You are on page 1of 46

Econ 522

Economics of Law

Dan Quint
Spring 2011
Lecture 4
So far, we have…

 …defined some important tools


 defined efficiency, and gave reasons for why we might want the law
to be designed to be efficient
 showed how externalities (among other things) lead to inefficiency
 introduced static games, the matrix representation of payoffs, and
how to find equilibria

 …showed two ways in which a lack of clear property rights


can lead to severe inefficiencies
 overfishing example
 farming/stealing game

2
Once we have private property rights, we’ll
have conflicts between mine and yours

 My neighbor likes tall trees


 can he plant a tree on his property if it shades my pool, or blocks my
view?

 You want to have a party


 do you have the right to make noise in your house?
 or do I have the right to a good night’s sleep in my house?

 I own a small power plant located on a river


 do I have a right to use water from the river for cooling?
 do I have a right to pollute as much as I want?

3
Up next: how should we design property
rights to achieve efficiency?

 Cooter and Ulen: property is


“A bundle of legal rights over resources that the owner is free to
exercise and whose exercise is protected from interference by others”

 Doesn’t tell us how property law should be designed

 Need to answer four fundamental questions:


 What things can be privately owned?
 What can (and can’t) an owner do with his property?
 How are property rights established?
 What remedies are given when property rights are violated?

 Today: wild animals and Coase


4
Foxes

5
One early, “classic” property law case

 Pierson v. Post (NY Supreme Court, 1805)


 Lodowick Post organized a fox hunt, was chasing
a fox
 Jesse Pierson appeared “out of nowhere,” killed
the fox and took it
 Post sued to get the fox back
 Lower court sided with Post; Pierson appealed
to NY Supreme Court

 Question: when do you own an animal?

6
One early, “classic” property law case

 Court ruled for Pierson (the one who killed the fox)
 “If the first seeing, starting, or pursuing such animals… should
afford the basis of actions against others for intercepting and killing
them, it would prove a fertile source of quarrels and litigation”
 (Also: just because an action is “uncourteous or unkind” does not
make it illegal)

 Dissenting opinion: a fox is a “wild and noxious beast,” and


killing foxes is “meritorious and of public benefit”
 Post should own the fox, in order to encourage fox hunting

7
Same tradeoff we saw earlier:

Pierson gets the fox Post gets the fox

 simpler rule (finders  more efficient incentives


keepers)

 easier to implement
 (stronger incentive to pursue
animals that may be hard to
 fewer disputes catch)

 Just like Fast Fish/Loose Fish vs Iron Holds The Whale


 Fast Fish/Loose Fish is the simpler rule, leads to fewer disputes
 Iron Holds the Whale is more complicated, but is necessary with
whales where hunting them the old-fashioned way is too dangerous
8
Coase

9
How should property rights be allocated?
Coase’s surprising answer: it doesn’t matter

 More specifically, under certain conditions, it doesn’t matter


for efficiency
 (Although it does matter for distribution)

 Coase Theorem: in the absence of transaction costs, if


property rights are well-defined and tradable, then
voluntary negotiations will lead to efficiency
 It doesn’t matter how rights are allocated initially…
 …because if they’re allocated inefficiently, they can be sold/traded
until they’re allocated efficiently

10
Example of Coase: you have a car worth
$3,000 to you, $4,000 to me
 Obviously, efficient for me to own it…
 …but we don’t need the law to give me the car
 If I start out owning the car:
no reason for you to buy it, I end up with it  efficient
 If you start out owning the car:
clear incentive for me to buy it, I end up with it  efficient
 Regardless of who owns the car at first, we get to the efficient outcome
 I’d rather start out with the car – so I don’t have to pay you for it
 You’d rather start out with it – so you end up with more money
 Efficiency doesn’t care about distribution – how much money we each end up
with – just who ends up with the car at the end.
 And that doesn’t depend on who starts with it.
 The key: lack of transaction costs

11
Another example: you want to have a party
in the house next door to mine
 If it’s efficient for you to have the party…
 Your benefit from having the party is greater than my benefit from a good
night’s sleep
 If you start out with the right to have the party, no problem
 If I start out with the right to quiet, you can pay me for the right to have the party
 If it’s efficient for you not to have the party…
 Good night sleep is worth more to me
 If I have right to silence, no problem
 If you have right to party, I can pay you not to have it
 The point: either way, we achieve efficiency
 If it’s efficient to have the party, you have the party
 If it’s efficient not to, you don’t
 Regardless of who started off with the right

