beim Einzelton und Klang,
larly the first. so steht man auch bei der Tonbewegung vor der psychologischen
43 “Der Leitton ist der Ansatzpunkt, wo die psychologisch-dynamischen Erscheinung, daß sich mehrere Wirkungstendenzen durchkreuzen und
Vorg€ange am intensivsten eindringen, w€ahrend die Grundtöne durchdringen können” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 208).
Angelpunkte der physikalisch gegebenen Verwandtschaften darstellen” 48 “Die Folge zweier Ganztöne und eines Halbtones (c–d–e–f) wiederholt sich
(Kurth [1931] 1947, 211; emphasis original). genau (g–a–h–c), und damit die einfache Dynamik einer Leittonzuspitzung
44 “Doppelte, dreifache Leittonwirkung usw.” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 212). gegen Zieltöne der Bewegung” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 205).
8 music theory spectrum 0 (2020)

(a)

example 3. Leading-tone strivings in the minor scale


(b)

Indeed, the different trajectories of motion in the second half


of the minor scale distinguish it from its major counterpart.
example 2. (a) Leading-tone strivings in the major scale
(“ melodic” representation). (b) “ Harmonic” representation of the 2. MAJOR-MINOR OPPOSITION IN THE TRIAD: THE SENSATION OF
major scale COLOR AND CHARACTER

In the triad, individual notes are charged with their scalar ten-
distinctive, pivotal roles within this conception of the major scale: dencies, infusing the chord with potential directionality. The
^4 is an intermediate goal away from ^1, and ^5 initiates another quale of a chord is a result of both the chord-as-sonorous-
motion toward ^ 1. Moreover, ^3 acts as an intermediate leading event and the direction of suggested motion. Kurth notes that
tone (Zwischenleitton) in the lower tetrachord, anticipating the in- this sensuous aspect of harmony is rarely discussed, because
tensified trajectory of ^ 7 in the upper tetrachord. It is in this dia- the immediacy of the impression overpowers the complexity of
lectical striving away from and back to the tonic that Kurth the moment: “[music] theory and naı̈ve listeners often ignore
locates the “effects” (Wirkungen) of subdominant and dominant. these [tension processes], because as immediate aural impres-
Then again, one could instead attend to the tonic-chord scale sions they express themselves in intensive sound colors.”51
degrees as pivotal points of motion, as shown in Example 2(b), As Example 4 highlights, a major triad contains an upward
that is, hearing ^1–^3–^ 5–^1 as a “gravitational field” to which all leading-tone tendency that lies “concealed” (verborgen) in the
other scalar tones relate. Kurth notes that any “harmonic” striving chordal third. Kurth is quick to emphasize that the experience
in this hearing “rests strongly in itself.” By contrast, listening to of this tendency is markedly different from that of a leading
the scale as a progression of two tetrachords (Example 2[a]), is tone within the scale, but the felt impression of upward striv-
suggestive of movement beyond the basic chord, indeed of caden- ing is nonetheless present. When it comes to the minor triad,
tial motion; thus it is this hearing that is melodically primordial.49 Kurth, like many before him, goes to great lengths to explain
Turning to the minor scale, Kurth presents only one exam- its opposite-yet-equal relationship to major. With emphasis on
ple of experiencing motion, shown in Example 3, while ac- parallel triads and with explicit reference to Riemann’s har-
knowledging the possibility of many others. Here, the monic dualism, he writes,
aforementioned gravitational field comes into play, with the
minor triad C–E[–G offering points of repose for the interme- The minor triad with the same root has the opposite con-
diate tones D and F. In the upper portion of the scale, two struction (not, as Riemann would like, one whose root is
displaced by a fifth [downward, i.e., F minor]). For the C
conflicting dynamic courses prevail: one “upwardly striving minor triad, with respect to the C major triad, involves a
with the leading-tone tetrachord G–A–B–C,” and one striving transformation in the characteristic third scale degree,
downward “in its exact [intervallic] reversal C–B[–A[–G.”50 which contains the suggestion of a downward-striving ten-
dency in relation to the form of the chord of nature (a
transformation of the E to E[); [and] again, only the sug-
49 “Neigt man im Hören mehr zu diesem [d. h. c–e–g–c], so ist auch die gestion, because the consonance [of minor] is also com-
‘harmonische’ Strebung in der Skala eine ganz andere; sie ruht st€arker in plete: it is based only on intervals that are contained in the
sich. . . . Diese Hörweise der Skala [d. h. erst gegen die Unterdominante, chord of nature and constitutes the only other consonant
dann zur Dominante und in die Tonika zurück] ist die melodische triadic form besides the major chord, determined through
ursprünglichere, indem sie von der Bewegungsdynamik an sich und noch the fusion of the same constituent intervals.52
nicht von Dreikl€angen beeinflußt ist” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 207). Even
further possibilities for experiencing the scale are outlined in Kurth 51 “Theorie und naives Hören gehen an ihnen vorüber, weil sie sich als
([1931] 1947, 207–8). Readers might regard Kurth’s melodic-harmonic unmittelbare Gehörseindrücke in intensiven Klangfarben kundgeben”
distinction as somewhat tenuous; indeed, following Heinrich Schenker, (Kurth [1931] 1947, 212; emphasis mine). At the end of Section 3 (pp.
Example 2(b) could be described as a melodic composing-out 238–49), Kurth identifies three intermingled sources of color in music: in-
(Auskomponierung) of the tonic triad. For Kurth, however, this reading strumental color, color within a fused simultaneity, and the movement of
would suggest that the triad takes priority over the sensation of motion. color (Farbenbewegtheit) through the movement of chords.
Ultimately, it is his emphasis on the embodied quality of music listening 52 “Gegenform ist der Molldreiklang gleichen Grundtons (nicht, wie
that put him at odds with Schenker; for more on this, see Tan (2015, esp. Riemann wollte, eines um eine Quint entfernten Grundtones); denn dem
120–23) and Tan (2017, esp. 20–21). C-Dur-Dreiklang gegenüber bedeutet der c-Moll-Dreiklang eine
50 “Aufw€artsstrebend mit dem Leitton-Tetrachord g–a–h–c, abw€arts in des- Ver€anderung im charakteristischen Terzton, der bei Beziehung auf
sen genauer Umkehrung (zwei Ganztönen und einem Leitton nach unten) Naturklangsform die Andeutung einer Tiefenstrebung (Ver€anderung des e
c–b–as–g” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 208). zu es) enth€alt, wieder nur die Andeutung, da die Klangkonsonanz auch
kurth and riemann on music theory and the mind 9

physical point of view, and not the psychological one, is


there something primary for the major triad (chord of na-
ture) since in music the degree of consonance [for major and
minor] is the same and the strivings are of the same nature,
only polar opposites of one another.56
The entire opposition between “monistic” and “dualistic”
example 4. “ Concealed” leading-tone strivings within major theory is thus invalid. The present explanation would be
and minor triads “monistic” in the sounding sense while “dualistic” in the en-
ergetic sense.57

