You are on page 1of 12

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/223959909

The Experimental Analysis of Human Behavior: Indispensable, Ancillary, or


Irrelevant?

Article in The Behavior analyst / MABA · October 1991


DOI: 10.1007/BF03392565 · Source: PubMed

CITATIONS READS

25 1,296

3 authors, including:

Michael Perone Mark Galizio


West Virginia University University of North Carolina at Wilmington
78 PUBLICATIONS 1,715 CITATIONS 111 PUBLICATIONS 2,924 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

All content following this page was uploaded by Mark Galizio on 03 June 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


The Behavior Analyst 1991, 14, 145-155 No. 2 (Fall)

The Experimental Analysis of Human Behavior:


Indispensable, Ancillary, or Irrelevant?
Alan Baron
University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee
Michael Perone
West Virginia University
Mark Galizio
University of North Carolina at Wilmington
There is growing recognition that psy- analysis emerged (Ferster, 1953; Perone,
chology as a whole is in an extraordinary in press; Sidman, 1960; Skinner, 1956).
state of transition. The changes have far- But these methodological prescrip-
reaching implications for the experimen- tions-the customs and codes that dis-
tal analysis of behavior, not only for the tinguish behavior analysis from the rest
theoretical interpretations that guide our of psychology -are increasingly violated,
research but also for the methods we use ironically, in favor of the very methods
to collect and analyze the data. to which the founders of behavior anal-
That methods of behavior analysis ysis objected (Baron, 1990).
should change over the years is not of The purpose of our target article (Bar-
itself remarkable. History tells us that on, Perone, & Galizio, 199 1) was to stim-
evolution, if not revolution, is part of the ulate discussion ofthis troublesome state
normal course of the development of a of affairs. We are honored that such a
science. What is remarkable is that many distinguished group ofscientists has seen
of these changes are taking place without fit to offer their comments in this issue
full acknowledgment or discussion. This of The Behavior Analyst. Their reasoned
has given rise to a lack of correspondence arguments will make a significant con-
between what is said and what is done. tribution to the eventual resolution of the
We continue to advocate to our students issues raised in our article. We regret that
a set of laboratory procedures, experi- the space allotted to us does not permit
mental designs, and data-analytic strat- a response to each and every one of their
egies derived from those developed in the points. We believe that we can best pro-
animal laboratories from which behavior ceed by trying to integrate our concerns.
The outcome, we hope, will be the start
of a dialogue that will help us find com-
This article was prompted by a series of com- mon ground.
mentaries (Branch, 1991; Buskist, Newland, &
Sherbume, 1991; Dinsmoor, 1991; Palmer & Don-
ahoe, 1991; Pierce & Epling, 1991; Shull & Law- THE PLACE OF THE
rence, 1991; Wanchisen & Tatham, 1991) that were HUMAN SUBJECT
written in response to a previous article of ours
(Baron, Perone, & Galizio, 1991). We thank the A good place to begin is with what ap-
commentators for their scholarly attention to the pears to be a misunderstanding. As in-
issues we raised and Editor Samuel M. Deitz for dicated by its title, our article asked
giving us the opportunity to engage in this stimu- whether application and behavioristic in-
lating dialogue.
Addresses for correspondence and reprint re- terpretation can replace laboratory re-
quests: Alan Baron, Department of Psychology, search with humans. Our efforts to an-
University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, Milwaukee, swer this question led us to assert that
WI 53201; Michael Perone, Department of Psy- laboratory research is an essential tool in
chology, West Virginia University, Morgantown WV the analysis of the reinforcement process
26506; Mark Galizio, Department of Psychology,
University of North Carolina at Wilmington, Wil- on the human level. We also commented
mington, NC 28406. on some rarely acknowledged limitations
145
146 ALAN BARON et al.

