You are on page 1of 16

Angelaki

Journal of the Theoretical Humanities

ISSN: 0969-725X (Print) 1469-2899 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20

Deleuze and Love

Hannah Stark

To cite this article: Hannah Stark (2012) Deleuze and Love, Angelaki, 17:1, 99-113

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2012.671669

Published online: 18 Jun 2012.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 481

View related articles

Citing articles: 1 View citing articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cang20

Download by: [University of Tasmania] Date: 13 December 2016, At: 14:12


ANGEL AK I
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 17 number 1 March 2012

illes Deleuze’s scattered writings on love sit


G uncomfortably in conventional understand-
ings of his work yet, I claim, they may have
unrealised potential for both scholars of his work
and theorists of intimacy more generally.
Although much work on sex and sexuality is
underpinned by Deleuze and Guattari’s concept
of desire, only recently have Deleuze’s writing on
love been theorised.1 This is perhaps not
surprising, as his work on love may appear to
be at odds with both his anti-humanism and his
refusal to regard the human subject as either
stable or coherent. But this is the case only if love
is imagined to require ‘‘the human’’ and ‘‘the
subject’’ to perform it, or if such matters are
presumed to be absent from Deleuze’s work.
Examining Deleuze’s comments on love is
hannah stark
important because love itself needs to be
subjected to more rigorous critical investigation.
In a 2007 lecture on love at the European
Graduate School, Michael Hardt suggested that DELEUZE AND LOVE
the academic reluctance to theorise love has not
only limited how it is understood but also
engendered critical resistance to intellectual complete but also – and more problematically –
work in the area (‘‘About’’). This problem has natural and inevitable. Love needs to be inter-
been caused partly by ideological investments in rogated, however, precisely because it is imbri-
the way in which love has been socially organised, cated in a network of discourses about gender,
particularly in conventional attitudes to both sexuality, patriarchy, capitalism and the family.
romantic and familial love.2 In the West, This is particularly important in the Western
Zygmunt Bauman argues, love is understood philosophical tradition, which, by constructing
predominantly in terms of sexual difference, and love as a metaphysical concept, enables its
the generative power of penetrative heterosexual problematic ideological investments to pose as
intercourse in reproduction (25). ‘‘The dominant both foundational and unchanging. What is lost
contemporary notions of love,’’ Hardt agrees, ‘‘do by positioning love in these ways is an acknowl-
indeed conceive love as [. . .] a process of fusion edgement of the various social and historical
or merging’’ (‘‘Red’’ 2). In this framework the constructions of both love and the practices of
heterosexual couple is represented as two com- loving.
plementary halves of the one whole. This The way in which love has traditionally been
structure positions heterosexuality as not only organised, in heterosexual couples and nuclear

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN1469-2899 online/12/010099^15 ß 2012 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2012.671669

99
deleuze and love

families, is socio-historically specific and there- to these questions, I will extrapolate the trajectory
fore subject to change. Although models of free, of Deleuze’s critique of the self/Other relation
radical, or ‘‘transgressive’’ love indicate that from his early publications (‘‘Description’’;
normative ideology has failed to monopolise the ‘‘Statements’’) to his important (and much
‘‘naturalness’’ of heterosexual love, they are criticised) later work on Tournier, which appeared
subject to the same contingencies. The various in the appendix to The Logic of Sense, and the
ways in which love can be both imagined and concluding remarks in the fifth chapter of
enacted is facilitated by the critiques of these Difference and Repetition: ‘‘Asymmetrical
normative structures. As Kelly Oliver argues: Synthesis of the Sensible.’’3 I then turn to the
infrequent, yet important, references that Deleuze
[o]ur relationships, family structures, and has made to love throughout his writings in which
family dynamics change when we can imagine
it becomes central to the negotiation of difference
them differently; and as we recreate our
and novelty.
families outside the restrictive and unrealistic
ideal of the nuclear family, we transform our This may all sound too humanist an investiga-
images of ourselves, our relations to others, tion to be appropriate to Deleuze’s work;
and the possibility of love. (16) however, as this trajectory demonstrates, this
line of investigation has been present in his work
This is not just a matter of imagining different since his earliest publications. My interest in this
structures. It also involves acknowledging that article is in how Deleuze’s work not only accounts
transgressions of these repressive structures are for a radical relationality between people but also
already occurring, although our current identitar- advances new resources for speculating about the
ian systems of meaning and value render them kinds of ethical practices, and the forms of
unintelligible. This is because any deviation from intimacy, that might be possible.
normative systems, no matter how minuscule,
reveals their failure by questioning the assump-
tion that they are culturally universal and/or
difference and identity
biologically innate. In Difference and Repetition Deleuze demon-
Deleuze’s work on love, I claim, provides a strates the existence of difference outside of the
radical framework for thinking about human ways it is captured in ‘‘identity, opposition,
intimacy, as it is premised on the proliferation analogy and resemblance’’ (29). To conceive of
of difference and is part of his project of critiquing difference solely in terms of these categories is to
identity and identitarian systems. Before extra- ignore the difference that, Deleuze suggests,
polating the particularity of Deleuze’s sustained subsists beneath them: ‘‘a swarm of differences,
interest in love, which I will address in the final a pluralism of free, wild or untamed differences; a
section of this article, I will offer a context into properly differential and original space and time’’
which this work can be placed. In the first section (50). The goal of a philosophy of difference, he
of the article I examine Deleuze’s philosophical writes, is to ‘‘rescue difference from its maledic-
position on identity and difference. If the tory state’’ (29) and to reveal the underlying field
Deleuzian subject is commensurate with the of differential relations.
ontology proposed in Difference and Repetition, Deleuze theorises difference in this way in
then it is founded on a metaphysical difference order to challenge the metaphysical place of
that undermines identity as anything but a identity. He does this through a sustained
momentary congealing in time. How, I ask, critique of Hegel.4 This can be seen as one of
might the extremely abstract subject that the outcomes of his work on the history of
Deleuze proposes, a subject who can make no philosophy (particularly as it is established in his
claim to identity, be considered to have a capacity work on Spinoza, Nietzsche, and Bergson), which
for relating to others? Furthermore, how might systematically demonstrates that there is another
this subject be capable of intimacy and love? In philosophy of difference whose legacy operates
the second section of this article, and in response counter to the Hegelian dialectic. Deleuze argues