For Kurth, the dualism of major and minor triads lies not in In arguing that there is something special about the major
their outer, symmetrical construction but in the opposite striv- triad from an acoustic (or “physical”) perspective, Kurth aligns
ings of their chordal thirds. Moreover, one perceives these himself with harmonic monism. But when insisting that psy-
strivings not in isolation but as attributes of the entire chord, chological equivalence is more important he situates himself
as chordal color: “the tonal striving that is inherent in the third within a dualist camp.58 Indeed, Kurth reassures the reader
tone radiates over the respective characters of major and minor that though the sources of tension in major and minor triads
chords, which are at once idiosyncratically clear and yet beyond are not identical, their outward striving, the leading-tone ef-
words.”53 fect, is.
Notably, Kurth’s explanation for the sources of upward- and
downward-directed tensions is not dualist, since he derives the 3. SHARPWISE AND FLATWISE DIRECTIONS AROUND THE CIRCLE OF
downward-striving tendency of the minor chord from a trans- KEYS: THE SENSATION OF CHANGING COLORS
formation of the major chord. But why not point instead to
leading-tone strivings in the descending minor scale as the Kurth’s third fundamental form is the circle of keys
source for the chordal third in minor? One reason might stem (Tonartskreis). As he explains, it is generally accepted that the
from Kurth’s assertion that the major scale, with its balanced ordering of major and minor keys as either a dominant-related
dynamic trajectory, is the generative element of the tonal sys- series (increasing sharps) or a subdominant-related series (in-
tem; the minor scale, with its various forms, cannot do the creasing flats) governs the tonal system and its colorful exten-
same conceptual work.54 However, in referencing the chord of sions (farbenreichen Ausweitungen), but the true dynamic aspect
nature, he also acknowledges that the major triad is acoustically of these arrangements remains concealed. The solid arrows in
privileged; and in so doing, he reveals that he, too, cannot Example 5 indicate that a single move sharpwise entails raising
shake the long history of grounding tonality in the overtone one scale step to activate a new leading tone; for instance, C in
series.55 Recognizing the possible confusion that might ensue G major becomes C] in D major. Conversely, as the dotted
from his explanation of major-minor duality, he clarifies in arrows in Example 5 indicate, a move flatwise causes a leading
two footnotes: tone in the starting key to deactivate: “the tone that was previ-
ously most intense (vordem intensivst wirkende Ton) is low-
Nevertheless, the present view maintains that the major
mode has no actual primacy in music. Only according to the ered.”59 As Kurth underscores, leading-tone strivings govern
the perceptual experience of the circle of keys; root relation-
ships are only an external reification of this experience: “This
eine vollst€andige ist: sie besteht nur aus Intervallen, die im Naturklang
enthalten sind und stellt die einzige noch konsonante Dreiklangsform 56 “Die vorliegende Auffassung schiebt dem Dur gleichwohl kein eigen-
neben dem Durakkord dar, durch Verschmelzung der gleichen tliches Primat in der Musik zu. Nur nach physikalischem Gesichtspunkt
Teilintervalle bedingt” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 214–215). l€age für den Durklang (Naturklang) eines vor, psychologisch nicht, da für
53 “Die im Terzton verfestigte Tonstrebung strahlt aber in den eigenartig die Musik der Konsonanzgrad der gleiche und die Strebungen gleichen
klaren, gleichwohl mit Worten nie beschreibbaren Gesamtcharakter der Wesens, nur polar einander entgegengesetzt sind” (Kurth [1931] 1947,
Dur- bzw. Mollakkorde aus” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 216). In Romantische 215n.3; emphasis original).
Harmonik ([1920] 1975), Kurth acknowledges a similar emphasis on the 57 “Der ganze Gegensatz zwischen ‘monistischer’ und ‘dualistischer’ Theorie
chordal third in August Halm’s harmony treatise (1900) but remarks that wird damit hinf€allig; ‘monistisch’ w€are die vorliegende Erkl€arung im klan-
Halm fails to identify the third’s origin in the leading tone. According to glichen, ‘dualistisch’ im energetischen Sinn” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 215n.2).
Kurth, “Halm is entangled in Riemann’s representation of major and mi- 58 For a succinct comparison of harmonic monism and dualism, see
nor as formal-inversion of triads, [and] therefore does not get away from Klumpenhouwer (2002, 459). In Voraussetzungen, Kurth speaks positively
the sonic foundation of music” (183, emphasis original). See Rothfarb of the harmonic theory of Georg Capellen, who coined the term
(2009, 53–54), for more on Halm’s energetic reading of the major third. “monism”; he views Capellen’s work as a “unification of the methods of
For the ramifications of Kurth’s dynamic dualism for augmented and di- Riemann and Sechter” (Rothfarb 1979, 136). See Bernstein (2002, 800–
minished chords, see Kurth ([1931] 1947, 215n.4). 2), for an overview of Capellen’s ideas.
54 Kurth ([1931] 1947, 209). 59 Kurth ([1931] 1947, 210). Note that Kurth does not mention that flatten-
55 Cook (2002) provides a short history of this pursuit. Unlike Schenker, ing ^7 generates a new ^4 (intermediate goal). Harrison’s (1994) own
Kurth in no way attributes any mythical import to the chord of nature; see “renewed dualist theory,” which bears a striking resemblance to Kurth’s,
Clark (1999). does address this transformation; see especially section 1.3.3.
10 music theory spectrum 0 (2020)

Finally, leading-tone accumulation also allows Kurth to


explain the effects of distant modulations within a single
piece of music. Here his position as a monotonal theorist
steeped in a world of highly chromatic music is evident, as
he argues for the psychological sustainability of a global
tonic:
There is a tonal memory that goes beyond the aural memory; it
does not capture the reality of the tone, but rather certain
energetic conditions, which [tonal memory] retains as its
center. . . . The [global tonic] can be so firmly held in
mind—semi-consciously [or] even unconsciously—that the
example 5. “ Activating” (solid arrow) and “ deactivating” entire character of the modulation is determined through
(dotted arrow) a leading tone between G major and D major it.63