of application and behavioristic inter- with humans and animals should pro-
pretation. ceed in parallel, with each informing the
It was not, however, our intention to other. In a similar vein, Buskist et al. see
assert the two alternative propositions discrepancies between experimental out-
that our colleagues rightly take up arms comes with humans and animals as a
against: that laboratory research with challenge, not as a reason for abandoning
humans can or should replace applica- the laboratory approach. The differences
tion and interpretation, or that labora- will serve as a spur for clarifying the op-
tory research with humans can or should eration ofbasic processes in the two cases.
replace research with animals. To the Shull and Lawrence also assert that hu-
contrary, we believe that these four ap- man research is capable of revealing fun-
proaches-human research, animal re- damental relations. They have serious
search, behavioristic interpretation, and reservations, however, about the utility
practical application-stand together in of the traditional methods of the animal
a symbiotic relation. Each has a unique laboratory, and they suggest that the full
role to play. All are needed for full un- potential of human research cannot be
derstanding of the principles that guide realized without new analytic prepara-
behavior. tions.
More to the point is the relative weight Branch, Dinsmoor, and Palmer and
that should be given each approach. Sev- Donahoe are in a different camp. In their
eral commentators caution that serious view, the discovery offundamental prin-
problems confront the researcher who ciples is the province of the animal lab-
ventures into the human operant labo- oratory; human research is relegated to
ratory. Many oftheir concerns echo those an ancillary role. They do not say, how-
which we have previously described in ever, that human research can make no
some detail (Baron & Galizio, 1983; Bar- contribution at all. Human experiments
on & Perone, 1982; Perone, Galizio, & provide tests of principles already de-
Baron, 1988). The commentators also veloped with animals (Dinsmoor; Palm-
express reservations about the ultimate er & Donahoe), especially when the sub-
success of any effort to analyze the re- jects are children (Branch). Behavioral
inforcement process through experi- processes can be studied that may not
ments with human subjects. Neverthe- reach full expression in animals, such as
less, a consensus emerges. In the end, all those involved in verbal behavior
subscribe to the view that laboratory re- (Branch; Dinsmoor; Palmer & Dona-
search with human subjects has a proper, hoe). Finally, human experiments pro-
albeit neglected, place in the experimen- vide adjuncts to animal research on the
tal analysis of behavior. Dinsmoor, in effects of "layers" or sequences of expe-
particular, makes it plain that we have riences (Branch).
misunderstood his position in this re- Wanchisen and Tatham's position is
gard. We are glad that he has set the rec- difficult to place. They provide an illu-
ord straight. minating review of the challenge posed
The commentators vary considerably by historical factors in the study of on-
in their views about the contribution to going behavior. An implicit aspect oftheir
be made by human research. At one end comments is the value of considering hu-
of the spectrum -the end where we place man and animal behavior in similar
ourselves-are the positions staked out terms. But they seem unduly pessimistic
by Pierce and Epling, by Buskist, New- about the likely success of such an effort.
land, and Sherburne, and by Shull and Laboratory observations, they tell us, are
Lawrence. They see a role for the human plagued by historical factors which are
subject in the search for fundamental exceedingly difficult to identify, much less
principles of behavior. Pierce and Epling bring under control. As we pointed out
are simply tired of waiting for answers in our article, historical factors cannot be
about human behavior to come from the taken lightly; histories can obscure basic
pigeon laboratory. In their view, research processes in humans and animals alike.
EXPERIMENTAL ANALYSIS OF HUMAN BEHAVIOR 147
Nevertheless, we remain confident that hope of collecting conclusive data. Ifdata
histories (as well as the other extra-ex- from humans and animals differ, the lim-
perimental variables mentioned in our itations of the experiment may be to
article) can be accommodated within the blame; yet ifthe data are similar, the un-
traditional methods of the experimental derlying processes still may be different.
analysis of behavior. We agree that no pattern of experimental
We should also acknowledge another outcomes can provide conclusive (in the
camp within behavior analysis, one that sense of deductive) proof for any theo-
is not represented among the commen- retical proposition. Nevertheless, posi-
tators (we are not sure whether we should tive outcomes provide inductive sup-
be relieved or disappointed). We refer to port, and when a sufficient number have
the view that human behavior exempli- accumulated, the proposed principle is
fies processes and principles that simply established by consensus. The consensus
have no counterpart in the performances is, of course, provisional. Scientific un-
of rats or pigeons. It follows that under- derstanding always is vulnerable to em-
standing of exclusively human processes pirical challenge.
requires equally exclusive reliance on the Branch and Dinsmoor also look to the
study of human subjects. In the target animal laboratory, but they see some val-
article we observed that acceptance of this ue in the product of human research.
proposition charts a course away from Branch approves of "trying to examine
the other biological sciences. Suffice it to directly the generality of basic condition-
say that this is not the direction that we ing principles that have been isolated with
or the commentators wish to take. nonhumans." And Dinsmoor argues that
"once the basic principles have been
THE GENERALITY OF worked out with rats and pigeons, I do
BEHAVIORAL PRINCIPLES think it is appropriate to conduct addi-
tional tests with human subjects." We
The commentators' differing views on take these statements about examining
the value of human research hinge on the and testing animal-based principles as
question of generality. What steps are evidence that Branch and Dinsmoor do
needed to substantiate the claim that not take the principles for granted. By
principles developed in the animal lab- raising questions about generality, hu-
oratory are fundamental for humans as man research can contribute to the for-
well as for animals? Palmer and Donahoe mulation of the principles, even if only
anchor one end of the continuum. Al- to send researchers back to the animal
though they are not completely disap- laboratory to try again.
proving of research designed to show that Pierce and Epling take the argument a
animal-based principles also govern hu- step further in their objections to the
man behavior, they argue that even suc- dominant status of animal experiments.
cessful demonstrations "will not advance They express considerable impatience
our formulation of basic principles." At with the "simple-to-complex research
best, human research "will serve mainly strategy," an approach that demands
to shore up the applications and inter- analysis of "the behavior of simple or-
pretations that have taken for granted the ganisms in simple environments" as the
generality of basic principles." prerequisite for the initiation of work at
We wonder about the wisdom of con- the human level. In their view, scientific
ferring axiomatic status on the outcomes understanding of human behavior can no
of experiments with animals. As we see longer await the discovery of order in the
it, generality is an empirical issue, al- animal laboratory. The time has come for
though not necessarily one that needs to a "two-pronged approach" that will give
be addressed at every stage of the sci- human research its due, one that involves
entific endeavor. Perhaps Palmer and simultaneous and complementary efforts
Donahoe are dubious about human ex- at both levels.
perimentation because they see so little There is plenty of room within the ex-
148 ALAN BARON et al.
perimental analysis of behavior for these retical contention. We argued elsewhere
