You are on page 1of 12

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/275657490

Democratic Theory after Transitions from Authoritarian Rule

Article  in  Perspectives on Politics · January 2011

CITATION READS
1 622

1 author:

Gerardo L Munck
University of Southern California
82 PUBLICATIONS   1,726 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Critical Junctures View project

Symposium on Critical Junctures and Historical Legacies View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Gerardo L Munck on 01 May 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


| |

Review Essay

Democratic Theory after Transitions from


Authoritarian Rule
Gerardo L. Munck

Democracy, Agency, and the State: Theory with Comparative Intent. By Guillermo O’Donnell. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2010. 280p. $85.00.
Democracy and the Limits of Self-Government. By Adam Przeworski. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
216p. $75.00 cloth, $23.99 paper.
Crafting State-Nations: India and Other Multinational Democracies. By Alfred Stepan, Juan J. Linz, and Yogendra
Yadav. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2011. 236p. $60.00 cloth, $30.00 paper.

ecent events across the globe make clear the com- one: These scholars have generated many fundamental

R plexities of the politics of “democratization” and the


importance of developing nuanced and compelling
understandings of these complexities. In Eurasia, “Color
insights, and their key texts are indispensible references in
current democratic theory.

Revolutions” have given way to democratic disappoint- Establishing a New Baseline: On


ments and “authoritarian regimes.” In north Africa, an Research Questions, Explanations,
unanticipated upsurge of democratic movements has felled and Testing 䡬
autocrats in Tunisia and Egypt, but the political outcomes Theorizing about democracy has a long history, from the
of these “transitions” are very much in doubt. Contempo- ancient writings of Plato, Aristotle, and Thucydides to the
rary political science has developed an elaborate vocabu- European social contract writers of the early modern period
lary for understanding such processes. And this vocabulary to the seminal nineteenth-century writings of John Stuart
owes a great deal to a small group of scholars—Juan Linz, Mill, Karl Marx, and Alexis de Tocqueville. In the early part
Guillermo O’Donnell, Philippe Schmitter, Alfred Stepan of the twentieth century, a more empirical approach emerged,
and Adam Przeworksi—who helped to lay the theoretical informed by the ascendancy of the new social scientific sen-
foundations of our current understanding of politics around sibility and pioneered by writers such as Max Weber, Rob-
the globe. erto Michels, and Joseph Schumpeter. This approach was
The publication of three new books by these authors central for the initiators of the behavioral revolution in the
offers an opportunity both to reflect on the enduring con- United States, and theorists such as Robert Dahl, Gabriel
tribution of the distinctive approach to democratization Almond, Barrington Moore, Seymour Martin Lipset, Arend
that they helped pioneer in the course of studying the Liphart, and Stein Rokkan further developed an empirical
democratic transitions of the last quarter of the twentieth theory of democracy, in close conjunction with the theory
century, and to consider further developments in the think- of modernization. This intellectual history is well known,
ing of these scholars as they reflected on the new political and it laid the foundations for contemporary political sci-
realities of the 1990s and 2000s. In this review essay, I will ence scholarship on democracy and democratization.
present an overview of their distinctive approach to the At the same time, contemporary political science would
study of democratization and then discuss their recent be unimaginable without the seminal contributions that
books in light of this account. My basic point is a simple emerged from the Woodrow Wilson Center project on
“Transitions from Authoritarian Rule.” 1 This project, the
brainchild of O’Donnell and Schmitter,2 began with three
Gerardo L. Munck is professor at the School of Inter- conferences, in 1979, 1980, and 1981, that gathered many
national Relations at USC. He would like to thank Abra- of the world’s most distinguished scholars of democracy,
ham Lowenthal, Sebastián Mazzuca, Guillermo O’Donnell including Dahl, Linz, Przeworski, Fernando Henrique Car-
and Adam Przeworski for their comments. He also owes a doso, and Albert Hirschman. And the final product of
special thanks to Jeffrey Isaac for his extensive constructive this project, the four-volume Transitions from Authoritar-
suggestions. ian Rule, and especially volume 4 of this work, O’Donnell

