You are on page 1of 15

Plato's Banishment of Poetry

Author(s): Morriss Henry Partee


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 29, No. 2 (Winter, 1970), pp. 209-
222
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/428602 .
Accessed: 08/01/2015 14:13

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Wiley and The American Society for Aesthetics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
MORRISS HENRY PARTEE

Plato's Banishment of Poetry

LIKE THE MEDIEVAL "Pearl" and Hamlet, Plato's consistent mistrust of art in his
the aesthetics of Plato provides ample explicit consideration of art must take pre-
ground on which the critic may exercise cedence over his tacit enjoyment and his
any particular hobbyhorse he chooses to use of poetry in the dialogues. In practice,
ride. While poet-baiters have used some Plato not only quotes poetry with obvious
parts of the dialogues to scandalize poetry- approval but he also creates dramatic scenes
lovers, Plato's theories of love and beauty which rival those of even the greatest of
have inspired generations of poets. To poets. Nevertheless, in the Republic X, his
those who would cite him to damn poetry, most thorough discussion of art, Plato
Plato offers such strictures as found in the strongly condemns poetry, both for its con-
Republic II, 377-383, III, 386-404, the fusing of the intellect and for its corrupting
Sophist 234-237, and the Laws II, 658-663, of the emotions. His extreme position in
VII, 800-812, and VIII, 829. To those who the last book of the greatest repository of
would defend poetry, he gives his theory of his thought represents his boldest conclu-
inspiration, his analysis of the ethical uses sions. His insistence throughout the greater
of poetry, and the example of the magnifi- part of the dialogues on the importance of
cent poetry in his dialogues. But the pres- Forms should warn the reader against dis-
ent inquiry has only one purpose: to con- missing the Republic as presenting an im-
sider Plato's most representative thought re- possible ideal. To Plato, the Republic was
garding poetry. His theory of divine inspi- more "real" than any state actually in exist-
ration, his frequent citation of poetry, and ence. In this book Plato states that he has
his use of ethical myths are historically im- banished all imaginative poetry-dramatic,
portant in the study of Plato's attitude to- epic, lyric. He does admit straight-forward
ward poets and poetry. But while this par- didactic poetry later in the discussion, but
tial sanction of imaginative literature has significantly he does not consider at this
some relevance to Plato's aesthetics, a critic point the possibility that this verse could be
must not ignore Plato's continual attacks beautiful in its own right. Judging poetry
on poetry, especially the final and complete solely in terms of its effects, Plato feels that
exclusion of poets in the Republic X. With artful language, the tool of the sophists,
the twentieth century's acceptance of meta- tends to seduce the unwary to embrace the
physical and formalist criticism, Plato's transient beauty of pleasure instead of to
stern moral judgment of poetry has fallen
lift the soul to contemplate the true beauty
into increasing disfavor. Thus, Plato's de-
of virtue. His sincerity and finality cannot
fenders are tempted to make him the friend
of poets, his attacks on Hesiod and Homer be questioned; only the semi-humorous re-
being irrelevant footnotes to his real devo- quest to hear a defense of poetry in the
tion to poetry. Republic X, 607b-8 tempers the passionate
conviction of his reasoning in X, 595-607a.
MORRISSHENRY PARTEE is assistant professor of Eng-
The philosophical authority of his ex-
lish at the University of California, Los Angeles. tended reasoning in the Republic far out-

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
210 MORRISS HENRY PARTEE

weighs his offhanded and ironic praise of rhapsodes or the education of the youth.
poetic inspiration in such dialogues as the The scattered sayings about inspiration, the
Ion and the Phaedrus. Plato's unyielding uses of poetry, and the nature of poetry
refusal to accept anything less than absolute itself only grudgingly, if at all, give up the
knowledge precludes any admission that heart of Plato's aesthetics.
beautiful language could lead man to vir- Scholars today usually avoid the issues in
tue. Accordingly, Plato applies the same the Republic X in their attempt to rescue
strictures to poetry that he places on lan- Plato from charges of philistinism. One ap-
guage throughout his dialogues. Rhetoric, proach would directly question the purpose
poetry, reasoned discourse, all must primar- of the Republic, the only dialogue which
ily contain the truth. Plato would and does seems to condemn poetry totally. Another
condemn even his own dialogues should any- line of thought suggests that Plato through-
one regard them as repositories of beauty out the dialogues never seriously attacks po-
and meaning in themselves. The dialogues, etry. A third, more easily supported, posi-
and indeed all acceptable uses of language, tion would admit that Plato has some reser-
must be taken as guides for thought; only vations about art, but would limit Plato's
under this ideal condition will literature attack to the abuse of art and, in particular,
and poetry of any sort be welcome in the realistic art. This third theory will be exam-
well-run state. We must not cut Plato's soar- ined here later; the first two positions must
ing thought down to an ill-considered and be carefully considered. First, the most fac-
inconsistent espousal of poetry. Plato's re- ile and tempting argument holds that the
luctance to sacrifice Homer and Hesiod to Republic is an ideal state, a kind of utopia.
the demands of the intellect makes further This interpretation stresses that poetry
tribute to poetry in his name unnecessary. deals with the emotions of real and fallible
Plato's theory of poetry is far more ab- men. Thus, Plato dismisses art lest the por-
stract and less applicable to the analysis of trayal of reality shatter the ideal like a
poetry than that of Aristotle. Plato's over- grubby finger destroys a soap bubble. In a
whelming bias towards ethics has tempted perfect state no imperfection can exist. Dar-
scholars to stress his linking of ethics with nell Rucker, a recent advocate of this posi-
poetry rather than to consider what he says tion, persuasively reasons that "Neither the
about poetry itself. But the issues Plato legislator nor the philosopher nor the poet
raises are important for aesthetics as well as has the same role in the Republic as he has
for ethics or literary criticism. Because of in an actual state; and these differences in
the unstated basis of his aesthetics, few crit- role are consequent upon the difference be-
ics have pursued the course of his reason- tween an ideal and an actuality." 3 G. M. A.
ing. The most vociferous attacker of poetry Grube likewise agrees that Plato is legislat-
in the Elizabethan Age, Stephen Gosson,' ing for an ideal republic, a pattern laid up
cites Plato's aesthetics as superficially as the in heaven. "In such a state no one has ever
great bishop of Hippo, St. Augustine, does.2 claimed a place for Pericles, Themistocles,
Plato's manner of presentation allows a or Solon, or indeed for any statesman that
wide latitude for the interpretation of his has ever lived. Why should an exception be
aesthetics. Since Plato was not a system- made for the poets?" 4 But one might argue
builder, a critic takes a firm stand at his that Plato does provide for enlightened rul-
own peril. In addition, the mask of the dia- ers-the philosopher-kings; he specifically
logue form increases the ambiguity intro- excludes all poets. And Plato would vio-
duced by the changing thought of Plato's lently object to his Republic's being consid-
long and productive life. His thought may ered less real than the decaying political
indeed represent a unity as Paul Shorey has organization of Athens in its decline. Great
so eloquently argued, but this unity is a though Athenian statesmen had been,
many-faceted jewel. To compound the Plato, like Machiavelli, saw the degenera-
problem, Plato never considers poetry by tion of past grandeur all around him.
itself. He is always pressing toward some Clearly, radical proposals were needed.
other conclusion, usually the ignorance of The argument stressing the Republic as