differing emphases. The important point that the evidence purporting to show the
is that the commentators agree that hu- existence ofdiscrepancies leaves much to
man research is logically continuous with be desired (Perone et al., 1988). In many
animal research, and therefore, an inte- cases, discrepancies are identified by
gral part of the basis for a general theory comparing limited samples ofhuman be-
of behavior (cf. Baron & Perone, 1982). havior against vague characterizations of
The search for fundamental relations "typical" patterns in animals. Our review
has led researchers to examine human of the literature on the so-called "fixed-
performances under schedules of rein- interval scallop" suggested that com-
forcement. Shull and Lawrence ask, "Do monly-held views about characteristic
the patterns of behavior engendered by performances are simply mistaken; there
different reinforcement schedules exem- is too much variability in the fixed-in-
plify fundamental relationships?" They terval performances of either animals or
comment that "Sometimes Baron et al. humans to permit general conclusions at
write as if they think so," and add that this stage of knowledge.
"relationships involving patterns are not
the foundation of any system that we are INTERPRETATION AND
aware of." These commentators then APPLICATION
make the case that the patterns in ques-
tion are secondary, that they "are usually Although behavioristic interpretation
conceptualized as the result of combi- and practical application cannot replace
nations of more fundamental variables." laboratory research, they can help extend
the generality of the basic principles dis-
Of course they are! Our view on this issue
covered in the laboratory. Palmer and
(Baron et al., 1991; Perone et al., 1988)
is no different from the one shared by Donahoe remind us how vital interpre-
most behavioral analysts (cf. Zeiler, tation is to the scientific enterprise. "We
engage in experimental analysis so that
1977), including Shull and Lawrence. (But
the notion mistakenly attributed to us- we can interpret the world.... Most of
that schedule-controlled response pat- our scientific understanding of the world
terns might be fundamental-is not as is interpretation: No one has done an ex-
far-fetched as Shull and Lawrence ap- perimental analysis of the tides or of the
parently believe; see Morse & Kelleher, orbit of the planets....." Interpretation
1977, and Zeiler, 1984.) is important; indeed, Palmer and Don-
ahoe's comments make it plain that it is
Having raised the issue of whether re-
sponse patterns are fundamental, Shull not only important but indispensable.
and Lawrence might have gone on to ex- We must, however, inquire further of
plain that these patterns, although sec-Palmer and Donahoe about the domains
ondary, represent an important way of they would have behavior analysts inter-
elucidating the more basic processes-forpret. For the physical scientist, interpre-
example, those related to the temporal tations of such matters as the orbits of
contingency of the fixed-interval sched-the planets are based on meticulously
collected observations. Unfortunately,
ule. Observation of the theoretically pre-
dicted temporal patterning gives us in- this is not the way things work in behav-
creased confidence in our understanding ioristic interpretations, as, for example,
of the processes that generate such an when the action of a fixed-interval sched-
outcome. Discrepancies, such as the ab- ule of reinforcement is detected in the
sence of temporal patterning in humans, behavior of students who put off studying
for exams until the last minute. More
are, therefore, more than curiosities. They
often than not, the object of behavioristic
raise doubts about our level of theoretical
understanding. interpretation is best described as "an-
Although human-animal discrepan- ecdotal"-descriptions and illustrations
cies must be reckoned with, in our view ofbehavior of unspecified origin that may
they have generated unnecessary theo- be collected without sufficient attention
EXPERIMENTAL ANALYSIS OF HUMAN BEHAVIOR 149
to errors of measurement and reported "skeptical about the utility of employing
selectively. Moreover, the interpretation (at least as they have been employed, for
may seriously misrepresent the behav- the most part, so far) direct analogues of
ioral principle that the interpretation is laboratory-conditioning procedures with
supposed to support (Michael [1980] re- adult humans." Shull and Lawrence ad-
ferred to the student example above as monish us that "nothing inherent in op-
"superficial nonsense"). Behavior anal- erant principles nor in traditional behav-
ysis lacks a set of agreed-upon observa- ior-analytic research methods requires
tional procedures that might provide ac- that the procedure mimic features of the
ceptable descriptive data about naturally rat's lever-box." Palmer and Donahoe
occurring behaviors (Baron & Perone, caution against research that "displays
1982; see also Bijou, Peterson, & Ault, only the superficial trappings of the an-
1968). Because so little progress has been imal laboratory," and Buskist et al. alert
made in this regard, the kind of inter- us to the dangers of "an infatuation with
pretation envisioned by the commenta- the operant chamber."
tors is rare. We wonder if the commentators are
Applied behavior analysis provides the confronting us with a straw person here.
other source of naturally occurring hu- In considering the wisdom of "mimick-
man behavior against which basic prin- ing" (or developing a "direct analogue")
ciples might be gauged. Branch sees many of an apparatus customarily used in an-
successes when behavioral principles are imal research, it is essential to keep sep-
directed toward the solution of practical arate the form of the apparatus (such as
problems, and he finds it hard to believe the lever used to detect the response or
that the positive outcomes could be epi- the lights and sounds that serve as dis-
phenomenal. We don't think these re- criminative stimuli) and its substance (the
sults are an accident either. We must re- principles of observation and measure-
iterate, however, that the bearing of the ment that enter into the design of the
results ofpractical application on the the- apparatus). Of course it is not essential
oretical concerns of the laboratory is lim- that human subjects be studied in struc-
ited at best. Applied research may help tures that resemble the rat's lever-box.
establish that reinforcement works, that What is essential-if one wants to com-
shaping works, that stimulus control pare the processes of operant condition-
works. But the theoretical concerns of ex- ing in humans and animals-is that the
perimental analysis run deeper. We doubt methods meet the requirements for the
that applied research can tell us much study of steady-state free-operant behav-
that will help us identify the origins of ior in the individual organism. (We trust
the fixed-ratio pause, assess the adequacy that there is agreement that this is and
of the delay-reduction hypothesis of con- should continue to be a major focus of
ditioned reinforcement, or decide among the experimental analysis of behavior.)
the various matching, melioration, and As things turn out, the lever-pressing
maximization accounts of choice. Ap- apparatus developed by Skinner does a
plied behavior analysis has an important pretty good job of incorporating the "tac-
mission, but it is more in connection with tics" needed for a steady-state analysis
solving human social problems than in (Sidman, 1960). The rat is confined in an
clarifying the theoretical issues currently environment that permits objective mea-
pursued in the laboratory. surement of a clearly defined response;
contingencies involving reinforcing and
TRADITIONAL METHODS discriminative stimuli are precisely con-
trolled; and behavior is shielded from un-
A number of the commentators take wanted influences. The commentators
us to task for advocating that research surely regard these experimental tactics
with humans should emulate the meth- as no less important when human be-
ods that have been used so successfully havior is the object of study. They should
in the animal laboratory. Branch is not, therefore, find it surprising or ob-
150 ALAN BARON et al.