12
The conditions for this to hold

 Property rights have to be well-defined…


 We need to be clear on who has what rights, so we know the
starting point for negotiations

 …and tradable…
 We need to be allowed to sell/transfer/reallocate rights if we want

 …and there can’t be transaction costs


 It can’t be difficult or costly for us to buy/sell the right

13
The Coase Theorem

 Ronald Coase (1960), “The Problem of Social Cost”

 In the absence of transaction costs,


if property rights are well-defined
and tradable, voluntary negotiations
will lead to efficiency.
 So the initial allocation of rights
doesn’t matter for efficiency

 However, it does matter for distribution


 And if there are transaction costs,
it may matter for efficiency too

14
Coase’s example: a rancher and a farmer

15
Rancher’s versus farmer’s rights

 English common law: “closed range” or “fencing-in”


(or “farmer’s rights”)
 Ranchers have responsibility to control their cattle
 Rancher must pay for any damage done by his herd

 Much of the U.S. at various times: “open range” or “fencing-out”


(or “rancher’s rights”)
 Rancher can let his cattle roam free
 Not liable for damage they do to farmer’s crops
(unless farmer had a good fence and they broke through anyway)

 Which rule is more efficient?

16
Open range versus closed range

17
Coase: either law will lead to efficiency

 If it’s cheaper for the farmer to protect his crops than for the rancher
to control his herd…
 Under open range law, that’s what he’ll do
 Under closed range law, rancher can pay farmer to build fence

 If smaller herd is more efficient, farmer can pay rancher to keep


fewer cattle
 Coase:
 Whatever is the efficient combination of cattle, crops, fences, etc.…
 …the rancher and farmer will negotiate to that efficient outcome, regardless
of which law is in place…
 …as long as the rights are well-defined and tradable and there are no
transaction costs

18
Rancher and farmer: numerical example

 Three possibilities:
 Rancher builds fence around herd… costs $400
 Farmer builds fence around crops… costs $200
 Do nothing, live with damage… costs nothing

 If expected crop damage = $100


 Open range: farmer lives with damage rather than building fence
 Closed range: rancher pays for damage rather than fence

 If expected crop damage = $500


 Open range: farmer builds fence – efficient
 Coase: closed range: rancher pays farmer to build fence
 So efficient outcome under either rule

19
Other examples from Coase

 Lots of examples from case law


 a building that blocked air currents from turning a windmill
 a building which cast a shadow over the swimming pool and sunbathing
area of a hotel next door
 a doctor next door to a confectioner
 a chemical manufacturer
 a house whose chimney no longer worked well after the neighbors rebuilt
their house to be taller

 In each case, regardless of who is initially held liable, the parties


can negotiate with each other and take whichever remedy is
cheapest to fix (or endure) the situation

20
Quoting from Coase (p. 13):

Judges have to decide on legal liability but this should not


confuse economists about the nature of the economic
problem involved.

In the case of the cattle and the crops, it is true that there
would be no crop damage without the cattle. It is equally true
that there would be no crop damage without the crops.
The doctor’s work would not have been disturbed if the
confectioner had not worked his machinery; but the
machinery would have disturbed no one if the doctor had not
set up his consulting room in that particular place…

21
Quoting from Coase (p. 13):

If we are to discuss the problem in terms of causation, both


parties cause the damage.

If we are to attain an optimum allocation of resources, it is


therefore desirable that both parties should take the
harmful effects into account when deciding on their course
of action.

It is one of the beauties of a smoothly operating pricing


system that… the fall in the value of production due to the
harmful effect would be a cost for both parties.

