You are on page 1of 13

North American Philosophical Publications

Progress in Philosophy
Author(s): Todd C. Moody
Source: American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 23, No. 1 (Jan., 1986), pp. 35-46
Published by: University of Illinois Press on behalf of the North American Philosophical
Publications
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20014123
Accessed: 19-09-2016 02:25 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/20014123?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

North American Philosophical Publications, University of Illinois Press are collaborating


with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Philosophical Quarterly

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Philosophical Quarterly
Volume 23, Number 1, January 1986

PROGRESS IN PHILOSOPHY
Todd C. Moody

A great deal has been written about progress in of their goal? Probably not. It is likely, however,
^"^ science; little has been written about progress that any of them would have a very well-developed
in philosophy.1 Perhaps the very subject is some? sense of when progress is being made and when it
thing of an embarrassment. is not. They may, but need not, rely on the judgment
What is to be avoided in an undertaking of this of an observer to tell them this. Sometimes they
sort is the temptation to evaluate progress in philos? must rely upon their own judgment. Call this "prog
ophy according to a scientific paradigm. This temp? ress2." Progress2 is the sort of progress that can be
tation is almost overpowering, due to the success made even where the goal cannot be specified in
of science. Only an obscurantist of heroic stubborn? any clear way, but given intervals of change can
ness would attempt to deny the dramatic progress nevertheless be identified as progress or regress,
of science. Yet it is clear that as long as our notion by either the individual or some observer. To place
of progress is limited to its scientific epitomization, a further restriction upon progress2, we shall stipu?
we will be unable to make out any sense of progress late that neither the overall goal nor the intermediate
in philosophy. An understanding of progress that sub-goals has clearly specifiable criteria.
is a suitable context for observations about philos? The poet, the painter, the composer and the
ophy is needed. sculptor are guided by some inner sense that tells
At first blush, it would seem that progress in them when they are "getting it right" and when
any activity presupposes some goal, and is mea? they are not. It is an intuitive sense; it is highly
sured with respect to that goal. Therefore, the first unlikely that any of them could articulate even
question that must be asked is "Does philosophy, strictly personal criteria for the subgoals (if any)
in general, have a goal?and if so, what is it?" that go into their activities. Therefore, what they
Before we can hope to answer it, however, there do exemplifies progress2.
is other work to do. The salient feature of progress2 is that its main
The dieter makes, or fails to make, progress criteria are subjective; it is the kind of progress
toward svelteness, the runner toward swiftness, the that we associate with "creative" activity. In spite
insurance salesman toward quota, and so on. What of this subjectivity, it is still a very real sense of
each of these cases has in common is a decidable progress. The subjectivity is balanced by the con?
goal. An ideal body weight, a target running time, straints placed on individual practice by the com?
a required number of policies sold?in each case, munal context in which it occurs. Even the most
it is possible for the individual to decide with con? iconoclastic artist works within a cultural context
fidence whether progress has been made during a that lets her (and others) judge the progress of her
given interval. It is possible for an observer to work. The accomplished musician makes progress2
decide it as well. Call this "progress1?" the kind of by extending her interpretive power (as distin?
progress that is available when there is a specifi? guished from the novice musician who learns
able, decidable goal. scales). To a certain extent, she is able to know
Not surprisingly, there is a whole range of cases that she is doing so in virtue of her sense of being
where things are not so crisply decidable. The con? able to perform more difficult passages than was
valescent makes progress toward health, the figure previously the case. The subjective sense of aug?
skater toward perfect form, the poet toward the menting one's previous range of competence and
perfection of her poem. Can any of these people of penetrating into areas of increasing difficulty are
say in advance just what will mark the attainment very important for assessing progress2, up to a

35

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
36 AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