doi:10.1017/S1537592711000600 June 2011 | Vol. 9/No. 2 333


| |

Review Essay | Democratic Theory after Transitions from Authoritarian Rule

and Schmitter’s Tentative Conclusions about Uncertain first question was disaggregated into two questions, about
Democracies, 3 became the first major statement on the the conditions for a transition from authoritarianism and
“third wave” of democratic changes that unfolded in the for a transition to democracy. That is, the overarching
wake of the overthrow of the Portuguese fascist dictator- research question—What explains democracy?—was bro-
ship in 1974. ken down into component parts that were both amenable
Reflecting the rapidly changing world of the last quar- to more careful analysis and explicitly linked together.
ter of the twentieth century, this new research on democ- Again, these were not new ideas. In particular, Dank-
racy soon expanded beyond the initial concern with wart Rustow had earlier introduced the distinction between
democratic transitions in Latin America and Southern a theory of democratic transitions and a theory of the
Europe, incorporating all three regions of what was still stability of democracy.7 But, in stressing the possible asym-
known as the Third World and eventually including the metry between processes of transition to democracy and
communist world in the East. Going beyond the question the breakdown of democracy, O’Donnell and Schmitter
of democratic transitions, but still focused on contempo- highlighted the need to consider the possibility that ques-
rary developments, attention increasingly turned to the tions about the origins and the durability of democracy
consolidation, or more precisely the durability, of the new might call for different answers. Moreover, by underscor-
democracies that flourished around the world. Further- ing that a theory of the demise of authoritarian rule is not,
more, as time went on, the link between democracy and by itself, a theory of democratic transitions, and by clari-
economic reforms gained prominence, multiple dimen- fying that liberalization is not the same as democratiza-
sions of the state were addressed, and nationalism and tion and can result rather in a liberalized autocracy
religion entered into the picture. (dictablanda) or a limited democracy (democradura),
As the twentieth century was coming to a close, the O’Donnell and Schmitter spelled out the explanatory chal-
world was changing rapidly, and scholars were trying to lenges with uncanny lucidity.8
make sense of these changes in real time. A wealth of new While O’Donnell and Schmitter’s way of framing the
research on democracy was published, including the results research on democratization has not, to be sure, been adopted
of various collective projects,4 and influential books such by all, it dramatically transformed scholarship on democ-
as Przeworski’s Democracy and the Market, Linz and Stepan’s racy. The consensus around the procedural minimum of
䡬 Problems of Democratic Transition and Consolidation, and democracy has broadened. In addition, more and more
Przeworski et al.’s Democracy and Development. 5 And a scholars distinguish between processes of transition to
new baseline for research on democracy was established. democracy and breakdowns of democracy. For example,
Ruth Berins Collier explicitly distinguishes the origins from
the endurance of democracy and has devoted considerable
Framing the Research Questions attention to the task of identifying the threshold countries
One element of this new baseline concerns the outcome must cross in a democratic transition.9 Charles Tilly simi-
to be explained. In this regard, this new literature helped larly places the distinction between processes of democra-
to cement an emerging consensus regarding the concept tization and “de-democratization” at the heart of his analysis,
of democracy. The question “What is democracy?” is a and repeatedly highlights the asymmetry between these two
matter of continuing discussion, as I will address below. processes.10 And Daron Acemoglu and James Robinson’s
Nonetheless, building on Dahl’s earlier work, O’Donnell “unified theory of democracy” centers on the challenge of
and Schmitter’s emphasis on the “consensus in the con- providing an explanation that can account for both the ori-
temporary world” regarding the status of a “procedural gins and the durability of democracy.11 At the same time,
minimum” as a “necessary” feature of political democracy the importance of distinguishing transitions from author-
was valuable.6 It helped to specify the outcome that called itarianism and transitions to democracy is at the heart of
for an explanation in terms that made sense to researchers the large new literature on “hybrid regimes,” that is, regimes
interested in a diverse set of countries at a time when that combine features of authoritarianism and democracy
doubts about such a procedural minimum were still raised and thus occupy a grey zone between clearly authoritarian
in some quarters. And it provided a much needed concep- and democratic systems.12 In all of these respects, the impact
tual anchor for empirical research. of the Woodrow Wilson Center project on transitions on
Relatedly, this new literature helped establish the impor- the framing of research was profound.
tance of disaggregating the problematic of democracy into
distinct questions in an organized fashion. At the broadest
level, understanding the conditions of democracy was seen Theorizing Political Dynamics
as hinging on two distinct questions: (1) What are the con- A second element of the new baseline established in the
ditions for a transition from some form of authoritarian- new phase of research on democracy concerns the devel-
ism to democracy? and (2) What are the factors that account opment of explanatory theories. The literature on demo-
for the durability or endurance of democracy? In turn, the cratic transitions, and in particular O’Donnell and

334 Perspectives on Politics


| |

Schmitter’s book and Przeworski’s early work on transi- The influence of this turn to political explanations is
tions,13 broke with the focus on macrosocietal forces that most obvious in recent institutionalist scholarship that
figured prominently in the earlier works of Lipset and treats political institutions as results of the decisions of
Moore and in other classic books.14 The reason for this political actors.22 It is also evident in recent research that
shift in approach, as the instigators of this shift have revisits some of the classic macrosocietal arguments of the
acknowledged,15 was largely political rather than purely earlier literature on democracy. For example, when Col-
scientific. In Przeworski’s words, in the older literature, lier revisited the debate about classes and democracy
outcomes were “uniquely determined by [macrosocietal] launched by Moore, she explicitly included political elites,
conditions, and history . . . [went] on without anyone both within and outside the state, in her explanatory frame-
ever doing anything.” 16 That is, the prevailing macroso- work.23 Similarly, attempts to revisit the classic macroeco-
cietal theories of the 1960s and 1970s were seen as overly nomic and macrosocial explanations of the 1960s using
deterministic and hence offering no guidance to political the tools of game theory highlight the strategic inter-
actors or, even worse, seemed to invite quiescence. Indeed, action among actors and the choices that elites in partic-
the political reading of these theories offered by some schol- ular make in light of the redistributive consequences of
ars highlighted that many authoritarian countries lacked state policies.24 These developments mark the emergence
the supposed prerequisites for democracy and that politi- of a new political sociology and political economy of
cal activity oriented toward promoting democracy when a democracy, more attuned to the duality of structure and
country was not ripe for democracy might actually be agency and to the endogeneity of societal forces and
counterproductive. The participants in the Wilson Center actors.25
project on transitions thus practiced what Abraham
Lowenthal characterized as “thoughtful wishing,” 17 reject-
ing “structural determinism,” unabashedly embracing Testing Propositions
democracy as a positive normative value, and searching Finally, a third element of the new baseline established in
for realistic possibilities to foster democracy. the new research on democracy concerns the empirical
If the break with prevailing macrosocietal theories in testing of propositions and, relatedly, the use of the results
this new literature was largely politically driven, the alter- of empirical research for the purpose of offering policy
native theoretical approach that these writers offered stands advice. The literature of the 1960s and 1970s was empir- 䡬
on its own merits. The new theorizing focused on process, ical. But few authors used cross-national data, provided
drew attention to both state actors and societal actors, and any sort of rigorous statistical test of their explanatory
analyzed the choices made by these actors. Rejecting struc- propositions, or paid much attention to matters of research
turalist determinism, O’Donnell and Schmitter argued design when drawing conclusions about the causes of
that political outcomes were “underdetermined” from the democracy. These limitations, however, did not stop authors
perspective of standard macrostructural factors, since polit- such as Samuel Huntington from mobilizing arguments,
ical outcomes were contingent on the strategic choices of among other things about the economic prerequisites of
actors and, most critically, because key characteristics of democracy, to support authoritarianism during the Cold
the relevant actors such as their power were not givens but War.26
rather were affected by their choices and underwent sig- These characteristics of the literature on democracy
nificant changes in the course of the political process itself.18 began to change, in large part due to the work of Przewor-
In developing these ideas, O’Donnell and Schmitter ski, starting with his 1997 World Politics article on mod-
drew on Rustow’s earlier work on transitions to democ- ernization theory and his 2000 book Democracy and
racy and Linz’s analysis of the breakdown of democracy.19 Development. 27 These publications showed that by invest-
Przeworski, too, had earlier stressed, in his analysis of social ing efforts in data generation, being attentive to endo-
democracy, that “Classes are not a datum prior to the geneity, and drawing on relevant statistical techniques, it
history of concrete struggles” and that “politics . . . should was possible to assess arguments in a much more rigorous
be seen as a contingent historical outcome of continual manner than was the case in earlier decades. They also
conflicts.” 20 But the Wilson Center project brought these showed how careful academic research could be used to
insights into greater prominence. The term “endogeneity,” unmask influential ideological arguments about democ-
used to denote explanatory factors that are affected by racy and offer a more responsible basis for debate about
the variables they are purported to affect, did not enter the policy choices.
vocabulary of students of democracy until later, in the Specifically, Przeworski tackled the argument that,
mid-1990s. But it is not a stretch to say that the new because economic development supposedly leads to democ-
literature on democratic transitions was grappling with racy and authoritarian governments ostensibly perform
the problem of endogeneity and suggesting, as Przeworski better in economic terms, the wise thing to do is support
put it later, that “everything is endogenous” and hence authoritarian governments and their development projects.
that “[t]he only motor of history is endogeneity.” 21 He showed, based on a more scientifically valid evaluation