100
stark

that Hegel conceived of difference as infinitely difference itself’’ (36). In this version of the
large by figuring it dialectically as contradiction, world, identity is only ever a momentary illusion
which positions difference at its absolute max- which undermines the ontological reality of
imum (Difference 44). Quoting from Science of incessant difference.
Logic, on which his criticism of Hegel in In light of Deleuze’s ontology of difference and
Difference and Repetition is principally based, repetition, locating the possibility of a functional
he writes: ‘‘[d]ifference as such is already subject in his work is a daunting task. Deleuze is
implicitly contradiction [. . .] receiving in contra- deeply suspicious of the subject because he
diction the negativity which is the indwelling considers it (like God) to be a ‘‘stronghold of
pulsation of self-movement and spontaneous transcendence in modern philosophy’’ (Neil 429).
activity’’ (Science 442 qtd in Difference 44; He worked on the history of philosophy partly in
emphasis Deleuze’s). For Deleuze, a model of order to create a system in which transcendent
difference which exists always at the (infinitely entities such as this would have no place. It is not
large) limit of contradiction and enables self- that subjectivity is absent in Deleuze’s work; he
constitution through negation is a ‘‘logical just did not want to confer on it metaphysical
monster’’ in the service of identity (Difference primacy which would make it a transcendent
49). The process of negation as formulated in principle. This is because he regards the subject
Hegel’s dialectic determines that things always as always the effect of other processes, both micro
contain what they are not as part of their essence and macro. What this means, Bryant concludes,
(Difference 45–46). Although this structure is that ‘‘the subject cannot function as the
allows for endless encounters with difference, ultimate ground’’ (178).
they are always aimed squarely at the horizon of The subject that Deleuze elucidates in
identity (which can never be reached). ‘‘Hegel’s Difference and Repetition is the one which he
circle is not the eternal return,’’ Deleuze writes, considers best suited to his ontology of difference
but ‘‘only the infinite circulation of the identical and repetition, in which identity is not a primary
by means of negativity’’ (50). manifestation but only ever a secondary effect.
What Deleuze offers in place of Hegel’s This subject cannot be constrained by identitar-
dialectical understanding of difference is an ian frameworks because it is always caught in the
ontology of difference and repetition, founded process of becoming different. In this text he
on the idea that difference is the origin of all continues his preoccupation with a radically
things. ‘‘[D]ifference is behind everything,’’ constructivist notion of subjectivity, which is
Deleuze writes, ‘‘but behind difference there is evident, significantly, in his early monograph
nothing’’ (57). Significantly, Deleuze does not Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on
deny the existence of identity as it is experienced. Hume’s Theory of Human Nature. Along these
Bryant confirms that: lines, Deleuze’s interest in Difference and
Repetition is in those processes and forces over
Deleuze is quite happy to say that representa- which the subject has limited control, but which
tion, identity and recognition are real phe- nonetheless constitute it along constructivist
nomena of our experience. We recognize
lines.
things. We identify things. We represent
The residual subject of Difference and
things. If we did not do these things, then
there would be no problem of representation Repetition is ‘‘larval,’’ because it exists beneath
and identity. (5) and prior to a subject endowed with the capacity
to act. This larval self is therefore the condition of
For Deleuze, however, identity can never be more all actions. ‘‘Selves are larval subjects,’’ Deleuze
than a secondary and temporary effect, because writes; ‘‘the world of passive syntheses constitutes
being is difference itself (Difference 50). the system of the self, under conditions yet to be
‘‘Being,’’ Deleuze writes, ‘‘is said in a single determined, but it is the system of a dissolved
and same sense of everything of which it is said, self’’ (Difference 78). This needs to be con-
but that of which it is said differs: it is said of textualised with Deleuze’s work on the Image of

101
deleuze and love

thought, in which he insists that thought does not address more adequately the concrete differences
emerge as evidence of the interiority of a which compose the world and undermine all
Cartesian subject but instead exists as a response knowable form. His point is that the ways in
to the problems which the world generates. which the Self is deployed limit our engagement
Deleuze concludes that thought can be sustained with a deeper level of difference. But there is a
not by a fully developed subject like Descartes’s more significant problem with the ‘‘I’’ and the
cogito (118) but only by a larval subject. This is ‘‘Self’’: in ignoring the processes of individuation
because Deleuze thinks that the dynamism which operate beneath their assumed coherence
required for the resonance of discordant series they are ‘‘defenceless against a rising of the
(which is central to both the processes of ground which holds up to them a distorted or
individuation and the manifestation of difference distorting mirror in which all presently thought
through different/ciation) can be experienced forms dissolve’’ (Difference 152).
‘‘only at the borders of the livable’’ (ibid.). It Nevertheless, Deleuze’s rendering of subjectiv-
occurs ‘‘under conditions beyond which it would ity is extremely abstract, with his subject
entail the death of any well-constituted subject remaining a slippery theoretical figure. If identity
endowed with independence and activity’’ (ibid.). is rejected on a metaphysical level, what does this
It is for this reason that Deleuze (and Guattari) mean for the potential for a Deleuzian subject-in-
return repeatedly to the figure of the embryo, process to engage with other subjects-in-process?
which, although incomplete, can sustain pro- If ethics can be seen to exist in the relational
cesses of becoming different which a fully space between individuals, what capacity is there
constituted adult cannot. The embryo can there- for Deleuze’s subject to relate to others in a
fore be seen to ‘‘live the unlivable’’ (Difference meaningful way? How can this subject be
215), because it embodies a flexibility which imagined to offer anything to our understanding
enables it to differentiate in a manner which a of human intimacy and love? The capacity to
fully formed adult would find impossible.5 The envisage intersubjective relations in the context
larval subject can also access the dynamism of Deleuze’s work is what occupies me in the next
manifested by the embryo because it is not a fully section of this article.
constituted and stable self but only a ‘‘rough
draft’’ (Desert 97). Instead of enabling the self to
consolidate into a subjective identity, the differ- the otherwise other
ential power of Ideas turns it into larvae. This is
because ‘‘larvae bear Ideas in their flesh’’ Deleuze’s work on the possibility of relationality
(Difference 219). This larval subject is capable between his radically abstract subjects is evident
of enacting difference in ways inconceivable for in his consideration of the figure of the Other.
the Enlightenment model of subjectivity. It Exploration of self/other relations, and what this
cannot be the foundation of thought precisely indicates about subjectivity, provides the founda-
because it is only the effect of other processes; it tion for his comments about love. The figure of
is the site rather than the source of thought. the Other is perhaps one of the most contested
For Deleuze, the recognisable subject is aspects of his work. Deleuze’s own ambivalent
replaced by those processes of individuation in treatment of the Other is mirrored in the field of
which difference is unfolded. His subject is Deleuze studies, which is split between those who
premised on the rejection of those aspects of claim Deleuze’s work on the Other is the basis of
subjectivity which constitute the liberal indivi- ethics, and those who think that his apparent
dual (such as agency, self-knowledge, consistency, eradication of the Other is both ethically and
coherence, and the ability to effect change rather politically problematic.6 This seeming annihila-
than be affected by it). In this respect he appears tion of the Other poses a significant challenge to
to embrace extreme abstraction. However, much twentieth-century philosophy, and to
because he already theorises the ‘‘I’’ and the ethical theory in particular, in which the Other
‘‘Self’’ as abstract universals, his imperative is to has come to occupy such a privileged position.