point. One should not conclude, however, that a This much is not controversial. Progress3 is
series of improvements is the goal of progress2. It exemplified by the linking of episodes of progress x,
is just not clear that after a certain point it is still in the absence of an overall, or final goal.
convenient for, say, a musician or a painter to The first move is to assume provisionally that
assess progress in terms of either performance philosophy is an inquiry; a discourse aimed at
extension or difficulty. A pianist such as Rubinstein finding things out. The expression "philosophical
in his later years may continue to make musical inquiry" is certainly well enough entrenched to indi?
progress even as his repertoire dwindles, by virtue cate that this is a plausible assumption.
of the sublime rendering of the pieces that remain By calling an activity an inquiry (a more
in it. Similarly, it becomes difficult to give much restricted class than "discourse"), we move into a
significance to the terms "difficult" and "easy" after context where several more assumptions are already
this point is reached. Perhaps personal satisfaction in place. An inquiry in this sense is typically a
and assimilation by a culture are the only reliable collective activity. When we speak of progress in
criteria of progress2. Certainly, the distinction an inquiry, we shall be referring to progress of the
between subjective and objective falters here. whole, and not the progress of this or that individual
Improvement may be one source of satisfaction, inquirer, for the time being. An inquiry takes a
but it is certainly not the only one. "realistic" stance toward its subject matter, at least
Progress3 is a hybrid. It applies to the scientist, to the limited extent that it assumes that there is
the gymnast, or the novice musician who is still some aspect of the subject matter that is "there"
trying to master the fundamentals of performance. independently of investigative efforts. The indi?
It is characterized by the availability of a series of vidual participant in an inquiry assumes that it is
fairly decidable intermediate goals, but no goal of within his power to discover true things about his
completion. The mathematician may not know, or subject matter.
care, what the "ultimate" goal of mathematics is, Let us borrow Kuhn's terminology and stipulate
but he has a pretty good idea of when he has and that there is a manageable distinction between
has not proved a theorem, worked out an algorithm, normal inquiry and abnormal ("revolutionary")
and the like. This is so in spite of the fact that he inquiry, and that the former is characterized by the
may not be able to say in advance what counts as relatively stable presence of consensus-generating
proof in general and what would count as proof in procedures (CGP's). Examples of normal inquiry
a given instance. Nevertheless, mathematics is a include the so-called "hard" sciences (at least,
progress3 activity, for at least two reasons. First, during "normal" intervals), engineering and
the mathematician may not be able to say up front technological research, and mathematics.
what would count as proof of a given theorem, but A manifestation of normal inquiry is textbook
he very likely can say what would count as a refu? education. That is, in normal inquiry, one learns
tation or counterexample. Second, and more impor? to participate by reading the textbook, solving
tant, mathematics progresses by the solution of dis? sample problems, and generally mastering the cur?
crete problems, which solutions are accepted as rent paradigm. In normal inquiry, the record shows
mathematical knowledge by the mathematical com? an accumulation of solved problems. This gives us
munity, by and large. This may be more prob? a sequence of instances of progress! and the col?
lematic today, with the proliferation of "schools" lected sequence, progress3.
of mathematics?formalist, intuitionists, logicist? Now, ex hypothesi, philosophy is an inquiry.
than it was a hundred years ago, but it still seems But is it a normal inquiry? How many of the charac?
about right. teristic features of normal inquiry are readily discer?
It would appear that the physical sciences are nible in philosophical inquiry?
also progress3 activities. There may be no agreed The first item to consider is the CGP. It is dif?
upon final goal for them, but progress within them ficult to discern CGP's in philosophy, for the simple
comprises the solutions of a series of problems, reason that it is difficult to discern consensus, espe?
whose accretion is called scientific knowledge. cially positive consensus about results. There may

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PROGRESS IN PHILOSOPHY 37

be a vague kind of consensus among philosopher The first and essential acid test for any theory is
within the various "schools" or "traditions" about whether it provides acceptable answers to interesting
what is the proper way to address a philosophical questions: whether, in other words, it provides satis?
question. factory solutions to important problems.2
An important part of philosophical inquiry is Of course, this presupposes CGP's to distinguish
agonism; one is expected to be called to task on between "satisfactory" solutions and errors,
any and all points. There are no safe places in between "interesting" problems and fool's errands.
philosophy. Having noted this, it is very plausible Laudan proceeds to argue that conceptual problems
to suppose that the immediate impetus for con? in science are to be played down in favor of "em?
tinuing philosophical research is not consensus at pirical" ones. Empirical problems are susceptible
all but perpetual and vociferous disagreement. to normal methods of solution: observation, exper?
There is a sense, which we will examine a bit later,
iment, and so forth. Laudan's conclusion is empha?
in which consensus among philosophers about the tic:
solutions to the main philosophical problems would
mark the end of philosophy. As it is, the only thing I have tried to argue that the single most general con
that philosophers are likely to agree about with gitive aim of science is problem solving. I have
claimed that the maximization of the empirical prob?
enthusiasm is the abysmal inadequacy of a par?
lems we can explain and the minimization of the
ticular theory. This negative consensus is peculiarly
anomalous and conceptual problems we generate in
corrosive because of the way in which it perpetuates
the process are the raison d'?tre of science as a cog?
the absence of positive consensus by enabling phi? nitive activity. I have claimed that any research trad?
losophers to accuse each other of "making the same ition which can exemplify this process through time
mistake that X makes." Agreement about the is a progressive one.3
inadequacy of a theory becomes a strategy for effec?
tive disagreement about the adequacy of another It is highly implausible to contend that the
theory. minimization of conceptual problems is the raison
Textbook education is also conspicuously absent d'etre of philosophy. If there is progress in philos?
in philosophy. Generally, the only textbooks are ophy, it is not manifest as an accumulation of solved
introductory ones, where some basic terminology problems, nor is it achieved by minimizing
is laid out and the novice is familiarized with the "anomalous and conceptual problems."
inadequacies of various historical important view? It would be a mistake to conclude, on the basis
points. These books are seldom used after the initial of these comparisons with the natural sciences, that
introductory course, and they are not always used there just is no progress in philosophy. Rather,
there. In philosophy the anthology of readings is these reflections place us in a position to deliver
much more popular as the basic pedagogical tool. the following verdict with some confidence: Philos?
The more controversial and polemical the readings, ophy is not a normal inquiry. Since we are still
the better. The teacher habituates the students to proceeding on the assumption that it is an inquiry,
thinking of philosophical problems as "issues" and however, we need to decide whether philosophy
their possible solutions as "positions." Compare seen as an abnormal inquiry is also a progressive
these terms with "hypothesis" and "result" in the inquiry. Meanwhile, an intermediate conclusion
sciences, or "theorem" and "solution" in mathema? emerges: Since we cannot adduce a record of solved
tics (not to mention "proof). philosophical problems, progressx and progress3
Does philosophy display a record of solved prob? must be ruled out. Therefore, we must examine
lems? It is difficult to think of a single philosophical with special care the remaining hypothesis that
problem that could unequivocally and uncontrover there is progress2 in philosophy.
sially be labelled "solved." Again, it is instructive The trouble with characterizing philosophy as
to compare the situation in philosophy with that in an abnormal inquiry is that in the absence of stable
the natural sciences. Larry Laudan proposes the CGP's, which absence is one of the hallmarks of
following criterion of success for a scientific theory: abnormal discourse, it is difficult to support the