22
What does Coase mean by “a cost for both
parties”?

 If the cheapest alternative is for the farmer to build a fence


for $200…
 The cost to build a fence is $200
 But the cost to not build a fence is more than $200 – since under a
closed-range law, the farmer could ask the rancher for more than
$200 to build the fence

 “Opportunity cost”

23
So, summing up…

 Coase Theorem: In the absence of transaction costs,


if property rights are well-defined and tradeable,
voluntary negotiations will lead to efficiency.
 The initial allocation of property rights therefore does not matter for
achieving efficiency…

 …provided there are no transaction costs

 (But if there are transaction costs, then the initial allocation can
matter for efficiency…

 …and it will always matter for distribution)

24
Bargaining

25
Some vocabulary about bargaining

 Example from before:


 Your car is worth $3,000 to you, and $4,000 to me
 Suppose I have $10,000

 $10,000 is my threat point


 the payoff I can get on my own, by refusing to cooperate with you
 also called reservation utility, or outside option

 $3,000 is your threat point

 Any outcome we both agree to must make us both at least as


well-off as our threat point

26
Some vocabulary about bargaining

 If I don’t buy the car from you…


 my payoff is 10,000 (my threat point)
 your payoff is 3,000
 combined payoffs are 13,000

 If I buy the car for some price P


 my payoff is 4,000 + 10,000 – P = 14,000 – P
 your payoff is P
 combined payoffs are 14,000 – P + P = 14,000

 $1,000 are the gains from trade (or gains from cooperation)
 no trade  combined payoffs of $13,000
 I buy car  combined payoffs of $14,000
 if we cooperate, our combined payoffs increase by $1,000

27
Some vocabulary about bargaining

 Threat points: 10,000 and 3,000

 Gains from cooperation: 1,000

 Suppose the gains from cooperation were split equally


 we’d each get 500 more than threat point
 my payoff would be 10,500, yours 3,500
 which means P = $3,500

 (Coase doesn’t specify gains will be divided equally, just that


they’ll be divided in some way)

28
Let’s go back to the rancher and farmer

 Cows do $500 damage; fence around herd costs $400;


fence around crops costs $200

Rancher’s Rights Farmer’s Rights

Rancher’s Threat Point 0 -400

Farmer’s Threat Point -200 0

Gains From Cooperation 0 200

Rancher’s Payoff (IF…) 0 -300



Farmer’s Payoff -200 100

Combined Payoffs -200 = -200


29
Relating Coase to general equilibrium/
first welfare theorem

 General equilibrium
 given prices, consumers maximize utility
 given prices, firms maximize profits
 prices are such that all markets clear

 First Welfare Theorem: general equilibrium is efficient

 But not when there are externalities, or “missing markets”

 Allowing the consumer to negotiate with the firm is like introducing


a “missing market” in air rights

30
Relating Coase to general equilibrium/
first welfare theorem

 General equilibrium
 given prices, consumers maximize utility
 given prices, firms maximize profits
 prices are such that all markets clear

 First Welfare Theorem: general equilibrium is efficient

 But not when there are externalities, or “missing markets”

 Allowing the consumer to negotiate with the firm is like introducing


a “missing market” in air rights

31
Getting back
to foxes…

32
Doesn’t Coase make Pierson v Post
irrelevant?

 Coase seems to say: for efficiency, it doesn’t matter who starts


off with the right to the fox
 If Post values it more, he can buy it from Pierson, or vice versa
 Seems to imply: one rule is just as good as the other, as long as we all
know what the rule is

 So why does Pierson v Post matter?


 Transaction costs!
 Majority: if Post gets the fox back, “it would prove a fertile course of
quarrels and litigation” – the ensuing lawsuits would be costly
 Dissent: killing foxes is a good thing (externality), so lots of people
benefit – so hard to get efficient amount of fox hunting through
bargaining

33
Transaction costs

 Coase: “in the absence of transaction costs,


if property rights are well-defined and tradable,
voluntary negotiations will lead to efficiency.”

 This suggests that if there are transaction costs,


voluntary negotiations may not lead to efficiency

 Car example (yet again)


 If transactions are costly, we may not trade
 And if we do trade, we incur that cost

34
Quoting Coase…

“If market transactions were costless, all that matters (questions


of equity apart) is that the rights of the various parties should be
well-defined and the results of legal actions easy to forecast.

But… the situation is quite different when market


transactions are so costly as to make it difficult to change
the arrangement of rights established by the law.

In such cases, the courts directly influence economic activity.

…Even when it is possible to change the legal delimitation of


rights through market transactions, it is obviously desirable to
reduce the need for such transactions and thus reduce the
employment of resources in carrying them out.