102
stark

Deleuze’s first engagement with the Other is commensurate with Deleuze’s repeated example
located in his early work on Sartre, whom he that there is no ‘‘person’’ to be fatigued: there is
describes as the ‘‘first great philosopher of the fatigue, ‘‘and that is all’’ (ibid.).9 In The Logic of
Other’’ (Logic 366 n. 12). In Deleuze’s relation- Sense he writes:
ship to Sartre, Faulkner detects both ‘‘fidelity’’
and ‘‘betrayal’’ (‘‘Deleuze’’ 25) because, although The error of philosophical theories is to reduce
the Other sometimes to a particular object,
Deleuze greatly admired Sartre, he ultimately
and sometimes to another subject. (Even a
distanced himself from Sartre’s conceptualisation
conception like Sartre’s, in Being and
of the self/Other relation.7 Articles translated as Nothingness, was satisfied with the union of
‘‘Description of Woman: For a Philosophy of the the two determinations, making the Other the
Sexed Other’’ and ‘‘Statements and Profiles’’ object of my gaze, even if he in turn gazes at
indicate that his engagement with Sartre had me and transforms me into an object.) (307)
begun prior to 1945. These publications fit
awkwardly into the Deleuzian oeuvre. Deleuze attempted to demolish Sartre’s concep-
Notwithstanding Faulkner’s rigorous defence of tion of the subject by arguing that, because
these texts, to describe their gender politics as ‘‘things do not have to wait for me in order to
problematic is an understatement because their have their signification’’ (‘‘Description’’ 17), the
position on women is essentialist and conspicu- Other must exist independently of its function in
ously equates women with the flesh. It must be subject/object relations: that structure is thereby
remembered, however, that Deleuze was in his made redundant. This critique emanates from his
very early twenties when he first published them, own theory of differential relations, which achieve
and that Simone de Beauvoir’s The Second Sex their potential by eradicating structural bound-
had not yet appeared in French. It is also worth aries such as subject and object.
considering that they may never have been re- This must also be read in the context of
published and translated into English if Deleuze’s Deleuze’s transcendental empiricism, which does
subsequent work had not attracted so much not concern itself with the lived experience of a
attention. They certainly cannot sustain much stable subject (Difference xx) because it is a way
critical interrogation. Nevertheless, they make of thinking about experience that does not depend
interesting reading in relation to feminist cri- on the distinction between subject and object.10
tiques of Deleuze, particularly by Jardine and Boundas claims that Deleuze always values
Braidotti.8 empiricism more highly than phenomenology
What Deleuze initially found attractive was (‘‘Deleuze’’ 5). The reason for this is evident in
Sartre’s focus on the structure of alterity, and his Elizabeth Grosz’s insight that Deleuze’s work is
construction of it as an ontological rather than not part of the affective turn, which she clarifies
epistemological concern (Boundas, ‘‘Foreclosure’’ as phenomenological, because of the value it
340). ‘‘Deleuze approves,’’ Boundas writes, when confers on a subject who experiences (252). For
‘‘Sartre offers the constitution of the self as a Deleuze, there is no subject who experiences the
problem to be solved, instead of an answer to a objective world: there is only experience. Because
non-existing question’’ (ibid.). Deleuze was experience is not internal to a subject, it operates
hesitant, however, about the place of ‘‘looking’’ transcendentally on a plane of immanence.
in Sartre’s work. This is evident when he objects Colebrook explains: ‘‘Deleuze argues that there
that Sartre’s formulation of subject/object rela- simply is the givenness of the world. From this we
tions assumes a ‘‘reciprocity of consciousness’’ might distinguish subjects and objects but this
(‘‘Description’’ 17), which enables the Other to would always be after the event’’ (58; emphasis in
be recognised as another subject. In the original). This implicit critique of Merleau-
Deleuzian schema, it also became problematic Ponty’s phenomenology, which posits a subject
to figure the Other as another subject, because who experiences the objective world, was to be
such a structure is not only limiting but also continued and developed in Deleuze’s work on
ontologically compromising. These attitudes are Tournier’s Friday.

103
deleuze and love

Published in French in 1967, and translated At this point Robinson encounters the ‘‘otherwise
into English in 1969, Tournier’s Friday is an Other’’ (Logic 319), the ‘‘real structure of
early postmodern reworking of Defoe’s Robinson alterity’’ (Boundas, ‘‘Foreclosure’’ 341). Deleuze
Crusoe, which examines how the stranded describes this as ‘‘not an Other, but something
protagonist relates to his surroundings in the wholly other’’ (Logic 317), that ‘‘otherwise
absence of other people. Friday interests Deleuze Other’’ which is revealed when the structure of
precisely because the absence of the Other the Other is erased. The function of Friday in
enables its role to be examined (Logic 307). Tournier’s text becomes evident here. Robinson
Deleuze separates the ‘‘a priori Other’’ (ibid.; finds himself otherwise only when he stops
emphasis in original), which is the possibility of organising his world thorough the structure of
the Other in a structural sense, from the the a priori Other.11 Re-birthing from the womb
‘‘concrete Other’’ (318; emphasis in original), of Speranza, he re-directs his desire into copulat-
which he describes as ‘‘I for you and you for me’’ ing with the ground, in what Jardine describes as
(ibid.), and in this way he distinguishes the a ‘‘cosmic orgy’’ (57): discovering beneath
general from the particular. The a priori Other Speranza another island, he encounters in
precedes the manifestation of subjects and Friday the otherwise Other.12 Only by abandon-
objects, which are subsequently organised ing the Other structure can he encounter the
through this structure. The Other is therefore a otherwise Other in their difference.
mediating structure which organises the percep- What Deleuze’s work in ‘‘Description of
tual field: bringing into existence things which Woman’’ and ‘‘Statements and Profiles’’ has in
the subject cannot perceive, it offers them as common with his later work on Tournier (and
potential objects of desire (Logic 305–06). The with Difference and Repetition) is the descrip-
Other therefore structures the world for us in tion of the Other as ‘‘the expression of a possible
such a way that, according to Levi Bryant, we world’’ (Logic 309). This is a phrase that he will
become social subjects (15). This anticipates a also use in relation to love. Deleuze himself
claim subsequently made by Deleuze and attributes the expression to Tournier, referring in
Guattari: namely, that desire is social, and that 1945 to the unpublished manuscript of Friday
its current organisation into heterosexual couples (‘‘Description’’ 23 n. 3). There are also strong
and nuclear families is socio-historically specific Leibnizian resonances in this notion of possible
(Anti-Oedipus). worlds, although the key difference between
Because the Other structure is a priori, Deleuze and Leibniz comes to the fore here in
Reynolds thinks that Deleuze’s exclusion of it such a way that Deleuze’s own concept of
from the transcendental field of difference and difference comes into relief. Whereas for
repetition is unsustainable (‘‘Deleuze’s’’ 81). Leibniz the world is inherently harmonious
However, I would argue that Deleuze positions (because only compossibility exists in an actual
the Other structure as a social rather than a sense), for Deleuze compossibility and incompos-
metaphysical a priori. What is significant is that sibility co-exist fundamentally. Consequently,
he is not claiming that the Other structure is not divergence can be reconfigured positively as a
part of our lived reality; rather, it is a secondary condition of possibility (Difference 123). Deleuze
manifestation which, to a certain extent, renders insists that the endless divergence within
coherent the complexity of the differential sequences can be affirmed as part of the series
relations of difference and repetition. The Other itself (56). This enables incompossibles (or
which Deleuze rejects is, therefore, not other alternative possible worlds) to diverge from,
people per se, but the a priori Other as the rather than contradict, one another (48).
general category. Deleuze illustrates this through This revision of Leibniz is critical to under-
the figure of Tournier’s Robinson, whose desire, standing Deleuze’s use of ‘‘possible worlds.’’ As
in the absence of other people, becomes ‘‘solar’’ Deleuze and Guattari point out in What is
(Logic 318): it is an ‘‘elemental’’ sexuality Philosophy?, Leibniz’s possible worlds are not
(Tournier, Friday 211; emphasis in original). endowed with reality (17). For Deleuze, however,

