You are on page 1of 25

Angelaki

Journal of the Theoretical Humanities

ISSN: 0969-725X (Print) 1469-2899 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20

INSTINCT, CONSCIOUSNESS, LIFE

Raymond Ruyer, Tano S. Posteraro ((translation and introduction)) & Jon


Roffe ((introduction))

To cite this article: Raymond Ruyer, Tano S. Posteraro ((translation and introduction)) & Jon
Roffe ((introduction)) (2019) INSTINCT, CONSCIOUSNESS, LIFE, Angelaki, 24:5, 124-147, DOI:
10.1080/0969725X.2019.1655283

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2019.1655283

Published online: 12 Sep 2019.

Submit your article to this journal

View related articles

View Crossmark data

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cang20
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 24 number 5 october 2019

raymond ruyer

tano s. posteraro (translation


and introduction)
jon roffe (introduction)

INSTINCT,
CONSCIOUSNESS, LIFE
The Horny Dog by Alexandru Manea.
ruyer contra bergson

A somewhat obscure twentieth-century


French philosopher of science, Ruyer
(1902–87) enjoyed a brief moment of inter-
Ruyer has been purely and simply effaced
from the field of theoretical references”
national renown in 1974, upon the publication (“Présentation” 1).
of his exposé of the ideas of an enigmatic but Ruyer is just starting to be rediscovered in
influential group of gnostic American scientists both the anglophone and francophone philoso-
(cf. Colonna, Ruyer 13–28). The conceit of the phical worlds alike. One of his most important
book, The Gnosis of Princeton: Scientists in works, Néo-finalisme, was reissued by Presses
Search of a Religion, was, however, a ploy. Universitaires de France in 2012. By 2014 it
Ruyer invented the scientists as a guise for his had made its way onto the French agrégation
own philosophy, with the hope of reaching a exam in philosophy. Special issues dedicated
wider audience. And it worked: the book was to Ruyer’s work have appeared in Les Études
an immediate best-seller. But much like philosophiques (2007 and 2013), Revue philoso-
Bergson, Ruyer was subsequently forgotten – phique de la France et de l’Étranger (2013), Cri-
and quite seriously as well. By the turn of the tique (2014), and Philosophia Scientiae (2017).
century, all of his works were out of print. In 2016, Néo-finalisme was translated into
“The fact is,” writes Fabrice Colonna, “that English by Alyosha Edlebi and published by

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/19/050124-24 © 2019 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2019.1655283

124
ruyer

University of Minnesota Press. A special issue Ellenberger, a geologist with whom Ruyer
of Deleuze Studies was dedicated to Ruyer in formed a strong, lifelong friendship.
2017. Shortly after came the wide release of Eli- Ruyer’s long-standing geographical isolation
zabeth Grosz’s The Incorporeal through Colum- is mirrored in his distance from the intellectual
bia University Press, a chapter of which is trajectories of French thought in the twentieth
dedicated to Ruyer, no doubt introducing him century. He had no time for “extremist phenom-
to an even larger audience. An English trans- enologists” (Ruyer, “Informations” 218) and
lation of Ruyer’s La Genèse des formes vivantes only vitriolic hatred for its closely related philo-
by Jon Roffe and Nicholas B. de Weydenthal is sophical movement: “I [am] appalled, down to
due out through Rowman & Littlefield Inter- the very core of my being, by existentialism,
national in October 2019. and everything that resembled it before the
word became fashionable” (“Raymond Ruyer”
3). His work contains no serious argument
introducing raymond ruyer with any of his contemporaries, and only
The isolation of Ruyer’s work from both the Bergson of his precursors receives more than
major trends in French thought and with passing attention. Cameos by the famous
respect to the English-speaking world finds a members of the canon – Parmenides, Plato,
close parallel, if not an explanation, in his bio- Descartes, Spinoza, Hegel – are only for the
graphy.1 Raymond Ruyer was born on 13 purpose of advancing Ruyer’s own position.
January 1902 in the small municipality of His interlocutors, then, were not philosophers,
Plainfaing, close to the German border and at and his texts most often keep company with a
the foot of the Vosges mountain range. His rather unusual pair, the French mathematician
father died when he was just two months old, and economist Antoine Cournot, and the
but despite this, and despite a cold relationship English essayist and fantasist Samuel Butler.
with his mother, Ruyer recalls a happy child- While Ruyer’s position often most closely
hood surrounded by a large Alsatian family.2 resembles that of Leibniz, it is Butler’s 1912
The story of his early life and study is that of Notebooks that he will advert to when any ques-
an autodidact. He had both Latin and tion of his intellectual lineage arises.
Homeric Greek by the age of fifteen, and was Rather than developing or combating the
a keen reader of work in every branch of the work of a philosophical forebear, Ruyer’s work
sciences. After three years at the Ecole is oriented by an inflexible commitment to
Normale Superière, he garnered his first teach- scientific research into the nature of reality.
ing position in 1924 at a high school in Saint- While almost all of his major works include
Brieuc just south of Paris. Exactly ten years extremely critical attacks on the way that scien-
later, he took up a post at the Université tists (biologists above all, he says in “Bergson et
Nancy 2, less than a two-hour drive from Plain- le Sphex ammophile”) view the meaning of their
faing. From this point on, Ruyer lived his work, Ruyer never wavered from the view that
whole life in the relative rural isolation of the scientific results themselves constituted the
landscape of his childhood. This idyll, inflected only meaningful body of knowledge. The task
by the work of teaching and writing, was only of the philosopher, as a result, is not to place
significantly broken up by four years spent in science in the broader context of a putative total-
Offizierslager XVII-A, a German prison camp ity (as in Hegel), or – as if stooping down – to
for officers in north-eastern Austria. It was explain to scientists the meaning of their
whilst imprisoned that Ruyer’s lifelong com- work. “No authentic philosopher has ever com-
mitment to a psychobiological perspective posed a simple ‘scientific philosophy’, or a
came to maturity, under the influence of simple ‘philosophy of science’. They have
other notable thinkers including the plant wanted to guide or correct this current, but by
physiologist Alexis Moyse, the experimental working with science and without attempting
biologist Etienne Wolff, and François to establish a para-scientific knowledge”

125
instinct, consciousness, life

(“Raymond Ruyer” 9). The entire tenor of position to its limits to show how it both fails
Ruyer’s work is well encapsulated by Brahms’ to account for basic phenomena – for instance,
famous exclamation Fix oder Nix! (Up to the the nature of perception, at stake in his critique
mark, or nothing), where the standard was of Bergson – and that it ends up pointing to a
always set by the most advanced and robust remainder that it cannot explain.
science of the day. For Ruyer, it is biological phenomena that
The essay translated below, “Bergson et le provide the most compelling cases for this
Sphex ammophile,” appeared in 1959, one approach, and which outline in the starkest
year after the publication of La Genèse des way the nature of this remainder or excess that
formes vivantes and the completion of Ruyer’s will form the true object of his philosophy of
systematic philosophy of biology. On the face biology, and of his philosophy more broadly.
of it, Bergson and Ruyer appear to share And here, the central example is embryogenesis.
much in common. If this fact is difficult to The development of the embryo is impossible to
appreciate, it is probably for two reasons. explain in terms of an ongoing accretion of parts
First, Ruyer dedicates himself in La Conscience relative to a structure because, at every moment
et le corps, the first book published after his of this development, the being in question is
theses, to refuting Bergson’s theory of percep- qualitatively transformed. No matter where we
tion and overcoming the resolution proposed try to locate the alleged structure of the
to the mind/body problem on its basis in embryo – whether by way of some kind of
Matter and Memory. Second, after La Con- retconned Platonism or in the differential
science, the only engagements with Bergson in chemical gradients in the embryonic field – it
Ruyer’s published works are glancing, and cannot explain this transformation-to-trans-
either mostly recapitulate the earlier criticisms formation process, one capable of dealing with
or serve to distance the two philosophers a wide range of invasive experimental interven-
further on related issues. “Bergson et le Sphex tions before being derailed into becoming some-
ammophile” is unique in this respect, as it thing different.
reveals an affinity between Bergson and Ruyer What the mechanist account of embryogen-
on the question of life, and situates their dis- esis, and of living beings in general, is incapable
agreement over the theory of perception of affirming while implicitly invoking are, for
within that context. In order to introduce the Ruyer, two interrelated things. On the one
article, and to assist in the appreciation of its hand, as the embryo demonstrates, the unity
place vis-à-vis Ruyer’s main biological works, of a living being cannot be characterized by
we begin here by tracing the broad outlines of invoking a fixed structure. There must instead
Ruyer’s philosophy of biology before sketching be, he argues, a kind of implicit, vague, imma-
Ruyer’s early critical engagement with Bergson nent form in play, something akin to a musical
and investigating some occluded points of theme and most like a latent memory, and in
overlap between the two. We conclude by relation to which the embryo improvises itself.
setting the stage on which the argument of This is shown by famous experimental results
“Bergson et le Sphex ammophile” unfolds. in grafting – for instance,

A graft of frog, of triturus cristatus or tae-


ruyer’s thought in outline niatus, of axolotl, will only ever produce
Ruyer’s primary mode of argumentation is the tissue of frog, triturus, or axolotl; but accord-
ing to the place where it is inserted in the host
reductio ad absurdum, and the primary object
(whether this host is frog or triturus), it will
of this reductio is the claim that any real being
produce ventral skin, or branchia, or a
can be properly understood as an accretion of kidney. (Neofinalism 179)
discrete parts organized partes extra partes in
accordance with a fixed structure that trans- That the graft tissue continues to develop along
cends it. In short, his approach is to press this the lines of its host might be explained