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
38 AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

hypothesis that philosophy is an inquiry, after all. "Final solution" is unambiguous. Wittgenstein did
We are caught on the horns of two apparently not abandon this view. In his later work he
incompatible intuitions: First, as philosophers, we developed the idea that it is possible to discern a
have the immediate and compelling feeling that clear and decidable goal for philosophical activity;
what we are doing is, in fact, finding things out namely, the cessation of philosophical inquiry or,
and not making them up as we go along. As much more accurately, the cure for the temptation to ask
as we might be willing to acknowledge our own philosophical questions.
contribution to what we claim to "discover," I think
One can defend common sense against the attacks
that we would be reluctant to relinquish the realistic
of philosophers only by solving their puzzles, i.e., by
stance altogether. Second, and most troublesome, curing them of the temptation to attack common
we are only too aware that it is difficult or impos? sense...6
sible to point to a record of permanent positive
philosophical "discoveries" (or solved problems), The latter passage is from The Blue and Brown
and that in the face of this fact the characterization Books, a collection associated with the develop?
of philosophy as an inquiry?one that never quite ment of Wittgenstein's "latter" thinking. Notice
manages to find anything out?loses much of its that he no longer speaks of solving problems; now
plausibility. it is "puzzles" that get solved. The shift is away
Faced with this dilemma, one option is to drop from looking at philosophy as an inquiry, but the
the idea that philosophy is an inquiry. Two philos? notion that philosophy has an end (or at least that
ophers who take this approach are Ludwig Wittgen? that sort of philosophy can come an end) is still
stein and, more recently, Richard Rorty.4 I shall present. It is also in this work that Wittgenstein
call their models of philosophical activity the explicitly dismisses the notion of "philosophical
"therapeutic model" and the "conversational problems."
model," respectively. ...in their correct and everyday use vagueness is
Wittgenstein's thoughts on the nature of philos? opposed to clearness, flux to stability, inaccuracy to
ophy do not lend themselves to easy encapsulation. accuracy, and problem to solution. The very world
It is well known that there are serious divergences "problem," one might say, is misapplied when used
between his "early" and "late" work. There is, how? for our philosophical troubles. These difficulties, as
ever, one point of convergence between the two long as they are seen as problems, are tantalizing, and
appear insoluble.7
periods: Wittgenstein believed that philosophical
problems are somehow spurious and that the It is later in the Philosophical Investigations,
activity of philosophy?at least in its problem-sol? that the therapy model is developed more fully. It
ving or question-answering aspect?should termi? is important to remember, however, that Wittgen?
nate with the withdrawal, or deconstruction, of stein viewed therapy as a terminating process, not
philosophical questions. Calling certain philosoph? an end in itself. His remark that "The real discovery
ical questions spurious is certainly not a remarkable is the one that makes me capable of stopping doing
procedure; it is a standard philosophical move. The philosophy when I want to,"8 epitomizes the
remarkable part of Wittgenstein's view is that phi? therapeutic model.
losophy as inquiry is seen as a terminating activity. It is not that Wittgenstein wanted to deny that
This passage from the preface to the Tractatus is there are philosophical puzzles, or troubles;
fairly explicit: instead, it was his belief that the only way to deal
with these troubles, is to see them perspicuously.
I therefore believe myself to have found, on all
This involves "seeing" the origin of these puzzles
essential points, the final solution of the problems.
And if I am not mistaken in this belief, then the second in the language we use.
thing in which the value of this work consists is that Thus, a great deal of Wittgenstein's later output
is shows how little is achieved when these problems involves what he described as "assembling remin?
are solved.5 ders for a particular purpose."9 The purpose is to