In Wolf’s “An den Schlaf,” for instance, the initial tonic, A[,
activation and deactivation of leading tones causes a change of continues to exert its strength even as the music strays toward
intensity units, already indicating a psychological-dynamic ef- the key of E major and leading tones are deactivated. Of
fect that penetrates the chordal voicing of the succession of fif- course, A[/G] continues to sound until the end of the work.
ths.”60 Thus from their origins in the scale, leading tones Yet even in cases where the global tonic is no longer acousti-
undergo “psychologically radical conversions” (psychologisch cally present, it nevertheless determines the character of the
durchgreifende Umsetzungen) to form the basis of large-scale modulation from its seat in the imagination: “the [starting]
tonal motions. tone becomes imaginary and yet [it persists as] a point of rela-
Notably, leading-tone strivings accumulate: traveling in the tion of magical power.”64
dominant direction around the circle of keys increases the *
overall number of upward-striving leading tones, while travel- Kurth invites the reader to compare his psychological ap-
ing in the subdominant direction decreases them. Kurth likens proach to older, well-known music theories, emphasizing that
increasingly distant key relationships “like that between C ma- “it is not an intellectual schematic but rather a dynamic inner
jor and D major or C major and A major, C major and E ma- tension on which this ‘diatonic’ chordal system is formed and
jor, etc.” to “simple dominant relationships” that grow that animatedly interfuses [it], despite appearances of outer
exponentially.61 The circle also governs individual harmonies rigidity.”65 Scale-degree theory (Stufentheorie), with its system-
within a progression, as well as chord-to-chord successions. atic construction of triads and seventh chords on degrees of
But just like melodic strivings within the major and minor tri- the diatonic scale, can certainly appear to gloss over experien-
ads, the effects of leading-tone activations cannot be brought tial differences among these chords.66 Yet it is Riemann’s
to conscious awareness through description alone. They must
be experienced. Kurth writes, 62 “Die Klangbewegung, welche die Relationswirkung zwischen den einzel-
nen Kl€angen im Quintenkreis schafft, verarbeitet jene ursprünglich in
The chordal motion, which creates the relational impact
among the individual chords in the circle of fifths, processes Leittonver€anderung beruhenden Intensit€atsunterschiede wieder in neuer
further, in a new way, those differences in intensity that Weise: über die einzelnen Akkordspannungen hinausgehend, l€aßt sie ein
originate in the leading-tone transformation: going beyond strömendes Spannungs- und Farbenspiel ins Empfinden treten, das zwar
the individual chordal tensions, it allows a streaming play of durch Leitton- (Vorzeichen-)Einheiten geregelt ist, aber als eine harmo-
tension and color to be experienced; [this play of tension and nische Erscheinung für sich verspürt wird; so ließe sie sich auch nie durch
color] is indeed regulated through leading-tone (accidental-) bloße Erkl€arung der verborgenen Leittonunterschiede oder auch der
units but is felt as a singular harmonic phenomenon. A simple Entfernungsgrade der Fundamente für jemand ins Bewußtsein rufen, dem
explanation of latent leading-tone differences or even of the etwa diese Wirkungen zu zeigen w€aren; denn auch sie stellen Wirkungen
degrees of distance from the fundamental would never suf- eigenen Grades und Charakters dar, die nur durch ihr Ertönen selbst dar-
fice to call the phenomenon to the mind of another to stellbar sind” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 212; emphasis original).
whom one wished to show these effects; for these constitute 63 “Es gibt eben auch ein Tonged€achtnis, das über Gehörsged€achtnis hinausgeht;
effects of a peculiar degree and character, which are only de- es erfaßt nicht die Realit€at des Tones, sondern gewisse Energiezust€ande,
ducible through their sounding.62 als deren Zentrum er vorschwebt. . . . Dennoch kann er halbbewußt, sogar
auch unbewußt, so fest vorschweben, daß der ganze Charakter der
60 “Dies Einschalten und Ausschalten von Leittönen bewirkt einen Wechsel Ausweichungen durch ihn bestimmt ist” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 232; em-
von Intensit€atseinheiten, weist also bereits auf eine psychologisch- phasis original).
dynamische Wirkung, welche die Klanglagerung der Quintreihen 64 “Der Ton wird imagin€ar und doch ein Beziehungspunkt von magischer
durchdringt” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 210, emphasis original). Kraft” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 232).
61 “Entferntere Verh€altnisse hingegen (wie zwischen C-Dur und D-Dur 65 “Es ist kein intellektuelles Schema, sondern eine dynamische
oder C-Dur und A-Dur, C-Dur und E-Dur usw.) sind am besten als Innenspannung, welche dieses ‘leitereigene’ Klangsystem bildet und trotz
potenzierte Dominantverh€altnisse den einfachen Dominantverwandtschaften scheinbarer, €außerlicher Starre lebensvoll durchsetzt” (Kurth [1931] 1947,
gegenüberzustellen” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 213). 218; emphasis mine).
kurth and riemann on music theory and the mind 11

theory of harmony that Kurth singles out as the greatest of- foundation for building all systems of music theory, it must
fender. Recall that Kurth refers to Riemann within his discus- be admitted at the outset that our entire music theory can-
not do without a certain instinctive character alongside of
sion of major and minor triads. In a subsequent section, he
an objective scientific one.71
states in no uncertain terms that his predecessor’s theory lacks
pragmatism and perceptual relevance: Lee A. Rothfarb has rightly highlighted that what Kurth is re-
ally after is a psychological logic, and he continues, “if psycho-
From this standpoint [that logic is paramount], one can
only consider it unfortunate that Riemann’s chordal system, logical logic is what we need, then variable human instincts
an impressive conceptualization and complete geometrical and mental processes come into play, meaning that no music
representation of harmony, contradicts hearing. For how theory can be wholly objective or unassailably ‘scientific.’”72 The
simple would the problems of music theory be—despite the distinction between “instinctive” and “objective scientific” in
somewhat large exertion of thinking—if they were all sub- the passage above certainly supports Rothfarb’s interpretation.
mitted to such rational symmetrical construction, which
furthermore, would merely have to be tied to the chord!67 Yet later in Voraussetzungen Kurth insists, “to a certain extent
music psychology, too, can be objectively defined.”73
Riemann’s appearance in Musikpsychologie, for anyone familiar Indeed, Kurth was not immune to the call of Wissenschaft.
with Kurth’s earlier writings, is hardly a surprise. Less obvious, In 1913, however, his position more closely resembles a late-
however, is that the principle of dynamic dualism is an out- nineteenth-century stance, one taken by Wundt for instance,
growth of Kurth’s engagement with Riemann over several dec- that “the human sciences (Geisteswissenschaften) are based on
ades, and that the increasingly psychological tenor of ‘immediate’ (unmittelbare) experience and the natural sciences
Riemann’s writings would prompt Kurth to refine his own upon ‘mediate’ (mittelbare) experience, abstracted from the for-
psychological views. In the next section, we will spend some mer.”74 That is, he was critical of music theories that relied on
time with Kurth’s responses to Riemann before and after acoustics not because of their claim to science but because of
1918. their pursuit of logical consistency at the expense of immediate
experience. Moreover, he took umbrage with the idea that a
responses to riemann theory could have greater intellectual import simply because it
described the world in measurable, precise ways.75
Ludwig Holtmeier has suggested that the “theory of dualistic Kurth was particularly critical of the justification for har-
derivation” is “synonymous with the notion of ‘science’ (or monic dualism that Riemann set forth in 1905, which reads:
rather, its more inclusive German correlate, Wissenschaft).”68 [W]hat distinguishes major from minor comes down to the
And Alexander Rehding has noted that Riemann in particular essence of major consonance being the simplest ratios in the
“was interested not so much in the results of science as in the increase in speed of vibration [4:5:6], and that of minor conso-
prestige that science enjoyed in his time.”69 Kurth makes a nance, by contrast, being the simplest ratios in the enlarge-
ment of the vibrating mass (wavelength, length of string,
similar observation about Riemann in Voraussetzungen, align-
etc.). Thus, put simply, the principle of major can be seen
ing Riemann’s dualist explanations for minor with tone psy- to lie in growing intensity, the principle of minor with ac-
chology.70 As we have seen, Kurth firmly disavows any cumulating mass. . . . Hauptmann’s “downward-dragging
association with tone psychology in 1931, but already in 1913, weight” of the minor chord can be fully grasped only when
he deems tone-psychological findings inadequate as the basis one recognizes the growing mass of the deeper tones con-
nected to tone 1, in contrast to which the upward-striving,
for music theory, or to use Riemann’s term, for musikalische
bright luminous character of the major consonance is best
Logik. He writes: explained in terms of all the tones connected to tone 1 (the
prime) owing their origin to the increases in frequency.76
The area in which the deficiency of scientific premises
emerges is in the uniform and complete transition from Furthermore, Riemann held that if undertones weren’t natural,
acoustics to musical logic. And as long as tone psychology
provides no clearly decisive solution to that basic question his dualist principles could operate independently of actual
[i.e., of the transition from acoustics to musical logic] as a sound: “These series do not require verification by way of