104
stark

the Other as the expression of a possible world is It is in the context of the perspectivism of
a potential and affective reality. The same Leibniz’s monad that Deleuze describes the
example is used in The Logic of Sense and individual as expressive. The Leibnizian indivi-
Difference and Repetition, where a terrified face dual contains Ideas and intensities, but expresses
exemplifies the expression of an alternative only a portion of them with clarity, thus leaving
relation to the world which Deleuze describes as the rest obscure. It expresses its perspective on
a frightening ‘‘possible world’’ (Logic 307; them without benefit of a subject to do the
Difference 260). In this way, he writes, ‘‘our expressing: there is only the expression itself. In
possibles are always Others’’ (Difference 260). this way, the immanent world becomes populated
Because the subject annihilates its own possible with differing expressions of the same virtual
world every time it encounters the one presented whole. Individuals express their perspectives
by the Other, the self is never more than a ‘‘past through a necessarily vague assemblage of affects
world’’ (Logic 310). ‘‘The mistake of theories of and sensations. Whenever we encounter another
knowledge,’’ Deleuze concludes, ‘‘is that they individual, we come into contact with the way
postulate the contemporaneity of subject and another person affectively engages with their
object, whereas one is constituted only through surroundings. Our own empirical engagement
the annihilation of the other’’ (ibid.). with the world is unique, Deleuze argues, and is
Deleuze regards the individual as an expressive broadened by witnessing how other individuals
structure. It is ‘‘[i]ndeterminate, floating, fluid, both engage in and articulate their own affective
communicative, and enveloping-enveloped’’ experiences of the world. ‘‘The duty of the other
(Difference 258). This focus on expression enables (if one may speak of duty),’’ Bogue writes, ‘‘is to
him to avoid crediting the Other with the internal affect and be affected, to suspend, as much as one
and coherent consciousness which he denies can, the categorization and comprehension of the
subjectivity. This enables Deleuze to posit the other, and to open oneself to the undetermined,
other person in such a way as to preserve an hidden possible worlds that are expressed in the
unrepresentable residue, thereby preventing them affective signs of the other’’ (Deleuze’s 13).
from being incarcerated in fixed categories of Deleuze’s rejection of the structural Other in
identity. ‘‘What remains ‘unthought’ and ‘out- favour of the otherwise Other indicates the
side’ representation,’’ Lambert writes, ‘‘is pre- importance he places on the particularity of
cisely the difference that is implicated and other people as complicated, and, at times,
enveloped (interiorized) in the idea of another incoherent, entities. In this way he gives value
possible world that the Other Person expresses as not to what conforms to the rigid ideal of what a
a reality’’ (33; emphasis in original). This is subject is but to how our relation to others reveals
centrally important to how Deleuze challenges the the fallacy of the stable, identitarian subject.
place afforded the subject in Western metaphy- Deleuze insists that the existence of other people
sics. Individuals express possible worlds through (as expressions of possible worlds) is what enables
affect and sensation, therefore the notion of the further individuation to be experienced because it
self as interiorised thought has no traction in his is premised on the explication and proliferation of
schema. This is not the relation between subject difference. By denying the self any significant
and object, nor self and Other, nor subject and role, Deleuze elevates the importance of other
subject: it is between expressive individuals. What and different expressions of the world
matters is how the Other expresses a world: such (Difference 281).14
expressions occur regardless of whether or not
there is a subject to ‘‘receive’’ it.13 As a result of
its continuous relations with others, the Deleuzian
love
individual exists in a constantly unfinished state Love cannot be described as a dominant theme in
of individuation. Consequently, Deleuze’s use of Deleuze’s work. However, its significance is
the term ‘‘individual’’ cannot be understood as a twofold. First, Deleuze had an enduring interest
form of self-contained individualism. in love, returning to it repeatedly. This is evident

105
deleuze and love

in his earliest articles, throughout the develop- coherence. In this way, love is an important
ment of his own philosophy of difference, and in illustration of how Deleuze envisages the
his collaborative publications with Guattari (and capacity for intersubjective relation.
Parnet). This brings me to my second point: for What also becomes apparent in these early
Deleuze, philosophy, particularly reading (and articles is the connection between the other as an
mutating) the history of philosophy, was a expression of a possible world and love. This
process of love. In Negotiations, in his letter to becomes important to his explication of love in
Michel Cressole, he makes the link between doing both The Logic of Sense and Difference and
philosophy ‘‘in his own name’’ and the undoing Repetition. ‘‘There is no love,’’ he writes, ‘‘which
of the subject which I have been discussing in this does not begin with the revelation of a possible
article. ‘‘Individuals,’’ he writes, world as such, enwound in the other which
expresses it’’ (Difference 261).16 In both these
find a real name for themselves, rather, only texts Deleuze relates this to the figure of
through the harshest exercise in depersonaliza- Albertine in Proust’s Remembrance of Things
tion, by opening themselves up to the multi- Past (Logic 308; Difference 261). By bringing to
plicities everywhere within them, to the
bear on this reference Deleuze’s most extended
intensities running through them. A name as
treatment of love in Proust and Signs, we can
the direct awareness of such intensive multi-
understand how love functions in his work as a
plicity is the opposite of the depersonalization
effected by the history of philosophy; whole. Deleuze’s book on Proust describes love as
it’s depersonalization through love rather an apprenticeship to signs (Proust 7). This is
than subjection. What one says comes intelligible as part of his general theory of
from the depths of one’s ignorance, the signification, which states that signifiers artifi-
depths of one’s own underdevelopment. cially over-code a field of difference. Love, here,
(Negotiations 6–7) is conceived of as a process of deciphering. Its
function is to expose that flux of difference,
This is, I think, a beautiful sentiment. Here which, instead of consolidating subject/object or
philosophy is divorced from the prerogative of self/Other positions, results in a process of
mastery and becomes an act of love. It is at those depersonalisation (Proust 37).
moments when the self is undone, and we are Deleuze returns to love again in Capitalism
confounded with what is unknown (rather than and Schizophrenia. The extended examination of
what is known), that thought and creativity love in these latter publications illuminates in
become possible.15 particular Deleuze’s own work on the self/Other
Deleuze makes explicit the connections relation and will be important to the ethical scope
between love, subjectivity and otherness in his of his work that I will outline in my concluding
earliest publications. ‘‘Description of Woman’’ statements. The examination of love in both
is, as I have already indicated, an engagement volumes of Capitalism and Schizophrenia is
with Sartre’s notion of the Other, but, more conducted outside the confines of the coded
specifically, it is a critique of his work on love. system of psychoanalysis. Love is a central
‘‘Statements and Profiles’’ continues to develop concept in Anti-Oedipus, Protevi argues, because
these themes. Faulkner outlines that this it is ‘‘anti-Oedipality itself’’ (187). In this text
opposition to Sartre’s notion of love signals Deleuze and Guattari attempt to liberate love
Deleuze’s refusal to privilege consciousness and from Oedipal configurations of it. ‘‘Sexuality and
therefore is consistent with his continual love,’’ they write ‘‘do not live in the bedroom
imperative to undermine Western Philosophy’s with Oedipus, they dream instead of wide open
privileging of the subject (Faulkner, spaces’’ (116). This is commensurate with
‘‘Introduction’’ 86). For Deleuze, to love some- Deleuze’s critical interest in ‘‘perversion’’ in
one is to find in them the particular, rather than both The Logic of Sense and ‘‘Statements and
the general, to locate not what makes them Profiles.’’ Both these texts examine the multiple
cohere as a subject but what undermines this ways in which desire and love can function when