June 2011 | Vol. 9/No. 2 335


| |

Review Essay | Democratic Theory after Transitions from Authoritarian Rule

than had ever previously been conducted, that “we do not are not prerequisites of democracy, they were silent about
have a shred of evidence that democracy need be sacrificed Rustow’s argument that there still was a key prerequisite
on the altar of development” and that “democracy is . . . of democracy, specifically that before a transition to democ-
neither inevitable nor impossible . . . [but rather] a con- racy can begin, national unity, understood as entailing an
tingent outcome of conflicts among several organized established sense of national identity and fixed territorial
groups.” 28 Przeworski thus added force to the rejection of boundaries, must be secured.34 But, starting in the early
the thesis about the economic prerequisites of democrati- 1990s, in the context of a resurgence of ethnonationalism,
zation offered by the Wilson Center project, mainly based this idea that the construction of a nation-state must pre-
on political considerations, by questioning the empirical cede democratization came under scrutiny and was increas-
validity of the sort of political arguments Huntington was ingly questioned.
known for.29 A second new line of inquiry has addressed the more
Much as with other changes introduced or consoli- purely conceptual question “What is democracy?” and
dated during this phase of research on democracy, not all the associated normative question “Why should democ-
writers on democracy have embraced the new standard racy be valued?” The Wilson Center project had touched
concerning the testing of propositions, especially when on these questions, but only briefly. The focus had largely
seeking to extract policy recommendations from research. been on making sense of a rapidly changing political
Perhaps more worrisome, several authors, including pub- world and developing explanatory theory that could ori-
lic intellectuals Fareed Zakaria and Francis Fukuyama, have ent the actions of prodemocratic actors. And the urgent
recently resurrected Huntingtonian arguments cautioning conceptual task at the time was to specify a target for
against the “premature” promotion of democratization.30 immediate action that was widely held to be desirable—a
While such calls for postponing, demoting or containing “minimalist” conception of democracy. Yet, also begin-
demands for democracy have increasingly placed empha- ning in the early 1990s, as it became a matter of conven-
sis on the need to secure political order and not just eco- tion to talk about the spread of democracy to all corners
nomic development before pushing for democracy,31 these of the world, some scholars started to reconsider the con-
claims about prerequisites of democracy are typically based cept of democracy that served as the anchor of explana-
on a clearly selective reading of the evidence and certainly tory theorizing and empirical analyses and, in effect, to
䡬 nothing that approximates a robust causal finding. revisit Dahl’s conceptual and normative arguments about
But such impressionistic arguments fly in the face of an democracy.35 The recent books by O’Donnell, Prze-
increasingly sophisticated body of research on democrati- worksi, and Stepan, Linz, and Yadav that are the occa-
zation driven by the commitment to collect cross-national sion for this review essay thus significantly extend the
data and subject explanatory claims to a systematic empir- original Wilson Center approach.
ical analysis.32 A heightened attention to questions of mea-
surement and data generation has been at the root of many
important advances in proposition testing. Equally crucial State and Nation in Explanations of Democracy
is the increased emphasis on matters of research design, The relationship between the character of the state and
which Robinson refers to as the “causality revolution,” democratization has long been central to the collaboration
which has gradually spread from the discipline of econom- of Linz and Stepan. These two scholars did some of the pio-
ics to the study of democracy.33 And though this more neering work on the topic in the 1990s, when the fate of
methodologically self-conscious literature has not addressed two ethnofederal states, the USSR and Yugoslavia, made it
prescriptive questions and political arguments as much as abundantly clear that the state could not be treated as a con-
it could and should, it implicitly exposes the purely ideo- stant and that it was necessary to theorize the relationship
logical nature of much advice offered in the name of pro- between the state, the nation, and democracy.36 These
moting democracy. authors have dedicated sustained attention to this complex
relationship over the past fifteen years, gradually broaden-
ing the empirical scope of their analysis and increasingly
Opening New Research Frontiers: On highlighting the role of federal institutions.37 The result of
the State and Democracy these efforts is their new book on the topic, coauthored with
Beyond establishing a new baseline for research on democ- Yogendra Yadav of the Centre of Developing Societies in
racy, the post-1986 scholarship also tackled theoretical Delhi: Crafting State-Nations: India and Other Multinational
issues that were not part of the agenda of the Wilson Democracies.
Center project on transitions. One new line of inquiry has Linz and Stepan argue that when a process of democ-
addressed the question of the nation-state. Interestingly, ratization starts to unfold in a society that is multi-
though the scholars who were part of the Wilson Center national, political demands will likely not focus solely on
project shared Rustow’s view that the economic and social altering the way key government offices are accessed. Ques-
factors that figured prominently in modernization theory tions will also be raised about the appropriateness of the