jectionable that precision and control in nearly as well. In our view, the problem
human research might require physical is not that the methods of the animal
arrangements analogous to those used laboratory have had too much influence
with rats. In our laboratories, the human on the experimental analysis of human
subject works in an isolated environment behavior, but rather that they have not
(sound-shielded chamber) in which re- had enough.
inforcing events (money) are contingent
on a specified response (pressing a key;
operating one or more switches) in the
presence of stimuli (geometric forms; DEFINING BEHAVIORAL UNITS
words; sentences) displayed on a com- Some of the commentators voice
puter monitor. All these features, in con- doubts about using button pressing as the
junction with long-term study of the in- response of interest. Branch asks whether
dividual subject, play essential roles in button pressing has the status of an op-
the steady-state analysis of human per- erant. "What evidence is there that a sin-
formances. gle push of a button by a human in a
Even a cursory review of the human laboratory is a functional unit of behav-
operant literature will uncover obvious ior?" Shull and Lawrence are more con-
methodological shortcomings. By com- cerned about the complex behavioral re-
parison with animal research, human re- lations into which button pressing may
search is less likely to involve significant enter.
degrees of exposure to the experimental A human's button press seems likely to be part of
conditions, control procedures such as many different behavior classes, including such
changeover delays, objective criteria for complex, higher-order classes as "strategies" for in-
identifying steady states, or within-sub- teracting with games, complex chains prompted by
ject replications (e.g., by way of reversal and prompting verbal behavior, and "test-taking"
designs). Equally troublesome is the in- repertoires reinforced and motivated by signs of
social approval and success.
sufficient attention paid to the conse-
quences that are supposed to function as Perhaps Shull and Lawrence's com-
the reinforcers of human operant behav- ments will help convince Branch that the
ior. We share Shull and Lawrence's con- human's button press, like the rat's lever
cerns about use of "points." In the ani- press and the pigeon's key peck, provides
mal laboratory, a standard set of a legitimate vehicle for studying a range
procedures underlies the use of food as of behavioral processes. After all, we press
an effective reinforcer (e.g., establishing buttons for a variety of reasons: to tune
the stimulus as a reinforcer by arranging a radio, to withdraw cash from an au-
appropriate levels of deprivation, deliv- tomatic teller machine, and to phone
ering the reinforcer for consumption dur- our friends. (Indeed, there are honored
ing the session, and preventing satiation). professions whose members appear
Such matters need to be given more care- to do little else but engage in such move-
ful consideration in human research; as ments, including telegraphers, computer
things stand, a wide variety of reinforce- programmers, and concert pianists.)
ment procedures is used with human Branch and Shull and Lawrence do
subjects, and the effectiveness of many agree about what they take to be a fun-
of them has yet to be established (Galizio damental difference between button and
& Buskist, 1988). lever pressing. Unlike the human's but-
The apparatus and methods developed ton press, the rat's lever press is said to
by Skinner for studying operant condi- be "arbitrary" (Branch) or "uncon-
tioning in the rat have remained more- strained" (Shull & Lawrence). As Branch
or-less unchanged for 50 years. Their wide puts it, "rats were not selected genetically
use in animal research by behavioral and in environments in which levers existed
biomedical scientists serves as a testi- and presumably they have not experi-
monial to Skinner's wisdom. By com- enced such levers in their lives before
parison, human research has not done they get to the experiment." The com-
EXPERIMENTAL ANALYSIS OF HUMAN BEHAVIOR 151