126
ruyer

mechanistically or genetically, but that it can capable of regenerating almost the entirety of its
adopt or “take up” the theme of the host organ- body from out of itself at any given moment –
ism cannot. gives us one extreme example of this, but
And on the other hand, the embryo, like all Ruyer’s more significant example is the cerebral
living beings, is not – cannot be, according to cortex. The brain is never “anatomically” fixed,
the reductio – composed of neutral, mutually but constitutes a field of ongoing transform-
indifferent building blocks, like the atoms of ation, where new connections can always be
nineteenth-century physics. An embryo is a formed provided the organism is alive. Thus,
dynamic, integral multiplicity, a unitas multi- to recall a memorable passage from Neofinal-
plex. Living beings are beings-in-formation, ism: “The brain is an embryo that has not fin-
immanent, differentiated morphogenetic indi- ished its growth; the embryo is a brain that
vidualities that nevertheless possess a form of begins to organize itself before organizing the
unity of their own. Ruyer will give this unity a external world” (69). There is a sense, then, in
variety of names, but in this context it is the which the body, for instance the human body,
moniker primary consciousness that is most is nothing other than a tool produced by the
apropos. This is fundamentally what conscious- brain in an ongoing fashion:
ness means for Ruyer – a point that will be deci-
sive in his encounter with Bergson. It is not a We walk and see, we manipulate objects
reflective awareness of anything (he will call because our cerebral nervous tissue is
this secondary consciousness), but the unity of directly capable of modifying itself and of
formation, improvisation and being itself.3 possessing itself absolutely in its thematic
forms and deformations. Our hands of
Now, it is true that at the level of their physi-
flesh and bone are only the auxiliary
ology, fully developed animals closely approach
machines of the “absolute hand” of our cer-
the mechanical state ascribed to them by the ebral cortex. While the corporeal hand was
nineteenth-century perspective: they are com- being formed on the basis of the primordia
posed of discrete limbs, themselves capable of of the embryonic limb bud, it was already
being replaced and extended by manufactured “absolute hand” – surface in possession of
objects (prostheses and tools), and organized itself and sounding melody – independent
according to a fixed structure. But the of the cerebral hand that did not yet exist.
moment the behaviour of the same living (Genèse 239)
being is also considered, the same integral,
improvisatory character once again comes to
the fore. To be a frog, an organism does not
ruyer contra bergson
just possess a certain physiological profile but Given the proximity of these ideas to many of
a suite of behavioural tendencies as well, the core tenets of Bergson’s philosophy of
where the deployment of the latter cannot be biology, it may appear curious that Ruyer did
predicted in advance. We see, then – in an iso- not engage more seriously, or perhaps charita-
morphy that is decisive for Ruyer – that the bly, with Bergson’s Creative Evolution. He
analysis of behaviour and the analysis of biologi- could have found there a set of complementary
cal life not only tend towards the same con- insights, if not novel resources, from which to
clusions but that they ultimately seem to draw in extending his own thinking further.
address the same phenomenon: the informed But it seems as if this possibility was annulled
but improvisatory transformations of a living from the outset, as Ruyer’s orientation
being in relation to an immanent, evocative towards Bergson’s philosophy of biology
theme. appears to have been unfortunately predeter-
The correlate of this point is that there always mined by his position on Bergson’s philosophy
remains in every living thing, to a greater or of perception. Ruyer worked out the latter in
lesser degree, some reservoir of embryonic equi- La Conscience et le corps, years before his own
potentiality. The hydra – an invertebrate that is turn to the philosophy of biology.

127
instinct, consciousness, life

Bergson famously begins Matter and consciousness; it is not a mere switchboard for
Memory by breaking with two accounts of the the transmission of images; and its images do
relationship between subjective perception and not exist outside of it. We must begin by realiz-
the object world perceived. On the idealist ing, for Ruyer, that what we normally think of
account, the universe is composed entirely by as the brain, “the brain of the physiologist,” is
the subject: it is the image of the universe pro- not a real being but a “reconstruction” (Con-
jected on the basis of subjective, unextended science 8). True, it is a reconstruction based
states, a for-itself without a correlative in-itself on empirical scientific research, but this latter
– an image without a corresponding reality. itself is nothing other than a collation of percep-
On the realist account, the universe is that tual experience. Whether we adopt an “objec-
which grounds knowledge, but it is itself tive,” scientific perspective or a “subjective”
unknown, a reality without its own image. The perspective characterized by a description of
striking – though, as Ruyer notes, not entirely “what it is like” to have a brain, the brain
unique (Conscience 2 n. 3, 10) – alternative he remains entirely on the side of the subject. In
advances is to consider every thing to be an other words, it is not that the brain is conscious
image. A thing is thus neither the realist’s or that we can have conscious third-person
really real correlate to conscious perception experience of the brain – the brain is conscious-
nor the idealist’s “universe [that] exists only in ness. It is for this reason that Ruyer writes that
our thought” (Bergson, Matter 25). There is “The field of consciousness is what is known as
nothing in excess of the image in the thing. the nervous system. The nervous system rep-
Correlatively, the images of material things as resents the appearance of the real being that is
I perceive them are not representations of the the field of consciousness in the form of an
universe at large but the effects of a reduction object” (26). And, more generally again:
of the complexity of that universe down to sets “Neither we nor any other being are really incar-
of distinct, practically navigable bodies: percep- nated. The duality of the body and the mind is
tion-images which result from the subtractive illusory, because there is no body, because our
work of perception itself. The operator of this organism is not a body” (27). Thus, in an aston-
reduction and translation is the living organism. ishing passage, versions of which appear in
Bergson defines it as a “center of action” that many of his works, Ruyer argues that Bergson
introduces a “zone of indetermination” into a was “right to say that the material brain does
causal order (5, 23). Living bodies can react in not produce sensation. The material brain as
a number of different ways to what stimulates such, the brain object, does not exist; there is
them. Nervous systems and brains – as well as no question of it producing anything” (10; cf.
their analogues in other life forms – receive Neofinalism 77).
stimulation, transmit it to relevant motor When we turn to the objects of experience,
centres, and present the living being with the the same point holds. It is not that there are
largest possible number of responses to it. Per- objects “out there” – whether the unknown
ception perceives these possibilities as images. things-in-themselves of traditional and critical
The brain does not contain them; it only realism, or Bergson’s object-images – that
selects and transmits them. The difference affect my brain, affections that are then trans-
between being and being perceived is a differ- lated into sensations. The photons studied by
ence in complexity, reduced in view of practical physicists are not the objective material corre-
interest. Consciousness, on this model, is the lates of subjective, perceived colours. Not only
domain not of perceptual images but of do the latter only exist in sensation, and there-
memory. It is distinct from the brain but oper- fore after being photons “at large,” these
ative through it via the introduction of mem- photons themselves only exist as already per-
ories into the action-perception circuit. ceived. What is real is essentially and uniquely
Ruyer thought that this theory was wrong on subjective. Lest this seem to merely be a recapi-
every count. The brain is not distinct from tulation of Berkeley with a scientific gloss, we

128
ruyer

need to simply insist on the fact that beings are terms of the “functioning” of a “fully-assembled
not fundamentally perceived for Ruyer (note the mechanism,” but as a dynamic process that is
passivity of Berkeley’s percipi) but perceivers – continually “forming itself” in “a certain pro-
primary consciousnesses or “subjectivities” longed rhythm of activities” (147, 149). Refer-
(Conscience 3).4 ring to Faraday, Bergson says much the same
So, in effect, Ruyer’s alternative consists in thing (Bergson, Matter 31, 266, 292, 304, 313,
pushing the Bergsonian account even further, 330; cf. Creative Evolution 188).
beyond any parallelism between subject and Both thinkers provide system-defining
object. Where the latter involved substituting accounts of how it is that matter comes to
the independent image for the unknowable assume the appearance of distinct, spatially
object = x in-itself, Ruyer will replace both determinate bodies interacting mechanistically.
subject and object with the reality of perception That is, they both explain the genesis of the
in-itself. In this way, he avoids what he thinks of “old idea” of matter from out of its quantum
as the ruinous consequences that attend Berg- formulation. For Bergson, it is the practically
son’s approach: the need to invoke, despite his oriented dictates of perception that account for
best efforts, some kind of “magical” causation the appearance of Newtonian matter. For
to explain how an image in-itself and the sen- Ruyer, it is the molar statistical aggregation of
sation I have of it can be correlated. Extrinsic molecular processes of individuals-in-formation
parallelism, with its unavoidable invocation of that is the culprit. But despite these differences,
causality, must be replaced with a strict identity both thinkers base their philosophies of science
of perception and consciousness. on their accounts of matter as action and its
appearance as body.
More particularly, they both form the critical
ruyer avec bergson foundations of their respective philosophies of
The concept of primary consciousness and its biology around their shared insight that the
relation to a trans-spatial domain of forms or mechanistic scientific determination of living
themes serves as one of the main threads beings takes for granted a now-outdated vision
through Ruyer’s engagement with Bergson in of matter, and applies to the organism the
“Sphex ammophile” as well. But before spatial concepts derived from it. Both Bergson
turning to the content and argument of this and Ruyer use their critiques of this paradigm
article, we pause to catalogue some of the over- in the life sciences to motivate their positive
arching commonalities between Bergson and philosophies of biology, both of which turn
Ruyer that Ruyer’s own disposition towards around an alternative ontological domain. For
Bergson seems to have perhaps unduly both, this is a domain populated not by fully
obscured. constituted actualities but by what Ruyer calls
At the most general level, Ruyer and Bergson “developmental form” or “mnemic theme”
share the distinctive philosophical aspiration to and what Bergson calls “tendency” or
produce a metaphysics adequate to the reality “memory.”
described by the most innovative scientific Both Ruyer and Bergson employ the same
developments of their times. Thus, for instance, relatively unique term for the modality of this
they both base their respective theories of domain: the virtual. While Bergson postulated
matter on the quantum reformulation of its ato- the virtual in order to explain the creativity of
mistic conception. Ruyer describes “the old the evolutionary process, Ruyer offers the
idea” of matter as made up of self-identical mnemic theme in order to explain the genesis
units localized in space, acting and reacting of particular living things from out of equipo-
according to their changeless nature (Neofinal- tential zones. Both understand the actual to be
ism 148). The new idea is that the atom is a derivative. Both articulate the distinction in
quantum of action, a stream of expressive terms of mereological specification: the actual
activity. The atom is not to be conceived in is determined through separable parts that