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Plato's Banishment of Poetry 211

visionary, but impractical, likewise reasons state or man; for if men, who are in fact
that, like the state, the ruler of the Repub- always imperfect, could reach perfection,
lic needs protection from the real world of they would only be realizing all that their
heat and dust. The philosopher-king must nature aims at being and might conceivably
be isolated by almost physical barriers, as in be." 10 Plato intends the Republic to de-
More's Utopia, to guard him from the rig- scribe a system better than that of any ac-
ors of a real state. Rucker states, "The phi- tual or foreseeable state. But his attack on
losopher in our world, as Plato says in the poetry is from the standpoint not of politics
Apology and Socrates exemplifies, must but rather of ethics. The dialogue deals as
exist in a private station. Short of the insti- much with education as with the state.
tutionalization of the education process of "Were it not for the title, it might be read
the Republic, the philosopher-king could for what it is, rather than as an essay in
not hope for the necessary support from the utopian political theory. It is a fact that
institutions and the citizens of his city." 5 only about a third of the work concerns
Indeed Plato is always mindful that philos- itself with statecraft as such." 11 If Plato
ophers were often ill-treated in the city says emphatically that poetry should be
state,6 and often alludes to their other- banished from the ideal state, then his criti-
worldliness.7 But the philosopher's present cism applies even more strongly to any less-
ills and seeming dreaminess are only the than-perfect state. If poetry is a necessary
appearances that the ignorant can see. evil in a real state, poetry must be excluded
The argument that the Republic is an from a more perfect commonwealth. A nec-
ideal state has by no means found universal essary evil is still an evil.
acceptance. Eric A. Havelock explicitly at- The philosopher to Plato is a realist in
tacks this view as a present-day fallacy: "On the widest sense of the word. As opposed to
the over-all issue, Plato is accommodated to the benighted politicians who must compro-
modern taste by arguing that the pro- mise their convictions, a true philosopher
gramme of the Republic is utopian and works both in the world of appearances and
that the exclusion of poetry applies only to in the world of higher realities. Plato him-
an ideal condition not realisable in the rec- self went to Syracuse in order to advise
ognizable future or in earthly societies. One Dionysius. And one must agree with Plato
might reply that even in that case why that Socrates lived and died more trium-
should the Muse of all people be selected phantly than did the tyrants who were su-
for exclusion from Utopia?" 8 Plato's seri- perficially successful in this world of shad-
ousness can be seen in his consistent de- ows. Otherwise, Plato would insist that the
mand that poetry and all discourse be sub- Phaedo be rejected from a proper state
ordinate to reason and thought in the because of its description of an unjust pun-
proper education of youth. From the Ion to ishment.
the Laws, Plato insists that poetry be
Moreover, in Plato's thought itself, the
judged in terms of its knowledge and its
usefulness. The great political figures in philosopher is constantly engaged with the
Athens' past offer the same danger to the world. The vision of absolute virtue and
Republic that poetry does: the weight of beauty makes the philosopher effective:
"Remember how in that communion only,
authority may detract from the force of ac-
tive reasoning. Besides, most good states- beholding beauty with the eye of the mind,
men act only through "right opinion." 9 he will be enabled to bring forth, not im-
The greatest danger in making the Re- ages of beauty, but realities (for he has hold
public an ideal is that the interpretation not of an image but of a reality), and bring-
denies Plato's carefully considered analysis ing forth and nourishing true virtue to be-
of knowledge. Our distinction between come the friend of God and be immortal, if
ideal and real is not Plato's. "The assertion mortal man may" (Symposium 212).12 Even
that theory comes closer than practice to at the moment of greatest remove from the
truth or reality is characteristically Pla- physical world, Plato makes the philoso-
tonic. The ideal state or man is the true pher bring forth the realities of true virtue.

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
212 MORRISS HENRY PARTEE
The poet, on the other hand, is likely to impossible" (VI, 502). A true utopia, a "no-
produce only "images of beauty." where" such as Sir Thomas More's, may be
Admittedly, the Republic is not to be a social satire, a skeptical attack on existing
found among actual states, but then, the institutions. The Republic, however, is no
true philosopher does not live on the same flight of the imagination; the dialogue rep-
plane with ordinary men. In his search for resents Plato's attempt to suggest the Form
justice, Socrates states: of the state.
When we set out to discover the essential nature Therefore, one cannot dismiss the attack
of justice and injustice and what a perfectly just on poetry in the Republic merely on the
and a perfectly unjust man would be like, sup- basis of its presenting an ideal state. If a
posing them to exist, our purpose was to use them critic is justified in dismissing any part with
as ideal patterns; we were to observe the degree which he happens to disagree, there is no
of happiness or unhappiness that each exhibited,
and to draw the necessaryinference that our own limit to the material he can ignore. The
destiny would be like that of the one we most re- Republic is neither an impossible ideal nor
sembled. We did not set out to show that these a blueprint for a possible state; its contribu-
ideals could exist in fact. (Republic V, 472) tion is both to politics and to ethics. Like
He recognizes that theory can never be com- Aristotle, Plato identifies the good of the
pletely realized in practice, for action al- individual with that of the state. A. E. Tay-
ways comes less close to truth than thought. lor comments on the purpose of this dia-
He asks, "Is our theory any the worse, if we logue: "It has sometimes been asked
cannot prove it possible that a state so or- whether the Republic is to be regarded as a
ganized should be actually founded?" contribution to ethics or to politics. Is its
(ibid). The Republic, then, is an honest subject 'righteousness', or is it the 'ideal
and courageous attempt to cut through the state?' The answer is that from the point of
confusion inherent in any society already view of Socrates and Plato there is no dis-
realized. tinction, except one of convenience, be-
Later, Socrates proposes that the philoso- tween morals and politics. The laws of
pher-king may be effective even in an actual right are the same for classes and cities as
state. The philosopher, in companionship for individual men. But one must add that
with the divine order, will first reproduce these laws are primarily laws of personal
that order in his own soul: morality; politics is founded on ethics, not
ethics on politics." 13 Plato proposes a guide
Suppose, then, he should find himself compelled for man to order his life, not a utopian
to mould other charactersbesides his own and to
shape the pattern of public and private life into scheme for intellectual amusement. He in-
conformity with his vision of the ideal, he will tends his precepts concerning ethics to be
not lack the skill to produce such counterpartsof universally applicable no less than does
temperance,justice, and all the virtues as can ex- Kant. Few men may follow the categorical
ist in the ordinary man. And the public, when
they see that we have describedhim truly, will be imperative, but men's failing does not ren-
reconciled to the philosopher and no longer dis- der the principle less true. So while any
believe our assertionthat happinesscan only come thoughtful discussion of the Republic's
to a state when its lineaments are traced by an applicability to our humdrum existence is
artist working after a divine pattern. (Republic
VI, 500) valuable, one must still consider whether
Plato seriously and consistently attacks po-
The philosopher's role is to create a hu- etry in this dialogue and elsewhere.
manity true to its highest possibilities, not The second method of making Plato a
to pander to the confused emotions of igno- patron of the arts does not attack the pur-
rant men. The guide of the philosopher, pose of the Republic but the seriousness of
the true artist, should be the ideal model of Plato in banishing poets. Following Sir
virtue. He is a lover of truth and reality. Philip Sidney's example, these apologists
The institutions described in the Republic claim that Plato condemns only the abuse
will certainly be the best if they can be of poetry. The Laws thus represents Plato's
realized. And Plato rather sanguinely states awakening to the necessity of poetry in
that "to realize them, though hard, is not human life; the Ion becomes an expose of