106
stark

it is no longer the domain solely of heteronorma- Tournier piece that the otherwise Other is neither
tive couples and nuclear families.17 subject nor object but a true double: ‘‘one who
In A Thousand Plateaus, love attains a reveals pure elements and dissolves objects,
cosmological pitch. In relation to the body bodies, and the earth’’ (Logic 317). In
without organs, it appears on a list which includes Dialogues, Deleuze and Parnet examine the
‘‘the simple Thing, the Entity, the full Body, the possibility of experiencing love by shattering it
stationary Voyage, Anorexia, cutaneous Vision, (46): only by abandoning limited notions of love
Yoga, Krishna’’ and ‘‘Experimentation’’ can new forms of love, desire and connection
(Thousand 167). Signalling the moment of become possible. This theme is tied inextricably
openness to a difference which is beyond identity, to subjective recognition and to the perceptibility
analogy, opposition or resemblance, love trans- of things within identity categories. What
cends the principles which determine intellig- possibilities might there be for love beyond that
ibility. Love is, therefore, not about recognition limited notion of it, which socially is coded
either of the Other or by the Other, but is instead (Oedipal) and sanctioned (as reproductive hetero-
impersonal. This does not mean that it is not sexuality)? What is possible beyond those forms
specific – only that it is concerned with the of love rendered recognisable by that ideology?
eradication of the stable and self-identical subject, More importantly, what possibility is there for a
the person, the organism. In this context, Deleuze love which not only does not require the stable
and Guattari write of love in terms of lines of and identitarian subject but is also actively
flight into imperceptibility, a point reaffirmed by engaged in undoing that structure? What are
Deleuze in his Dialogues with Parnet (46). It is the consequences of this radical construction of
worthwhile quoting Deleuze and Guattari at some love for Deleuze’s interrogation of subjectivity?
length on this matter: In A Thousand Plateaus Deleuze and Guattari
explicitly connect love to naming. They write that
One has become imperceptible and clandestine love is an act of depersonalisation on the body
in motionless voyage. Nothing can happen, or without organs, and that it is precisely what
can have happened, any longer. Nobody can makes naming possible. This is because, by
do anything for or against me any longer. My denying recognition and undoing the pretence of
territories are out of grasp, not because they
the coherence of identity positions, we can
are imaginary, but the opposite: because I am
experience others as multiplicities. By refusing
in the process of drawing them. Wars, big and
little, are behind me. Voyages, always in tow to confer primacy on identity we can acknowledge
of something else, are behind me. I no longer that the changing and multi-faceted desires of
have any secrets, having lost my face, form, subjects make them complex and incoherent.
and matter. I am now no more than a line. I This is why Deleuze and Guattari describe love as
have become capable of loving, not with an ‘‘[h]eavenly nuptials, multiplicities of multipli-
abstract, universal love, but a love I shall cities’’ (Thousand 39–40). The interaction
choose, and that shall choose me, blindly, my between lover and beloved is founded on their
double, just as selfless as I. One has been saved unknowability, a condition determined by the
by and for love, by abandoning love and self. virtual and the process of becoming. In this
Now one is no more than an abstract line, like context, Watson writes, love is molecular because
an arrow crossing the void. Absolute deterri-
it is what dissolves personhood and the subject: it
torialization. One has become like everybody/
is ‘‘[i]ntimacy without subjectification’’ (90).
the whole world (tout le monde), but in a way
Love, Deleuze and Guattari argue, brings into
that can become like everybody/the whole
world. One has painted the world on oneself, existence the ‘‘most intense discernibility in the
not oneself on the world. (Thousand 220–21) instantaneous apprehension of the multiplicities
belonging to him or her, and to which he or she
This passage encapsulates the extraordinary range belongs’’ (Thousand 40).
of Deleuze’s critical attitude to love. The idea of For Deleuze, the constitutive function of love
the double here is reminiscent of his claim in the generates the proliferation of difference. This is