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PROGRESS IN PHILOSOPHY 39

eliminate the temptation to ask philosophical ques? Philosophy as a discipline thus sees itself as the
tions. These reminders are not rigorous proofs. attempt to underwrite or debunk claims to knowledge
Thus, he does not offer a deductive argument in made by science, morality, art, or religion.
sections 66-67 of the Investigations to the effect
To know is to represent accurately what is outside
that we understand "game" by our sensitivity to an
the mind; so to understand the possibility and nature
overlapping set of family resemblances and partici?
of knowledge is to understand the way in which the
pation in a form of life. Instead, we are supposed mind is able to construct such representations. Philos?
to see the force of the analogy between family ophy's central concern is to be a general theory of
resemblances and fibers in a thread. Once we see
representation, a theory which will divide culture up
this, we will no longer be tempted to inquire into into the areas which represent reality well, those which
the "essence" of games, although we shall not have represent it less well, and those which do not represent
"proved" anything about essentialism. it at all (despite their pretense of doing so).10
The fact that the therapeutic model of philosophy The historical fact of the matter is that these
provides a decidable terminus indicates that,
efforts have not succeeded and, Rorty insists, the
according to it, philosophy is a progress1 activity. cumulative effect of the work of certain twentieth
When philosophy ends, the goal will have been
century figures, including Wittgenstein, has been
reached, and that's that. According to the
to cast doubt upon the very possibility of success.
therapeutic model, there is little more to be said.
As he puts it, "The attempts of both analytic philos?
There is a problem of historiography about whether
ophers and phenomenologists to 'ground' this and
Wittgenstein was in fact content to rest with the
'criticize' that were shrugged off by those whose
therapeutic model. I shall comment a bit later on
activities were purportedly being grounded or
what he might have envisioned as a successor to criticized."11
therapy.
Central to Rorty's view is the thesis that the task
So, we have gotten one answer to the question,
of philosophy as he has described it is a hangover
"Is there progress in philosophy?" I think that few
from elements of seventeenth and eighteenth cen?
philosophers today can accept this particular
tury thinking that have long ago been superseded
answer. For one thing, the efficacy of the therapy
in other disciplines. He trades heavily on the ana?
rests upon enough philosophers "seeing" the source chronism of philosophy, as can be seen in this
of the trouble. While individual philosophers may remark:
successfully penetrate a variety of philosophy puz?
zles, the only time it seems reasonable to attribute It is the notion that human activity (and inquiry,
the search for knowledge, in particular) takes place
this "seeing" to the philosophical community in
within a framework which can be isolated prior to the
general is when it is "seen" that a given theory just
conclusion of inquiry?a set of presuppositions dis?
does not work. It cannot be maintained that Witt?
coverable a priori?which links contemporary philos?
genstein's ideas have been ignored, but philosophy ophy to the Descartes-Locke-Kant tradition.12
has not ground to a halt, either. The therapy, even
for those who have undertaken it most zealously, Rorty's observations are, I believe, important
has not eradicated philosophical troubles. We may and mostly correct. Still, the significance and impli?
well seek another model. cations of these insights need to be evaluated care?
What I am calling the conversational model of fully.
philosophy is articulated by Richard Rorty as a First, Rorty urges that the realistic stance be
default position based on what he perceives as the relinquished. This is the move whereby he rejects
failure of philosophy to succeed at its self-appointed the idea of philosophy as an inquiry. He says,
task. Most ofPhilosophy and the Mirror of Nature We might just be saying something?participating
is devoted to demonstrating the nature and extent in a conversation rather than contributing to an inquiry.
of this failure. The following two passages are rep? Perhaps saying things is not always saying how things
resentative: are.13

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
40 AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

Our certainty will be a matter of conversation systematic representation of the relationship between
between persons rather than a matter of interaction philosophy and culture.
with nonhuman reality.14
3. The reactive role that Rorty assigns to edifying
But these are false dilemmas. We do not have to philosophy turns out to be none other than a reintroduc?
choose between just "saying something," itself a tion of philosophy as the high court of reason, the
rather empty notion that manages to say virtually debunker of debunkers. But you can't debunk debunk?
nothing, and inquiring, or between "conversing" ing, any more than you can refute refutation. Edifying
and "interacting with nonhuman reality." It is quite philosophy is the emperor's new mirror.
clear that in doing philosophy we are interacting Getting back to the question of progress, the
with all-too-human reality; philosophers interact conversational model does not lend itself to any
mainly with each other. ready assessment. Perhaps as long as the conversa?
Rorty opposes "edifying" to "systematic" philos? tion continues, progress is being made. This is an
ophy. By "systematic" philosophy, he means the extremely minimalistic sort of progress that does
attempt to construct a fairly broad, coherent rep? not appear to fit any of the senses adumbrated ear?
resentation of reality, or some portion, thereof. lier in this chapter. More likely, conversation
"Edifying" philosophy comes down to the fol? should be viewed as non-progressive and non-ter?
lowing recommendation: minating?that is, merely perpetual.
It appears that by relinquishing the notion of
...the point of edifying philosophy is to keep the philosophy as an inquiry we have rather effectively
conversation going rather than to find objective truth.
put it out of reach of progress, unless we accept
Such truth, in the view I am advocating, is the normal
Wittgenstein's terminating therapy model. This is
result of normal discourse. Edifying philosophy is not
a desperate move at best, and it is arguable that
only abnormal but reactive, having sense only as a
Wittgenstein himself adopted it for polemical pur?
protest against attempts to close off conversation
through the hypostatization of some privileged set of
poses: to shatter the dogmatic slumbers of
descriptions. The danger which edifying discourse positivism.
tries to avert is that some given vocabulary, some way To recall the difficulty at which this essay
in which people might come to think of themselves, arrived: If we view philosophy as a species of
will deceive them into thinking that from now on all abnormal discourse, as it seems we must, then we
discourse could be, or should be normal discourse.15 cannot plausibly view it as an inquiry. But we have
not done justice to the possibility of abnormal
Again, Rorty proposes a false dilemma in the inquiry, aside from noting the resistance within the
first sentence of the quoted passage. It is just not philosophical community to the abandonment of
clear that objectivity goes out the window with the view that philosophy is an inquiry.
"normalcy." If by "reactive" Rorty simply means A recent attempt to develop an inquiry-based
"emerging as a result of suspicion about the confi? model of philosophical activity has been made by
Robert Nozick. I shall designate this, catachresti
dence with which prior views have been held,"
then all discourse is to some extent reactive. Here, cally, as the "explanational model." The explana
tional model is overtly normative; Nozick is defi?
then, are three reminders of some difficulties of
nitely making recommendations for the rehabilita?
the conversational model:
tion of philosophy. Paraphrased, the most salient
features of the model are these:
1. If the point of edifying philosophy is to keep the
conversation (of Western culture) going, it need hardly 1. The basic task of philosophy is to explain not the
be "edifying" to accomplish that. Any philosophical necessary conditions for anything, but merely the suf?
activity, no matter how relentlessly dogmatic, sys? ficient conditions. Philosophy offers explanations of
tematic, metaphysical, or aprioristic will suffice. how things are possible.