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Plato's Banishment of Poetry 213
contemporary Greek criticism. Stressing the claim to knowledge of those things he is
Ion, Allan Gilbert argues that "Plato at- inspired to say (or make), Plato has no
tempted to banish the bad critics that the quarrel with him as a poet." 17 In light of
poets might appear as they truly were and Plato's careful qualification, however, one
are, even if only to the fit audience who can cannot accept his seriousness in praising in-
discern their nature as artists." 14 This line spiration. The Ion does indeed attack only
of reasoning is attractive, for Plato's main the unlearned rhapsode. But the theory of
thrust in the Ion certainly appears to be poetic inspiration (Ion 533), far from prais-
against the stupidity of the rhapsodes. ing the poet, only testifies to poetry's power.
Then, too, Plato's constraints on poetry are, And Plato never questions the effects of po-
for the most part, overshadowed by his fre- etry. His question is how dangerous are
quent citations of poetry. Finally, the Re- these effects to the intellect.
public II and III as well as the Laws II and Although his theory of divine inspiration
VII censure primarily immoral poetry. If has been extremely influential on poets and
some poetry is moral, Plato would have to literary critics, Plato does not develop his
admit its presence in the well-run state. scattered comments into a philosophy. In-
Unfortunately, grave difficulties beset deed, this minor motif runs counter to Pla-
each of these arguments. Nowhere in the to's serious investigation of poetry. The
Ion does Plato accept poetry as a guide to Phaedrus, which cites the poet favorably,
proper conduct. Instead, we have only an mentions four kinds of madness. The sub-
ambiguous praise of the source of poetry, jects of the dialogue are love and rhetoric;
the Muse. This divine source of inspiration only one short section (245) mentions po-
plays no integral role in Plato's discussion etry at all. Similarly, the Symposium 205
of knowledge or virtue. Surprisingly touches on the poet on its way to an exposi-
enough, Plato never mentions poetic inspi- tion of Absolute Beauty. The passages are
ration in the context of his examination of frequently attacks on the poet's knowledge,
poetry. He quotes poetry often, but seldom poetry being praised in a backhanded man-
pauses to consider the poetic worth, the ner. The Phaedrus 245 would make the
beauty of any passage. The quotations poet a "divine madman," several degrees
usually illustrate some point about conduct. below the inspired philosopher. Here Plato
Next, the dialogue form may not express does attribute the same sort of greatness to
Plato's final position. Again, if we dismiss poet and to philosopher. But the philoso-
whatever we please in the dialogues simply pher more typically in Plato is one who
because of the tentative nature of Plato's knows rather than one who is "inspired."
reasoning, we have little hope of under- Two other dialogues are even less favora-
standing any of his thought. Finally, if ble in their citation of divine inspiration of
other dialogues accept the possibility of the poet. The Apology 22 states that "there
moral poetry, the Republic X certainly de- is hardly a person present who would not
nies that any poetry which Plato knew have talked better about their poetry than
would fulfill the requirement. Plato's final they did themselves. Then I knew that not
comment on poetry in the most complete by wisdom do poets write poetry, but by a
exposition of his thought surely takes pre- sort of genius and inspiration; they are like
cedence over the trivial Ion15 and the im- diviners or soothsayers who also say many
portant but pedestrian Laws.16 fine things, but do not understand the
To vitiate Plato's attack on art in the meaning of them." This passage, dripping
Republic X, critics often cite his famous with Socratic irony, is hardly matter on
praise of divine inspiration. Rucker empha- which to build a significant praise of inspi-
sizes that Plato praises inspiration and con- ration. The Laws shows little development
demns only art which unjustly pretends to or refinement of those concepts expressed
knowledge. "Socrates does not attack Ion's early in Plato's thoughts on poetry. The
ability as a rhapsode in the Ion; he attacks Athenian states that
Ion's claim to knowledge of the topics of
the poet, according to the tradition which has
his recitations. So long as the poet makes no ever prevailed among us, and is accepted of all