107
deleuze and love

what enables him to depart radically from their expressions’’ (Difference 261). This may
philosophical tradition, which represents love in sound like a ridiculously complex way to arrive at
terms of merging, unity, and recognition. The the idea that other people are perhaps unknow-
encounter with other people, with otherwise able, and to confirm that epistemology does
Others, is a process by which the self is violence to ontology. But it has far-reaching
undone.18 The depersonalisation which love implications for ethical theory. For what Deleuze
entails eradicates the subject while retaining is claiming is that ethical relations are not made
both subjectivity and subjective experience. possible by developing better knowledges of
This is what enables the consolidation of either the Other or of other people. This model
differences in forms beyond those which are is not identitarian: recognition is neither con-
recognisable and perceptible within our current ferred nor received. Instead, ethics becomes
identitarian systems. Far from erasing subjectiv- possible by constantly suspending knowledge,
ity, Deleuze’s work proliferates the possibilities and reaffirming that suspension in every
for subjectivities which are unrecognisable encounter.
because they are beyond our current systems In focusing on the relations between indivi-
for establishing meaning and ascertaining value. duals in this article I do not want to suggest that
By refusing to accept the fiction that subjectivity this makes the world more harmonious. Deleuze
is stable and that identity can be either does not consider the relations between indivi-
metaphysically definitive or strategically valu- duals harmonious: on the contrary, writes
able, we enable new points of connection to be Reynolds, he ‘‘continually reaffirms the impossi-
made and therefore new assemblages to become bility and failure of all theoretical positions that
possible. This is why in Protevi’s formulation presuppose any kind of harmonious connection
love is ‘‘complexity producing novelty’’ (191). between self and world, and self and others’’
‘‘Love,’’ he writes, ‘‘is the call to enter that (‘‘Deleuze’s’’ 70). This is commensurate with
virtual and open up the actual, to install inclusive both his valuing of dissonance and his postulation
disjunctions so that the roads not taken are still of a ‘‘new harmony’’ based on discord (Fold 121).
accessible, so that we might experiment and The relation to other people is not reassuring: we
produce new bodies’’ (184). It is because this do not find in others either a reflection of our
productive relationality is such a radical compo- self, or a system of identifications, or a structure
nent of Deleuze’s work that ethics is an of reciprocal recognition. In this sense, refusing
important, albeit often implicit, aspect of it. to participate in identity or identitarian systems
can be seen as an ethical prerogative. Deleuzian
ethics acknowledges the differential relations
conclusion: ethics
which compose ontology and undermine identity.
What I think is important in Deleuze’s references The scope for the realisation of relationality in
to love is that they can be read as an illustration Deleuze’s work is particularly significant for
of the ethics that can be located in work. For ethical debates, as our capacity to relate to
Deleuze, love is tied to the notion of novelty, both others, and, more importantly, to those who are
in the generation of philosophy as a creative act different from ourselves, is a central aspect of
and also in the production of new affects and ethical practice. Deleuze’s ontology of difference
sensations, new bodies, assemblages and subjec- and repetition is premised on the refusal of
tivities, in encounters with other people. In identity and the continual proliferation of
Difference and Repetition these encounters can difference. Because this ontology prevents the
be seen as the location of ethics. Here the ethical Deleuzian subject from being premised on the
imperative is: ‘‘not to explicate oneself too much recognition of identity, it becomes open to
with the other, not to explicate the other too difference in a fundamental sense. In this way,
much, but to maintain one’s implicit values and love, as Deleuze theorises it, becomes exemplary
multiply one’s own world by populating it with of ethics. Love is the negotiation of alterity
all those expresseds that do not exist apart from through the explication and generation

108
stark

of difference. Only by abandoning identity can demonstrates a debt to Deleuze.This work can be
the subject engage with others in a way that situated within a broader movement in contem-
enables it to experience this alterity comprehen- porary critical theory to re-examine love’s politi-
sively. A Deleuzian engagement with both others cal potential, of which recent work by Terry
Eagleton, bell hooks and Chela Sandoval can be
and the world, Bryant writes, requires us to ‘‘seek
seen as typical. In his work with Antonio Negri in
out those gaps, events, traumas, shocks, and
Multitude, Hardt suggests that what we need is ‘‘a
encounters which upset the smooth continuity of more generous and more unrestrained conception
the subject, call its recognition into question, and of love’’ (351). Hardt attributes to love a dynamism
introduce it to a domain that is neither that of the which figures it as a constitutive force. In according
subject nor of the object’’ (266). love the power to be ‘‘productive, even ontologi-
It is for this reason that Deleuze rejects the a cally productive’’ (‘‘About’’), Hardt suggests that
priori Other in favour of the otherwise Other. The love needs to be conceptualised as a negotiation
version of love he proposes must be seen in this in which things are practised and learned. In this
light: abandoning what is recognisable about both way, he proposes that love can be seen as a ‘‘kind
the self and other people does not limit the of training ground for the creation of subjectivities
capable of [. . .] democracy’’ (‘‘About’’). This is sig-
capacity for ethics, politics, human interactions
nificant to the way in which we read Deleuze’s
or even love to be theorised; instead, for Deleuze,
work on love because it offers a version of the
these are the conditions which enable the Deleuzian subject which is capable of political
realisation of the possibility of love. This engagement.
reconfiguration of love necessarily relocates the
ethical relation and the possibi- 2 Catherine Belsey, for example, finds the implica-
tion of love in both normative heterosexuality and
lity for intimacy beyond identity
traditional models of gendered behaviour proble-
and constructs an ethics in which
matic.Theorising love from a feminist perspective
difference is not merely enabled is difficult for Belsey because it has been ideologi-
but affirmed. cally mobilised so thoroughly and in ways that con-
tribute to the social and political constraint of
notes women (74).
I would like to acknowledge Jessica Murrell, Ken 3 This path through Deleuze’s work is significant
Ruthven and MandyTreagus for their helpful com- because it has been subject to much of the criti-
ments on this work in its various forms. I would cism of his work on ethical and political grounds,
also like to thank the anonymous Angelaki advanced notably by Peter Hallward (Out), Alice
reviewer for their careful and insightful reading of Jardine and Dorothea Olkowski. Olkowski’s work
this piece. inThe Universal (in the Realm of the Sensible) is parti-
cularly interesting for this article because she sug-
1 To date, the most significant treatment of love in
gests that Deleuze’s work on self/Other relations
relation to Deleuze’s work is by John Protevi. Love
offers an impoverished rendering of human rela-
is also examined in Janell Watson in order to the-
tionships. She writes that in this schema it is
orise what Deleuze and Guattari’s writings on
‘‘impossible that there would ever be any intimate
courtly love mean for intimacy and domestication,
relations between anyone’’ (43). This article is, in
by Stephen Hawkins in relation to the event, and in
part, a response to Olkowski’s suggestion that
a brief vignette on love’s erotics by Todd May in
Deleuze’s world might actually be a loveless place
Gilles Deleuze: An Introduction. John Raymaker’s
situated in a plane of immanence which is ‘‘anon-
Empowering Philosophy and Science with the Art of
ymous, empty, gray’’ (47).
Love: Lonergan and Deleuze in Light of Buddhist^
Christian Ethics also examines Deleuze and love 4 It is perhaps unfair to accuse Hegel, as Deleuze
but, in privileging a transcendent religious frame- does, of being subservient to identity; he is cer-
work, is at odds with Deleuze’s work.This book is tainly not a generous reader of Hegel’s work. In
not in dialogue with the field of Deleuze studies contrast, Judith Butler’s work on the ecstatic
and as such I have disregarded it. I would suggest nature of the Hegelian subject as always ‘‘beside
that recent work by Michael Hardt (‘‘Prison’’; itself’’ (20), or Jean-Luc Nancy’s work on the
‘‘About’’; ‘‘Red’’) on a political concept of love also ‘‘trembling’’ Hegelian subject (45), provides good