2. Edifying philosophy cannot be done without, in 2. Philosophical theorizing should incorporate explicit
the process, doing something systematic as well. Phi? reference to metatheoretical orientation, when possi?
losophy and the Mirror of Nature is an extremely ble.

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PROGRESS IN PHILOSOPHY 41

3. The agonistic, argumentative dimension of philos? what one says is believed by the individuals to
ophy should be discontinued, or somehow muted. whom one says it, one has committed one's will
to it; one has adopted the argumentative or, better,
Concerning (1), Nozick writes,
agonistic stance. Nozick writes,
The form of these questions is: how is one thing
Just as dependence is not eliminated by treating a
possible, given (or supposing) certain other things?
person dependently, and someone cannot be forced
Some statements rx,... ,rn are assumed or accepted or
to be free, a person is not most improved by being
taken for granted, and there is a tension between these
forced to believe something against his will, whether
statements and another statement p; they appear to
he wants to or not. The valuable person cannot be
excluder's holding true. Let us term the rj the apparent
fashioned by committing philosophy upon him.18
excluders (of/?). Since the statement/? also is accepted,
we fact the question of how p is possible, given its Here, Nozick would do well to heed his own
apparent excluders.16
recommendation (2). It is certainly startling to
The real contribution of the explanational model suggest that philosophers are out to "improve" per?
is its attention to "apparent excluders." Many of sons, or to "fashion" valuable ones. There is a very
the most interesting topics of speculation are pre? definite sense in which one's respect for a person
cisely those things whose very possibility not only includes one's willingness to challenge her views,
need to be explained but are apparently excluded to take them seriously enough to oppose them.
Nozick thinks that this is "not nice."19 What most
by something else. The inquiry into the possibility
of scientific knowledge derives some of its urgency philosophers would readily agree, I believe, is "not
from the availability of skeptical arguments. nice" is to be either ignored or patronized, yet this
Altruism is most puzzling against a background of is the upshot of Nozick's recommendation.
selfishness. Perhaps, having recognized that argument is rather
What I have presented as recommendation (2) central to philosophical practice, what needs to be
of Nozick's explanational model points toward a said is that philosophers should be heedful of when
greater metaphilosophical candor. Philosophers argument has reached its limit. To miss the signifi?
should perhaps become more self-conscious and cance of argument in philosophy with the bland
explicit about the metaphilosophical background remark that it is "not nice" is to epitomize what
conditions of their work, even though these may the non-philosophical community probably con?
be presupposed without argument. Nozick remarks
siders to be the worst philosophical vice: oblivious
that "A metaphilosophy will be part of a total phil? ness to what is going on around one.
osophical view rather than a separate neutral theory
above the battle."17 What is the judgment concerning progress in
philosophy, if we use the explanational model?
His use of "battle" is revealing, since it conflicts
Apparently, we get an accumulation of explana?
with the third recommendation. No doubt, philo?
tions, without any particular dialectical coherence,
sophical arguments, like any argument, can get out
since argumentation is not included in the model.
of hand, become destructively violent and create
Without confrontational argument, theories cannot
more confusion than they dispel. Nevertheless,
recommendation (3) rather naively misses the nor? easily be compared, seen as successors of other
mative urgency of any explanation, not just philo? theories, or judged adequate or inadequate. The
sophical argument. To offer any explanation, or philosophical community would just crank them
metaphor, or expression of delight, or curse, is at out, without "compelling" anyone to as much as
least in part to issue an invitation to "see the world take notice. The problem of the absence of CGP's
as I do." Nozick sees argumentation as "coercive," is sidestepped by declaring consensus to be of no
but is it necessarily more coercive than invitation? value whatsoever in philosophy. Nonetheless, as
It is simply incredible to imagine philosophers long as philosophers keep themselves busy,
calmly cranking out "explanations" without caring according to the explanational model progress is
if they are believed! As soon as one cares whether being made. Nozick uses a vivid analogy:

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
42 AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