336 Perspectives on Politics


| |

political unit, that is, over what territory and what pop- For example, Linz’s statement that “without a state there
ulation a state should govern. Thus, discussions about can be no democracy” seems to be an overreach.41 Indeed,
democracy and the state cannot be divorced. Yet the stan- as Schmitter has noted, “it is an exaggeration to claim that
dard answer—that only nation-states, that is, states that without a state there can be no democracy.” 42 And Linz’s
contain only one nation, can generate the necessary degree statement is also problematic from a theory-building per-
of trust in the major institutions of the state that a mod- spective. We might interpret it as referring to a defini-
ern democracy needs, and hence every state should be a tional matter, meaning that inasmuch as democracy refers
nation and every nation should be a state—is problem- to, at the very least, the access to government offices,
atic. When a society is multinational, building a nation- democracy presupposes, as a matter of conceptual logic, a
state is likely to be incompatible with developing state.43 But we might also interpret it as a claim about the
democracy, requiring the marginalization of important causes or consequences of democracy. On a critical matter
sectors of the population and even a heavy dose of repres- of theory, we are left wondering.
sion. Moreover, the difficulty of creating nation-states It is also noteworthy that Linz and Stepan explicitly
through state policies has been increasingly demon- argue that the state is a prerequisite of democracy in the
strated in the twentieth century. sense that “democracy requires statehood,” that is, the
Seeking a way out of this quandary, Linz and Stepan recognition of a territorial unit as a sovereign state.44 But
offer some interesting ideas. First, they introduce the con- this claim is challenged, on empirical grounds, by the grow-
cept of a “state-nation,” characterized by multiple but com- ing literature on the international dimensions of democ-
plementary political identities and loyalties, a high degree ratization. As Schmitter remarks, this literature, and
of positive identification with the state, and pride in being especially the strand that studies the vast array of activities
citizens of that state, which they see as more appropriate that have as a stated aim the international promotion of
than the idea of the nation-state for culturally diverse soci- democracy, is not highly theoretical—another reason to
eties and multinational societies in particular. They also be dubious about the strong prescriptions offered by some
suggest that democratization need not be incompatible authors regarding what Western governments should do
with a questioning of the appropriateness of the political and not do in the name of democracy.45 Nonetheless, it
unit if multinational societies opt for asymmetrical feder- shows that starting in the 1990s, in cases such as Cambo-
alism, an arrangement in which some cultural preroga- dia, Bosnia, Eastern Slavonia, Kosovo, and East Timor, 䡬
tives are constitutionally embedded for subunits with salient the international community—and, more specifically, the
and mobilized territorial identities, along with other con- UN—assumed some or all of the governmental powers of
sociational features. a territory and treated the transfer of power from an inter-
In short, emphasizing institutional choices in a manner national administration to an elected government as the
that is reminiscent of Lijphart,38 Linz and Stepan develop key mechanism of an exit strategy.
a theoretical argument that counters Rustow’s view that To be sure, there is an inescapable contradiction involved
national unity is a key prerequisite of democracy.39 The in efforts to impose democracy from the outside through
Rustow thesis, Linz and Stepan’s analysis implies, is based such international administrations of a territory. After all,
on an unduly restrictive model of the state that does not the inhabitants of these territories under international
envision the real possibility that questions regarding the administration did not elect their administrators. But the
political unit need not be settled before democratization essential point is that, in some cases, the restoration or the
but, instead, can be tackled simultaneously. That is, Linz gaining of sovereignty is the result of a process, not its
and Stepan show how the question of the state can be point of departure. As the experience in Kosovo shows,
endogenized within a theory of democratization rather not only can democratization proceed when the political
than treated as a fixed background condition. status of a territory is a central unresolved issue. In addi-
Linz and Stepan’s ideas about the relationship between tion, democratization can be fueled precisely by the aim
the state and democracy do not settle the question of how of establishing a claim for sovereignty. Thus, there is such
to incorporate the state within a theory of democracy, let a thing as democratization without a state.46
alone arguments about whether the state is a prerequisite To sum up, Linz and Stepan shed important light on
of democracy. The viability of their alternative depends to the challenges of constructing democracy in the context
a large extent on the independent power of institutions, a of multinational and, more broadly, multicultural soci-
matter that they do not directly address.40 Moreover, when eties. But there is still much work to do done on this
Linz and Stepan focus on dimensions of the broad prob- topic. Much hinges on how the relationship between the
lematic of the state that go beyond the appropriateness of concepts of the state and democracy is understood. Yet
the political unit, they more or less explicitly posit that the scholars have barely begun to grapple with the various
state still is, in some senses, a prerequisite of democracy. ways in which the state—or more accurately, dimensions
However, these other arguments, introduced without much of the state—might be considered as causes of democracy,
elaboration, are either unclear or questionable. as consequences of democracy, and/or, yet another option