66 See Kurth ([1931] 1947, 219) for an assessment of Sechter’s work. 71 Trans. Rothfarb (1989, 22).
67 “Von diesem Gesichtspunkt kann man es gewiß nur als schade bezeich- 72 Rothfarb (1989, 19); emphasis mine.
nen, daß Riemanns Klangsystem, eine imposante Denkleistung und volle 73 Trans. Rothfarb (1979, 97); emphasis mine.
Geometrisierung der Harmonik, der Hörweise widerspricht; denn wie 74 Ash ([1995] 1998, 23).
einfach w€aren—trotz der etwas größeren Denkanstrengung—die 75 He writes in Voraussetzungen: “The dispute concerning the scientificity of
Probleme der Musiktheorie, wenn sich alles solch verstandesm€aßigem music theories is thus relegated simply to preliminary psychological dem-
Symmetrieaufbau fügte, der zudem lediglich an den Klang zu knüpfen onstrations, and as long as these remain hypothetical, the idea of the sci-
h€atte!” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 219n.1). entificity of music theory is relative. In this sense, the scientific status of
68 Holtmeier (2011, 11). Riemann’s theories, too, remains relative, even though the system as such is
69 Rehding (2003, 108). carried out with mathematical exactitude.” Trans. Rothfarb (1989, 22);
70 See Rehding (2003, 52–53 and 108–9), for a discussion of Riemann’s emphasis mine.
attempts to make Stumpf’s fusion hypothesis work to dualistic ends. 76 Trans. Bent (2011, 182).
12 music theory spectrum 0 (2020)

acoustical phenomena, referral to which only complicates and music are psychological phenomena, [i.e.,] basic functions
confuses the understanding of what are in themselves very sim- of hearing, [and] not random constructions of fantasy.82
ple ratios.”77
In brief, immediate impressions of space, motion, matter, and
Kurth disputes this explanation in the fourth chapter of
force occur in the course of music listening, but they can never
Voraussetzungen. He singles out the reference to Hauptmann’s
be brought to full and precise conscious awareness, not least
The Nature of Harmony and Meter, in which the author also
through any tangible external representation.
suggests that the character of the minor triad corresponds to
Returning to Kurth’s youthful suggestion for salvaging
the “hanging boughs of the weeping willow as contrasted with
dualism—as an imagined abstraction—it is worth noting that
the aspiring arbor vitae.”78 Kurth notes that this is merely a vi-
this bears significance in two of Riemann’s later publications:
sual metaphor and not one that is immediately given through
“Ideas for a Study ‘On the Imagination of Tone’” (Ideen zu
musical listening and associated embodied responses. Further,
einer “ Lehre von den Tonvorstellungen,” 1914–15) and “New
he argues, Riemann’s suggestion that the gravitational center
Contributions toward a Study ‘On the Imagination of Tone’”
of the chord lies in its highest note goes against human experi-
(Neue Beitr€age zu einer Lehre von den Tonvorstellungen, 1916).
ence. Kurth writes: “In our perception we recognize only
In these, Riemann rehearses yet another justification for dual-
weight pressing upon a base and not pendulous weight, and
ism, described by Daniel Harrison as follows: “Riemann’s in-
even the most comprehensible, systematic presentation is inca-
ability to provide a respectable acoustic explanation for his
pable of changing anything in the psychology of our musical
experiences of major/minor duality forced him to consider a
perception.”79 Nevertheless, he is willing to admit the allure of
psychological-philosophical explanation. And, while he does
dualism. He muses that perhaps the perceptual given of the
overtone series could spark an analogous but purely abstract
undertone series. In this way, “the physical basis of the theory 82 “Alle Zeichen jener Unwirklichkeit erscheinen nun dem merkwürdigen
would no longer be dual, but the organization of the system Ph€anomen der Raumvorstellung aufgepr€agt. Die Kraft vermögen wir
unmittelbar zu erfühlen und wir erkennen in tönenden Symbolen ihre
would still be based upon a type of psychological dualism.”
Verlaufsformen; sie gibt sich also gefühlsm€aßig und sinnlich kund. Die
That is, undertones could be plausibly imagined.80 Materieempfindung vermögen wir im sinnlichen Eindruck aufzunehmen,
Moreover, Kurth does not dismiss the idea that musical freilich beruht sie erst in einer psychisch bedingten Umwandlung der
phenomena carry impressions of mass and weight. On the Tonreize. Der Raum aber entzieht sich sowohl der deutlichen Erfühlung
contrary, he suggests that in musical listening, the sensation of wie auch dem klaren Bewußtwerden; die Raumvorstellung verfließt sogar
motion (which we encountered in relation to dynamic dual- gerade dann, wenn man sie in die Regionen der Deutlichkeit, eines
ism) as well as the sensations of mass and weight give rise to a geometrisch-anschaulichen Raumes heben will. Raum und Materie sind
die Erscheinungen einer Zwischenschicht zwischen unterbewußten
“conception of space” (Raumvorstellung), underscoring: “in the
Tiefenvorg€angen und der eigentlichen Klangwelt. Dennoch sind auch
conception of space with regard to tones, it is not so much a Raum- wie Materieempfindungen in der Musik psychologische
matter of any specific geometrical formations as it is of the Ph€anomene, Grundfunktionen des Hörens, nicht etwa zufallsbedingte
aforementioned characteristics of the spatial dimension: mass Phantasiegebilde” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 116).
and weight.”81 Almost two decades later, Kurth further devel- Kurth’s conception of space as resistant to reification, combined with
ops this idea, devoting an entire section of Musikpsychologie to his emphasis on an embodied sensation of motion, resembles Bergson’s
the impressions of “Force, Space, Matter” (Section 2). He treatment of the subject in An Introduction to Metaphysics ([1912] 1999).
Bergson begins this essay by considering the movement of an object in
writes,
space. The viewer, “placed outside the object itself,” can express this mo-
All indications of that unreality seem imprinted in the tion using various points of reference and symbols; this is what Bergson
strange phenomenon of the concept of space. We are able terms “relative” motion. In contrast to this, he describes an “absolute”
to feel force directly, and we recognize in sounding symbols movement that anticipates Kurth’s perspective: “I am attributing to the
its forms of development; this manifests itself emotionally moving object an interior and, so to speak, states of mind; I also imply
and sensually. We are able to absorb the sensation of matter that I am in sympathy with those states, and that I insert myself in them
in the sensory impression; to be sure, it is based only on a by an effort of imagination. . . . And what I experience will depend neither
psychically conditioned transformation of the sounding on the point of view I may take up in regard to the object, since I am in-
stimuli. Space, however, eludes both the clear inner feeling side the object itself, nor on the symbols by which I may translate the mo-
and the precise becoming-conscious; the concept of space tion, since I have rejected all translations in order to process the
slips away just when one wants to elevate it into the realm original” (21).
of clarity, [into] a geometric-descriptive space. Space and In Musikpsychologie, Kurth cites Bergson on a few occasions, though
matter are phenomena of an intermediate layer between not this particular essay; see n. 31 above. Dahlhaus (1973) proposes that
subconscious depth processes and the actual sounding Bergson’s influence is pervasive throughout Kurth’s life’s work: “decisive
world. Nevertheless, the sensations of space and matter in themes, from which Kurth’s music-theoretical thinking were determined
and supported, go back to Bergson (and Schopenhauer, by whom Bergson
77 Trans. Bent (2011, 185). was in turn influenced).” De la Motte-Haber (1986–87, 103), in contrast,
78 Hauptmann ([1888] 1989, 17). suggests that Bergson’s influence has been over-estimated by scholars after
79 Trans. Rothfarb (1979, 127). his time. Tan (2013, 31–34) briefly examines these differing viewpoints,
80 Trans. Rothfarb (1979, 62–63). but a focused study on this subject by a scholar well versed in Bergson’s
81 Trans. Rothfarb (1979, 106). writings is warranted.
kurth and riemann on music theory and the mind 13