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
214 MORRISS HENRY PARTEE

men, when he sits down on the tripod of the Since the form of the dialogue is still employed
muse, is not in his right mind; like a fountain, he and no speaker can be identified with the author,
allows to flow out freely whatever comes in, and it is impossible to say that Plato's opinions are
his art being imitative, he is often compelled to absolutely laid down. I find it impossible to think
represent men of opposite dispositions, and thus that the Athenian who takes the chief part, for
to contradict himself; neither can he tell whether Socrates no longer appears, is Plato himself, or at
there is more truth in one thing that he has said least represents more than aspects of Plato's mind.
than in another. (Laws IV, 719) The comic picture of eminent generals and states-
men solemnly reciting bad verses is hardly to be
The poet cannot, therefore, be a legislator, explained as the serious opinion of a man who
for a legislator must not give two rules knew and loved Homer as Plato did.18
about the same thing. These passages about Yet Plato has already admitted in the Re-
inspiration say little about what poetry is. public X that Homer is "the first and great-
Plato stresses the poet's ignorance even est of the tragic poets." But truth must not
while accepting his divine calling. be sacrificed for personal satisfaction: "if
Plato admits that beauty in all its forms the dramatic poetry whose end is to give
has a profound effect on the soul. He
pleasure can show good reason why it
stresses, however, that only the beauty of should exist in a well-governed society, we
virtue and of knowledge does not lead to for our part should welcome it back, being
the impure enjoyment of pleasure. Except ourselves conscious of its charm; only it
for the early training and discipline of the
would be a sin to betray what we believe to
soul through harmony, poetry does not lead be the truth. You too, my friend, must have
directly to an understanding of proper con- felt this charm, above all when poetry
duct. The poet cannot possess knowledge of
what he does unless he becomes a philoso- speaks through Homer's lips" (X, 606). Of
course Plato is charmed. But he does not on
pher too. The poet himself is usually the this account accept disruptive poetry into a
passive agent of the Muse; the inexplicable well-run state.
beauty of poetry comes from its divine ori- Rather than question the Laws, however,
gin. But when Plato looks at the poet's own most critics agree that here Plato offers a
contribution to the process, he finds the
serious theory of art. Warry states that "in
poet only an unlearned imitator. Plato's the Laws, which, though it lacks the literary
doctrine of divine inspiration applies more
power of the Republic, offers us a far saner
to his theory of love than to his concept of and more practical version of an ideal
poetry. The Phaedrus and the Symposium State, no automatic criterion of poetry and
suggest an affinity between the soul and art is offered. Instead, tragedy and comedy
beauty with which the doctrine of the are cautiously admitted, subject to
Forms does not completely agree. Refer- reservation." 19 Grube agrees that "by far
ences to poetic inspiration, however, are al- the most mature, as well as the most com-
most a dead end; Plato does not attempt to
plete, discussion of art, is to be found in the
integrate this inspiration with his main Laws, where it should be noted we are no
thought on poetry and language. In no longer dealing with the ideal state." 20 Just
place in the dialogues does Plato consider as a man at the north pole can move only
what poetry is together with its source in
south, any variation in the perfect Republic
the Muse. Thus Plato's occasional refer- must be for the worse. The less visionary
ences to poetic inspiration do not constitute
Laws, however, seems to allow as much po-
a significant approval of poetry itself.
Besides considering the theory of poetic etry as needed to regulate the souls of im-
perfect men.
inspiration, critics may emphasize the dia- But Plato's treatment in the Laws is at
logues which admit some ethical uses of po- heart almost exactly the same as in the Re-
etry. Indeed, only the Republic X seems to public. Both admit only praises of noble
deny even the possibility of good poetry. men and of gods; neither dialogue allows
Plato's strictures in the few places where he evil in poetry. Both the Republic (III, 400)
directly considers poetry seem overweighed and the Laws (VII, 810) allow poetry to
by his overall attitude toward the art of the stimulate harmony in the young. And even
ancients. Gilbert comments on the Laws: the Republic X, 606 states that "we can

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Plato's Banishment of Poetry 215
admit into our commonwealth only the po- grasped through the emotions. Neverthe-
etry which celebrates the praises of the gods less, Plato then seems to permit poetry to
and of good men." The Laws would require reenter the state precisely under the same
the poet to "express, as he ought, by fair conditions as in Books II and III. Since
and noble words, in his rhythms, the fig- Plato feels that he has banished poetry, his
ures, and in his melodies, the music of tem- admission of didactic verse must have little
perate and brave and in every way good resemblance to what he deems to be poetry.
men" (II, 660). The major difference be- The combination of his censure of poetry
tween the dialogues is that the Republic with his "poetic" style creates a problem of
defends this restriction philosophically interpretation, but the confusion is ours,
while the Laws is more concerned with im- not Plato's.
plementing the selection of such noble po- The Republic X is central to any discus-
etry. The art Plato seems to accept, how- sion of Plato's aesthetics, both for its inher-
ever, is not actually poetry, but philosophi- ent philosophy and for its historical impor-
cal and didactic discourse. tance. Without this book, most critics
The argument so far has been essentially would take little offense at Plato's insistence
negative. The Republic cannot be dis- on the moral judgment of poetry. The ear-
missed as an "ideal," nor do Plato's com- lier parts of the Republic and most of the
ments elsewhere constitute an endorsement Laws present a fairly acceptable attack on
of poetic inspiration or of ethical poetry. obviously immoral poetry and on foolish
His mistrust of poetry obviously exists side misinterpretations by the uneducated. His
by side with his love of poetry. The task epistemological attacks on poetry and his
remaining is to see whether Plato's reasons ad hominem attack on Homer in Book X,
for banishing poetry are consistent and well however, have seldom appealed to readers.
thought out. If the Laws and the Republic Critics are at loggerheads over the role of
do indeed contain the same attitude toward the tenth book in the dialogue as well as its
art, the discussion of poetry in the Republic content. Cornford states in his translation
X should apply equally to both dialogues. of the Republic that "the attack on poetry
The Republic X, the source of most of the in this Part has the air of an appendix, only
controversy over Plato's aesthetics, alone superficially linked with the preceding and
contains his explicit expulsion of poetry. In following context. Possibly the strictures on
this book, he first considers poetry's mis- dramatic poetry in Chapter IX had become
leading of the intellect, then its catering to known and provoked criticism to which
the emotions. Poetry is guilty of both offen- Plato wished to reply." 21 Havelock, on the
ses. In 595-99 Plato argues that a carpenter other hand, states that "an author possess-
follows a divine form in making a bed, and ing Plato's skill in composition is not likely
an artist copies that imitation. Plato then to blunt the edge of what he is saying by
explicitly analyzes the analogy between the allowing his thought to stray away from it
painter and the poet. At this point he seems at the end." 22 Both agree that the discus-
to leave room for poetry which encourages sion of poetry is a break in the argument of
virtue and restraint as he has suggested in Republic IX and the Myth of Er.
the second and third books of the Republic. The first books of the Republic are tenta-
But Plato then extends his attack to all po- tive positions in Plato's study of man and
etry in the Republic X, 601-7. Poetry, by the state. Plato's comments on poetry are
stimulating the emotions, confuses the in- not extreme here; his ideals obviously re-
tellect. Although he does not advance new semble those in the Laws. But scholars have
arguments concerning poetry's effect on the often debated the exact relationships be-
emotions, the previous four books have in- tween these first thoughts on poetry and the
troduced a theory of the soul which renders final statement in the tenth book of the
poetry, an appeal to the soul directly dialogue. One argument maintains that
through beauty, largely unnecessary. The Plato was serious in the first part; in the
soul's perception of beauty is to be me- last book he is stretching the point. Plato's
diated through knowledge, not immediately argument may carry him further than he