mentators may be missing an important unit" of behavior -that it may not mark
point. Behavior analysts now recognize a "natural line of fracture" (Branch;
that the responses chosen for study in the Palmer & Donahoe)? It is important to
operant conditioning laboratory are remember that functional units are not
hardly arbitrary. We should have real- defined structurally, as an emphasis on
ized long ago that their successful use in the button press implies. Further, there is
experiments depends in large part upon disagreement about whether functional
their status within the animal's natural units should be identified on the basis of
repertoire. Although the particular de- order in the behavioral patterns to which
vices used in the laboratory to detect the a given response contributes, or in terms
responses (levers, keys) may not have of the contingency that relates the re-
been encountered previously, the behav- sponse to reinforcement (cf. Schick,
iors that activate these devices have oc- 1971). According to the latter, more
curred repeatedly (rearing and grasping commonly accepted view, functional
by the rat, pecking by the pigeon). Quite units have more to do with the schedules
relevant here is Schoenfeld, Antonitis, arranged by the experimenter than with
and Bersh's ( 1950) suggestion concerning the engineering of the operandum. With
the source of the "unconditioned a fixed-ratio 50 schedule, for example,
strength" of the lever-press response. the functional unit may be the run of 50
They attributed responding prior to ex- responses rather than the individual key
plicit reinforcement in the experiment to peck, lever press, or button press.
the generalized extinction of responses of Button pressing in the laboratory can
a similar character that had been con- enter into functional units of varying de-
ditioned in the history of the organism. grees of complexity. It is instructive to
A theme of our article was that the sample the range oftheoretical issues that
sorts of concerns that alarm the com- have been studied with this response. The
mentators frequently have counterparts human subject may press a button to see
in the animal laboratory. We can only a meter (vigilance; Holland, 1958), to
remind them that previous concerns identify a stimulus that resembled one
about the "prepared" nature of the op- previously presented (matching-to-sam-
erant responses of rats and pigeons (e.g., ple; Sidman, 1969), to prevent the oc-
Bolles, 1970; Seligman, 1970) have yield- currence of a signal correlated with the
ed to solutions. The pigeon's key peck, loss ofmoney (avoidance; Baron & Kauf-
in particular, has withstood challenges man, 1966), to produce stimuli correlat-
from those who have argued that our ed with the components of a compound
knowledge from studies of key pecking schedule of positive reinforcement (ob-
on operant schedules-studies which serving, Perone & Baron, 1980), to re-
constitute the majority published in the view scores reflecting a fellow subject's
Journal of the Experimental Analysis of performance (auditing, Hake, Vukelich,
Behavior (Grossett, Roy, Sharenow, & & Kaplan, 1973), or to answer "yes" or
Poling, 1982)-is flawed by the peck's "no" to questions about recent behavior
susceptibility to non-operant influences on a conditional discrimination task (ver-
(e.g., Williams & Williams, 1969). No bal self-reports; Critchfield & Perone,
doubt, complex determinants-experi- 1990). Each of these behaviors is func-
ential as well as biological-enter into a tionally distinct. Little purpose is served
human's, a rat's, or a pigeon's execution by lumping them together into a single
ofthe complex movements needed to op- class simply because the operandum hap-
erate a button, lever, or key (cf. Schwartz, pens to be the same.
1974). But this recognition does not seem
a very good basis for discarding the re- HISTORY AND CONTEXT
sults of experiments that involve such
responses. Research is conducted in laboratories
What about concerns that the button to isolate relations between the indepen-
press may not represent a "functional dent and dependent variables. The iso-
152 ALAN BARON et al.