not go so far as to say that the duality of major and minor is impose rules upon it.”88 Hence the student learns to envision a
an act of the ‘imagining spirit’ . . . the psychological nature of single tone in one of six possible ways—as major and minor
this duality for him . . . is strongly suggested.”83 So described, triadic roots, thirds, and fifths—thus engendering a
Riemann would seem to be operating along similar lines to “representation of a tonal complex” (Klangvertretung). In turn,
Kurth in 1913. each interval of a third or fifth can represent two possible
“What do we really imagine?,” Riemann asks several times triads—one major and the other minor. Finally, given mani-
in the 1914–15 article. By this he means, what can we be fold possibilities of meaning for a single tone or single interval,
taught to imagine? For the ultimate goal of his course of study Riemann’s Principle of the Greatest Economy for the Musical
is to train the mind of the listener to access the mind of the Imagination is applied: the mind will select the meaning that
composer. He notes that one would be misguided to search for “weighs less heavily on the powers of interpretation.”89 All
the essence of musical artistry in the musical work itself; how- told, Riemann presents a musical logic that could be construed
ever, musical notation serves as a reliable conduit for the trans- as a psychological logic, just as Kurth, a year prior, had indi-
ference of mental images. Riemann writes: cated was sorely needed.
Indeed, in the 1914–15 article, Riemann distances himself
[T]he ‘Alpha and Omega’ of musical artistry is not found in from Stumpf’s and Helmholtz’s tone-psychological work, em-
the actual, sounding music, but rather exists in the mental
image of musical relationships that occurs in the creative phasizing the inadequacy of their physical and physiological
artist’s imagination—a mental image that lives before it is foundations.90 And in their place, he adopts a new ally: Kurth.
transformed into notation and re-emerges in the imagina- In a 1918 review of Kurth’s Grundlagen, Riemann suggests
tion of the hearer. The process of notating an artistic crea- that their approaches to music and mind are fundamentally
tion as well as the sounding performance of the work are the same. He writes,
merely expedients to transplant musical experiences from
the composer’s imagination into the imagination of the mu- In contrast [to the foregoing faults of Grundlagen], much
sical listener.84 more important, actually new, striking, and sensational is
Kurth’s aesthetic fundamental philosophy of the essence of music:
Reading Riemann, it is clear that seeing is knowing. Robert his oppositional stance against the attempts at [establishing a]
Wason and Elizabeth West Marvin posit that Riemann’s use tone-psychological foundation for the theory of music. Here
of the word “Vorstellung” comes closest to that of Kurth proves to be an intrepid comrade-in-arms for the es-
Schopenhauer, that is, “an exceedingly complicated physiologi- tablishment of a study on the imagination of
tone. . . . Essentially, what appears here is identical to what
cal process in the brain of an animal, the result of which is the
I stated as ideas for a study on the imagination of tone in
consciousness of a picture there.”85 Brian Hyer, in turn, high- the Jahrbuch der Musikbibliothek Peters (1914–15 and
lights Riemann’s explicit appeals to visual representation, in- 1916).91
cluding his allusions to painting and reading. Hyer writes:
“For Riemann, the decisive factor in the cognition of music— Kurth, however, was reluctant to go to battle alongside
the moment music comes alive—is visual rather than aural. It Riemann, responding immediately that their ideas were far
is the ability to form visual images from the raw data of aural from identical.92 For since his 1913 habilitation thesis, Kurth
perception that allows a musician to synthesize musical experi- had deepened his conviction that a psychology of music had to
ence into a unified temporal consciousness.”86 Components of account for impressions that were irretrievable from the depths
Riemann’s theoretical apparatus also presuppose a correspon- of the unconscious; this put him increasingly at odds with his
dence between the aural and visual senses. His Table of Tonal predecessor. Kurth also grew more adamant that the
Relations, for instance, is a spatial grid for relating pitches,
harmonies, and keys; as Hyer notes, it “represents a vast ab- 88 Trans. Wason and Marvin (1992, 85).
straction from musical experience, a mental construct, less real, 89 Trans. Wason and Marvin (1992, 88).
perhaps, than imaginary.”87 90 Sounding very much like Kurth, Riemann states: “The hope that Stumpf
In Riemann’s teaching, such mental constructs line the would transport the foundation of music theory from a physiological to a
path from confusion to clarity. Indeed, his belief that the mind psychological domain has not been fulfilled, and music listening still
appears as a physical process in Stumpf, even more so than in Helmholtz.
seeks clarity, simplicity, and order is reflected in the study’s
The ‘logical activity’ of musical hearing, which I had postulated already in
credo: “that from the very start and from then on we investi- 1873, plays no role in his work” (trans. Wason and Marvin 1992, 82).
gate the active imagination, the images of tone, and that we seek 91 “Viel wichtiger, wirklich neu, frappierend und sensationell ist dagegen die
to ascertain which categories of thought guide and determine the €asthetische Grundanschauung Kurths vom Wesen der Musik, seine oppositio-
living, working musical imagination, and which categories nelle Stellungnahme gegenüber den Versuchen tonpsychologischer Grundlegung
der Theorie der Musik. Hier erweist sich mir Kurth als ein wackerer
Mitstreiter für die Grundlegung einer Lehre von den
83 Harrison (1994, 263). Tonvorstellungen. . . . Im Grunde ist das, was er dabei findet, identisch
84 Trans. Wason and Marvin (1992, 82). mit dem, was ich als Ideen zu einer Lehre von den Tonvorstellungen im
85 Wason and Marvin (1992, 73; emphasis mine). Jahrbuch der Musikbibliothek Peters (1914/15 und 1916) vorgetragen
86 Hyer (1995, 104). habe” (Riemann 1918, 27; emphasis original).
87 Hyer (1995, 102). See also Mooney (1996). 92 See Kurth (1918).
14 music theory spectrum 0 (2020)