129
instinct, consciousness, life

function together causally, while the virtual con- them or resembling them in advance. Though
sists of preindividual tendencies (Bergson) or there are no doubt appreciable differences
themes (Ruyer) whose realization in the actual between them, Bergson’s and Ruyer’s renewed
always implies a degree of creativity or differ- biological finalisms share more in common
ence. They both solve the puzzles of psychologi- than not. One implication shared by both is
cal, biological, and evolutionary resemblance (or that natural selection ought to be understood
convergence) by conceiving actual individuals as as a secondary mechanism that sifts through a
derivative on preindividual themes (what more fundamental expressive activity. For
Bergson called tendencies). Just as we might Ruyer, any evolutionary theory based in
find ourselves behaving in the same way in two natural selection has to be considered a statisti-
different scenarios, due to the invocation in cal science; as such, it cannot address the origins
each of the same memory or habit, so too of life, variation, or its evolutionary trajectories.
ought we to posit behind “the organic resem- Once all these are given, natural selection acts,
blance of two individuals of the same species” in Ruyer’s words, as “a simple instrument of
the same mnemic theme, their “specific poten- equilibration and external regulation”
tial” (Neofinalism 131). We can just as well (Élements 161). In Bergson’s words, natural
see in “the resemblance of organs between two selection “explains the sinuosities of the move-
very different species” the actualization of one ment of evolution, but not its general directions,
developmental theme. Ruyer goes still further, still less the movement itself” (Creative Evol-
suggesting that “the resemblance of these ution 102). For both, evolutionary science goes
organs to our tools” indicates the presence of wrong in restricting itself to the actual and in
the mnemic as well, so that across individuals, attempting to explain away the appearance of
species, and even technologies the ontological finality through the operation of blind mechan-
fact remains the same: the actual suffused with isms. It requires a philosophy of virtual finalism
the virtual, the constituted individual with the as its supplement and corrective.
mnemic themes that exceed it (132). In sum, it does not seem unreasonable to
On the basis of this modal shift, they both expect Ruyer to have found in at least some
reinvigorate a version of finalism in biology as aspects of Bergson’s Creative Evolution a comp-
well. Bergson’s is an inverted finalism, the lement to his own work in La Genèse and Neo-
ends of which are located at the virtual origin finalism.5 Yet after La Conscience, and aside
of processes of evolution and development, sub- from the theory of perception criticized in that
sisting through their actual trajectories as the text, Ruyer does not engage extensively with
impetus that initially impelled them. Isabel Bergson again, and many if not most of
Gabel has suggested that Ruyer developed his Ruyer’s subsequent works contain no mention
own “neo-finalism” as a partial response to Berg- of Bergson at all. The references to Bergson in
son’s critique of “radical finalism” (Gabel 52). Ruyer’s main works in the philosophy of
Bergson argued that radical finalism, the doc- biology are not only almost uniformly critical
trine according to which actual events and the but also usually brief and glancing as well.
processes of their unfolding merely realize a The only such significant engagement with
program set out for them in advance, involves Bergson other than La Conscience and
the denial of the positive reality of time. “Bergson et le Sphex ammophile” appears
Ruyer’s “neo-finalism,” apparently worked out across three pages of Élements de psycho-biolo-
against this Bergsonian critique, thus attempted gie (29–30, 42). Here, Ruyer introduces his
to reconcile the end-directedness of processes of theory of the thematic character of formation
formation with the efficacious reality of their into the earlier text’s critique of Bergson’s
temporal unfolding. This means, for Ruyer, theory of perception. He extends his critique to
that mnemic themes inform and direct the the conception of the body (qua nervous
course of developmental processes, activities, system) that Bergson’s theory of perception
and work, without thereby predetermining assumes. Ruyer contends that Bergson

130
ruyer

incorrectly locates subjectivity in the capacity of reading of an aspect of Bergson’s philosophy


the nervous system to introduce indetermination of biology that has been badly understood and
into a perception-action circuit (29). For Ruyer, both overblown and unduly neglected for that
it is the cells of the nervous system, as true reason. This is Bergson’s theory of biological
forms primarily conscious of their formative sympathy as it is evidenced by the parasitic
themes, that are capable of provoking the second- instincts of solitary wasps. Against its detrac-
ary consciousness of subjectivity. Ruyer con- tors, Ruyer attempts to demonstrate the viabi-
cludes that Bergson’s conception of the body lity of the theory, at least in outline. Second,
remains Cartesian: it relies on what is constituted Ruyer provides a helpful and clarifying sup-
and actual while missing the thematic character plement to Bergson’s dense and difficult argu-
of its development (30). Later in the same text, ment that the wasp appears to “know” the
Ruyer makes one of his only references to Berg- anatomy of its prey, the caterpillar, when in
son’s élan vital (42). But it is a curious remark. fact the wasp acts out of an intuitive sympathy
He invokes the élan only to reduce it to the dis- for it. Ruyer introduces an analogy between
tinction between instinct and intelligence, claim- parasitism and fertilization, and uses the cases
ing again that Bergson missed the thematic of sexual dimorphism and the differentiation
character of the development of the living of sexual organs in hermaphroditic organisms
being who is afterward capable of intelligence. to arrive at Bergson’s conclusion via what is
For there is intelligence at work already in its for- most likely a clearer line of reasoning. Finally,
mation. Its instincts appear afterward as isolated third, Ruyer recalls his criticism of Bergson’s
and regimented dimensions of the intelligence theory of perception and situates it in the
operative through its formative process. Ruyer broader context of the article’s topic. We are
recalls this line on instinctual knowledge in thus given a fresh sense for the significance of
“Bergson et le Sphex ammophile,” but he is, as that criticism to Ruyer’s reception of Bergson’s
we will see, remarkably less critical in the philosophy of biology more generally.
article than he is in Élements. Nearer the end Ruyer’s “Bergson et le Sphex ammophile”
of Élements Ruyer makes brief and passing refer- offers a complex defence of one of the most
ence to Bergson’s theory of sympathy on the eccentric passages of Bergson’s Creative Evol-
question of symbiotic relations (160). This too ution from the critics that he claims misunder-
is a line to which he returns, and which he stood it. This is the infamous passage in which
extends, in the later article.6 Bergson invokes Fabre’s reports on the instincts
Aside from “Bergson et le Sphex ammophile,” of parasitizing wasps in order to connect a
Ruyer even seems occasionally as if he studiously theory about the “thematic” nature of instinct
avoided exploring what the two might have to a theory about the “sympathetic” nature of
shared in common. (He makes no real mention instinctual knowledge. Against the Neo-Darwi-
of Bergson’s theory of the virtual, for instance.) nian contention that sophisticated instincts
Perhaps this is a matter of the narcissism of have been assembled over generations, step by
little differences, or perhaps it is owed to the step, out of earlier, less complex behaviours,
popularity of Bergson at the time. Whatever Bergson holds that
the explanation, its consequence is that
“Bergson et le Sphex ammophile” appears to be instinct is everywhere complete but it is more
relatively unique in Ruyer’s corpus for its sus- or less simplified, and, above all, simplified
differently […] Most likely, the degree of
tained and charitable engagement with Bergson’s
complexity [of the “same” instinct in differ-
philosophy of biology.
ent species or stages of development] has
nothing to do with any greater or smaller
the wasp number of added elements. We seem rather
to be before a musical theme, which had
“Bergson et le Sphex ammophile” does three first been transposed as a whole into a
things. First, it provides a close and charitable certain number of tones and on which, as a

131
instinct, consciousness, life

whole, different variations had been played, agreed: the story of the wasp and the theory of
some very simple, others very skillful. (Crea- instinct derived from it constituted a series of
tive Evolution 171; translation modified) mistakes better forgotten. It was no accident
that contemporaneous with Russell’s disparage-
This is the thematic conception of instinct. ment was the growing success of behaviourism’s
After positing it, Bergson cites Fabre’s story endeavour to reduce all instincts to mechanical
of the “Ammophila Hirsuta” [sic], a parasitic reflexes. Instinct theory would have to wait
wasp that “gives nine successive strokes of its until the 1950s for Lorenz’s and Tinbergen’s
sting upon nine nerve-centers of its caterpillar, Darwinian ethology until it could once again
and then seizes the head and squeezes it in its be considered a valid domain for scientific
mandibles, enough to cause paralysis without inquiry. Ruyer is writing in that context. His
death” (172). The Ammophila is a solitary defence of Bergson’s theory of instinct is
wasp; it has learned nothing from a community. threefold:
Yet it appears to possess so high a level of
knowledge about the anatomy of caterpillars (1) Ruyer correctly observes that the thematic
that the precise nature of what it was doing to conception of instinct is in principle dis-
them eluded the entomologists themselves for tinct from Fabre’s account of the parasitic
decades. Indeed, before Fabre, entomology’s instincts of solitary wasps. Thus, even if
best explanation was that the wasp must be the latter were to have been thoroughly
injecting some kind of preservative substance discredited by subsequent scientific devel-
into its dead prey after killing it (Fabre, opments, the former ought to retain its
Hunting Wasps 9). Entomologists had yet to conceptual autonomy and would still
determine the internal organization shared have to be evaluated independently.
across each of the wasps’ favourite victims: a (2) Ruyer insists that the story of the wasp,
centralization of motor functions to be put though not an indispensable premise in
offline by a series of precise stings (48). The Bergson’s argument, is in fact not only
wasp seems to know the facts of her victim’s accurate but also perfectly appropriate as
nervous system intimately; and that knowledge, evidence in support of Bergson’s position
acted without apparently being “known,” out- as well. This is the stronger claim. The
stripped human intellect for quite a while. story of the wasp is accurate, for Ruyer,
How could it have acquired it? Bergson con- because it can accommodate the data
tinues: “The Ammophila, we imagine, must that were supposed to have invalidated
learn, one by one, like the entomologist, the pos- it. Its invalidation is usually attributed to
itions of the nerve-centres of the caterpillar – the Peckhams, a pair of entomologists of
must acquire at least the practical knowledge the early twentieth century compelled to
of these positions by trying the effects of its pursue the study of solitary wasps after
sting. But there is no need for such a view if reading Fabre’s own reports. They note
we suppose a sympathy (in the etymological that Fabre had claimed of Ammophila
sense of the word) between the Ammophila that its instincts can “never have varied
and its victim, which teaches it from within, to any appreciable extent from the begin-
so to say, concerning the vulnerability of the ning of time,” since any deviation would
caterpillar” (Creative Evolution 173–74). This upset their capacities as parasites and
principle of “inner access,” opposed to the lead to their extinction (Peckham and
exterior knowledge of the intellect, comprises Peckham 52). And they respond that
Bergson’s theory of instinct-sympathy. the conclusions that we draw from the
Bertrand Russell famously remarked that the study of this genus differ in the most
“love of the marvellous may mislead even so striking manner from those of Fabre.
careful an observer as Fabre and so eminent a The one preeminent, unmistakable
philosopher as Bergson” (56). Most others and ever present fact is variability.