35
We can see the Coase Theorem as either a
positive or negative result

 “In the absence of transaction costs, if property rights are well-


defined and tradable, voluntary negotiations will lead to
efficiency.”

 We can read this as…


 “As long as transaction costs aren’t a big deal, we’ll get efficiency”
 Or as, “we’ll only get efficiency automatically if there are no transaction
costs”

 Coase also gives two examples of institutions that may emerge in


response to high transaction costs:
 Firms
 Government regulation

36
Many externalities can be thought of as
missing property rights

 Overfishing in communal lake?


 It’s because property rights over those fish aren’t well-defined

 Firm polluting too much?


 It’s because property rights over clean air aren’t well-defined

 So one solution…
 Make property rights complete enough to cover “everything,” and
tradable, and use the law to minimize transaction costs…
 …Then Coase kicks in and we get efficiency! (Booya!)
 So why not do this? COSTS!

37
Demsetz

38
We motivated property law by looking at a
game between two neighboring farmers

ORIGINAL GAME MODIFIED GAME

Player 2 Player 2
Farm Steal Farm Steal

Farm 10, 10 -5, 12 Farm 10 – c, 10 – c -5 – c, 12 – P


Player 1

Player 1
Steal 12, -5 0, 0 Steal 12 – P, -5 – c -P, -P

 Changing the game had two effects:


 Allowed us to cooperate by not stealing from each other
 Introduced a cost c of administering a property rights system 39
39
Harold Demsetz (1967), “Toward a Theory
of Property Rights”

 “A primary function of property rights is that of guiding


incentives to achieve a greater internalization of externalities”

 “[ In order for an externality to persist, ] The cost of a


transaction in the rights between the parties… must exceed
the gains from internalization.”

 “Property rights develop to internalize externalities when the


gains from internalization become larger than the cost of
internalization.”

40
Harold Demsetz (1967), “Toward a Theory
of Property Rights”

 “Property rights develop to internalize externalities when


the gains from internalization become larger than the
cost of internalization.”

 Private ownership of land among Native Americans


 Cost of administering private ownership: moderate
 Before fur trade…
 externality was small, so gains from internalization were small
 gains < costs  no private ownership of land

41
Harold Demsetz (1967), “Toward a Theory
of Property Rights”

 “Property rights develop to internalize externalities when the


gains from internalization become larger than the cost of
internalization.”

 Private ownership of land among Native Americans


 Cost of administering private ownership: moderate
 Before fur trade…
 externality was small, so gains from internalization were small
 gains < costs  no private ownership of land
 As fur trading developed…
 externality grew, so gains from internalization grew
 gains > costs  private property rights developed

42
Friedman tells a similar story: “we owe
civilization to the dogs”

The date is 10,000 or 11,000 B.C. You are a member of a


primitive tribe that farms its land in common. Farming land in
common is a pain; you spend almost as much time watching each
other and arguing about who is or is not doing his share as you do
scratching the ground with pointed sticks and pulling weeds.

…It has occurred to several of you that the problem would


disappear if you converted the common land to private property.
Each person would farm his own land; if your neighbor chose not
to work very hard, it would be he and his children, not you and
yours, that would go hungry.

43
Friedman tells a similar story: “we owe
civilization to the dogs”

There is a problem with this solution… Private property does


not enforce itself. Someone has to make sure that the lazy
neighbor doesn’t solve his food shortage at your expense.

[Now] you will have to spend your nights making sure they are
not working hard harvesting your fields. All things considered,
you conclude that communal farming is the least bad solution.

44
Friedman tells a similar story: “we owe
civilization to the dogs”

Agricultural land continues to be treated as a commons for


another thousand years, until somebody makes a radical
technological innovation: the domestication of the dog.

Dogs, being territorial animals, can be taught to identify their


owner’s property as their territory and respond appropriately to
trespassers. Now you can convert to private property in
agricultural land and sleep soundly. Think of it as the bionic
burglar alarm.

-Friedman, Law’s Order, p. 118

45
So…

 Coase: if property rights are complete and tradeable, we’ll


always get efficiency

 Demsetz:
 yes, but this comes at a cost
 property rights will expand when the benefits outweigh the costs
 either because the benefits rise…
 …or because the costs fall

 Of course, Coase wasn’t completely ignoring costs…


 Next week: what are transaction costs, how do we deal with them?

46

You might also like