June 2011 | Vol. 9/No. 2 337


| |

Review Essay | Democratic Theory after Transitions from Authoritarian Rule

(raised next), as constitutive of democracy. Moreover, work Regarding the concept of democracy, the most obvi-
on data collection and analysis is sorely needed to turn ous difference is that between O’Donnell and Dahl.
this discussion into more than a debate about theory. In O’Donnell deliberately seeks to broaden the meaning of
this regard, the paucity of empirical analyses of the state democracy as elaborated by Dahl.49 He reframes Dahl’s
compared to analyses of modernization theory is striking. operational, pared-down concept of polyarchy as corre-
While the role of the state is thus increasingly addressed in sponding to what he labels the democratic regime, and
research on democracy, more theoretical and empirical then argues that a full understanding of democracy must
research is needed to develop this relatively new line of reach beyond the democratic regime and encompass, on
inquiry. the one hand, a distinct set of rights and freedoms related
to the civil, social and cultural aspects of citizenship and,
on the other hand, the legal backing of the agency of all
Conceptualizing and Valuing Democracy citizens. But O’Donnell’s view does not necessarily clash
The second new line of inquiry that extends the agenda of with Dahl’s. After all, Dahl not only goes beyond a strictly
the Wilson Center project involves a reconsideration of procedural conception by introducing the idea that cer-
the concept of democracy and its normative value. In the tain rights traditionally understood as civil rights are inte-
early 1990s, O’Donnell had already suggested that because gral to democracy.50 In addition, he raises the possibility
the conventional view on democracy is based on the expe- that there are certain features—such as vastly unequal
rience of the rich democratic countries of Western Europe economic resources—that are external to the democratic
and North America, the spread of democracy well beyond process yet which can affect the proper functioning of
this region in the last quarter of the twentieth century democracy.51 And, going even further, Dahl holds that it
gave urgency to a reconsideration of standard conceptual- is not out of the question to consider whether the very
izations of democracy. Since then, he has tackled that chal- principle that justifies democracy—the principle of equal
lenge in a series of essays in which he stressed, among intrinsic worth in Dahl’s case, and the principle of agency
other things, how the state and its multiple dimensions is in the case of O’Donnell (pp. 25–49)—is upheld in realms
presupposed by democracy.47 This long process of reflec- that are not directly linked to the democracy process.52
tion has now culminated in his book Democracy, Agency, Dahl’s and O’Donnell’s approaches thus offer an interest-
䡬 and the State. ing dialogue on ways of extending the conception of
Along similar lines, Przeworski has responded to the democracy.
perception that the group of scholars that participated in Przeworski’s concept of democracy is closer to Dahl’s
the Wilson Center project “studied transitions to democ- than O’Donnell’s. His four key conditions of democracy—
racy without asking questions about democracy” (p. xii) equality, participation, representation, and liberty—
by turning his attention to conceptualizations of democ- resemble Dahl’s quite closely. Moreover, in contrast to
racy. Indeed, since the 1990s, he has considered the mean- O’Donnell, Przeworski keeps the focus squarely on the
ing of democracy but also the distinct question of what process of collective decision making and on political insti-
should be expected from democracy and what, if any, are tutions rather than rights. But Przeworski moves well
the limits of democracy.48 And, much as in O’Donnell’s beyond a Schumpeterian minimalist concept of democ-
case, this sustained research over many years has been racy and even Dahl’s concept of polyarchy. Rather than
rounded off with a book, Democracy and the Limits of focus only on whether access to government offices occurs
Self-Government. through competitive elections, Przeworski considers what
O’Donnell’s and Przeworski’s books are alike in many governments can do and cannot do, and stresses how super-
respects. They both rekindle the link between democracy majority rule protects vested interests. He places a heavy
studies and political and legal theory. They both ground emphasis on effective equal opportunities and the condi-
their analyses in sweeping historical overviews of the devel- tions of political equality. And his warning that “we may
opment of democracy. And they both are so substantial be seeing a new monster: democracy without effective cit-
that they invite comparison with Dahl’s earlier landmark izenship” (p. xiv) resonates with much of O’Donnell’s writ-
work on the meaning and value of democracy. But these ings. In short, though the differences between O’Donnell
two books also differ in ways that have significant impli- and Przeworski are significant, they both propose con-
cations for research and for policy debates about democ- cepts of democracy that go beyond the essentially mini-
racy. Indeed, it is instructive to compare, if in a necessarily malist concept used in the Wilson Center project on
superficial manner, the responses O’Donnell and Przewor- transitions.
ski offer to two fundamental questions: What is democ- Regarding the value of democracy, Dahl and O’Donnell
racy? And why should democracy be valued? And, because hold roughly similar views. Dahl argues that a compre-
the work of these two authors invites a comparison with hensive set of benefits accrue to democracies. And
Dahl, it is also informative to draw attention to their sim- O’Donnell, as might be expected in light of his focus on
ilarities and differences with Dahl. agency and emphasis on rights, sees democracy as having

338 Perspectives on Politics


| |

a number of benefits beyond the strictly political arena. a concept of democracy that goes beyond the minimalist
Nonetheless, Przeworski’s position is the most telling, in concept used in the Wilson Center project and indeed in
that he makes an assessment of the value of democracy a most of the empirical literature on democracy.
central research goal and considers various possible ben-
efits of democracy both from a theoretical and empirical Conclusion
perspective.53 And, interestingly, Przeworski’s conclusion Democratic theory, understood as encompassing concep-
about the potential virtues of democracy differs consider- tual and normative questions as well as empirical and pre-
ably from Dahl’s and O’Donnell’s. Democracy, according scriptive questions, is at the heart of the study of politics. It
to Przeworski, is beneficial because it offers a peaceful way also plays an important role in shaping how choices are
of processing conflicts and embodies the ideal of self- framed by civil society organizations, politicians, govern-
government of the people. But, he underscores, choosing ments, and international organizations, thus helping to shape
rulers by elections does not lead to greater economic growth public debate. As I have tried to suggest, the evolution of
and does not assure rationality, representation, or social democratic theory since the publication of Transitions from
and economic equality. That is, Przeworski advances a Authoritarian Rule in 1986 has brought significant advances
considerably more modest rationale for supporting democ- in the state of knowledge. By shedding light on the com-
racy than either Dahl or O’Donnell. plexities associated with authoritarian breakdowns, demo-
Przeworski also offers a political counterpoint to cratic transitions, and the endurance of democracy; by
O’Donnell. O’Donnell (pp. 209–10) stresses that, though clarifying the role of political agents in actuating these
democracy is preferable to its alternatives simply because outcomes; and by revisiting the role of the state and the con-
it provides a peaceful way of deciding who will govern, the cept of democracy, the study of democracy and democra-
normative appeal of democracy extends beyond this basic tization has proven itself a vital and evolving line of research,
value. In contrast, Przeworski counters the common ten- offering both theoretical and practical insight.
dency to think naively about the promises of democracy At the same time, the continued evolution of this
by drawing attention to the limits of democracy, cautions research program would seem to require not simply meth-
against holding democracy up to a standard no other sys- odological rigor and theoretical cleverness, but a willing-
tem meets and criticizing democracy for what it cannot ness on the part of a new generation of political scientists
realistically deliver, and calls for a discussion of and action to engage with conviction the big political issues of the 䡬
on feasible reforms. In other words, a difference between day. The advances associated with the Wilson Center
these two scholars—which actually makes their analyses project and subsequent efforts to extend the original Wilson
complementary rather than contradictory—is that Center approach were driven by an approach to scholar-
O’Donnell is especially attentive to the way political ide- ship infused by a strong concern with normative issues
als serve as a motivation for political action and Przewor- and a real sense of politics. Yet the growing drive toward
ski is particularly concerned with offering a guide for professionalization and specialization in the discipline of
political action shorn of unreasonable expectations. political science, and the discipline’s tendency to reward
O’Donnell and Przeworski’s calls for a broadening of knowledge that is mainly technical in nature, makes it
the agenda that has typically occupied students of democ- increasingly hard for young political scientists to emulate
racy have major implications. It is worth recalling that the kind of scholarship produced by Linz and Stepan,
most of the research that seeks to explain democracy relies O’Donnell and Schmitter, and Przeworski. This is an unfor-
on a minimalist concept of democracy centered on the tunate development well worth pondering. Indeed, it will
formation of government. This approach ignores matters be necessary for us to give serious thought to how young
such as the ability of a majority to change the status quo scholars can be enabled to follow in the footsteps of the
and the role of money in politics, is fully divorced from scholars whose work I have been discussing.
substantive as opposed to procedural considerations, and
ignores the ways in which the state itself might be consid-
ered constitutive of democracy. Yet these issues—frequently Notes
referred to as matters pertaining to the “quality of 1 The full name of the project is “Transitions from
democracy”—are increasingly moving to the center of the Authoritarian Rule: Prospects for Democracy in
political agenda in many countries, raising new questions Latin America and Southern Europe.” For recollec-
about political strategy and complex tradeoffs among mul- tions about the Woodrow Wilson Center project by
tiple values. Thus, this new line of inquiry invites students O’Donnell, Schmitter, and Przeworski, see Munck
of democracy to tackle two big challenges: the develop- and Snyder 2007 (288–94, 323–29, 465–69).
ment of a new consensus about the conceptual and nor- 2 Fernando Henrique Cardoso also participated in
mative underpinning of research on democracy, and the the initial discussions that hatched the idea of
generation of ideas about the new empirical and prescrip- studying transitions from authoritarian rule. But
tive questions that are inevitably raised by the adoption of his growing involvement in Brazilian politics, a road