132
ruyer

Variability in every particular – in the that the sophisticated consistency of


shape of the nest and the manner of instinct was built up out of them over
digging it, in the condition of the time. Their conclusion is not licensed by
nest (whether closed or open) when new data. One could well accept the data
left temporarily, in the method of they use without accepting the conclusion
stinging the prey […] (53)
they derive from them. Indeed, this is just
what Bergson seems to have done. He
The Peckhams asserted variability as a cites the Peckhams’ corrections to
requisite for any theory of instinct after Fabre’s story of the wasp, but asserts
Darwin. And as a consequence, as nonetheless that “because instinct is,
Keijzer observes, they “became portrayed like intelligence, fallible, because it also
as the standard antagonists of Fabre: he shows individual deviations, it does not
being the defender of the God-given and at all follow that the instinct of the
eternal fixity of instinct, they the defen- Ammophila has been acquired, as has
ders of a Darwinist view who claimed been claimed, by tentative intelligent
and reported the presence of variability experiments” (Creative Evolution 173).
of almost all aspects of insect behavior” Ruyer thinks that Bergson accurately
(Keijzer 510). For popular scientific reports the extant evidence of parasitizing
opinion, it followed that even instincts instincts in solitary wasps. He contends
as sophisticated as those of the solitary that the report is appropriately utilized
wasps required for their explanation in service of Bergson’s position on the
nothing other than the Darwinian main- thematic character of instinct as well.
stays of heritable variation coupled with Ruyer takes what he calls “thematism”
differential mortality over time. Bergson to be a well-established facet of compara-
appears to have made too much of a mis- tive ethology. He dedicates much of the
taken story, and in leveraging it as article to elaborating its details and
support for his own theory of instinct he drawing implications for the study of
risked discrediting the latter as a result. instinct. Ruyer concludes that to the
Fabre was, however, already well aware extent that Bergson’s reference to the
of the facts that the Peckhams employed story of the Ammophila serves “to chal-
in their criticism of him. After exclaiming lenge the pseudo-scientific thesis […]
over “how infallibly and with what trans- that considered instinct as a mosaic of
cendental art [the wasp] acts when guided reflexes placed alongside genetic variation
by the unconscious inspiration of her and natural selection,” it is a legitimate
instinct,” Fabre observes “how poor she use of an accurate story to furnish what
is in resource, how limited in intelligence, would become a respectable scientific pos-
how illogical even, in circumstances ition (“Bergson et le Sphex ammophile”
outside her regular routine” (Hunting 164).
Wasps 107; cf. 119). He concludes that (3) Ruyer argues, finally, that Bergson’s
instinct is perfectly fitted to its object theory of instinct-sympathy is best under-
under ideal conditions; but any changes stood as the attempt to outline a positive
in those conditions lead to variations solution to the problem that the case of
and deviations in the performance of the solitary wasps poses for Neo-Darwinian
instinct. Fabre privileges the sophisti- theories of instinct. Here is the problem:
cated consistency of instinct over its vari- if it is true that instinct cannot be
ations, and argues that the latter explained as a mosaic of reflexes
represents a deficient, mistaken execution assembled over generations by selection,
of the former. The Peckhams privilege if it is thematic, then how does the wasp
the variations, and argue on the contrary possess and act it out? If the wasp did

133
instinct, consciousness, life

not build it up step by step over evolution- story of the beginning of the war of 1914 in
ary time, then what is the principle of their small History of France. The conspicuous
relation that obtains between the wasp uniforms of the French soldiers are mentioned
and the theme? Bergson’s theory of there, and the children retain the impression
instinct-sympathy suggests that the wasp that the first of France’s defeats is due only to
does not “know” its object, the anatomy red trousers.
of its prey, in the same way that the ento- It would already be unfair to condemn the
mologist does: from the outside, based on entire Bergsonian theory of instinct even if the
observation and induction. Rather, the story of the Sphex was false because Bergson
wasp is supposed to “sympathize” with cites and uses many other very accurately
its object. Its parasitizing instincts are a reported facts. But most curious is that the
correlate of that sympathy. In order to story of the Sphex is accurate – whatever its
explain the precise nature of a “sympath- critics say – and is also perfectly suitable as an
etic” relationship between two organisms, argument in support of the thesis for which
Ruyer turns from Bergson’s own account Bergson uses it. Bergson cites it in the course
in order to attempt a parallel and analo- of a critical discussion of Neo-Darwinian the-
gous argument for the same conclusion. ories, according to which “this or that useful
step, accomplished by the individuals by
On the content of the argument and its impli- virtue of an accidental predisposition of the
cations for the relationship between the two germ, would have been transmitted from germ
thinkers, we should like to let Ruyer’s article to germ while waiting for the chance to add
speak for itself. new improvements to it by the same process”
– according to which, in short, the instinct is
••• constituted by the progressive addition of new
elements.10
Bergson demonstrates the improbability of
BERGSON AND THE this theory by logical arguments on the one
AMMOPHILA SPHEX7 hand, and by the examination of facts on the
raymond ruyer other. When we compare the different forms
of the same instinct, of the same instinctive
On the question of instinct, Bergson was victim theme in various species of Hymenoptera, we
of a veritable prank played by the memory of cannot arrange these forms in linear series in
readers, then aggravated by the writers of text- order of increasing complexity. The instinctive
books. All his concepts have clung, at least in theme is really a central theme “which trans-
the minds of distracted readers, to Fabre’s poses itself as a whole in different directions
story of the Ammophila Sphex “that gives and on which, also as a whole, is performed in
nine successive stings to nine nervous centers every species different variations,” the differ-
of its caterpillar, and finally snatches the head ences of complexity not always corresponding
and squeezes it in its mandibles, just enough to an order of filiation, as they should on the
to cause paralysis without death.”8 Bergson Neo-Darwinian hypothesis.11 One could cite
may well have immediately added: “No doubt, innumerable examples in favour of the thesis
it is far from the case that the operation is of “thematism”: various uses of thread by the
always perfectly executed,” and quoted the various species of spiders; types of display
Peckhams to correct Fabre,9 but the impression among the birds; types of camouflage or parasit-
remained that Bergson supports his whole ism among the crabs; the theme of “brandishing
theory of instinct on Fabre’s embellished the pincers” among the twenty-seven species of
stories, and that the Peckhams later demolished Uca cabs in Panama; the “courtship dance”
the observations on which Bergson relied. It is a theme among the various Sticklebacks. The pro-
little like the way children read the simplified ponents of comparative ethology have been able

134
ruyer

to make veritable etymologies of instinctive Neo-Lamarckism of the time. Our comparison,


behaviours. A certain “root” (in the linguistic in Lamarckian spirit, of the variations of the
sense) of behaviour undergoes displacements, instinctive theme with those of a linguistic
variations, complications, simplifications, theme, is limited in that the linguistic trans-
changes of sense in the related neighbouring mission is socio-cultural, and not biological
species. Bergson limits himself to briefly citing like the transmission of instinct. Instinct,
the social instinct among the various Apidae according to Bergson, is no more an intelligent
(where the differences in complexity do not cor- discovery of some individuals of the species,
respond to an order of filiation) and finally the degraded into habit and transmitted by her-
paralysing instinct of various species of Hy- edity, than a mosaic of fortuitous mutations.
menoptera, where the theme – the etymological The linguistic theme is unconscious or sub-
root – “to paralyse a prey and to deposit its eggs conscious in individual speakers. That is why
there” is varied or weakened according to the it seems to have a life of its own, independent
different species of prey: spider, beetle, caterpil- of its bearers and transmitters – in which it
lar, cricket. resembles an instinct. But it is evidently not
The fact that one can so easily combine Berg- related to the organic form of the species and
son’s thesis with the modern conceptions of com- in this it differs from instinct. Instinct is inse-
parative ethology proves that far from being parable from the organic formation and has its
behind on the science Bergson anticipated it. origin in a super-individual [sur-individuel]
He was perfectly right to challenge the pseudo- and even super-specific [sur-speć ifique]
scientific thesis, fashionable at the time when “domain of consciousness,” which is to say in
he wrote Creative Evolution, which considered the cosmic consciousness of the élan vital.
instinct as a mosaic of reflexes placed alongside This consciousness “gives us the key to all
[juxtaposés] genetic variation and natural selec- vital operations,” and is the common origin of
tion. The variations of an instinctive theme all species, of all formative instincts, and of all
resemble linguistic variations, and it is almost instincts of behaviour. We see that if Bergson
as absurd to explain the variations of the theme rejects Neo-Darwinism, he limits himself to cor-
“paralyse” in the various species of Hymenoptera recting the Neo-Lamarckism in a way that is
by accumulation of genetic mutations as it would truly radical, by transporting it from the
be to explain the variations of the unknown Indo- psychological or psychobiological level to a
European root signifying “girl,” which makes metaphysical level. The vital consciousness is a
duhitar in Sanskrit, thugatêr in Greek, Tochter consciousness, but it is no longer an intelligent,
in German, by genetic mutations of various calculating consciousness, as is human con-
Indo-European groups. sciousness, which is based on the perception of
The contemporary ethologists do not reject external objects and bears on these objects
natural selection, or even the possibility in from the outside.
certain cases – never directly verified, to tell This yields the key to a Bergsonian theory
the truth – of a genetic origin of behavioural that has until now appeared entirely verbal, lit-
variations. But they more often invoke the the- erary, metaphorical: the theory of instinct-sym-
matic variation of behaviour as the primary pathy. After having made critical usage of the
material on which selection then works, and as example of the paralysing Sphex, Bergson pro-
the first origin of specification by isolation and poses a positive solution, in rather vague
segregation.12 As if, to continue our example, terms, we must admit, and with a discomfort
a linguistic difference in a group led secondarily emphasized by the use of conditional verbs.
to a separation of two or more subgroups, or We are wrong, says Bergson, in wanting to
reinforced an already initiated [amorceé ] translate the “science” of the Hymenoptera in
segregation. terms of intelligence and consequently assimi-
To put it more simply, Bergson’s discussion lating the Sphex with the biologist who knows
bears on both the Neo-Darwinism and the the caterpillar from the outside:

135
instinct, consciousness, life

The Sphex would have to learn one by one, civilized man, and had ignored the role of the
like the entomologist, the positions of the father in procreation and had believed to be
nervous centers of the caterpillar […], but making [ frayer] only “a way to the spirits”
it would no longer be the same if one sup- [un chemin aux esprits], like the Melanesians
posed between the Sphex and its victim a or Kanakas.
sympathy (in the etymological sense of the
By “sympathy,” Bergson means a “non-intel-
word) which teaches it from within, so to
lectual knowledge [savoir]” or, more exactly, a
say, about the vulnerability of the caterpillar.
This feeling of vulnerability may owe nothing “non-perceptual knowledge,” a knowledge that
to external perception, and result from the has no need of information about the external
mere presence together of the Sphex and object conveyed step by step along transmission
the caterpillar, considered no longer as two channels. What to say? The problem of instinc-
organisms, but as two activities. It would tive behaviour becomes much clearer if it is
express in a concrete form the relation of posed in the form: “Is it a matter of knowledge
the one to the other. Certainly, a scientific [savoir]? or of ability [pouvoir]?” In general, if a
theory cannot appeal to considerations of being does what he does, it is first that he knows
this kind. It must not put action before and second that he can do it. I swim, because I
organization, sympathy before perception
can swim (I do not have muscular cramps), and
and knowledge. (Bergson, Creative Evol-
ution 174)
because I know how to swim (I learned to swim,
and I do not have neurological disorders, no
apraxia). In many languages, knowledge
Reading such passages, the biologist shrugs [savoir] and ability [pouvoir] are poorly distin-
his shoulders and taking advantage of the con- guished when it comes to a learned action and
fession that the conception of instinct-sympathy not an acquired notion (for which all the
has nothing in common with a scientific theory languages agree to use the word “knowing
he returns to his experiments on the role of hor- [savoir and connaître],” and not the word “the
mones or on the “innate trigger mechanisms.” ability to know [pouvoir]”). We say in English
However, the biologist would do well to and in German: “I can swim,” whereas we say
remember the instinctive situations where he in French “I know how to swim.” Is it English
found himself as representative of the human or French that is right? English or German
species. For example, married very young and would certainly be wrong to talk about “ability
naive, before having completed his studies and [pouvoir]” if these languages meant by this –
having very precise scientific notions about pro- what they do not – a purely physical power
creation, embryology, sexual hormones, he [pouvoir], a “power to function.” In fact, they
knew how to behave in the presence of his mean a capacity, a psycho-physiological “com-
wife in such a way that he had a child – petence,” an “effective knowledge [savoir].”
though not without a lot of awkwardnesses and The danger of confusion is between physical
clumsinesses analogous to what the Peckhams power [pouvoir] and effective mental knowledge
detect in the behaviour of the Sphex. [savoir psychique]. And this possible confusion
Everything happened as if he had known – is extremely important in the problem of
before having consulted any treatise – the instinct.
anatomy, or the physiology, of the reproductive If the yellow-winged Sphex paralyses the
organs of man and woman. He would have done cricket and its three pairs of legs, if the Ammo-
entirely as well if he had been, like the biologists phila paralyses the nine nervous centres of the
of the eighteenth century, “ovist” or “animalcu- caterpillar, Bergson says it is because it knows
list,” or if he had been a convinced Aristotelian how to do it. The positivist biologists would
and if he had believed that man brings form to object to this answer: it is simply that it can
feminine matter. He would have done just as do it mechanically. Given the structure of its
well – probably better – if he had not been an body with the stinger, and the structure of the
intellectual, and even if he had not been a body of the victim, it stings as it can. But, the

136
ruyer

Bergsonian could respond, even admitting all as stimulus-signal. But this “part” is not a part
possible clumsinesses, whence does the Sphex in the geometrical sense of the word, it is a
know that his stinger is at least made for sting- “schema”: angeborene auslösende schéma
ing and that he uses it for that in a more or less [innate triggering schema], a kind of particu-
adroit fashion instead of remaining unrespon- larly expressive extract. The animal perceives
sive in front of the cricket or the caterpillar? this attractive or dangerous “expressive
This “knowing how to use [savoir employer]” extract” as the man perceives a very familiar
an organ, retorts the positivist biologist, is situation, by a trait, a detail, or a characteristic
itself only an “ability [pouvoir]” or a “micro- aspect, as when he “runs after a petticoat” or
ability” of nervous systems of the Sphex. “avoids a military cap.” The stimulus-signal
These systems are arranged so that, stimulated always seems like a simplification, a secondary
or triggered by the image of the caterpillar, reduction of a “gnosic” situation; it is not the
they function so as to control in turn the oper- primary and constituent element. Also, it is
ation of the stinger. Nowhere is there knowl- often impossible to use the method of simulacra
edge, only abilities. And abilities in the to extract a specific stimulus-signal to which the
strictly positivist sense of the term: it is not a animal is sensitive in the general situation, as
matter of potentiality beyond the actual [poten- E.S. Russell pointed out.
tialite ́ sur-actuelle], which would revert to a Last, instinct is also thematic in the move-
competence, to a “virtuality of ability,” that is ments, or rather, the actions of consumption.
to say again to a knowledge. It is a matter only They might sometimes take on the appearance
of an “ability to function,” as when it is said of a motor melody that can even unfold itself
that a gearshift in a car can take four positions meaninglessly [se dérouler á vide]. This might
or that a ratchet can rotate in one direction. make one think, according to Tinbergen, of
Thus defined, today the debate is evidently well-localized and hierarchized nervous mechan-
decided in Bergson’s favour, at least in favour isms that function once triggered in an auton-
of instinct-knowledge, and against the notion omous way. Yet the actions of effection or
of an instinct-ability, an instinct-function. consumption – that is, precisely the case of the
Instinct is thematic in each of its phases. In Sphex stinging the caterpillar – are more often
each of its phases it includes an element of very flexible, regulated by [réguleś à mesure
“sense,” of abstract and unspecified knowledge sur] indication stimuli or orientation stimuli,
[savoir abstrait et non preć isé], cognition [con- or again, by internal irritations that the actions
naissance] beyond mechanical actuality seek to relax in one way or another. In all
[l’actuel mécanique]. The internal hormonal these cases, both those described by Lorenz
sensitization evokes a half-oriented search be- and Tinbergen and those described by the
haviour, an observable counterpart of a American school hostile to “autonomous melo-
concern, of an anxious presentiment. The stimu- dies,” the observable movements of the animal
lus, or rather the external object putting an end always constitute actions. They are not really
[mettant fin] to the search behaviour, is not a stereotypes like the movements of an automaton
mechanical trigger, a key of precise form that of cams and spikes, they are significant, they
would correspond to an automaton lock [un seek a realization, even if they do not imagine
automate à serrure], it is an object or a situation it in advance. They are oriented by a knowledge
corresponding to a certain instinctive “gnosis” – [savoir], and not pushed according to the power
according to the very exact technical term – that of a fully assembled mechanism.
is to say to a cognition [connaissance] or to a But the decisive argument against pure
capacity for re-cognition [re-connaissance]. instinct-ability, actual mechanical ability, is pro-
Experimental studies – especially those of vided by the basic complementarity of equival-
Buytendijk, Tinbergen and the Dutch school – ence between instinct and organization, as
have used lures and simulacra to show that Bergson saw perfectly. Let us admit, in fact,
only a part of the stimulant is really effective that the Sphex uses its stinger as it can,

137
instinct, consciousness, life

according to the structure of this organ, and one go? Why should it, in one go, assemble
according to the actual structure of nervous mechanisms that would henceforth only have
mechanisms which, once triggered by the sight to function, instead of continuing to improvise
of the caterpillar, control the use of the assemblages [montages] and formative beha-
stinger. In any case, it was necessary over the viours, to complete the assemblages already
course of the ontogenesis of the Sphex that acquired and integrate their functioning with a
every part of its hypothetical nervous mechan- meaningful global action? Instincts are rela-
isms, as well as the stinger with its muscles tively complementary with organic forms pre-
and accessory glands, be constructed from cisely because organic forms are themselves
scratch from the fertilized egg. This construc- the result of embryonic instincts, of the
tion was epigenetic for the one as for the embryo’s “knowing how to act [savoir agir].”
other. It is not explicable by an “actual mechan- In certain cases by the mere sight of organic
ical power” of the egg, but by a “capacity,” a forms one can guess which instincts use them:
“competence,” a “virtual power,” a “potential- a stinger is made to sting, a wing to fly, the
ity.” Either all these words mean nothing, or hard beak of the unhatched chick to break the
else they designate more or less well what shell. But from the examination of forms alone
must be considered as a “knowledge [savoir].” it is not always possible to guess the instinct
But then, against the well-established facts that uses them. All spiders possess just about
demonstrating the thematic character of the same seric glands, and yet some of them
instinct, why connect the instinctive actions to make a regular web, others an irregular web,
fully assembled nervous mechanisms? For in others emit threads to be lifted away by the
any case these mechanisms themselves have wind, others simply line their nest. Lloyd
been constructed not by the functioning of Morgan argues that no one could have deduced
other mechanisms, by hypothesis not yet the remarkable migrations of the eel by examin-
given, but by what must be called a knowledge ing the structure of its body – and even less, we
or a morphogenetic instinct “behind” the egg will add, by examining the structure of its genes
or embryo observable in actual space. Unless and of DNA molecules, even with an ideal pre-
we adopt a long abandoned and refuted con- cision. From the anatomy of the antlion, one
ception of the nature of genes or fall back on can conclude that it is carnivorous, not that it
the old preformationist errors about DNA mol- digs a hole in the sand and waits for an ant to
ecules there is no way to escape the fall in. For that matter, it happens that similar
consequence. instincts are manifested by animals with very
Rejecting the epigenetic character of the different corporeal structures. Ants and ter-
ontogenesis of instinct is useless since we must mites have very similar social behaviours, yet
in any case accept the epigenetic character of they belong to quite distant families.
the ontogenesis of the organs that instinct uses Forms and instincts – or, more exactly, for-
and that nervous mechanisms are supposed to mative instincts and behavioural instincts –
control. The bird makes its nest – in the are relatively independent while complementing
strong sense of “make [ faire],” with know- each other precisely because they are of the
how [savoir-faire], if not with “know-why same nature. Instinct is not only a secondary
[savoir pourquoi].” It is not a simple mechanical function – and functioning – of forms already
intermediary between the mechanisms of its constructed by formative instincts. Instinct
brain and the materials of the nest, because uses acquired knowledge [l’acquis], but it over-
the body of the bird, brain included, is made flows it [le déborde]. It is the form (of the organ-
precisely like the nest, with know-how, and ism as of the behaviour) which is a function of
without us able to find any part of effector mech- the activity. It is necessary not to get things
anisms already assembled. backwards. So, when we say that the bird
Why would epigenesis, that is to say the makes its nest, that the nest is its work
emergence of formative action, be realized in [œuvre] and not an automatic result, this