unconscious was a “self-existing power” (eine selbstbestehende from Kurth’s conception of an ineffable, evolving space (recall:
Macht) that deserved attention.93 Indeed, the very opening of “Space, however, eludes both the clear (inner) feeling and the
Romantische Harmonik highlights Kurth’s emphasis not on precise becoming-conscious; the concept of space slips away
imagination or representation, but on inaudible forces and just when one wants to elevate it into the realm of clarity,
movement. He writes: “Harmonies are reflexes of the unconscious. [into] a geometric-descriptive space”). Finally, the entire study
Everything sounding in music is only the apparent emanation of Tonvorstellungen, with its emphasis on “the consciousness of
of far more powerful primordial processes, whose forces circu- a picture there,” brushes aside experiences that elude categories
late in the inaudible realm.”94 And in Musikpsychologie he of thought—sensations of motion, space, and matter, along
makes a distinction between unconsciously experienced psychic with color and tension—experiences that accompany even ru-
contents and consciously arranged mental concepts: dimentary constructs like the scale, chord, and circle of keys.
Thus while it may have raised music theory to the rank of an
In conscious life, the entirety of an expression becomes “actual science” (eigentliche Wissenschaft), for Kurth, it never-
clearer the more it is organized; in the unconscious [life], it is
the reverse: any structuring threatens to cloud the totality. theless fails to account for the true essence of music.99
Because one extracts the particulars from the whole, they are
no longer psychic contents, but rather become concepts; they
experience an “abstraction” (extraction) from the whole and 99 See Kurth ([1920] 1975, 182n.1). Locating precise antecedents for
are lifted out of their embedding in the psychical original- Kurth’s view of the unconscious, which undergirds his criticisms of
impression and thus from their original character.95 Riemann, is no easy feat. As many commentators have rightly suggested,
comparisons to Arthur Schopenhauer are inevitable; Kurth frequently
In contrast to his own views, Kurth positions Riemann’s references “the psychic activity of the will,” and as I note above (n.31), he
alongside philosophies that treat the unconscious as an embry- explicitly references Schopenhauer in relation to the immediacy of experi-
onic state where conscious thoughts lie before they are fully ence. Moreover, there are hitherto unacknowledged similarities in their
treatments of the body (as intrinsic to one’s perception of the external
formed.96 He questions whether Riemann’s study of
world and to the will); this is what I find most suggestive for
Tonvorstellungen “can suffice” to capture the full experience of Musikpsychologie and worthy of further investigation. Kurth’s ([1931]
music listening. Surely, he writes, “not if one accepts uncon- 1947, 108) insistence, for example, that “we imbue the changing position
scious processes only as weakened representations, and this of bodies with that feeling of motion that in reality lies within us,” reso-
appears to inform Riemann’s agenda throughout.”97 Indeed, nates with Schopenhauer’s discussion of the body in The World As Will
with his exercises on tones and intervals, Riemann presumes and Representation. For instance: “[The body] is given in intelligent per-
with certitude that focused concentration will call to mind dor- ception as representation, as an object among objects, liable to the laws of
these objects. But it is also given in quite a different way, namely as what
mant representations. Moreover, his Table of Tonal Relations
is known immediately to everyone, and is denoted by the word
advances a static, grid-like conception of space that prescribes will. . . . The act of will and the action of the body are not two different
how tones could (or should) be heard;98 this was far removed states objectively known, connected by the bond of causality; they do not
stand in the relation of cause and effect, but are one and the same thing,
93 Kurth ([1931] 1947, 41–42). though given in two entirely different ways, first quite directly, and then
94 Kurth ([1920] 1975, 1). in perception for the understanding.” (Schopenhauer [1859] 1966, Vol. 1,
95 “Im bewußten Leben wird das Ganze eines Eindrucks um so klarer, je §18, 100; emphasis original.) Daniel A. Schmicking (2007) discusses this
mehr es sich gliedern l€aßt, im unbewußten ist es umgekehrt: jede passage in his illuminating article on Schopenhauer’s relevance for the
Gliederung droht die Totalit€at zu trüben. Denn indem man die modern-day study of embodied cognition. Kurth’s own relationship to
Einzelheiten aus dem Ganzen herauslöst, sind sie nicht mehre psychische this area is considered in Tan (2017).
Inhalte, sondern werden zu Begriffen, sie erfahren eine ‘Abstraktion’ Other influences on Kurth’s unconscious have been posited. Helga de
(Herausziehung) aus dem Ganzen, werden aus ihrer Einbettung im psy- la Motte-Haber (2008, 569), for instance, suggests that his main influen-
chischen Ureindruck, somit aus ihrem ursprünglichen Charakter ces are Gustav Theodor Fechner and Eduard von Hartmann, who both
herausgehoben” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 29). Here, I read “psychischen provide extensive treatments on the topic—or in Kurthian terms, treat the
Ureindruck” as synonymous with “psychischen Funktion,” discussed in unconscious as a self-existing power. Kurth indeed refers to these figures
the first part of the article. in Musikpsychologie on several occasions but finds neither viewpoint en-
96 Gottfried Leibniz exemplifies such a stance with his “petites perceptions”; tirely satisfactory. He suggests that bifocal layers of consciousness (Ober-
see Kurth ([1931] 1947, 41n.4). Trevor Pearce (2008) provides a valuable oder Unterbewußtsein) found in both philosophies fail to capture the irra-
account of the philosophical origins of Riemann’s theory of musical hear- tional processes that govern musical experience; Kurth ([1931] 1947,
ing, situating it within a nineteenth-century Kantian tradition that 41n.1). Moreover, he asserts that Fechner’s “inner threshold,” which must
includes Christopher Sigwart, Moritz Wilhelm Drobisch, and Hermann be overcome for something to be brought to consciousness, does not yet
Lotze. address the unconscious itself; Kurth ([1931] 1947, 53n.1). See
97 “Was aber jenes Grundpostulat betrifft, so erscheint es fraglich, ob die Heidelberger (2010) and Gardner (2010) for more on Fechner and
Bezeichnung einer ‘Lehre von den Tonvorstellungen’ genügen kann; Hartmann, respectively.
sicherlich dann nicht, wenn man die unbewußten Vorg€ange nur als Brian Hyer’s (1990) provocative reading of Romantic Harmony through
geschw€achte Vorstellungen anerkennt, und das scheint Riemanns the lens of Sigmund Freud also merits consideration here. With Hyer, I
Ansichten durchwegs zugrundezuliegen” (Kurth [1931] 1947, 47). agree that Kurth would likely have encountered Freud’s writings during
98 As Burnham (1992, 6) notes, “Riemann conceives of harmonic motion his student years in Vienna, though probably only Interpretation of
spatially, as the filling in of possible spaces in a coherently arranged under- €
Dreams. (Hyer alludes to the “Ich,” “Es,” and “Uber-Ich,” concepts Freud
lying network.” formulated only in 1923, years after Romantic Harmony.) Kurth may even
kurth and riemann on music theory and the mind 15

both sides now refer back to Riemann’s writings directly but took a detour via
Kurth.”102
The point of departure for harmony as we see it is the truest To be sure, Kurth’s mature writing bears some resemblance
and most exhaustive analysis possible of what a musician of to Riemann’s in its tone and content. Indeed, it might seem
our time and culture actually hears in chords and their
connections—uninfluenced by any theoretical prejudices. curious that after making a name for himself with style-
The direct evidence of true musical perception and under- historical analysis, Kurth takes an approach to harmony that,
standing provides the empirical facts whose simplest and while serving as a corrective to Riemann’s own, is nevertheless
most complete “comprehensive description” . . . is the true speculative. Musikpsychologie appears to be a turn away from
task of a theory of harmony. what Wason has described as the “new empiricism” of the
—Rudolf Louis and Ludwig Thuille early twentieth century: a renewed focus on practical analysis,
of which the harmony treatise of Robert Louis and Ludwig
Several scholars have proposed that Kurth provides an im- Thuille is exemplary (see quote above).103 Yet Kurth and
portant continuation of Riemann’s thinking. Ernst Bücken, a Riemann each contend that his study of harmony is able to ex-
contemporary of Kurth, notes admiringly that “the overcom- plain, in a comprehensive fashion, what a listener actually hears
ing of rationalistic music theory, encouraged and attempted in chords and their connections, to quote Louis and Thuille.
by Riemann [in his Tonvorstellungen essays], has only now be- Riemann, on the one hand, promises his listener the means of
come a reality in the works of the Bern professor Ernst cutting through uncertainty and the path to absolute clarity.
Kurth.”100 Hermann Erpf, a student of Riemann, also por- Kurth, on the other hand, encourages his listener to revel in
trays Kurth’s contributions as following on the heels of his the anfractuous journey through musical time.
teacher’s. While criticizing Kurth for avoiding specific termi- Kurth’s displeasure with harmonic dualism is symptomatic
nology, he ventures: “Kurth [in Romantische Harmonik] pro- of a broader philosophical disagreement over the explanatory
vided highly valuable new suggestions for music theory, which power of music theory and its relation to psychology at the
had become completely helpless and unproductive after the time. But lest his own emphasis on “dualism” in
conclusion of Riemann’s work, as he taught a new vision of Musikpsychologie be viewed, ultimately, as a red herring, con-
the artwork, as opposed to the rigidity in paper concepts, and sider Harrison’s assertion that dualism is a “tried-and-true
first, made the starting point of his contemplation not a strategy of human inquiry . . . one of the very basic mental
formal-theoretical idea but rather the living artwork.”101 More instincts in human beings.” Indeed, “the dual organization of
recently, Holtmeier has taken an even stronger stance, declar- ideas leaves no field of endeavor and experience untouched.”104
ing, “[I]t was thanks to Kurth that many of Riemann’s central It is perhaps inevitable, then, that Kurth, a theorist who situ-
theoretical ideas gained considerable popularity: almost all im- ated his approach to music within a broad context of worldly
portant later developments of Riemannian concepts did not experiences, would eventually articulate a theory of harmony
with dualist over- (or under-) tones. Dualism gave Kurth a fa-
miliar frame of reference from which to counter what he
have found Freud’s ideas compelling, since they, too, were shaped by the regarded as static, schematic music theories. In describing how
writings of Schopenhauer, Hartmann, and further, Kurth’s philosophy opposing forces govern the experience of listening to scales,
professor Wilhelm Jerusalem; see Gödde (2010, 271). Moreover, as chords, progressions, and beyond, Kurth uses the language of
Hyer notes, the fact that Kurth never cites Freud in his writings is of
dualism to approach an intangible: the dynamic aspect of music.
minimal consequence; to do so would have been ill advised from a pro-
fessional standpoint, since Freud was generally not welcomed by univer-
sity intellectuals. I am less convinced, however, that Kurth adopted works cited
Freud’s unconscious sexual drives as a ready model—or that we need to
do so in order to understand Kurth. At issue is how we are to read his
analytical prose style. The psychoanalytical potential of Kurth’s theoreti-
Adorno, Theodor W. [1933] 1984. “Ernst Kurth’s
cal ideas, which Hyer and Wolfgang Krebs (2006), too, identify, is based ‘Musikpsychologie.’” In Musikalische Schriften VI.
on the assumption that Kurth ascribes some measure of agency to the Herausgegeben von Rolf Tiedermann. Band 19, Gesammelte
music itself (for instance, that one chord can prevent another from re- Schriften. 350–58. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
solving). This is certainly a reasonable perspective to take when reading Ash, Mitchell G. [1995] 1998. Gestalt Psychology in German
Grundlagen, Romantische Harmonik, and Bruckner. However, Kurth’s Culture, 1890–1967. Reprint. Cambridge: Cambridge
analyses cannot be divorced from the conceptual foundations expressed
University Press.
in Voraussetzungen and Musikpsychologie. With these texts in mind, the
analyses must be interpreted differently: as attempts to situate the reader
Bent, Ian. 2011. “The Problem of Harmonic Dualism: A
within the music; put another way, agency rests in the listener as a partic- Translation and Commentary.” In The Oxford Handbook of
ipant moving through the musical landscape. For a more detailed consid-
eration of Kurth’s “participant perspective,” see Tan (2017). 102 Holtmeier (2011, 39).
100 Bücken (1924–25, 358); trans. Rothfarb (1991, 3). 103 Louis and Thuille (1907); trans. in Wason (1985, 118–19).
101 Erpf (1927, 12–13); emphasis original. For more on the intersection of 104 Harrison (1994, 16). Wason (In Preparation) discusses Schenker’s own
Riemann’s and Kurth’s ideas in Erpf’s work, see Harrison (1994, 308–13), dualist tendencies as expressed in an untitled and unpublished, pre-
and Holtmeier (2011, 39–40). Harmonielehre essay on the origin of the tonal system.
16 music theory spectrum 0 (2020)