June 2011 | Vol. 9/No. 2 339


| |

Review Essay | Democratic Theory after Transitions from Authoritarian Rule

that eventually led him to the presidency of Brazil, 16 Przeworski 1991, 96.
precluded him from becoming one of the project 17 Lowenthal 1986, viii.
directors. 18 O’Donnell and Schmitter 1986, 3–5, 24.
3 O’Donnell, Schmitter, and Whitehead 1986; 19 Rustow 1970; Linz 1978. Another precedent, which
O’Donnell and Schmitter 1986. served as a point of reference for the Woodrow
4 Three collective projects during the late 1980s and Wilson Center project on transitions, was Hir-
early 1990s that resulted in substantial contribu- schman’s advocacy of “possibilism.” Hirschman
tions to this new body of literature deserve men- elaborated this notion in the context of research on
tion. One is the project directed by Larry economic development, but extended it to the topic
Diamond, Linz, and Seymour Lipset, which con- of democracy in a 1980 lecture. Hirschman 1971;
vened a large group of researchers in 1985 to ana- Hirschman 1986.
lyze democracy in all three main regions of the 20 Przeworski 1985, 69, 4.
Third World. This project produced three large vol- 21 Przeworski 2010, xv; Przeworski 2004a, 168.
umes entitled Democracy in Developing Countries. 22 Leff 1999; Cheibub 2007; Gandhi 2008.
Diamond, Linz, and Lipset 1988/1989. The prom- 23 Collier 1999; Moore 1966.
ised volume 1 never materialized, but the coedi- 24 Boix 2003; Acemoglu and Robinson 2006; Dunning
tors did offer a brief overview chapter in 1990 and 2008.
a longer version of this overview in 1995, and 25 We still lack, however, a strictly political culture of
later on, they each provided book-length statements democracy. Indeed, the study of political culture
of their views. Diamond, Linz, and Lipset 1990; largely takes attitudes and perceptions about politics
Diamond, Linz, and Lipset 1995; Linz and Stepan as prepolitical.
1996; Diamond 1999; Lipset and Lakin 2004. 26 Huntington and Nelson 1976, 23, 35–37, 42–43.
A second collective project, coordinated by Linz and 27 Przeworski and Limongi 1997; Przeworski et al.
Arturo Valenzuela and launched with a confer- 2000. See also the earlier article by Przeworski and
ence in 1989, produced a two-volume work titled Limongi 1993.
The Failure of Presidential Democracy, which scruti- 28 Przeworski et al. 2000, 271; Przeworski 2004b, 491.
䡬 nized Linz’s theses about the perils of presidential- 29 Though Huntington wrote a book in which he
ism. Linz 1990, Linz 1994, Linz and Valenzuela asserts that “democracy is good in itself ” and
1994a, Linz and Valenzuela 1994b. Finally, the presents himself as a “democratic Machiavelli”
Group on East-South Systems Transformations, led offering “guidelines for democratizers,” his more
by Przeworski and including many of the same influential works offer a quite different message.
scholars who contributed to the initial Woodrow Huntington 1991, xv.
Wilson Center Transitions project, met between 1990 30 For example, Zakaria warns that countries that do
and 1992, and produced books titled Economic not follow the “capitalism and the rule of law first,
Reform in New Democracies and Sustainable Democ- and then democracy” sequence will pay the conse-
racy, along with a number of papers that appeared quences of engaging in “premature democratiza-
as journal articles. Bresser Pereira, Maravall, and Prze- tion.” And Fukuyama holds that “There is nothing
worski 1993; Przeworski et al. 1995; O’Donnell wrong in principle . . . [with] the idea that govern-
1993; O’Donnell 1994; Schmitter 1993; Stepan and ments seek order first, then economic development,
Skach 1993. and only later democracy.” Zakaria 2003, 55, 58;
5 Przeworski 1991; Linz and Stepan 1996; Przeworski Fukuyama 2007, 10. See also Mansfield and Snyder
et al. 2000. 2005. The Huntingtonian origin of these statements
6 O’Donnell and Schmitter 1986, 8. can be verified by comparing them to passages in
7 Rustow 1970. Huntington 1968 (1, 7) and Huntington and Nel-
8 O’Donnell and Schmitter 1986, 3–5, 7–13, 18–19. son 1976 (23, 42–43).
9 Collier 1999. 31 Huntington 1968, 1, 7.
10 Tilly 2007. 32 For example, a key innovation of Przeworski’s statis-
11 Acemoglu and Robinson 2006. tical work on democracy was the generation of a
12 Levitsky and Way 2010. new dataset explicitly geared to identifying transi-
13 O’Donnell and Schmitter 1986; Przeworski 1986; tions to and from democracy. Przeworski et al.
Przeworski 1991. 2000, ch. 1. Similarly, Przeworski’s new dataset on
14 Lipset 1960; Moore 1966. the right to vote made it possible for him to test
15 Przeworski 1991, 95–97; Woodrow Wilson Inter- competing arguments about the extension of the
national Center for Scholars 2005, 2; O’Donnell suffrage. Przeworski 2009.
2010, 183–84. 33 Robinson 2010, 1; Angrist and Pischke 2010.