Treating philosophy as a black box, we might view culture at large. Their debates have become sterile
its "output" not as a single theory, not even as one and incapable of making any contribution to
set of theories, but as a set of questions, each with humanity. To the extent that philosophers have
its own set of associated theories as possible answers.20 withdrawn into the isolation of internecine technical
quarrels, they have evaded their traditional respon?
As long as there is "output," there is progress.
sibilities.
Perhaps we may consider it non-terminating prog?
ress^ No doubt, this is a caricature of Nozick's Kekes claims that the proper problems of philos?
actual idea. Like most caricatures, it has a point. ophy are the so-called "enduring" problems, of
The point is that you can't take the argumentative,
which there are two kinds: problems of life and
problems of reflection. Problems of life are essen?
agonistic, coercive element out of philosophy
tially survival problems, such as food, shelter, and
without mutilating it.
the like. Problems of reflection arise when one
In the final analysis, what is needed is a sense
reflects upon what course of action will best enable
of "philosophical" that does not attempt to sidestep
one to cope with some problem of life. The impor?
philosophical disagreement, but incorporates it.
tant point here for the later development of Kekes's
The fact that there are negative CGP's in philoso?
phy, resulting in a fair degree of consensus that view is that problems of life are not "theoretical"
this or that theory, as it stands, does not work, is things; they are pretheoretical and primordial. In a
significant just because it propels philosophers to sense, problems of life are the "given" in Kekes's
new efforts. metaphilosophy. The following passage states this
As was claimed earlier, positive consensus on quite clearly:
all issues would represent the end of philosophy, Problems of reflection are indeed theory-generated,
its final exhaustion. An idea that I have argued but problems of life are not. Problems of reflection
elsewhere21 is that the possible commensurability arise because problems of life have competing solu?
of presently incommensurable discourses informs tions. So while it is true that problems of reflection
the theory of philosophical objectivity, without pro? presuppose a theory, it is no less true that the theory
viding a decision procedure, although it may is held because it is expected to provide solutions to
problems of life. Theories presuppose problems of
suggest certain lines of inquiry. life.24
There is another model that I also want to
include. It is a prominent recent contribution to the Kekes is of course anticipating and rejecting the
metaphilosophical literature. I shall call it the "pe? objection that all problems, even problems of life,
rennial" model, developed by John Kekes in his are theory-laden. I shall comment a bit later.
book, The Nature of Philosophy.22 Since problems of life are never solved for all
Basically Kekes's idea is that the only defensible time, their attendant problems of reflection are
purpose of philosophy is to offer solutions to certain likewise enduring problems. These generate peren?
perennial problems. It is, at its best, a problem-sol? nial disputes over "ideals"?human ends. These
ving discipline on his view. In the first chapter, disputes may be internal, concerning the precise
entitled "The Case Against Philosophy," he collects definition of some ideal, or external, concerning
some fairly deprecatory observations of what phi? its appropriateness of acceptability. Justice, ration?
losophy in the analytic tradition has become. He ality, and democracy are ideals in Kekes's sense,
notes that what little consensus there is in philos? as well as tyranny and oppression, if perchance
ophy is negative, the exposure of errors. Even the these latter are in fact desired and valued. Philos?
greatest philosophers, he complains, are destined ophy concerns itself with generating the perennial
"to become labels for a style of thinking in which arguments about the nature and acceptability of
students of philosophy are enjoined not to ideals. Since the primordial facts that are respon?
engage."23 More significantly, Kekes accuses con? sible for the problems of life are constantly chang?
temporary philosophers of retreating from the prob? ing, the need for these arguments is, in fact, peren?
lems that are considered generally important in the nial.

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PROGRESS IN PHILOSOPHY 43

It turns out that Kekes has three tests in mind to No doubt, when food and shelter can be provided
determine whether a theory, or worldview, contains for all humans, one of the enduring problems will
the solution to a problem of life. Two are quite have been solved; it is simply not plausible to claim
straightforward: logical consistency and "criticiza that none will remain. It implies, for example, that
bility," which is his version of falsifiability. It must in the United States, where death from starvation
be shown that a given theory is not self-contradic? and exposure is rare, the only remaining problems
tory and that it is possible to identify possible con? of life are medical. There is room here for disagree?
ditions that could tend to undermine it. The third ment.
criterion is "adequacy of interpretation." Kekes The obvious response is to extend the notion of
writes, problems of life to include the various other sorts
of survival problems mentioned above. Of course,
The second way of testing the truth-directedness of
this means that we must reject the claim that the
a theory is through the adequacy of the interpretation
it offers. As we have seen, an acceptable theory must problems of life are not in any sense theory-bound,
offer a logically and initially plausible solution to the since the problems of justice, distribution, alien?
enduring problem that prompted it. The solution is an ation, and meaning are only intelligible within some
interpretation which provides a possible way of theory. Even biological survival is not the same
thinking about a segment of reality. Interpretations problem for the would-be suicide that it is for the
can be thought of as issuing a conditional: if you think would-be octogenarian! Can we distinguish their
of reality in this way and act accordingly, then what problems without "theories"?
was previously problematic will no longer be so.25 The rejection of the claim that the enduring prob?
lems of life are "given" and not theory-bound vit?
The true theory is the one that solves the enduring
iates the use of these as the source of a set of
problem. Since the problems of life are not theory
bound, it is evidently not a theoretical issue whether
adequacy-criteria external to any theory. We are
driven to the conclusion that there is no extra-phil?
they are solved by a given theory or not.
There are several problems inherent in the peren?
osophical cognitive vantage point from which we
nial model, even though it is certainly an impressive can assess the claims of philosophy. Unfortunately,
recent attempt to develop a complete the perennial model leans quite heavily, and fatally,