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
216 MORRISS HENRY PARTEE

would willingly go: "In X. there is an un- about is not the kind of thing we identify
mistakable trace of sophistry, a use of argu- today as poetry. Or more properly that his
ments which cannot have appealed to the poetry and our poetry may have a great
better judgment of the writer; the reason- deal in common, but that what must have
ing in II. and III. is direct, serious, and changed is the environment in which po-
convincing.... In the latter book he seems etry is practised. Somehow, Plato is talking
to be seeking strictly philosophical consider- about an over-all cultural condition which
ations to support the verdict of the earlier no longer exists." 26 A. E. Taylor, however,
passage, to be trying to show that this al- would extend Plato's attack to poetry for
most a priori conclusion is in harmony with all times. "It is not the floridity of Timoth-
the great principles upon which the Repub- eus or Agathon which is the object of at-
lic rests." 23 Superficially, Plato does seem to tack, but the art of the Periclean age. We
change his position.24 In Book II he attacks are only throwing dust in our own eyes if
the content of contemporary poetry, in we suppose that Socrates wants merely to
Book III the form. Some more useful and repress the cheap music-hall and the garish
purified poetry would then be a possibility. melodrama, or the equivalents of freak
But Plato progressively develops the de- movements like Dada. He is seriously pro-
scription of the best state and of the ruler posing to censure just what we consider the
of that state. In the fourth book he dis- imperishable contributions of Athens to the
cusses the nature of the soul. In the tenth art and literature of the world, because he
book he shows the effects of the lesser holds that they have tendencies which are
beauty of poetry on the soul. The enlight- unfavourable to the highest development of
ened soul should contemplate the beauty of moral personality." 27 Plato saw too clearly
virtue directly. Knowledge, not the impure to confuse the degenerate art of his own
mixture of emotion and thought found in time with all possible art. If Plato's aesthet-
poetry, should guide man. Since the last ics comments only on a vanished social
part of the Republic was probably written situation, his thought has value only for the
much later than the earlier parts, we may antiquarian.
conjecture that the tenth book answers The Republic does not attack simply a
some contemporary objections to his pre- way of interpreting poetry. The position ex-
vious discussion of poetry.25 Plato states pressed in this dialogue goes beyond the
that "our commonwealth has many features reasoning in the Ion. Plato argues as if
which make me think it was based on very Homer himself were claiming authority,
sound principles, especially our rule not on not just the ignorant rhapsode. Yet, Corn-
any account to admit the poetry of dra- ford denies that Plato is interested in aes-
matic representation. Now that we have dis- thetics for its own sake in this book: "The
tinguished the several parts of the soul, it main object of attack, however, is the claim,
seems to me clearer than ever that such po- currently made by sophists and professional
etry must be firmly excluded" (X, 595). The reciters of the Homeric poems, that Homer
reason for the exclusion is that poetry may in particular, and in a less degree the trage-
injure minds which do not understand its dians, were masters of all technical knowl-
true nature. edge, from wagon-building or chariot-driv-
Critics not only disagree on the relation- ing to strategy, and also moral and religious
ship of the tenth book to the rest of the guides to the conduct of life." 28 In the Ion,
dialogue but they question the relevance of Plato has suggested that everyone, not just
his comments to any useful study of poetry. the professionals, interpreted poetry incor-
Havelock argues that the Republic does not rectly. So Plato attacks false literary criti-
launch a philosophical attack on the poets, cism in the Ion, but he extends his reason-
but rather proposes a social criticism. He ing in the Republic. Plato does not directly
states that the political framework of the mention in the Republic that the sophists
dialogue may be utopian, but Plato is seri- used poetry to bolster their effectiveness. In
ous about the role of poetry in education. fact, he even cites the sophists as his allies
"It is obvious that the poetry he is talking against the poets; Homer's authority chal-

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Plato's Banishment of Poetry 217
lenges that of Protagoras of Abdera and Sidney will stress poetry's effectiveness, its
Prodicus of Ceos (Republic X, 600). ability to move man's hardened heart, Plato
The Republic X itself shows that there demands as a prerequisite that there be
can be little doubt that Plato intended to complete clarity of the goals for mankind.
banish at least all "realistic" poetry from The effectiveness of language will follow di-
the well-run state. Carried to the extreme rectly from this vision of the absolute. Art
by Zeuxis and Apollodorus, realism was is inherently amoral, and thus is a poor
particularly liable to misinterpretation. guide to virtue. Poetry is liable to the same
Basing his argument on his doctrine of misinterpretation that Jonathan Swift sees
Forms, Plato states that there are three for satire. In the preface to Battle of the
realms of reality: the gods', the carpenters', Books, Swift declares that satire is a kind of
and the painters'. For instance, the divine glass in which beholders generally discover
maker creates the form of a bed. Then the everybody's face but their own. For this rea-
carpenter copies the form, and the painter son, satire receives a kind reception in this
imitates the copy of the bed. Thus, "the world, and very few are offended by it. Po-
work of the artist is at the third remove etry may confirm, but it seldom converts.
from the essential nature of the thing" (X, Plato could argue that the rational part of
597). Such art is banished, not for its abuse the soul receives little instruction from its
of the emotions, but for its confusing of the contemplation of the static picture of a cob-
intellect: bler at his trade. The painting might inci-
The art of representation, then, is a long way dentally be beautiful. But a man must have
from reality; and apparently the reason why there virtue and knowledge first; otherwise he re-
is nothing it cannot reproduce is that it grasps ceives not happiness but pleasure from
only a small part of any object, and that only an beauty.
image. Your painter, for example, will paint us
a shoemaker, a carpenter, or other workman, Nevertheless, Plato's condemnation of
without understanding any one of their crafts; realistic art need not apply to all art. As
and yet if he were a good painter, he might de- Havelock notes, mimesis is "truly a protean
ceive a child or a simple-minded person into word."29 Elsewhere in the dialogues, the
thinking his picture was a real carpenter, if he
showed it them at some distance. (Republic X, good man "imitates" the Form of virtue.
598) And as Sir Philip Sidney says in his Apolo-
gie for Poetrie, the poet "painteth not Lu-
Thus, anyone who claimed to be able to cretia whom he never saw, but painteth the
produce a copy of every trade must not be outward bewty of such a vertue."30 The
allowed in the state. Plato, of course, is artist need not be limited to
photographic
thinking of poetry and its claims for knowl- copying, the "creating" the world with a
edge it does not possess. It has been argued, mirror (X, 597). If a man can imitate the
reasonably enough, that a painter could not Form of virtue, the poet who copies his ac-
put knowledge of cobbling into a picture tions will be imitating that virtue. Plato
even if he were also an expert cobbler. To himself seems to admit a second kind of
this Plato might reply that, according to his imitation in the Republic
V, 472: "Then
theory of the division of labor found in the suppose a painter had drawn an
Ion and the Republic, no man can be a beautiful ideally
figure complete to the last touch,
good painter and a good cobbler at the would you think any the worse of him, if he
same time. The painter, like the poet, has could not show that a
person as beautiful as
no specific trade: all humanity is their prov- that could exist?" Plato admits that art
ince. But only the possessor of wisdom, the be true and poetry may contain may
great
philosopher, can understand what is right truths, but only as a possibility. Neverthe-
for man. Just as Sir Philip Sidney closely less, he does not explicitly allow the artist
identifies artist with philosopher, Plato this ability, and the Republic X seems to
makes the philosopher the supreme crafts- deny even the possibility. Plato does not
man. Sidney stresses the virtue of beauty, reconcile ignorant imitation in art with
Plato the beauty of virtue. true copying of the eternal forms. "Why
Whereas an apologist of poetry such as should not works of art be imitations in the