Neo-Riemannian Music Theories. Edited by Edward Gollin Halm, August. 1900. Harmonielehre. Leipzig: Göschen.
and Alexander Rehding. 167–93. Oxford: Oxford Harrison, Daniel. 1994. Harmonic Function in Chromatic
University Press. Music. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bergson, Henri. [1912] 1999. An Introduction to Metaphysics. Hauptmann, Moritz. [1888] 1989. The Nature of Harmony
Translated by T. E. Hulme. Reprint. Indianapolis: Hackett and Metre. Translated by William Edward Heathcote.
Publishing Company. Reprint. New York: Da Capo Press.
Bernstein, David. 2002. “Nineteenth-Century Harmonic Theory: Heidelberger, Michael. 2010. “Gustav Theodor Fechner and
The Austro-German Legacy.” In The Cambridge History of the Unconscious.” In Thinking the Unconscious: Nineteenth-
Western Music Theory. Edited by Thomas Christensen. Century German Thought. Edited by Angus Nicholls and
778–811. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Martin Liebscher. 200–40. Cambridge: Cambridge
Bücken, Ernst. 1924–25. “Ernst Kurth als Musiktheoretiker.” University Press.
Melos 4: 358–70. Herbst, Kurt. 1931. “Musikpsychologie und Musikwissenschaft.
Burnham, Scott. 1992. “Method and Motivation in Hugo Eine grunds€atzliche Betrachtung über E. Kurths
Riemann’s History of Harmonic Theory.” Music Theory ‘Musikpsychologie.’” Acta Musicologica 3 (2): 64–68.
Spectrum 14 (1): 1–14. Holtmeier, Ludwig. 2011. “The Reception of Hugo Riemann’s
Clark, Suzannah. 1999. “Schenker’s Mysterious Five.” 19th- Music Theory.” In The Oxford Handbook of Neo-Riemannian
Century Music 23 (1): 84–102. Music Theories. Edited by Edward Gollin and Alexander
———. 2001. “Seduced by Notation: Oettingen’s Rehding. 3–54. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Topography of the Major-Minor System.” In Music Theory Hsu, Dolores Menstell. 1966. “Ernst Kurth and His Concept
and Natural Order from the Renaissance to the Early of Music as Motion.” Journal of Music Theory 10 (1): 2–17.
Twentieth Century. Edited by Suzannah Clark and Hyer, Brian. 1990. “Musical Hysteria.” Review of Ernst Kurth
Alexander Rehding. 161–80. Cambridge: Cambridge as Theorist and Analyst by Lee A. Rothfarb. 19th-Century
University Press. Music 14 (1): 84–94.
Cook, Nicholas. 2002. “Epistemologies of Music Theory.” In ———. 1995. “Reimag(in)ing Riemann.” Journal of Music
The Cambridge History of Western Music Theory. Edited by Theory 39 (1): 101–38.
Thomas Christensen. 78–105. Cambridge: Cambridge Kim, Youn. 2003. “Theories of Musical Hearing, 1863–1931:
University Press. Helmholtz, Stumpf, Riemann and Kurth in Historical
Dahlhaus, Carl. 1973. “Nachwort.” In Ernst Kurth, Die Context.” Ph.D. diss., Columbia University.
Voraussetzungen der theoretischen Harmonik und der tonalen Klumpenhouwer, Henry. 2002. “Dualist Tonal Space and
Darstellungssysteme. Reprinted in Schriften zur Musik 14. Transformation in Nineteenth-Century Musical Thought.”
Munich: Katzbichler. In The Cambridge History of Western Music Theory. Edited
De la Motte-Haber, Helga. 1986–87. “Die Musikpsychologie by Thomas Christensen. 456–76. Cambridge: Cambridge
von Ernst Kurth: Tonpsychologie und Musikpsychologie.” University Press.
Schweizer Jahrbuch für Musikwissenschaft 6–7: 95–108. ———. 2011. “Harmonic Dualism as Historical and
de la Motte-Haber, Helga.. 2008. “Zur Suche nach Logik und Structural Imperative.” In The Oxford Handbook of Neo-
Bedeutung von Music: Geschichte und Gegenwart von Riemannian Music Theories. Edited by Edward Gollin and
Interdiziplinarit€at im Bereich musiktheoretischer Forschung.” Alexander Rehding. 194–217. Oxford: Oxford University
In Music Theory and Interdisciplinarity: 8th Congress of the Press.
Gesellschaft für Musiktheorie. Edited by Christian Utz. 563–75. Krebs, Wolfgang. 2006. “Zwischen Schopenhauer und
Graz: PFAU-Verlag. Freud. Ernst Kurths Musiktheorie als hermeneutisches
Erpf, Hermann. 1927. Studien zur Harmonie- und Klangtechnik Potential.” Zeitschrift der Gesellschaft für Musiktheorie 3
der neueren Musik. Leipzig: Breitkopf & H€artel. (2): 223–43.
Gardner, Sebastian. 2010. “Eduard von Hartmann’s Philosophy Kurth, Ernst. [1913] 1973. Die Voraussetzungen der theoreti-
of the Unconscious.” In Thinking the Unconscious: Nineteenth- schen Harmonik und der tonalen Darstellungssysteme.
Century German Thought. Edited by Angus Nicholls and Reprinted in Schriften zur Musik 14. Munich: Katzbichler.
Martin Liebscher. 173–99. Cambridge: Cambridge ———. 1917. Grundlagen des linearen Kontrapunkts: Bachs
University Press. melodische Polyphonie. Bern: Drechsel. 2nd and 3rd edition.
Gödde, Günter. 2010. “Freud and Nineteenth-Century Berlin: Hesse, 1922, 1927. Reprinted Bern: Krompholz,
Philosophical Sources on the Unconscious.” In Thinking the 1946, 1956.
Unconscious: Nineteenth-Century German Thought. Edited ———. 1918. “Zur Stilistik und Theorie des Kontrapunkts:
by Angus Nicholls and Martin Liebscher. 261–86. Eine Erwiderung.” Zeitschrift für Musikwissenschaft 1:
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 176–82.
Gollin, Edward and Alexander Rehding, eds. 2011. The ———. 1920. Romantische Harmonik und ihre Krise in Wagners
Oxford Handbook of Neo-Riemannian Music Theories. New “ Tristan.” Bern: Haupt. 2nd and 3rd edition. Berlin: Hesse,
York: Oxford University Press. 1922, 1923. Reprint. Hildesheim: Olms, 1975.
kurth and riemann on music theory and the mind 17