109
deleuze and love
illustrations of how this subject can be said to exist way. Tournier’s Robinson could be said to usurp
in a state in which its identity is constantly dis- female space, or at least to appropriate it for male
placed. Although Deleuze’s reading of Hegel might self-transformation, when he declares: ‘‘I must con-
render it in black and white, this (mis)reading still sider myself feminine and the bride of the sky’’
needs to be recognised as a significant element of (Friday 212; emphasis in original). But Jardine’s
Deleuze’s construction of his own ontology of claim that this is a world of ‘‘mono-sexual, broth-
difference. erly machines’’ (59) cannot be sustained in light of
Deleuze’s appeal to the otherwise Other. For
5 In A Thousand Plateaus Deleuze and Guattari
an interesting refutation of this piece see
explain that his reference to an embryo (and to an
Bogue (‘‘Speranza’’), who, with reference to
egg) has nothing to do with regression (181). Deleuze’s work on Tournier’s Friday, argues that
6 Deleuze’s work in this area is affirmed by the absence of woman inTournier’s novel is not so
Boundas (‘‘Foreclosure’’), James Williams (working much misogynistic (as Jardine contends) but
on morality) (Gilles Deleuze’s Difference; Gilles homoerotic.
Deleuze’s Logic; ‘‘Why’’), and Bogue (Deleuze’s; 12 The gendering at work here is problematic.
‘‘Speranza’’); it is criticised by Jardine, Hallward Robinson’s re-birth codes Speranza as not only
(‘‘Deleuze’’; ‘‘Limit’’; Out), Olkowski, and Reynolds female and maternal but also as an object of male
(‘‘Deleuze’s’’; ‘‘Transcendental’’). It should be noted self-transformation. His copulation with the
that Olkowski’s hesitation with Deleuze appears in ground is also commensurate with representa-
the cited publication and not in her previous work. tions of colonisation as rape.
7 Deleuze reveals his admiration of Sartre in 13 This contrasts explicitly with Sartre’s focus on
Dialogues (12, 57). In his biographical sketch of the gaze as something which objectifies the
Deleuze,Tournier notes that, in his early twenties, Other, and in turn makes the subject the object
Deleuze was ‘‘heavily’’ influenced by Sartre of the Other.
(‘‘Gilles’’ 202). In Deleuze’s piece on Sartre’s refusal
of the Nobel Prize,‘‘He Was MyTeacher,’’published 14 Tournier likewise signals that others are more
initially in1964 and again in English in Desert Islands, important than the self by naming his novel after
Deleuze describes that Sartre taught ‘‘new ways Friday rather than Robinson.
to think’’ (77), and concludes: ‘‘Sartre remains my 15 Love is also an important element of Deleuze’s
teacher’’ (79). collaborative work. In the same letter he notes
8 Like the concept of becoming-woman, the pro- that his work with Guattari was founded on ‘‘the
blematic nature of gender politics in Deleuze’s own way we understood and complemented, deperso-
work and his collaborations with Guattari could nalized and singularized ^ in short, loved ^ one
be reinvestigated profitably in relation to his another’’ (Negotiations 7). Deleuze’s collaborative
juvenilia. work brings up the notion of friendship, and the
relationship this has to the possibility of creativity.
9 See also Deleuze ‘‘Statements’’ and ‘‘The Deleuze’s treatment of friendship is ambivalent.
Exhausted’’ (Essays). Although in the ABC interviews he suggests that
10 As Boundas argues, however, Deleuze’s rejec- he is not interested in an‘‘actual friend’’ but in how
tion of the categorical distinction between subject this figure has operated in the history of philoso-
and object does not mean his transcendental phy (qtd in Goh 220), his relationship with
empiricism is not tied to the problem of subjectiv- Guattari (and also Parnet) as ‘‘actual’’ friends/colla-
ity, which he returns to throughout his work. He borators was important for the production of
comments: ‘‘Deleuze will never waver in his con- much of his work and for how he conceptualised
viction that only empiricists have the right access creativity. Like love, the concept of friendship
to the problem of subjectivity’’ (‘‘Deleuze’’ 14). comes up many times throughout Deleuze’s work
and, although I do not have the space to map this in
11 This is, notably, the point at which Jardine’s cri- this article, it is important for Deleuze studies to
ticism of Deleuze is directed because she takes the consider because friendship, like love, is about the
eradication of the Other to mean the eradication meaningful ways in which we relate to the Other/
of the feminine (59).This interpretation is certainly other. For a detailed analysis of the place of friend-
plausible if Deleuze’s work is read in a particular ship in Deleuze’s work and life see Charles J.

110
stark
Stivale, and for a discussion of Deleuze’s references Immanence. Evanston: Northwestern UP, 2008.
to friendship in relation to community see Goh. Print.
16 The connection of love to (possible) worlds will Butler, Judith. Undoing Gender. New York and
be taken up once again in Anti-Oedipus in which London: Routledge, 2004. Print.
Deleuze and Guattari write: ‘‘we always make
Colebrook, Claire. ‘‘Questioning Representation.’’
love with worlds’’ (294).
SubStance 92 (2000): 47^ 67. Print.
17 This supports Verena Andermatt Conley’s
Conley, Verena Andermatt. ‘‘Thirty-Six Thousand
claim that Deleuze and Guattari’s work anticipates
Forms of Love: The Queering of Deleuze and
contemporary queer theory (24).
Guattari.’’ Deleuze and QueerTheory. Ed. Chrysanthi
18 This is not unlike Butler’s claim that our rela- Nigianni and Merl Storr. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP,
tions to others undo us (19). For both these thin- 2009. 24 ^36. Print.
kers, the encounter with difference alters the
De Beauvoir, Simone. The Second Sex. Trans. H.M.
subject so fundamentally as to undo its coherence.
Parshley. New York: Vintage,1989. Print.
They disagree, however, on the ethical place of
recognition in this process. For Butler, the sub- Defoe, Daniel. Robinson Crusoe. Oxford: Oxford
ject’s engagement with the other is filtered neces- UP, 2008. Print.
sarily through recognition. For Deleuze, on the
other hand, only by abandoning recognition can Deleuze, Gilles. ‘‘Description of Woman: For a
the subject engage with others in a way that Philosophy of the Sexed Other.’’ Trans. Keith W.
enables it to experience alterity comprehensively. Faulkner. Angelaki 7.3 (2002): 17^24. Print.
Deleuze, Gilles. Desert Islands and Other Texts
1953^1974. Trans. Mike Taormina. Cambridge, MA
bibliography and London: MIT P, 2004. Print.
Bauman, Zygmunt.‘‘On Postmodern Uses of Sex.’’
Deleuze,Gilles. Difference and Repetition.Trans. Paul
Love and Eroticism. Ed. Mike Featherstone. London:
Patton. New York: Columbia UP,1994. Print.
Sage,1999.19^33. Print.
Deleuze,Gilles. Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay
Belsey, Catherine. Desire: Love Stories in Western
on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature. Trans.
Culture. Oxford: Blackwell,1994. Print.
Constantin Boundas. New York: Columbia UP,
Bogue, Ronald. Deleuze’s Way: Essays in Transverse 1991. Print.
Ethics and Aesthetics. Aldershot and Burlington,
Deleuze, Gilles. Essays Critical and Clinical. Trans.
VT: Ashgate, 2007. Print.
Daniel W. Smith and Michael A. Greco. London
Bogue, Ronald. ‘‘Speranza, the Wandering Island.’’ and New York: Verso,1998. Print.
Deleuze Studies 3.1 (2009): 124 ^34. Print.
Deleuze, Gilles. The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque.
Boundas, Constantin. ‘‘Deleuze, Empiricism, and Trans.Tom Conley. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P,
the Struggle for Subjectivity.’’ Empiricism and 1993. Print.
Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human
Deleuze, Gilles. The Logic of Sense. Trans. Mark
Nature. By Gilles Deleuze. Columbia and New
Lester with Charles Stivale. New York: Columbia
York: European Perspectives,1991.1^19. Print.
UP,1990. Print.
Boundas, Constantin. ‘‘Foreclosure of the Other:
Deleuze,Gilles. Negotiations.Trans. Martin Joughin.
From Sartre to Deleuze.’’ Sartre’s French
New York: Columbia UP,1995. Print.
Contemporaries and Enduring Influence. Ed. William
L. McBride. New York and London: Garland, 1997. Deleuze, Gilles. Proust and Signs. Trans. Richard
338 ^ 49. Print. Howard.Minnesota: U of Minnesota P, 2000. Print.
Braidotti, Rosi. Pattern of Dissonance: A Study of Deleuze, Gilles. ‘‘Statements and Profiles.’’ Trans.
Women in Contemporary Philosophy. Cambridge and Keith W. Faulkner. Angelaki 8.3 (2003): 85^93.
Oxford: Polity,1991. Print. Print.
Bryant, Levi. Difference and Givenness: Deleuze’s Deleuze, Gilles, and Fe¤lix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus:
Transcendental Empiricism and the Ontology of Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Trans. Robert Hurley,