138
ruyer

thesis is true contra the mechanical conception development, fusion and condensation, displa-
of instinct; but it should not be used contra cement and translocation, is exactly analogous
the conception of an ontogenesis of instinct. to the teratology of instinct, as we can verify
The bird that makes its nest is at once the indi- by comparing E. Wolff and Freud.
vidual bird (already “made” by embryogenesis), We seem to have lost sight of Bergson.
and, through it, the specific bird-type. The indi- Instead, we have followed a parallel path that
vidual bird is at once work and worker; by leads to a very similar point. If “action is
working at its nest it still continues to be before organization” as Bergson suspected,
worked [œuvré]. The knowledge is not entirely then instinct is a “knowledge,” a consciousness,
its own knowledge. Above all, by its already not a functional ability but a knowledge and a
constructed nervous system, it brings orienting primary consciousness more fundamental than
or controlling “gnoses” to an instinctive theme individual consciousness and knowledge,
that “arrives” in its nervous system in the which are mere developers of primary knowl-
same way that formative themes arrive in edge. This is the same definition that Bergson
embryonic primordia over the course of their gives of “sympathy,” and the life-consciousness
organic formation. equivalence.
Tinbergen’s experiments on the instinctive However, it must be recognized that Berg-
reactions of young blackbirds in the nest to son’s own considerations, and the way in
the arrival of the nourishing parent have which he represents this “primary conscious-
shown this mixed character of instinctive ness” of life, are vitiated by a grave error due
action. When the young chick extends its open to their recapitulation of Matter and
beak towards the nourisher, the action seems Memory’s misguided theory of perception.
unified. Yet it is composed, with a certain obser- According to this theory, the sensory appara-
vable lag [décalage], of an autonomous motor tuses do not produce the image, the sensory rep-
theme (open the break upward), combined, resentation, because the universe is in principle
when the chick has ceased to be blind for two already only an ensemble of images. Here
or three days, with an orientation towards the Bergson has given in to Berkeleyan influences
nourisher. This orientation represents the part and generated elegant solutions by systematic
played by the individual nervous system that reversal of the terms of the problem and by
has become functional. In short, to use Weiss- return to the immediate. The sensory appara-
mann’s scheme, the bird does not “make” the tuses are, like the rest of the body, apparatuses
egg, the egg is made in it. On the contrary, it for action, not for the generation of represen-
“makes” its nest, but the nest is in part also tations. Perception is a selection. The image
made in it or through it, like the egg, by the (in principle) in its entirety is reduced to what
same specific knowledge that follows the conti- interests my action. The image of the object
nuity of the germ. (which interests me) is not formed in my
Embryology and the psychobiology of visual centre, then projected in the place
instinct are increasingly revealing themselves where the real object would be: “the object,
to be two chapters of the same science. The the rays that it emits, the retina and the inter-
same scientific concepts are used: primordia, ested nervous elements form an integral
territories, formative themes, autonomous whole, and it is there where the object is, and
development, stimuli-signals, stimuli-orientors, not elsewhere, that the image is formed and
induction, regulation, competence, importance perceived.”13
of timing. The “chemistry” of instinct is the If we are not mistaken, to try to understand
same as the chemistry of embryogenesis; the how the Sphex possesses a non-intellectual,
hormones of the sexual instinct are the same extra-sensory “knowledge [savoir]” of the
as the hormones that realize the genetic sex or anatomy of the caterpillar, Bergson uses two
potentially make it change in laboratory exper- different theories without being clearly aware
iments. Organic teratology, by arresting of the duality:

139
instinct, consciousness, life

(1) The thesis that life is unitary, that it forms An organism has a primary unity underlying
a “whole sympathetic to itself” (Bergson, the spatial distinction of its parts. The exper-
Creative Evolution 167), that this unity imental study of ontogenesis, regulation, and
pre-exists the super-imposed secondary regeneration has shown that the living individ-
dissociations, the divisions of labour, of ual is primarily an equipotential domain, not
the cells of the organism, individuals in a an assemblage [mosaı̈que]. Even after a certain
colony or society, or different species in spatial distribution of formative themes, each
a fauna or a flora, and that this unity region still retains equipotentiality in relation
reappears when necessary: “The instinc- to the theme it has received. It differentiates
tive knowledge that a species possesses itself first as a whole and according to this
of another species on a certain particular general theme before distributing it in its
point, therefore has its root in the very turn. From one equipotential region to another
unity of life” (ibid.). the synchronizations and harmonizations are
(2) The thesis (recalling Matter and Memory) operated by stimuli (chemical inducers); but
that perception (which bears on another in the interior of each region the stimuli path-
living being, or on a distant star) is in prin- ways play only a secondary role. If one cuts
ciple a knowledge [connaissance] at a dis- one of these regions it forms two complete
tance, without an intermediate organizations in the place of one; if one joins
progression of information: two of these symmetrical regions (before any
internal “distribution”) they form only one
A man born blind, who had lived
organization (whence symmelia, cyclopia, and
among others born blind, could not
all the monstrosities by fusion). In the adult
be made to believe in the possibility
of perceiving a distant object without organism a whole network of internal communi-
first perceiving all the objects in cations, nervous or chemical, is indispensable to
between. Yet vision performs this harmonize the life of the whole. But in the egg
miracle. In a certain sense the blind or young embryo it is not the same; the unity
mind is right, since vision, having its depends on a primary equipotentiality, as if
origin in the stimulation of the the organism in formation were analogous to a
retina, by the vibrations of the light, field of consciousness, to an acquired visual sen-
is nothing else, in fact, but a retinal sation, where the details are at once distinct and
touch … But we have shown elsewhere yet form an immediate conscious unity without
that the philosophical explanation of
needing to be seen again by an internal eye. Or,
perception must be of another kind
better understood, the analogy or dependence is
… Now, instinct also is a knowledge
[connaissance] at a distance (168). in the opposite direction, and it is the visual cor-
tical area that is clearly conscious, unitas multi-
This second thesis is very different from the plex, of a field only because it retains the
first (as stated previously). It relates not to life equipotential property of a young embryonic
but to perception in general, to which is attrib- organism or area in the adult.
uted a quasi-magical character of influence at a From the primary unity of an organism one
distance. Apart from Bergson’s very artificial passes easily to the primary unity of two organ-
reasoning here, it would be proven if Rhine’s isms. Two univitellin twins [of a single egg]
contestable and suspicious experiments on differ little more than the right hand and the
extra-sensory perception could be verified and left hand – especially if like Marie and É milie
confirmed. On the contrary, the first thesis (on Dionne they manifest a mirror symmetry. The
the primary unity of life, on the unity of male and female of a dioecious species [having
spatially distinct organisms, and even of organ- male and female reproductive organisms in sep-
isms of different species) is much more solid arate individuals] are two distinct organisms.
and today relies on a large number of biological The male and female organs of a monoecious
facts. or hermaphroditic species are formed in two

140
ruyer

regions of the same embryo. There is nothing the female according to a certain auslösende
unwarranted in admitting, with Bergson, or in schéma [triggering schema] on the other, does
Bergson’s style, that when a male and female not exempt him from having a “competence”
of the same species are brought together, like of the same nature as the competence of the pri-
the Sphex and the caterpillar, the stimuli- mordium of the male organs to differentiate in
signals evoking instinctive sexual behaviours the hermaphroditic organism.
represent only an accessory guidance; that the Bergson does not give enough credit to
male “does not have to learn one by one, like science when he adds: “Certainly, a scientific
the biologist, the positions [of the reproductive theory cannot appeal to considerations of this
organs in the female], nor to acquire the practi- kind. It must not put action before organization,
cal knowledge [connaissance] of these positions sympathy before perception and knowledge”
by experimenting [the effects of copulation]” (ibid.). It is the experimental embryology
(173). One can even add, with the text of Crea- itself which furnished the theory of instinct
tive Evolution, that “everything happens as if with these notions of “competence,” “equipo-
there were, [between the male and the female], tentiality,” “evocation,” which Bergson antici-
a sympathy which informs [the male] from the pates with a vocabulary obviously less precise,
inside about [the sexual characteristics of the but less inadequate than it seems at first sight.
female]” (173–74). Can we finally pass, then, from the male–
It is better to stop here, and not continue with female situation (of the same species), to the
Bergson, who adds: “This feeling [of the sexu- Sphex–caterpillar situation? The step is impor-
ality of the female] may owe nothing to the tant, and the jump is difficult, especially if one
external perception and result from the mere renounces the “magical” theory of perception
presence together [of the male and the female] at a distance of any object as one certainly
considered no longer as two organisms, but as must, to contaminate or to “complicate
two activities” (174). In fact, it is highly doubt- [corser]” the thesis of the primary unity of the
ful that orienting stimuli-signals, guiding exter- organism, of organisms and even species. Diffi-
nal perceptions, could be completely absent in cult, but not absolutely impossible, because
the most surprising instinctive performances, after all, living species, even the most distant
such as eel migrations, for example. There is from each other today, are born from a bifur-
nothing magical about the evocation of instinct; cation in an organic domain which does not
like development, it always has inductors, most differ essentially from a twin bifurcation [une
often chemical. But it is true that once evoked, bifurcation gémellaire]. It is not even absol-
instinctive actions overflow the evocator, the utely excluded that there is a “finality in the
inductor, the stimulating perception by their service of others,” or, to use Bergson’s
complexity. The animal is guided by light, or expression, “primary sympathy” from plant to
smell, it is not guided by it like an automaton. animal, as we have believed to be the case with
The external stimulating perception does not galls where the plant seems to accommodate a
bring it [the animal] complete information. dwelling for the parasitic insect, or again with
The instinct evoked is informed by itself: once entomophilic plants.
again, it is “knowledge [savoir].” This knowl- To tell the truth, we are personally very scep-
edge is of the same nature as “competence” (in tical on this point, and this is why we preferred
the sense that embryologists use this word), as to comment and to defend Bergson’s general
the competence, for example, of an embryonic theses on instinct-knowledge [savoir] and
area to unitarily differentiate according to the instinct recovering primary consciousness,
theme that was distributed to it when it is which is the very texture of life, substituting
induced to do so by a chemical inducer emanat- the example of the male–female situation for
ing from a neighbouring area. the Sphex–caterpillar situation.
The obligation for the male to be sensitized The very possibility of this hesitation and
by hormones on the one hand, and to perceive substitution is strange only at first glance. If