lation is necessarily imperfect in the anal- ment is governed largely by historical


ysis ofbehavior; as Skinner often pointed variables (what else could be exerting
out, the outcome of an experiment de- control?), and significant contact with the
pends on the behavior the organism experimental variables is needed before
brings to it as well as on the conditions their effects take hold. This logic is at the
imposed by the experimenter (e.g., Skin- very foundation of the steady-state ap-
ner, 1958). A major theme of our article proach to operant conditioning. While
was that the human organism, in partic- our colleagues seem to share our enthu-
ular, arrives at the laboratory equipped siasm for steady-state research, they ex-
with a complex repertoire, one that re- press considerable doubt about its utility
flects the effects of diverse extra-experi- in overcoming history effects (Branch;
mental factors, both historical and con- Dinsmoor; Shull & Lawrence; Wanchi-
temporary. sen & Tatham). Wanchisen and Tatham
Not surprisingly, our colleagues also put it this way: "Whether history effects
are concerned about the complications eventually diminish as a correlate of ex-
introduced by these factors, and several tended exposure to the conditions under
take pains to remind us that it is much which the history effect is revealed is es-
easier to control histories in animals than sentially an open question within both
in humans (Branch; Dinsmoor; Palmer the human and non-human behavioral
& Donahoe; Wanchisen & Tatham). It is, history literature."
of course, easier to control almost every- More research will be needed to close
thing in animals. Nevertheless, control of the matter, but the available data lead us
history is not routine practice in the an- to be optimistic that history effects will
imal laboratory; researchers commonly yield to steady-state experimental de-
report without apology that their subjects signs. In an instructive study, Todorov
have had previous experience with a va- and his colleagues (Todorov, de Oliveira
riety of procedures (particularly if the Castro, Hanna, de Sa, & de Queiroz Ba-
subjects are of long-lived species such as rreto, 1983) found that sensitivity to con-
pigeons and monkeys). This casual ap- current schedules diminished as pigeons
proach should not be judged too harshly. gained experience with successive pairs
In their review of reinforcement and pun- of schedules. But when the schedule con-
ishment, Morse and Kelleher (1977) ditions were sufficiently extended- 55
pointed out that historical variables can rather than 30 sessions-sensitivity re-
be overridden by experimental proce- turned. In a similar vein, Freeman and
dures that are "especially forcing" -in the Lattal (in press) gave pigeons a history
case of animals, food following depri- that engendered high and low rates in the
vation or a painful shock. Procedures with components of a multiple schedule and
humans usually suffer by comparison then exposed the birds to a common test
(Buskist et al.'s commentary provides schedule in the presence of the compo-
some interesting lore on this point), thus nent stimuli. Although response rates dif-
making laboratory studies of human be- fered at the outset of the test, in 5 of 6
havior more vulnerable to history effects. birds they converged within about 40 ses-
The obvious antidote is to seek stronger sions. These two sets of data show nicely
forms of experimental control that can that variability caused by different his-
be imposed in the human operant labo- tories can be reduced by sufficient ex-
ratory. Although the human researcher is posure to the conditions of current in-
constrained by ethical considerations terest. As common observation tells us,
(Dinsmoor), the remedy often is within the effects of the past usually diminish as
reach -money rather than points as the the past becomes more remote.
reinforcer, for example. Do studies such as the ones cited above
A different way of dealing with history establish that we can escape the past?
effects is through long-term exposure to Branch points out that once established,
the experimental conditions. A subject's a history can never be eliminated. But
behavior at the beginning of an experi- can its effects be eliminated? Wanchisen
EXPERIMENTAL ANALYSIS OF HUMAN BEHAVIOR 153