111
deleuze and love
Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane. Minneapolis: U of hooks, bell. All About Love: New Visions. New York:
Minnesota P, 2005. Print. Morrow, 2000. Print.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Fe¤lix Guattari. A Jardine, Alice.‘‘Women in Limbo: Deleuze and His
Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Br(Others).’’ SubStance 3.4 (1984): 46 ^ 60. Print.
Trans. Brian Massumi. London: Continuum, 2004.
Lambert,Greg.The Non-philosophyof Gilles Deleuze.
Print.
New York: Continuum, 2002. Print.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Fe¤lix Guattari. What is
May, Todd. Gilles Deleuze: An Introduction.
Philosophy? Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2005. Print.
Burchell. New York: Columbia UP,1994. Print.
Nancy, Jean-Luc. Hegel: The Restlessness of the
Deleuze, Gilles, and Claire Parnet. Dialogues 2.
Negative. Trans. Jason Smith and Steven Miller.
Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam.
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2002. Print.
New York: Columbia UP, 2002. Print.
Neil, David.‘‘The Uses of Anachronism: Deleuze’s
Eagleton,Terry. AfterTheory. London: Penguin, 2003.
History of the Subject.’’ Philosophy Today 42.4
Print.
(1998): 418 ^31. Print.
Faulkner, Keith W. ‘‘Deleuze in Utero: Deleuze ^
Oliver, Kelly.‘‘Conflicted Love.’’ Hypatia 15.3 (2000):
Sartre and the Essence of Woman.’’ Angelaki 7.3
1^18. Print.
(2002): 25^ 43. Print.
Olkowski, Dorothea. The Universal (in the Realm of
Faulkner, Keith W. ‘‘Introduction.’’ Angelaki 8.3
the Sensible). Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP, 2007. Print.
(2003): 85^ 86. Print.
Protevi, John. ‘‘Love.’’ Between Deleuze and Derrida.
Goh, Irving. ‘‘The Question of Community in
Ed. Paul Patton and John Protevi. London:
Deleuze and Guattari (II): After Friendship.’’
Continuum, 2003.182^94. Print.
Symploke 15.1^2 (2007): 218 ^ 43. Print.
Proust, Marcel. Remembrance of Things Past. Ware:
Grosz, Elizabeth. ‘‘Feminism, Art, Deleuze, and
Wordsworth, 2006. Print.
Darwin: An Interview with Elizabeth Grosz.’’
NORA 15.4 (2007): 246 ^56. Print. Raymaker, John. Empowering Philosophy and Science
with the Art of Love: Lonergan and Deleuze in Light of
Hallward, Peter.‘‘Deleuze and the ‘World without
Buddhist^Christian Ethics. Lanham: UP of America,
Others’.’’ Philosophy Today 41.4 (1997): 530 ^ 44.
2006. Print.
Print.
Reynolds, Jack. ‘‘Deleuze’s Other-Structure:
Hallward, Peter. ‘‘The Limit of Individuation, or
Beyond the Master^Slave Dialectic, but at What
How to Distinguish Deleuze and Foucault.’’
Cost?’’ Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental
Angelaki 5.2 (2000): 93^111. Print.
Philosophy 12.1 (2008): 67^ 88. Print.
Hallward, Peter. Out of the World: Deleuze and the
Reynolds, Jack. ‘‘Transcendental Priority and
Philosophy of Creation. London and New York:
Deleuzian Normativity: A Reply to James
Verso, 2006. Print.
Williams.’’ Deleuze Studies 2.1 (2008):101^ 08. Print.
Hardt, Michael.‘‘About Love.’’ European Graduate
Sandoval, Chela. Methodology of the Oppressed.
School. 24 June 2007. Web. 6 Jan. 2012. 5http://
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2000. Print.
www.youtube.com/watch?v¼ioopkoppabI4.
Smith, Daniel. ‘‘G.W.F. Leibniz.’’ Deleuze’s
Hardt, Michael.‘‘PrisonTime.’’ Yale French Studies 91
Philosophical Lineage. Ed. Graham Jones and Jon
(1997): 64 ^79. Print.
Roffe. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP, 2009. 44 ^ 66.
Hardt, Michael.‘‘Red Love.’’ 2009.TS. Print.
Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. Multitude:War Stivale, Charles J. Gilles Deleuze’s ABCs: The Folds of
and Democracy in the Age of Empire. New York: Friendship. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 2008.
Penguin, 2004. Print. Print.
Hawkins, Stephen.‘‘Love and Event in Deleuze.’’ De Tournier, Michel. Friday. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
Philosophia 18.2 (2005): 43^52. Print. UP,1997. Print.

112
stark
Tournier, Michel. ‘‘Gilles Deleuze.’’ Deleuze and
Religion. Ed. Mary Bryden. London and New York:
Routledge, 2001. 201^ 04. Print.
Watson, Janell.‘‘Intimacy without Domestication:
Courtly Love in A Thousand Plateaus.’’ L’Esprit
Cre¤ateur 44.1 (2004): 83^95. Print.
Williams, James. Gilles Deleuze’s Difference and
Repetition: A Critical Introduction and Guide.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP, 2003. Print.
Williams, James. Gilles Deleuze’s Logic of Sense.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP, 2008. Print.
Williams, James.‘‘Why Deleuze Doesn’t Blow the
Actual on Virtual Priority: A Rejoinder to Jack
Reynolds.’’ Deleuze Studies 2.1 (2008): 97^100. Print.

Hannah Stark
University of Tasmania
Private Bag 82
Hobart 7000
Australia
E-mail: hannah.stark@utas.edu.au

You might also like