141
instinct, consciousness, life

we have to dissociate the two types of instinctive secondary adjustments obtained at first hapha-
situation, if the male and female organisms zardly. The distance is smaller than it appears
present together still benefit from a primary between sexuality and parasitism or predation.
organic unity in the one case and they no Fertilization is a break-in; in mammals, the
longer benefit in the other – where it is a embryo is a parasite on the mother, and is
matter of predator–prey or host–parasite – implanted in the uterus like mistletoe on an
then from where does their resemblance come? apple tree. Many animals are killed by sexual
And, finally, how to explain the Sphex’s “knowl- rapprochement. Laying eggs on a parasitized
edge [savoir]” of the caterpillar? Must we return animal is a behaviour that differs little from
decidedly, at least in cases of this kind, to Neo- that of some species of male whose gametes
Darwinism, and to the accumulation of acciden- occasionally migrate throughout the whole
tal mutations? But no Neo-Darwinian can argue body of the female. It is very probable that in
that in the male–female case and in the often- many symbioses, parasitisms, or predations,
complex courtship instincts, the instincts of whole stretches of sexual behaviour have been
the male and the instincts of the female are introduced after displacement and modification,
formed separately by accumulation of just as one can still recognize themes of attack,
mutations. The two instincts are often coordi- combat, flight, as well as the offer of nourish-
nated in a very rigorous way, like the male and ment or infantile behaviours in many courtship
female forms of a dioecious plant. Selection, if behaviours.
it intervened, had to intervene on the male– The resemblance between the male–female
female organic unity with which we therefore situation and the Sphex–caterpillar situation is
cannot, in any case, dispense. Orthodox Neo- thus explained in this way. In the abstract,
Darwinism therefore compounds the incongru- nothing is more opposed than natural selection
ity rather than elucidating it. It unduly accentu- and the unity of an organic domain. But in
ates the contrast between the two situations. fact, one penetrates the other to various
The solution to this problem has been given degrees. The unitary organic themes are still
by studies on disjunctions, displacements, at work, but more or less dissociated and re-
transpositions, and readjustments of instinc- adjusted to the potential of the species.
tive themes in comparative animal ethology,14 Chance and selection count little in the interplay
on the role of selection in these displacements of the sexes. They count more in symbioses and
and readjustments on the one hand, and of parasitisms. The evolutionary history of paralys-
these displacements on the selective action on ing Hymenoptera, entomophilic flowers,
the other. Once distributed, the initially mimetic forms – especially of those that even
unitary theme – that is, capable of inaugurating imitate physical accidents – must look a little
the formation of an entire individual or a global less than Bergson believes like an invention in
behaviour – becomes a multiplicity of themes, orthogenesis, or like the linear evolution of a
coordinated but nevertheless obliged from now technical or artistic form in a homogeneous
on to perfect that coordination. Selection bears human culture, and a little more like a
on the adjustment from theme to theme and “history” in the strong sense of the word, like
also on the displacements used by these disso- a political or linguistic history, complex and
ciated themes much more than on the fortui- capricious. The history of the evolution of
tous mutations of the genes or molecules of instincts, like organisms, is a mixture of organ-
DNA. ization and chance, of sense and of fortuitous
Selection does not resemble a mechanical displacements of sense, of improvisations to
sorting, but an organic learning by trial and suit the circumstances, and corrections [rattra-
error at once directed and fortuitous. Even in pages] by means of fortune. Bergson is certainly
sexual formations and behaviours, there are, wrong to speak of a theme “which transposes
despite the primary organic unity, many the- itself as a whole and on which, also as a
matic dissociations and consequently many whole, variations can be performed.”15

142
ruyer

Biological themes, like words, are composites. invention, is a provisional and erasable cortical
But, overall, Bergson’s mistake is minor. morphogenesis. It thus relies on the primary
organic self-structuring property applied to
••• these objects instead of being applied to
organic tissues as tissues, thanks to the fact
The Bergsonian conception of instinct is there- that the brain is at once organic tissue and a
fore generally correct. Its weaknesses are due screen where the forms of external objects are
rather to its less auspicious connections to projected.
neighbouring theories. Why do all animals with a cortex “informed”
The instinct–intelligence opposition, and by sensory organs – that is to say a good part of
especially the bifurcation between animal instinct vertebrates, and even metazoans – not fabricate
and human intelligence, is certainly forced. This tools if they have organs, beak, mandibles,
is incompatible with the incontestable thesis that hands, etc., capable of holding a material
does not dissociate instinct and organization. The object? Why do only some insects, some birds,
body of man is formed like that of animals. His and the anthropoid apes sporadically use
psyche is fundamentally the same. Comparative thorns, pebbles, sticks? It is because the
ethology finds in man the same instinctive crucial transition [le passage capital] is less
bases as the mammals: internal sensitization, the use of tools than the constitution of symbo-
stimuli-signals and gnoses, phenomena of displa- lism. The monkey intelligently uses a stick, but
cement, etc. Autonomous motor melodies are for lack of an idea, of a cerebral assembly
rarer, but they are not lacking, as A. Gesell and [montage] corresponding to the stick, it does
Piaget have shown. And, moreover, they are not put it in reserve or set it aside as a “perma-
also rare in other mammals. nent tool.” The constitution of a symbolic
As Baerend’s observations have demon- activity was the decisive fact, much more than
strated, on the one hand, even the instincts of the use of a tool for a present problem. It is
insects include variable phases of rigidity and this fact that has allowed for both social
flexibility [souplesse], the phases of flexibility culture and external technics.
and “broad” adaptation not being due to a Bergson has tried to escape from the common
mixture of intelligence but to a sort of thematic error for which all panpsychists fall, which con-
breadth of instinct itself, “foreseeing” a collab- sists in attributing to instinct, formative or not,
oration with learning, if one can so speak. The an evanescent or asymptotically null conscious-
instincts in man and the higher animals are ness. Consciousness of the instinctive act, says
exceptionally “broad,” but they are authentic Bergson, is not null, but annulled [annulée]:
instincts. the representation is stopped up [bouchée] by
On the other hand, the characterization of action. Consciousness is there, but neutralized.
instinct as the capacity to form organic tools, As the action hesitates, the representation
and intelligence as the ability to form inorganic appears (144). But this theory of Bergson’s is
tools, without being false does not help us grasp very bizarre in addition to the fact that it agrees
– at least as Bergson presents it – the modality badly with the conception of instinct-intuition
of the passage from the organic tool to the fab- in contrast with pragmatic intelligence. It is
ricated tool. The use and fabrication of a tool, applied only to certain actions of man or
by man, and exceptionally by the monkey, is animals with advanced brains. The obstacle to
still an “organic formation” if one thinks the action in progress requires “mental exper-
about it, like any intelligent activity more gener- iments” based on imagination. But let us apply
ally. In fact, the use and fabrication of the tool it to the formative instinct or the instinct of
are directed by the brain and imply spontaneous animals without developed brains: if we prevent
changes in the brain tissue of the motor and an embryo from gastrulating, or if we disturb a
sensory areas that direct the movements of use Stentor with grains of carmine, it is very doubtful
and fabrication. Fabrication, technical that a representational consciousness appears.

143
instinct, consciousness, life

The mistake is to make “consciousness” the in their assembly [ensemble] and in their stat-
synonym for “representation.” Representational istical effects on the other.
consciousness is only a secondary consciousness, Bergson works true wonders to catch a
involving a cerebral tissue modulated by external glimpse of what would come clearly to the scien-
objects. Primary consciousness is the very form tists themselves a few years after Creative Evol-
of organization and of its behaviours, as it is in ution. His conception of the “ideal genesis of
itself, without having to reflect the image of matter,” relaxing in geometry and numbers; his
another thing. It is presentation (of itself), and conception of movement as primary relative to
not re-presentation (of another thing). This substantial mobiles (301–02); his conception of
form for itself is perfectly distinct and precise, the appearance of quality, are so many presenti-
as precise and distinct as a visual field. But it is ments: in effect, two physics were to be consti-
a visual field in which it would see only itself tuted, or rather two stages of physics and of
and its own possibilities. Existing as an absolute science in general. Science itself would soon
domain of space and time, it is present unitarily realize that mechanisms at our scale and the prin-
to its own parts and to its own thematic develop- ciples of mechanics, far from being fundamental,
ment as well. represent, if not a “relaxation,” as Bergson said,
As for the fabrication of tools, Bergson does at least a statistical appearance obtained from
not realize that representational, cerebral con- leaving out a very large number of “actions.”
sciousness is itself possible only through the These actions, individualized, irreducible to
primary consciousness of the cerebral tissue as mechanical operations – since they appear only
organic tissue. We only see things, and we as the result of these actions – already have the
only fabricate them, because our protoplasmic essential characteristics of actions attributable
tissue “sees” and “fabricates” itself. to the most complex individualities. They are
All individualized forms, cerebral, proto- expressed by “an energy multiplied by time,”
plasmic, or even chemical, are indissolubly which is not very far from Bergson’s fundamen-
“conscious.” Consciousness is not a “current tal thesis. Time is inherent in their structure,
sent through matter,” as Bergson says in an time is structuration of action, emerging and
unfortunate metaphor.16 Matter as such, creating, and is not the simple unfolding of an
apart from religious or philosophical myths, already given spatial structure.
is only a secondary mode of primary individua- Bergson was born relative to the scientific
lized forms when they constitute aggregates revolution of the twentieth century as if Des-
edge to edge [bord à bord], without their own cartes had been born before Galileo and had
unity. written almost all the same things, the Medita-
Bergson’s real philosophical misfortune is to tions and the Principles. We will appreciate
have been born at a very bad time. At the end of Bergson’s merit all the more if we consider
the nineteenth century, one had doubts about that even today so many philosophers, so
the artificial character of mechanistic and deter- many scientists lost in their speciality, and
ministic science but one saw no other solution especially so many biologists – such as Fonte-
than to seek the truth outside of science. One nelle, too faithful to the Cartesianism of his
could not anticipate the scientific revolution youth – still imagine that science has remained
that micro-physics was about to bring by disco- with the principles of nineteenth-century
vering the domains of individuality beneath the physics and completely misunderstands the
secondary and statistical laws. Micro-physics extent of the revolution brought about by
also permits one to follow the progressive com- micro-physics. This revolution
plication of lineages of individualities, from the is as important as the Galilean
atom to macro-molecules, to viruses, to cells, to revolution, which it corrects –
multicellular organisms on the one hand, and otherwise than Bergson had
the appearance of classical secondary laws anticipated, but in the sense of
when multitudes of individuals are considered his presentiments.