metaphilosophy. The first and most conspicuous on the claim that there is such a vantage point.
one is the claim that the so called problems of life Without it, Kekes's following remarks are jejune:
are in some sense prior to any theories. Suppose For there is a true of false answer to the question
we re-christen Kekes's problems of life as "survival whether a theory is logically consistent, whether its
problems." This done, it is clear that there is a interpretation accounts for all the relevant facts, and
fairly broad range of such problems, from "sur whether it has survived all available criticism. From
vival-as-a-biological-organism" to "survival-as-a there being a correct answer, it does not follow that
group-member" to "survival-as-a-non-alienated it is easy to find it. The persistence of disagreements
indicates just how difficult it is.26
being," and so on. Does Kekes mean to restrict the
enduring problems of life to the problems of biolog? Ultimately, the dichotomy of problems of life
ical survival? If so (and his references to food and and problems of reflection fails. The notion of
shelter in this context support this interpretation), external adequacy criteria fails. Is there progress
then a case can no doubt be made that these are
in philosophy according to the perennial model? If
pre- or non-theoretical problems. It would also
the foregoing caveats are taken seriously, it is dif?
seem to entail that any being whose biological sur?
ficult to see how there can be more than "output"
vival is not in jeopardy, such as a well-fed slave,
has no problems of life. On a collective scale, it again. No one has ever doubted that philosophical
means that when the minima of biological survival arguments are perennial; we seek a progress that
can be provided for every human being, the is more than perpetuity.
enduring problems of mankind will have been sol? The state of the argument is this: An analysis of
ved. progress has been offered. Four models of philo

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
44 AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

sophical inquiry have been compared and "follow the argument where it leads," we are not
criticized. The absence of stable CGP's in philos? entitled to stop when we get there. We must also
ophy was noted. Consensus is defined as agreement ask if we are willing to stay where the argument
or the cessation of controversy, at least. It remains leads.
to be seen how actual disagreements in the present
A probative orientation of the sort at issue here is
day philosophical community are to be handled,
axiological?it embodies certain value predispositions
since the "persistence of disagreement" is salient regarding the probative appraisal of theses and argu?
in all the models examined.
ments.... Accordingly, such a perspective is not an
Nicholas Rescher has stated that, concerning algorithm for producing solutions to philosophical
philosophical disagreement, "The nature of the problems given certain constraints, but rather serves
enterprise is itself such that it is unrealistic to expect to define the constraints themselves, forming a part
consensus, and inappropriate to lament its of what is needed to mark a solution as acceptable,
to see that the solution is a solution.30
absence."27 While urging the recognition of "orien
tational pluralism" in philosophy?the view that
The sources of these predispositions and con?
"philosophical issues are always such that argu?
straints may not be easily identifiable, or even cog
ments of substantial prima facie cogency can be
nitively structured. This does not make them unfit
built up for a cluster of mutually incompatible
for the role they play in philosophical reasoning,
theses"28?Rescher does not attempt to downplay
but it requires the dialectical effort of the entire
the role of argument. Instead, he notes that the
community even to uncover what they are. Things
arguments are "non-preemptive."
are not always what they seem, and this goes for
In philosophy, supportive argumentation is never orientational commitments as much as anything
alternative-precluding. Thus the fact that a good case else.
can be made out for giving one particular answer to The two most important features of this view are
a philosophical question is never to be considered as (1) it is not anarchistic; there are still rational con?
constituting a valid reason for denying that an equally straints upon what positions can be plausibly linked
good case can be produced for some other incompat?
with which orientations; (2) the viability of a given
ible answers to this question.29
perspective is in part contingent upon the vitality
He calls these families of alternative solutions of its adherents and their ability to continue the
to a given philosophical problem "aporetic clusters" game of rationality.
and notes that every philosophical problem gener? What is the operational payoff of Rescher's line,
ates them. While theories, supported by positive if any? He states it as follows:
argumentation, do indeed proliferate, there is also It is not only possible but appropriate at once to
a dialectical undertow at work, eliminating certain work out what is the appropriate answer to philosoph?
views: the negative CGP's. Not all positions are ical problems?as best we can determine it "from
eliminated, however; they become philosophical where we sit"?and nevertheless to recognize that
classics, paradigms, if you will, that generate their other solutions are available and need to be reckoned
with.31
own aporetic clusters.
The process of eliminative undertow in philos?
One may still wonder why Rescher thinks that
ophy is not simply one of exposing deductively this state of affairs is not to be lamented. The
faulty arguments. Rescher notes that perfectly valid
answer, fittingly, is that the proliferation of disag?
argument are evaluated in terms of the conclusions
reement is the source of variety in the cultural idea
to which they lead, and their prima facie plausibil? pool. Argumentation prevents the stagnation that
ity, as well as the correctness of the deductive orthodoxy brings. Negative consensus has the
steps. This evaluation takes into account the "costs" effect of continually pushing the philosophical sur?
of a given position, frequently in terms that extend vivors to the fore. The net result is that not only
far beyond the parameters of the position as it is do we accumulate rejected theories, we select the
presented. In following the Socratic injunction to fittest ones for further scrutiny. The "fitness" of a