340 Perspectives on Politics


| |

34 Rustow 1970, 351–52. Cheibub, José Antonio. 2007. Presidentialism, Parlia-


35 Dahl 1956; Dahl 1989. mentarism, and Democracy. New York: Cambridge
36 Linz and Stepan 1992; Linz and Stepan 1996, ch. 2; University Press.
Linz 1993. Also noteworthy among the early studies Collier, Ruth Berins. 1999. Paths Toward Democracy:
is Laitin 1995. Working Class and Elites in Western Europe and South
37 See, among other writings, Linz 1997, Linz 1999, America. New York: Cambridge University Press.
and Stepan 2001. Dahl, Robert A. 1956. A Preface to Democratic Theory.
38 Lijphart 1977. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
39 Rustow 1970. _. 1971. Polyarchy. New Haven, CT: Yale Univer-
40 This is the same problem that affects Lijphart’s 1977 sity Press.
argument. _. 1985. A Preface to Economic Democracy. New
41 Linz 1997, 117. Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
42 Schmitter 2010, 26. See also Whitehead 2005 _. 1989. Democracy and Its Critics. New Haven,
(4–7). CT: Yale University Press.
43 Przeworski et al. 1995, 13; Mazzuca 2010. Diamond, Larry. 1999. Developing Democracy: Toward
44 Linz and Stepan 1996, 17–19. There is ambiguity Consolidation. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
again in Linz and Stepan’s statement. Sometimes, Press.
they refer to the formal status of the state as a sover- Diamond, Larry, Juan J. Linz, and Seymour Martin
eign state, that is, whether it is recognized by other Lipset, eds. 1988/1989. Democracy in Develop-
states as a state. But other times, they refer to the ing Countries. Vol. 2, Africa; Vol. 3, Asia; Vol. 4,
state in Weberian terms. Latin America. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner
45 Schmitter 2008, 28–31. Publishers.
46 Tansey 2007; Tansey 2010. _. 1990. “Introduction: Comparing Experiences
47 O’Donnell 1999, part 4; O’Donnell 2007. with Democracy.” In Politics in Developing Countries:
48 Przeworski 1999; Przeworski, Manin, and Stokes Comparing Experiences with Democracy, ed. Larry
1999. Diamond, Juan J. Linz, and Seymour Martin Lipset.
49 Dahl 1971, 3, 235–36; Dahl 1989, 222. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers. 䡬
50 Dahl 1989, 167–83, ch 6. _. 1995. “Introduction: What Makes for Democ-
51 Though Dahl does not include any socio-economic racy?” In Politics in Developing Countries: Comparing
features in his famous lists of “institutions” necessary Experiences with Democracy, ed. Larry Diamond, Juan
for polyarchy, he does argue that modern “corporate J. Linz, and Seymour Martin Lipset. 2nd ed. Boulder,
capitalism” tends “to produce inequalities in social CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
and economic resources so great as to bring about Dunning, Thad. 2008. Crude Democracy: Natural Re-
severe violations of political equality and hence of source Wealth and Political Regimes. New York: Cam-
the democratic process.” Dahl 1985, 60. bridge University Press.
52 Dahl 1989, 167. Fukuyama, Francis. 2007. “Liberalism versus State-
53 Przeworski 1999; Przeworski 2010; Przeworski et al. Building.” Journal of Democracy 18(3): 10–13.
2000. Gandhi, Jennifer. 2008. Political Institutions under Dic-
tatorship. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hirschman, Albert O. 1971. A Bias for Hope: Essays on
References Development and Latin America. New Haven, CT:
Acemoglu, Daron and James A. Robinson. 2006. Eco- Yale University Press.
nomic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy. New _. 1986. “In Defense of Possibilism.” In Rival Views
York: Cambridge University Press. of Market Society and Other Recent Essays. Cambridge,
Angrist, Joshua D. and Jörn-Steve Pischke. 2010. “The MA: Harvard University Press.
Credibility Revolution in Empirical Economics: How Huntington, Samuel P. 1968. Political Order in Chang-
Better Research Design is Taking the Con out of ing Societies. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Econometrics.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 24(2): _. 1991. The Third Wave: Democratization in the
3–30. Late Twentieth Century. Norman: University of Okla-
Boix, Carles. 2003. Democracy and Redistribution. New homa Press.
York: Cambridge University Press. Huntington, Samuel and Joan Nelson. 1976. No Easy
Bresser Pereira, Luiz Carlos, José María Maravall, and Choice: Political Participation in Developing Countries.
Adam Przeworski. 1993. Economic Reform in New Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Democracies: A Social-Democratic Approach. New York: Laitin, David. 1995. “Transitions to Democracy and
Cambridge University Press. Territorial Integrity.” In Sustainable Democracy, Adam