and Tatham argue that even when his- sue. Although there appears to be con-
tory-related differences have disappeared sensus that attention must be paid to dis-
in the face of extended training, latent crepancies, there is considerable
effects may be lurking below the surface. disagreement about the interpretation to
The task here is to identify the conditions be placed on them.
under which the latent becomes mani- It is important to recognize that the
fest. We agree with Wanchisen and Tath- results of different experiments are iden-
am (cf. Wanchisen, 1990) that the focus tified as "discrepant" not merely because
of operant research and theory on con- they differ, but also because there is no
temporary influences has led to neglect principled explanation for the difference.
of the possible influences of remote his- For example, the fact that a given drug
torical factors (including their sequential increases the rate offood-reinforced lever
effects; Branch). We certainly encourage pressing in one study but decreases it in
greater attention to such factors, as an another represents a discrepancy only
area of study in its own right as well as until we have the principle of rate de-
a potential source of confounding vari- pendency to explain the difference.
ables. But we hasten to add that the tra- Discrepancies, then, are valuable be-
ditional methods of the animal labora- cause they reveal our ignorance about
tory have already proven to be up to the principles. In seeking a common expla-
task, not only with animal subjects, but nation of human and animal behavior, it
also with humans (e.g., Weiner, 1969). seems reasonable that research using
Buskist et al.'s concerns with extra-ex- analogous methods will identify discrep-
perimental factors go beyond history. ancies-gaps in our understanding- more
They note that an experiment takes place clearly than applied behavior analysis or
within a broader environmental context behavioristic interpretation.
that can have decided effects on what But identifying discrepancies is the easy
happens during the session. Perhaps many part. The challenge is in their resolution.
context effects, like those of history, can And that is where we may part company
be overriden by experimental manipu- with some of our colleagues.
lations that are sufficiently "forcing." But Should we be satisfied by saying that
unlike historical factors, which are rela- discrepancies in human and animal per-
tively remote, contextual factors are rel- formances would not have emerged if we
atively contemporaneous, and they may had viewed the problem at the proper
be more potent contributors to labora- level of analysis? If we had managed to
tory behavior. We agree with Buskist et measure the behavior along its natural
al. that the manipulation of contextual lines offracture? If we had controlled the
variables may pay dividends in the ex- context or history better? If we had been
perimental analysis of human behavior. able to simplify the subject's repertoire
And, again, we look to the animal labo- to eliminate hypothesis-testing, rule-fol-
ratory for illustrations of how traditional lowing, or attempts to please or confound
methods can be put to this use, for ex- the experimenter? If we had used more
ample, in the study of open versus closed potent reinforcers? The list of possibili-
economies (e.g., Hursh, 1984). ties may be endless. And as plausible as
such accounts sound, they are not prin-
CLOSING REMARKS cipled explanations of the differences that
might be observed in human and animal
Our target article pointed to apparent behavior. If we stop at such accounts, we
discrepancies in the outcomes of exper- have accomplished nothing more than
iments with humans and animals as pro- asserting our faith that a principled ex-
voking somewhat of a crisis in behavior planation eventually will emerge. A much
analysis. The range of viewpoints ex- greater effort is required to derive a pre-
pressed by our colleagues, and the fervor cise, verifiable explanation through ex-
with which they hold them, bear out the perimental analysis. And, because the ex-
need for continuing dialogue on this is- perimental answer must be rooted in data
154 ALAN BARON et al.
rather than logic, the answer will be for- actions and avoidance learning. Psychological
ever tentative. Review, 77, 32-48.
Is the effort worthwhile? Our col- Branch, M. (1991). On the difficulty of studying
"basic" behavioral processes in humans. The Be-
leagues acknowledge that at least some havior Analyst, 14, 107-1 10.
human research is needed in behavior Buskist, W., Newland, M. C., & Sherburne, T.
analysis. Indeed, some advise us to exert (1991). Continuity and context. The Behavior
greater energies in this regard (or, per- Analyst, 14, 111-116.
Critchfield, T. S., & Perone, M. (1990). Verbal
haps, put them to better use), in the di- self-reports of delayed matching to sample by
rection of studies on complex forms of humans. Journal ofthe Experimental Analysis of
human behavior such as handwriting, so- Behavior, 53, 321-344.
cial behavior, information processing, Dinsmoor, J. A. (1991). The respective roles of
and, of course, verbal behavior in gen- human and nonhuman subjects in behavioral re-
search. The Behavior Analyst, 14, 117-121.
eral. These are worthwhile avenues for Ferster, C. B. (1953). The use of the free operant
future research. Our concern at present, in the analysis of behavior. Psychological Bulle-
however, is with fundamental principles tin, 50, 263-274.
of reinforcement, and we find that a num- Freeman, T. J., & Lattal, K. A. (in press). Stimulus
control of behavioral history. Journal of the Ex-
ber of us are satisfied to use animal data perimental Analysis of Behavior.
as the benchmarks. In such a case, human Galizio, M., & Buskist, W. (1988). Laboratory
"demonstrations" ofprinciples that have lore and research practices in the experimental