———. 1925 [1971]. Bruckner. 2 vols. Reprint. Hildesheim: Introductory Essay.” Master’s thesis, Hartt College of
Olms. Music, University of Hartford.
———. 1931 [1947]. Musikpsychologie. Reprint. Bern: ———. 1988. Ernst Kurth as Theorist and Analyst.
Krompholz. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Kusch, Martin. 1995. Psychologism: A Case Study in the ———. 1989. “Ernst Kurth’s Die Voraussetzungen der theoreti-
Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge. London: Routledge. schen Harmonik and the Beginnings of Music Psychology.”
Lorenz, Alfred. 1930. “Ernst Kurths ‘Musikpsychologie.’” Die Theoria 4: 10–33.
Musik 23 (3): 182–87. ———. 1991. Ernst Kurth: Selected Writings. Cambridge:
Louis, Rudolf, and Ludwig Thuille. 1907. Harmonielehre. Cambridge University Press.
Stuttgart: Grüninger. ———. 2009. August Halm: A Critical and Creative Life in
McCreless, Patrick. 1983. “Ernst Kurth and the Analysis of Music. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
the Chromatic Music of the Late Nineteenth Century.” Schmicking, Daniel A. 2007. “Schopenhauer on Unconscious
Music Theory Spectrum 5: 56–75. Intelligence and Embodied Cognition.” History of
Mersmann, Hans. 1931. “Musikpsychologie und Analyse.” Philosophy Quarterly 24 (1): 89–108.
Melos: Zeitschrift für Musik: 107–9. Schopenhauer, Arthur. [1859] 1966. The World as Will and
Mooney, Kevin. 1996. “The ‘Table of Relations’ and Music Representation. 2 vols. Translated by E. J. J. Payne. Reprint.
Psychology in Hugo Riemann’s Harmonic Theory.” Ph.D. New York: Dover Publications.
diss., Columbia University. Stein, Deborah J. 1985. Hugo Wolf’s Lieder and Extensions of
Moshaver, Maryam A. 2009. “Structure as Process: Rereading Tonality. Ann Arbor: UMI Research Press.
Hauptmann’s Use of Dialectical Form.” Music Theory Stumpf, Carl. 1907. “Erscheinungen und psychische
Spectrum 31 (2): 262–83. Funktionen.” Aus den Abhandlungen der königlichen
Pearce, Trevor. 2008. “Tonal Functions and Active Synthesis: Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften vom Jahre 1906.
Hugo Riemann, German Psychology, and Kantian Berlin: Verlag der königlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften.
Epistemology.” Integral 22: 81–116. Tan, Daphne. 2013. “Ernst Kurth at the Boundary of Music
Probst, Stephanie. 2018. “Sounding Lines: New Approaches Theory and Psychology.” Ph.D. diss., Eastman School of
to Melody in 1920s Musical Thought.” Ph.D. diss., Music, University of Rochester.
Harvard University. ———. 2015. “Beyond Energetics: Gestalt Psychology in
Rehding, Alexander. 2003. Hugo Riemann and the Birth of Ernst Kurth’s Musikpsychologie.” Theoria 22: 99–129.
Modern Musical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge ———. 2017. “‘As Forming Becomes Form’: Listening,
University Press. Analogizing, and Analysis in Kurth’s Bruckner and
Riemann, Hugo. 1905. “The Problem of Harmonic Dualism.” Musikpsychologie.” Journal of Music Theory 61 (1): 1–28.
Translated by Ian Bent. In The Oxford Handbook of Neo- Taycher, Ryan. 2012. “Deceiving the Ear: Recontextualization,
Riemannian Music Theories. Edited by Edward Gollin and Key Association, and Auxiliary Cadence in Two Songs by
Alexander Rehding. 165–93. Oxford: Oxford University Hugo Wolf.” Journal of Schenkerian Studies 6: 93–113.
Press, 2011. Wason, Robert. 1985. Viennese Harmonic Theory from
———. 1914/15. “Ideen zu einer ‘Lehre von den Albrechtsberger to Schenker and Schoenberg. Ann Arbor: UMI
Tonvorstellungen.’” Jahrbuch der Musikbibliothek Peters für Research Press.
1914/15 21–22: 1–26. ———. In Preparation. “Schenker’s Untitled Essay On the
———. 1916. “Neue Beitr€age zu einer Lehre von den Origin of Tonal Systems.” In Reading Heinrich Schenker’s
Tonvorstellungen.” Jahrbuch der Musikbibliothek Peters für Theory of Harmony (1906). Edited by Robert Wason and
1916 23: 1–21. Matthew Brown. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
———. 1918. “Die Phrasierung im Lichte einer Lehre von Wason, Robert W. and Elizabeth West Marvin. 1992.
den Tonvorstellungen.” Zeitschrift für Musikwissenschaft 1 “Riemann’s ‘Ideen zu einer “Lehre von den
(1): 26–39. Tonvorstellungen”’: An Annotated Translation.” Journal of
Riley, Matthew. 2004. “The ‘Harmonic Major’ Mode in Music Theory 36 (1): 69–117.
Nineteenth-Century Theory and Practice.” Music Analysis Wellek, Albert. 1931. Review of Musikpsychologie by Ernst
23 (1): 1–26. Kurth. Acta Musicologica 5 (2): 72–80.
Robinson, Daniel N. 1995. An Intellectual History of
Psychology, 3rd edition. Madison: University of Wisconsin
Press.
Rösler, Hans-Peter. 1997 [1998]. Die Musiktheorie von Ernst
Music Theory Spectrum, Vol. 0, Issue 0, pp. 1–17, ISSN 0195-6167,
Kurth und ihr psychologischer Hintergrund. Reprint. electronic ISSN 1533-8339. V C The Author(s) 2019. Published by Oxford
Ammersbek bei Hamburg: Lottbek. University Press on behalf of The Society for Music Theory. All rights
Rothfarb, Lee A. 1979. “Ernst Kurth’s The Requirements for a reserved. For permissions, please e-mail: journals.permissions@oup.com.
Theory of Harmony: An Annotated Translation with an DOI: 10.1093/mts/mtz017

You might also like