144
ruyer

notes large part as a contribution to beginning to fill


this gap. Beyond the commonalities between
Raymond Ruyer’s “Bergson et le Sphex ammo- Bergson and Ruyer catalogued above, there are a
phile” was first published in French in Revue de number that still remain to be explored as well.
métaphysique et de morale 64.2 (1959): 163–79. These include, for instance, the location of
The article is reproduced here in English by kind freedom internal to the activity of nature as an
permission of Presses Universitaires de France, immanent expression of all self-constituting forms
the publisher of the original article. (Ruyer) or self-organizing centres of action
1 Although this isolation continues to this day – (Bergson), as well as the complex relationship
the first volume to appear on Ruyer’s thought in between naturalized freedom and naturalized con-
any language was the publication of conference sciousness, such that both thinkers appear in their
proceedings (Vax and Wunenberger) – the ice way to be endorsing a kind of panpsychism. This
appears to be thawing. Two studies of Ruyer’s last point, however, is one on which Ruyer will dis-
work as a whole have appeared recently. See tinguish himself from Bergson by insisting on a dis-
Colonna, Ruyer; Louis and Louis. In the world of tinction between two forms of consciousness. We
French philosophy, scholars are beginning to return to this consideration below.
appreciate the extent to which Ruyer influenced 6 The catalogue of Ruyer’s other invocations of
better known figures such as Simondon and Bergson is, as we have indicated above, brief. All
Deleuze as well. The influence is clearest in Simon- mention of Bergson in Neofinalism is critical and
don’s case, as he explicitly responded to some of insubstantial (8, 12, 38, 128, 137, 208). There are
Ruyer’s work and incorporated revised versions only two mentions of Bergson in La Genèse, and,
of its themes into his own thinking (cf. Gagnon; again, neither is very significant (66, 122). One of
Bardin). Ruyer’s influence on Deleuze, although few positive mentions of Bergson appears in “The
apparently profound, was somewhat subterranean, Vital Domain of Animals and the Religious World
and is still in the process of being excavated and of Man,” which was translated into English in
explained (cf. Bogue; Roffe). 1957, two years before the publication of
2 These details are recounted by Ruyer himself in “Bergson et le Sphex ammophile.” In this article,
the first and only volume of his Souvenirs. Ruyer refers to Bergson’s discussion of the
instincts of the Sphex wasp in order to deny the
3 On the distinction between primary and second- contention that animals are world-less automatons
ary consciousness in Ruyer, and the problems that merely mechanically reacting to stimuli (40). Ruyer
it appears to court, see the incisive analysis in suggests that Bergson’s discussion of wasps shows
Barbaras. that instinct is a means of access to another crea-
ture, a kind of supple knowledge, not the deploy-
4 Cf. ibid. 18–19.
ment of a blind mechanism triggered by the right
5 This connection remains largely overlooked in cues. “Bergson et le Sphex ammophile” appears
the secondary literature. Kerslake is an important to return to, expand upon, and complete this
exception, as it includes what is perhaps the only appreciation for the role played by parasitism in
mention in English scholarship of Ruyer’s defence Bergson’s thought. Finally, a last brief engagement
of Bergson’s theory of instinct – with reference with Bergson appears in an English article from
to the article translated below (62–65). Bremondy 1988 excerpted from what was at the time a still
is a notable exception as well, though its focus is on unpublished work, entitled Au Dieu inconnu,
Ruyer’s critique of Bergson’s theory of perception Source de toute vie. This work was since published
and thus does not explore the possibility of positive in 2013 under the new title L’Embryogenèse du
overlap between the two thinkers. Ansell-Pearson monde et le Dieu silencieux. The excerpted trans-
refers to Bremondy’s article and its relevance for lation, “There is No Subconscious: Embryogenesis
an understanding of the significance of Ruyer and and Memory,” recalls some of the argumentation
Bergson for Deleuze. Colonna refers to some of of “Bergson et le Sphex ammophile” on the topic
Ruyer’s attempts to position himself vis-à-vis of memory (“No Subconscious” 35–36). Ruyer
Bergson (Ruyer 20). Finally, Alliez makes brief argues, contra Bergson, that habitual memory is
mention of the two together (236 ff.). The litera- delocalized and thematic, continuous with embryo-
ture remains incomplete. We offer this article in nic developmental and therefore virtual, while

145
instinct, consciousness, life

image memory is abstracted from it. He thus Ansell-Pearson, Keith. “Thinking Immanence: On
inverts the priority of Bergson’s distinction the Event of Deleuze’s Bergsonism.” Deleuze and
between the two, and concludes that Bergson’s Guattari: Critical Assessments of Leading
conception is “not only false, but the very antipode Philosophers. Vol. 1. Ed. Gary Genosko.
of the truth” (ibid.). It is worth noting that Ruyer’s New York: Routledge, 2001. 412–41. Print.
discussion of the topic in “Bergson et le Sphex
Barbaras, Renaud. “Vie et extériorité. Le Problème
ammophile” is far less critical.
de la perception chez Ruyer.” Les Études philosophi-
7 Trans. Tano S. Posteraro. This article originally ques 1.80 (2007): 15–37. Print.
appeared in French in 1959, as “Bergson et le
Bardin, Andrea. Epistemology and Political Philosophy
Sphex ammophile,” in the Revue de métaphysique
in Gilbert Simondon: Individuation, Technics, Social
et de morale 64.2, 163–79. The title is somewhat
Systems. Dordrecht: Springer, 2015. Print.
confusing. Ammophila is the name of a genus in
the thread-waisted wasp family; Sphex is the Bergson, Henri. Creative Evolution. Trans. Arthur
name of another. Mitchell. Mineola: Dover, 1998. Print.
8 Fabre, Nouveaux souvenirs 114 qtd in Bergson, Bergson, Henri. Matter and Memory. Trans. Nancy
Creative Evolution 172. Margaret Paul and W. Scott Palmer. New York:
Zone, 1988. Print.
9 Peckham and Peckham 28.
Bogue, Raymond. “Raymond Ruyer.” Deleuze’s
10 Bergson, Creative Evolution 168–69.
Philosophical Lineage. Ed. Graham Jones and John
11 Ruyer seems to run together the following two Roffe. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP, 2009. 300–20.
passages from Bergson, Creative Evolution 171. (1) “In Print.
other words, instinct is everywhere complete, but it
Bremondy, François. “La Critique de Bergson par
is more or less simplified, and, above all, simplified
Ruyer est-elle justifiée?” Bergson et les neurosciences.
differently”; (2) “We seem rather to be before a
Ed. Philippe Gallois and Gérard Forzy. Le
musical theme, which had first been transposed,
Plessis Robinson: Institut Synthélabo, 1997. 169–
the theme as a whole, into a certain number of
95. Print.
tones and on which, still the whole theme, different
variations had been played […]” [Translator’s note.] Colonna, Fabrice. “Présentation.” Les Études philo-
sophiques 1.80 (2007): 1–2. Print.
12 Cf. Tinbergen, L’Étude 280.
Colonna, Fabrice. Ruyer. Paris: Belles Lettres, 2007.
13 Bergson, Matter 37–38. Note that by rejecting
Print.
Bergson’s theory we do not return to the theory
of “projection.” Our thesis is that the visual sen- Fabre, Jean-Henri. The Hunting Wasps. Trans.
sation is in our head, and that it stays there. It has Alexander Teixeira de Mattos. New York: Dodd,
no more to be projected than to be straightened 2001. Print.
since it is the whole of our visual consciousness.
Fabre, Jean-Henri. Nouveaux souvenirs entomologi-
14 Cf. especially Tinbergen, L’Étude; Social ques. Paris: Delagrave, 1882. Print.
Behaviour.
Gabel, Isabel. “Biology and the Philosophy of
15 Ruyer is referring again to Bergson, Creative History in Mid-Twentieth Century France.” Diss.
Evolution 171 (see n. 9). [Translator’s note.] Columbia U, 2015. Web. 3 Aug. 2019. <https://
16 Ruyer is referring to ibid. 265. [Translator’s doi.org/10.7916/D8DR2TX4>.
note.] Gagnon, Philip. “Ruyer and Simondon on
Technological Inventiveness and Form Outlasting
its Medium.” Deleuze Studies 11.4 (2017): 538–54.
bibliography Print.

Alliez, Eric. “On Deleuze’s Bergsonism.” Trans. Keijzer, Fred. “The Sphex Story: How the
Tom Conley and Melissa McMuhan. Gilles Deleuze: Cognitive Sciences Kept Repeating an Old and
A Reason to Believe in this World. Spec. issue of Questionable Anecdote.” Philosophical Psychology
Discourse 20.3 (1998): 226–46. Print. 26.4 (2013): 502–19. Print.

146
ruyer

Kerslake, Christian. Deleuze and the Unconscious. Vax, Louis, and Jean-Jacques Wunenberger, eds.
New York: Continuum, 2007. Print. Raymond Ruyer, de la science à la théologie. Paris:
Kimé, 1995. Print.
Louis, Fabrice, and Jean-Pierre Louis. La Philosophie
de Raymond Ruyer: Repères. Vrin: Repères philoso- Wolff, Étienne. Trois pattes pour un canard: souvenirs
phiques, 2014. Print. d’un biologiste. Paris: Fondation Singer-Polignac,
1990. Print.
Peckham, G.W., and E.G. Peckham. Wasps, Social
and Solitary. Westminster: Constable, 1905. Print.
Roffe, Jon. “The Egg: Deleuze between Darwin and
Ruyer.” Deleuze and Evolutionary Theory. Ed. M.
Bennett and T. Posteraro. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
UP, 2019. 42–58. Print.
Russell, Bertrand. The Analysis of Mind. New York:
Macmillan, 1921. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. “Bergson et le Sphex ammo-
phile.” Revue de métaphysique et de morale 64.2
(1959): 163–79. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. La Conscience et le corps. Paris:
Alcan, 1937. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. Éléments de psycho-biologie. Paris:
PUF, 1946. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. La Genèse des formes vivantes.
Paris: Flammarion, 1958. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. “Les Informations de présence.”
Revue philosophique de la France et de l’Étranger
152 (1962): 197–218. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. Néo-finalisme. Paris: PUF, 1952.
Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. Neofinalism. Trans. Alyosha
Edlebi. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2016. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. “Raymond Ruyer par lui-même.”
Les Études philosophiques 80 (2007): 3–14. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. Souvenirs – 1 – Ma famille alsacienne
et ma vallée vosgienne. Paris: Vent d’Est, 1985. Print.
Ruyer, Raymond. “There is No Subconscious: Tano S. Posteraro
Embryogenesis and Memory.” Trans. R. Scott 240 Sparks Building
Walker. Diogenes 36.142 (1988): 24–46. Print. University Park, PA 16802
USA
Ruyer, Raymond. “The Vital Domain of Animals
and the Religious World of Man.” Trans. Elaine P.
E-mail: gzp132@psu.edu
Halperin. Diogenes 5.18 (1957): 35–46. Print.
Jon Roffe
Tinbergen, Niko. L’Étude de l’instinct. Paris: Payout, Deakin University
1953. Print. 221 Burwood Highway
Tinbergen, Niko. Social Behaviour in Animals with Burwood, VIC 3125
Special Reference to Vertebrates. London: Methuen, Australia
1962. Print. E-mail: jon.roffe@deakin.edu.au

You might also like