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
218 MORRISS HENRY PARTEE
same sense, expressing the Ideas in the cation of humanity only indirectly, if at all,
physical world, without the intermediate leads to a higher understanding:
model of that physical world itself? There
Then, instead of trusting merely to the analogy
is nothing in Plato's conception of the rela- from painting, let us directly consider that part
tionship between the two worlds which pre- of the mind to which the dramatic element in
cludes such an escape out of the difficulty. poetry appeals, and see how much claim it has to
There is, however, a very definite objection, serious worth. We can put the question in this
way. Drama, we say, represents the acts and for-
namely that he himself never says a word to tunes of human beings. It is wholly concerned
indicate anything of the kind." 31 Similarly, with what they do, voluntarily or against their
a critic cannot argue for Plato's acceptance will, and how they fare, with the consequences
of good and ethical poetry on the basis of which they regard as happy or otherwise, and
his admitting the divine origin of poetry. with their feelings of joy and sorrow in all these
experiences. (Republic X, 603)
Plato never makes this connection. Like-
wise, Plato's thought on the nature of po- These emotions are unsuitable for the
etry does not directly relate to his discus- stage, since displays of passion reveal a di-
sion of the use of poetry in the education of vided soul. Plato has previously argued that
the young. Critics may emphasize Plato's reason springs from within; "the impulses
sanction of language which produces har- driving and dragging the soul are engen-
mony, but they are liable to gloss over Pla- dered by external influences and abnormal
to's real objections to poetry itself. conditions" (Republic IV, 439).
Plato next attempts to prove that in fact So with the empiricism usually attributed
no physical art or language can capture the only to Aristotle, Plato points out the diffi-
eternal Forms. Art is seductive; only the culty in portraying a man of wisdom and
intellect can distinguish its true beauty moderation on the stage. Just as today
from mere pleasure, which art can power- when popular indifference to temperate
fully suggest. After banishing imitative po- characters calls for Amos to be superseded
etry for its liability of being misinterpreted, by Kingfish and Pogo by Albert, Plato
Plato discusses poetry which portrays men could observe in his own time that only
in action. Earlier in the Republic, Plato great emotions make characters interesting
had admitted the possibility that poetry can for the masses. "This fretful temper gives
stimulate harmony in the soul. If laments scope for a great diversity of dramatic rep-
are prohibited because they encourage soft- resentation; whereas the calm and wise
ness, perhaps descriptions of courage will character in its unvarying constancy is not
arouse the nobler spirit. Nevertheless, Plato easy to represent, nor when represented is it
wishes to extend his argument that poetry readily understood, especially by a promis-
is an imitation of an imitation. The conclu- cuous gathering in a theatre, since it is for-
sion toward which his discussion of realistic eign to their own habit of mind" (X, 604).
poetry has been leading is "that paintings Dramatic poets appeal to the forces which
and works of art in general are far re- undermine the reason and exalt the irra-
moved from reality, and that the element in tional. Plato makes no distinction between
our nature which is accessible to art and drama and epic; Homer is the greatest tra-
responds to its advances is equally far from gedian. Presented literally in either form,
wisdom" (X, 603). Both visual art and po- no human action is sufficient to inculcate
etry are condemned. Here Plato suggests an virtue.
obvious fact: the appreciation of art is not Plato ends the discussion of poetry in
exclusively a rational process. Few critics what seems at least to him to be a complete
would disagree although they might enlarge rejection of all except overtly didactic verse.
the province of the rational. One may dispute whether he has proven his
The subject of both painting and poetry point, but he himself is satisfied with his
is man's action and his earthbound for- reasoning:
tunes. Drama focuses on human beings
You must be quite sure that we can admit into
rather than on the Forms. Thus, the glorifi- our commonwealth only the poetry which cele-