June 2011 | Vol. 9/No. 2 341


| |

Review Essay | Democratic Theory after Transitions from Authoritarian Rule

Przeworski et al.. New York: Cambridge University Mansfield, Edward D. and Jack Snyder. 2005. Electing to
Press. Fight: Why Emerging Democracies Go to War. Cam-
Leff, Carol Skalnik. 1999. “Democratization and Disin- bridge, MA: MIT Press.
tegration in Multinational States: The Breakup of the Mazzuca, Sebastián. 2010. “Access to Power versus
Communist Federations.” World Politics 51(2): Exercise of Power: Reconceptualizing the Quality of
205–35. Democracy in Latin America.” Studies in Comparative
Levitsky, Steven and Lucan A. Way. 2010. Competitive Development 45(3): 334–57.
Authoritarianism: Hybrid Regimes after the Cold War. Moore, Barrington. 1966. Social Origins of Dictatorship
New York: Cambridge University Press. and Democracy: Lord and Peasant in the Making of the
Lijphart, Arend. 1977. Democracy in Plural Societies. Modern World. Boston: Beacon Press.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Munck, Gerardo L. and Richard Snyder. 2007. Passion,
Linz, Juan J. 1978. The Breakdown of Democratic Re- Craft, and Method in Comparative Politics. Baltimore:
gimes: Crisis, Breakdown, and Reequilibriation. Balti- Johns Hopkins University Press.
more: Johns Hopkins University Press. O’Donnell, Guillermo. 1993. “On the State, Democra-
_. 1990. “Perils of Presidentialism.” Journal of De- tization and Some Conceptual Problems (A Latin
mocracy 1(1): 51–69. American View with Glances at Some Post-
_. 1993. “State Building and Nation Building.” Communist Countries).” World Development 21(8):
European Review 1(4): 355–69. 1355–70.
_. 1994. “Presidential or Parliamentary Democracy: _. 1994. “Delegative Democracy.” Journal of De-
Does It Make a Difference?” In The Failure of Presi- mocracy 5(1): 55–69.
dential Democracy. Vol. 1, Comparative Perspectives, _. 1999. Counterpoints: Selected Essays on Authoritar-
ed. Juan J. Linz and Arturo Valenzuela. Baltimore: ianism and Democratization. Notre Dame, IN: Uni-
Johns Hopkins University Press. versity of Notre Dame Press.
_. 1997. “Democracy Today: An Agenda for Stu- _. 2007. Dissonances: Democratic Critiques of De-
dents of Democracy.” Scandinavian Political Studies mocracy. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame
20(2): 115–34. Press.
䡬 _. 1999. “Democracia, multinacionalismo y federal- O’Donnell, Guillermo and Philippe Schmitter. 1986.
ism.” Revista Española de Ciencia Política 1(1): 7–40. Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Tentative Conclu-
[An English version of this article is “Democracy, sions about Uncertain Democracies. Baltimore: Johns
Multinationalism and Federalism.” 1997. Working Hopkins University Press.
paper #1997/103, Juan March Institute, June.] O’Donnell, Guillermo, Philippe Schmitter, and Lau-
Linz, Juan J. and Alfred Stepan. 1992. “Political Identi- rence Whitehead, eds. 1986. Transitions from Authori-
ties and Electoral Sequences: Spain, the Soviet Union, tarian Rule: Prospects for Democracy. Baltimore: Johns
and Yugoslavia.” Daedalus 121(2): 123–39. Hopkins University Press.
_. 1996. Problems of Democratic Transition and Przeworski, Adam. 1991. Democracy and the Market:
Consolidation: Southern Europe, South America and Political and Economic Reforms in Eastern Europe and
Post-Communist Europe. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Latin America. New York: Cambridge University
University Press. Press.
Linz, Juan and Arturo Valenzuela, eds. 1994a. The _. 1985. Capitalism and Social Democracy. New
Failure of Presidential Democracy. Vol. 1, Comparative York: Cambridge University Press.
Perspectives. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University _. 1986. “Some Problems in the Study of the Tran-
Press. sition to Democracy.” In Transitions from Authoritar-
_. 1994b. The Failure of Presidential Democracy. Vol. ian Rule: Comparative Perspectives, ed. Guillermo
2, The Case of Latin America. Baltimore: Johns Hop- O’Donnell, Philippe Schmitter, and Laurence White-
kins University Press. head. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1960. Political Man: The Social _. 1999. “Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A
Bases of Politics. New York: Doubleday/Anchor Books. Defense.” In Democracy’s Value, ed. Ian Shapiro and
Lipset, Seymour Martin and Jason Lakin. 2004. The Casiano Hacker-Cordón. New York: Cambridge
Democratic Century. Norman: University of Okla- University Press.
homa Press. _. 2004a. “The Last Instance: Are Institutions the
Lowenthal, Abraham. 1986. “Foreword.” In Transitions Primary Cause of Economic Development?” European
from Authoritarian Rule: Tentative Conclusions about Journal of Sociology 45(2): 165–88.
Uncertain Democracies, ed. Guillermo O’Donnell and _. 2004b. “Capitalism, Development and Democ-
Philippe Schmitter. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Uni- racy.” Brazilian Journal of Political Economy 24(4):
versity Press. 487–99.

342 Perspectives on Politics


| |

_. 2009. “Conquered or Granted? A History of _. 2010. “Twenty-five Years, Fifteen Findings.”


Franchise Extensions.” British Journal of Political Journal of Democracy 21(1): 17–28.
Science 39(2): 291–321. Stepan, Alfred. 2001. “Toward a New Comparative
Przeworski, Adam et al. 1995. Sustainable Democracy. Politics of Federalism, (Multi)nationalism, and De-
New York: Cambridge University Press. mocracy: Beyond Rikerian Federalism.” In Arguing
Przeworski, Adam, Michael E. Alvarez, José Antonio Comparative Politics, ed. Alfred Stepan. New York:
Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi. 2000. Democracy Oxford University Press.
and Development: Political Institutions and Well-Being Stepan, Alfred and Cindy Skach. 1993. “Constitutional
in the World, 1950–1990. New York: Cambridge Frameworks and Democratic Consolidation: Parlia-
University Press. mentarism versus Presidentialism.” World Politics
Przeworski, Adam and Fernando Limongi. 1993. “Polit- 46(1): 1–22.
ical Regimes and Economic Growth.” Journal of Tansey, Oisín. 2007. “Democratization without a State:
Economic Perspectives 7(3): 51–69. Democratic Regime-Building in Kosovo.” Democrati-
_. 1997. “Modernization: Theories and Facts.” zation 14(1): 129–50.
World Politics 49(2): 155–83. _. 2010. “Does Democracy Need Sovereignty?”
Przeworski, Adam, Bernard Manin, and Susan Stokes, Review of International Studies. Available on CJO
eds. 1999. Democracy, Accountability, and Representa- September 2, 2010.
tion. New York: Cambridge University Press. Tilly, Charles. 2007. Democracy. New York: Cambridge
Robinson, James A. 2010. “Comparative Democratiza- University Press.
tion: Advances in Quantitative Research.” APSA-CD Whitehead, Laurence. 2005. “Freezing the Flow: Theo-
8(3): 1, 8–11. rizing about Democratization in a World in Flux.”
Rustow, Dankwart A. 1970. “Transitions to Democracy: Taiwan Journal of Democracy 1(1): 1–20.
Toward a Dynamic Model.” Comparative Politics 2(3): Woodrow Wilson International Center for Scholars.
337–63. 2005. “Reflections on the Transition to Democracy
Schmitter, Philippe C. 1993. “The International Con- Project 25 Years Later.” Noticias: Latin American
text of Contemporary Democratization.” Stanford Program Newsletter (Winter): 1–4.
Journal of International Affairs 2(1): 1–34. Zakaria, Fareed. 2003. The Future of Freedom: Illiberal 䡬
_. 2008. “International Democracy Promotion and Democracy at Home and Abroad. New York: W. W.
Protection: Theory and Impact.” In The International Norton.
Politics of Democratization: Comparative Perspectives,
ed. Nuno Severiano Teixeira. New York: Routledge.

June 2011 | Vol. 9/No. 2 343

View publication stats


You might also like