already been agreed upon are luxuries that analysis of human behavior: Selecting reinforcers
we might be able to do without-an an- and arranging contingencies. The Behavior An-
alyst, 11, 65-69.
cillary effort at best. But will this position Grossett, D., Roy, S., Sharenow, E., & Poling, A.
satisfy those who are not impressed by (1982). Subjects used in JEAB articles: Is the
expressions of faith and demand instead snark a pigeon? The Behavior Analyst, 5, 189-
firm empirical support for claims about 190.
Hake, D. F., Vukelich, R., & Kaplan, S. J. (1973).
the relevance of animal-based principles Audit responses: Responses maintained by access
to human behavior? And if one believes, to existing self or coactor scores during non-so-
as we do, that human data can contribute cial, parallel work, and cooperation procedures.
to the formulation of fundamental prin- Journal ofthe ExperimentalAnalysis ofBehavior,
ciples, then the experimental analysis of 19, 409-423.
Holland, J. G. (1958). Human vigilance. Science,
human behavior is indispensable. 128, 61-63.
Hursh, S. R. (1984). Behavioral economics. Jour-
nal of the Experimental Analysis ofBehavior, 42,
435-452.
REFERENCES Michael, J. (1980). Flight from behavior analysis.
The Behavior Analyst, 3, 1-21.
Baron, A. (1990). Experimental designs. The Be- Morse, W. H., & Kelleher, R. T. (1977). Deter-
havior Analyst, 13, 167-171. minants of reinforcement and punishment. In W.
Baron, A., & Galizio, M. (1983). Instructional K. Honig & J. E. R. Staddon (Eds.), Handbook
control of human operant behavior. The Psycho- of operant behavior (pp. 174-200). Englewood
logical Record, 33, 495-520. Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Baron, A., & Kaufman, A. (1966). Human, free- Palmer, D. C., & Donahoe, J. W. (1991). Shared
operant avoidance of "time-out" from monetary premises, different conclusions. The Behavior
reinforcement. Journal of the Experimental Analyst, 14, 123-127.
Analysis ofBehavior, 9, 557-565. Perone, M. (in press). Experimental design in the
Baron, A., & Perone, M. (1982). The place of the analysis of free-operant behavior. In I. H. Iversen
human subject in the operant laboratory. The & K. A. Lattal (Eds.), Techniques in the behav-
Behavior Analyst, 5, 143-158. ioral and neural sciences: Experimental analysis
Baron, A., Perone, M., & Galizio, M. (1991). An- of behavior. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: El-
alyzing the reinforcement process at the human sevier.
level: Can application and behavioristic inter- Perone, M., & Baron, A. (1980). Reinforcement
pretation replace laboratory research? The Be- of human observing behavior by a stimulus cor-
havior Analyst, 14, 95-105. related with extinction or increased effort. Jour-
Bijou, S. W., Peterson, R. F., & Ault, M. H. (1968). nal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 34,
A method to integrate descriptive and experi- 239-261.
mental field studies at the level of data and em- Perone, M., Galizio, M., & Baron, A. (1988). The
pirical concepts. Journal of Applied Behavior relevance of animal-based principles in the lab-
Analysis, 1, 175-191. oratory study of human operant conditioning. In
Bolles, R. C. (1970). Species-specific defense re- G. Davey & C. Cullen (Eds.), Human operant
EXPERIMENTAL ANALYSIS OF HUMAN BEHAVIOR 155
conditioning and behavior modification (pp. 59- Skinner, B. F. (1958). Reinforcement today.
85). New York: Wiley. American Psychologist, 13, 94-99.
Pierce, W. D., & Epling, W. F. (1991). Can op- Todorov, J. C., de Oliveira Castro, J. M., Hanna,
erant research with animals rescue the science of E. S., de Sa, M. C. N. B., & de Queiroz Barreto,
behavior? The Behavior Analyst, 14, 129-132. M. (1983). Choice, experience, and the gener-
Schick, K. (1971). Operants. Journal of the Ex- alized matching law. Journal ofthe Experimental
perimental Analysis of Behavior, 15, 413-423. Analysis ofBehavior, 40, 99-111.
Schoenfeld, W. N., Antonitis, J. J., & Bersh, P. J. Wanchisen, B. A. (1990). Forgetting the lessons
(1950). Unconditioned response rate ofthe white of history. The Behavior Analyst, 13, 31-37.
rat in a bar-pressing apparatus. Journal of Com- Wanchisen, B. A., & Tatham, T. A. (1991). Be-
parative and Physiological Psychology, 43, 41- havioral history: A promising challenge in ex-
48. plaining and controlling human operant behav-
Schwartz, B. (1974). On going back to nature: [A ior. The Behavior Analyst, 14, 139-144.
review of Seligman and Hager's Biological Weiner, H. (1969). Controlling human fixed-in-
boundaries of learning]. Journal of the Experi- terval performance. Journal of the Experimental
mental Analysis of Behavior, 21, 183-198. Analysis of Behavior, 12, 349-373.
Seligman, M. E. P. (1970). On the generality of Williams, D. R., & Williams, H. (1969). Auto-
the laws of learning. Psychological Review, 77, maintenance in the pigeon: Sustained pecking de-
406-418. spite contingent non-reinforcement. Journal of
Shull, R. L., & Lawrence, P. S. (1991). Prepara- the Experimental Analysis ofBehavior, 12, 511-
tions and principles. The Behavior Analyst, 14, 520.
133-138. Zeiler, M. D. (1977). Schedules of reinforcement:
Sidman, M. (1960). Tactics ofscientific research. The controlling variables. In W. K. Honig & J.
New York: Basic Books. E. R. Staddon (Eds.), Handbook of operant be-
Sidman, M. (1969). Generalization gradients and havior(pp. 201-232). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Pren-
stimulus control in delayed matching-to-sample. tice-Hall.
Journal ofthe ExperimentalAnalysis ofBehavior, Zeiler, M. D. (1984). The sleeping giant: Rein-
12, 745-757. forcement schedules. Journal of the Experimen-
Skinner, B. F. (1956). A case history in scientific tal Analysis ofBehavior, 42, 485-493.
method. American Psychologist, 11, 221-233.

View publication stats

You might also like