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Plato's Banishment of Poetry 219
brates the praises of the gods and of good men. clearly saw that art tends to be amoral;
If you go further and admit the honeyed muse one's final response to beauty is emotional,
in epic or in lyric verse, then pleasure and pain
will usurp the sovereignty of law and of the prin- a reaction either of pleasure or of pain.
ciples always recognized by common consent as This emotional response should be con-
the best. (Republic X, 607) demned only when the "poetry" of lan-
As in the earlier books of the Republic and guage interferes with its truth. In reaction
in the Laws, Plato here admits the poetry to the claims of the sophists and of the
which praises gods and virtuous men. Epic rhapsodes, Plato insists that style is largely
and drama are too directly anthropocentric. irrelevant to meaning. Thus, his continual
Plato's theory of knowledge does not allow attention to style shows him in a quandary
him to develop a system of literary criticism about the necessity of being effective, yet
which would honor the presentation of hating the false effectiveness of the sophists.
Plato consistently admits encomia in every
strong emotions. But one might ask why he
does not group lyric poetry with encomia, discussion of poetry only because he does
for a well wrought eulogy of virtue may not banish language from his common-
wealth. Didactic poetry has the same role as
give pleasure. Presumably these encomia
need not resemble such lyric modes as the his dialogues do; discourse which points to-
Mixed Lydian or Hyperlydian, which have ward the Good is an integral part of the
already been censured.32 Indeed, pleasure perfect state. Yet all language, as it tends
and pain would not necessarily corrupt the towards poetry, is liable to misinterpre-
tation. Paul Friedlander argues that Plato
principles of his state, for an effective trib-
ute to "gods and good men" may cause intends his dialogues to be an example of
both delight and agony. But Plato here is the "art" allowed in the Republic. It is dif-
not concerned with the effectiveness of po- ficult to draw a stable character. "But did
not Plato represent, always and everywhere,
etry. Earlier in the Republic he has dis-
cussed the usefulness of poetry in promot- precisely this type of man in Socrates? In
the Phaedo, when Socrates sends away the
ing harmony in the souls of its hearers; the
last book simply states that the only safe women dissolved in sorrow and admonishes
and cheers the weeping friends? In the Sym-
poetry for this purpose is the obviously di-
dactic. posium, when the Logos defeats the danger
Plato's admission of any poetry at this of comic disorder and humiliation? ...
Thus it is even more clear than before that
point would seem to convict him of incon-
he claimed for himself the very place he
sistency either in his reasoning or in the
asked the tragic poets to vacate." 33 But one
example which his dialogues present. His
dialogues seldom confine themselves to might object that Plato has specifically ban-
ished lamentations. The dialogues are more
straighltforward praises of virtue; the de-
than sketches of Socrates; Plato may present
scription and dramatization of Socrates'
encounters resemble the art Plato has con- contradictory opinions or even praises of
demned. The earlier dialogues-the Char- immorality as shown by Callicles' speech in
mides, the Lysis, the Laches-show Socrates the Gorgias. Each dialogue falls under pre-
in deliberately inconclusive arguments. The cisely the same judgment that literature
Phaedrus contains a praise of selfish desire, does. Therefore, the Phaedo, moving as it
and the Symposium presents conflicting is, must suggest the truth lying beyond the
speeches on love. Thus, his own dialogues, physical scene, or Plato would insist that
with all their artistic power, must prove this dialogue too must be banished.
themselves to be "praises of the gods and of While Plato certainly regarded his dia-
good men." And conversely, these praises of logues as more suitable for the Republic
virtue must prove themselves as something than most contemporary poetry could be,
else than poetry. he would never wish to take the place of
An examination of Plato's view of the poets. The fault in Greek poetry was that
relationship of language and thought may the beauty of language tended to discour-
clarify his attitude toward poetry. Plato age thought. Indeed, Havelock stresses that

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
220 MORRISS HENRY PARTEE

Plato's fundamental objection to art is that rects man to his own inadequacy. Plato's
poetry in Athens represented a social con- focus on the transcendent suggests that lan-
sciousness rather than the individual guage can be the vehicle for man to escape
thought that Plato demanded. Rather than his earthbound existence. A modern man
questioning the meaning behind poetry, the usually lacks this mingled respect and frus-
Greeks were overwhelmed by its beauty. tration with language. A literary critic or a
Just as Socrates continually probed beyond linguist will focus on minute nuances of
the physical world, Plato would insist that style or syntax rather than on the meaning
the dialogues be points of departure for lying beyond the words. The poetry of
thought, not works of art in themselves. Greece, on the other hand, was essentially
To Plato, language is a living body of oral and for the most part intended for a
thought, philosophy being possible only in wide audience. The Republic itself was
the dialectic. Poetry errs in seeming to fix probably composed as "a matter of oral
knowledge in order to pass it down from teaching in the school."36 The written
age to age. Drama and epic, as written and word to Plato, therefore, follows from the
established by the beloved ancients, inter- heat of discourse. To use a phrase of Toyn-
fere with the process of reasoning, for the bee, the dialogues of Plato resemble a type-
beauty of language tends to obscure the script, the basis for "winged words."
beauty of thought. Precisely because of the Both the written word and the language
dual role of language as the vehicle of of poetry have the property of fixing the
thought and as the source of mere pleasure, logos, of establishing an idea rather than
the poet in Plato struggles constantly letting thought range freely. In illiterate so-
against the philosopher. "Again and again cieties, memory takes the place of writing,
Plato's written work is mimesis; but it and words such as those of Homer can be
struggles against being nothing but mime- transmitted with great accuracy for genera-
sis. And where it seems to represent most tions. Thus Plato questions the worth of
strongly a pure work of art, it must not any language, written or orally recited, not
ultimately be read as such, but as an 'exis- immediately involved with philosophical
tential' document, that is, with the constant reasoning. This probing extends to his own
reminder tua res agitur." 34The gifted liter- dialogues. "There is no doubt that Plato, in
ary style of the dialogues shows that Plato, Ihis early and even in his later years, was
like the sophists, was aware that philosophy conscious of the problematic nature of all
must be effective. But Plato will not com- writing and that he did not believe he had
promise the truth in any way for the sake of said the most serious things in his written
mere effectiveness. Didactic verse is permit- work, that is, in what has come down to us
ted in the Republic because such language and what we are often inclined to regard as
is not poetry at all. Like the bad verse he his greatest creation, and perhaps the great-
seems to sanction in the Laws, literature in est achievement of Greek genius." 37 Plato,
the Republic must never sacrifice truth on of course, took his dialogues seriously. But
the altar of pleasure and emotional appeal. precisely because of his seriousness, he feels
As Havelock suggests, poetry and lan- that language is a poor vehicle to describe
guage had a different role in Athenian so- his vision of the Good. This gulf between
ciety from that which art has in our own. language and thought explains part of Pla-
Rhetoricians such as Isocrates and Alkida- to's great effectiveness: his use of myths to
mas debated the proper uses of the written suggest meaning that words cannot reveal.
language. In Greece the written word did Plato's attack on poetry comments elo-
not have the authority which such estab- quently on the way he intends his dialogues
lished language now possesses.35 Our atten- to be interpreted. Superficially, the Repub-
tion to static language derives in part from lic seems to have all of the qualities which
the Hebraic tradition of veneration of sa- Plato condemns in poetry. Not only does
cred writings. The Judeo-Christian empha- the dialogue have allegories, myths, dra-
sis on the fixed language of revelation redi- matic situations, and the presentation of