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PROGRESS IN PHILOSOPHY 45

philosophical theory is, in a sense, the measure of inconclusiveness. That there are "aporetic clusters"
the objectivity ofthat mode of philosophical reason? is evidence of a kind of progress. That the necrology
ing. Nevertheless, the fact that free philosophical of failed arguments is so long is further evidence.
inquiry tends to counteract, by way of its agonism, Having distinguished three kinds of progress, it
the forces of dogmatism within a culture, is still is appropriate to ask which kind applies to philos?
an epiphenomenon of such inquiry. Individual phi? ophy, even though the answer has already been
losophers who attempt to take this as their private implied by exclusion. I think we must conclude
goal would be no more than polemicists. Hence, that there is progress2 in philosophy. To recall,
it may be a mistake to see this agonism in opera? progress2 is paradigmatically undecidable progress,
tional terms. Individual philosophers must address the sort where a final goal cannot be formulated,
the question of why the prevention of dogmatism and where intermediate sub-goals are likewise
is to be desired; doing so will commit them to without uniform criteria of success, but where the
inquiry again. sense of development nevertheless importunes. In
Perhaps the important point is that numerous this respect, at least, philosophy is closer to the
positions should be recognized as having some arts than to the sciences. Having arrived at this
legitimate validity, not merely as logical pos? conclusion?that there is progress in philosophy?
sibilities but as inhabited places, if you will allow the provisional utility of distinguishing the three
the metaphor. A perspective is only interesting if senses of progress is, no doubt, exhausted.
it is someone's. Objectivity requires the recognition There is, among philosophers, a widespread
of and respect for other inquiring agents. feeling that metaphilosophical speculation is
The "rightness" of a theory is not the extent to somehow faulty, of at least decadent. This attitude
which it excludes other theories. The peculiarity of contempt is displayed, for example, in the fol?
of this sort of objectivity lies in the fact that incom? lowing passage from Gilbert Ryle's "Ordinary Lan?
patible views may have equal and legitimate claims guage":
to our attention. There is nothing peculiarly philo?
We run, as a rule, worse, not better, if we think a
sophical about this; it has been known for a long
lot about our feet. So let us, at least on alternate days,
time in literary criticism and historical analysis. It speak instead of investigating the concept of causa?
has begun to be recognized in mathematics and in tion. Or, better still, let us, on those days, not speak
the hard sciences. Perhaps the lesson of these of it at all but just do it.32
diverse inquiries of the twentieth century will be
seen by posterity as the realization that cognitive I oppose the view that metaphilosophical specu?
pluralism does not entail nihilism. lation is a symptom of decadence; on the contrary,
I think it is its antidote. It is the mark of a re-dedi?
For the last time, we ask "Is there progress in
cation of effort to one of the most venerable of the
philosophy?" The answer is: Philosophy progresses
by its inability to produce consensus in the short Socratic questions: How does the philosopher differ
run, by its inherent instability, by subjecting every from the sophist? If there is such a difference, it
theory to "unfair" criticisms (criticisms derived is not, as Socrates knew, simply a matter of what
from a different probative orientation), by pre? they say. It is in what they do. The sophists, ulti?
venting permanent dogmatism at the level of the mately, were specialists in conversation; philoso?
individual philosopher, and at the cultural level. phers may be this, but they are not merely this.
The record of this progress is really the evolution The Socratic answer still deserves our attention:
of objectivity itself. Given any problem in the phil? While the sophist merely speaks, the philosopher
osophical tradition, it is hard to avoid a sense of seeks. That is how there can be progress in philos?
development of positions, even amid frustrating ophy.

St. Joseph's University Received January 9, 1985

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
46 AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

NOTES

1. Nicholas Rescher's The Strife of Systems (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1985) is one recent attempt to fill this gap.
2. Larry Laudan, Progress and Its Problems (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977) p. 13.
3. Ibid., p. 124.
4. Rorty, of course, sees himself as following through on the insights of Wittgenstein and others.
5. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans, by D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1961) p. 5.
6. Ludwig Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books (New York: Harper and Row, 1958; London: Basil Blackwell, 1958; reprint
ed. New York: Harper Colophon, 1965) p. 58.
1. Ibid., p. 46.
8. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (London: Basil Blackwell, 1958; reprint ed. New York: Macmillan Pub?
lishing Co. Inc., 1968), p. 49e (#133)
9. Ibid., #127.
10. Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: University of Princeton Press, 1978) p. 3 (both passages).
U. Ibid., p. 5.
12. Ibid., p. 8.
13. Ibid., p. 371.
14. Ibid., p. 157.
15. Ibid., p. 377.
16. Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981) p. 9.
17. Ibid., p. 19.
18. Ibid., p. 5.
\9.Ibid.,p. 13.
20. Ibid., p. 20.
21. Todd C. Moody, "The Objectivity of Transcendental Arguments," forthcoming in Metaphilosophy.
22. John Kekes, The Nature of Philosophy (Ottowa: Rowman and Littlefield, 1980).
23. Ibid., p. 6.
24. Ibid., p. 44.
25. Ibid., p. 115.
26. Ibid., p. 125.
27. Nicholas Rescher, "Philosophical Disagreement: An Essay Towards Orientational Pluralism in Metaphilosophy," Review of
Metaphysics, vol. 32 (1978), pp. 217-251 (see p. 219).
28. Ibid., p. 220.
29. Ibid.
30. Ibid., p. 226.
31. Ibid., p. 241.
32. Gilbert Ryle, "Ordinary Language," in V. C. Chappell ed., Ordinary Language (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1964)
p. 39.

This content downloaded from 66.7.210.88 on Mon, 19 Sep 2016 02:25:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like