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Plato's Banishment of Poetry 221
contrary opinions but immediately after does indicate his interest in continuing the
Plato's attack on imaginative literature dialectic. The truth will emerge from the
comes the Myth of Er. This flight of fancy confrontation of Plato's attack and the
does not make Plato a poet, for myths in poet's defense, not from an uncritical ac-
Plato never stop with their literal state- ceptance of the philosopher's words.
ment. The myths claim no more authority In short, Plato's condemnation of imagi-
for themselves than does Socrates in his fa- native literature in the Republic X is con-
mous profession of ignorance. Praises of the sistent with his attack on empty rhetoric
gods and of noble men are allowed in the and misguided literary criticism. His state-
state because they are not poetry, poetry ments about inspiration and the ethical
being language beautiful in itself. Plato ac- uses of poetry, while historically important,
cepts any language which teaches the soul do not contradict his insistence that lan-
to ascend the ladder of the dialectic. Pla- guage must at all times point the way to
tonic dialogues or encomia may serve this virtue. Plato's frequent quotations from po-
purpose. The Republic would be allowed etry and his own masterful style show a
in the well-run state until someone mistak- powerful response to the charm of lan-
enly turned to study the dialogue as a repos- guage. But as he says, "We must take a
itory of beauty and knowledge rather than lesson from the lover who renounces at any
as the vehicle of winged words. Plato's re- cost a passion which he finds is doing him
luctance to claim undue authority for his no good" (X, 607). Certainly, Plato loved
dialogues extends even to his wry profession beauty, and especially the beauty of poetry.
of willingness in the Republic X, 607-8 to Nevertheless, poetry, as beautiful language,
hear a defense of poetry. His admission of had to be banished from the well-run state
the beauty of poetry does not constitute a for its ethical as well as for its intellectual
sudden change of heart; his seeming impar- dangers.
tiality here has overtones of further con- A few concluding generalizations may
tempt for contemporary poetry. "Indeed, put the problem in perspective. One must
the terms in which he makes the concession admit that Plato's aesthetics is not fully de-
to poetry, to plead her case if she chooses, veloped in the dialogues. While his thought
are themselves damning. For he treats her reveals a surprising unity for such a varied
in effect as a kind of prostitute, or as a approach to philosophy, Plato almost al-
Delilah who may seduce Plato's Samson if ways considers art as incidental to some
he lets her, and so rob him of his other study. By evaluating poetry only in
strength." 38 Although he has strongly felt terms of its immediate ethical and intellec-
thle charm of Homer, Plato insists that it tual effects, Plato closes the door to any
would be a sin to betray the truth: "It is metaphysical or formalist criticism. His as-
fair, then, that before returning from exile sumptions concerning the soul might be
poetry should publish her defense in lyric called into question; the treatment of po-
or some other measure; and I suppose we etry rests on his analysis of the tripartite
should allow her champions who love po- soul. Plato largely denies the importance of
etry but are not poets to plead for her in the lesser elements, for the spirited and the
prose, that she is no mere source of pleasure appetitive elements must always be subordi-
but a benefit to society and to human life" nate to the rational. Whereas the dialectic
(Republic X, 607). Plato declares that he appeals primarily to the rational element,
will be disposed to accept the worth of po- poetry appeals chiefly to the emotion,
etry, but the arguments already given may whether to the nobler passions or to the
serve "as a counter-charm to save us from senses. Such dialogues as the Phaedrus and
relapsing into a passion which most people the Symposium have, of course, suggested
have never outgrown." Accordingly, his re- that love and beauty can lift the soul in its
sponse to any defense will probably be that contemplation of virtue. But Plato does
"such poetry has no serious claim to be val- not, in his final analysis, allow poetry to
ued as an apprehension of truth." Yet he strengthen the rational element through

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
222 MOR RISS HENRY PARTEE

the direction of the well-disciplined spirited 8 Eric A. Havelock, Preface to Plato (Cambridge,

element. In the Phaedrus 253-4, the white Mass., 1963), p. 7.


9 See Meno 99.
horse, or the spirited part, does not guide 10Francis MacDonald Cornford, The Republic of
the charioteer, the rational element. Simi- Plato (New York, 1966), pp. 175-76. All quotations
larly, in the Republic V, 434-42, the spir- of the Republic will be taken from this edition.
ited element should help the rational to 11Havelock, p. 3.
12 The Dialogues of Plato, ed. Benjamin Jowett
subdue the appetite. But Plato does not
(New York, 1937). All references to dialogues other
show how this partnership is to be formed than the Republic will be taken from this transla-
and strengthened. tion.
Plato might admit that poetry may ide- 13Plato: The Man and His Work (London, 1927),
ally present its own golden world, but he p. 265.
14"Did Plato Banish the Poets or the Critics?"
would insist that poetry in the world of SP 36 (1939): 19.
philosophic questioning gives us beauty 15 See A. E. Taylor, p. 38.
rather than truth. The lover of wisdom 16Paul Shorey, What Plato Said (Chicago, 1962),
seeks only the beauty of virtue and knowl- p. 355.
17 Rucker, p. 170.
edge, not the lesser beauty of language. 18Literary Criticisnm:Plato to Dryden, ed. Allan
This vision, as Diotima describes it in the Gilbert (Detroit, 1964), p. 55.
Symposilum 210, is ineffable; she doubts 19J. G. Warry, Greek Aesthetic Theory (London,
that even Socrates can reach this height. 1962), p. 64.
20 Grube, p. 196.
But Plato must still wrestle with the almost 21Cornford, p. 321.
insurmountable problem of what means 22Havelock,
p. 3.
one can use to describe this realm. Poetry is 23Carleton Lewis Brownson, Plato's Studies and
an important battleground for Plato's di- Criticisms of the Poets (Boston, 1920), p. 97.
vergent approaches to beauty and to knowl- 24See J. Tate, "'Imitation' in Plato's Republic,"
edge, but his treatment of poetry is too per- CQ 22 (1928): 16-23 and "Plato and 'Imitation,''"
CQ 26 (1932): 161-69.
sonal, too fragmented to be fully resolved 25 See Shorey, p. 248.
by us or even by Plato himself. The scraps 26 Havelock, p. 10.
scattered throughout the dialogues only 27
Taylor, pp. 279-80.
whet the appetite. His aesthetics shows us 28 Cornford, p. 322.
not a banquet of thought, but a hunger. 29 Havelock,p. 30.
30Sir Philip Sidney, Prose Works, ed. Albert Feuil-
lerat (Cambridge, 1963), III, 10.
31 Grube,
p. 202.
32 See
1 The Schoole of Abuse, ed. Edward Arber (Lon- Republic III, 398.
don, 1868), p. 20. 33Paul Friedlander, Plato: An Introduction (New
2Augustine, Basic Writings, ed. York, 1964), p. 121.
Whitney J. Oates,
34 Friedlander, p. 124.
2 (New York, 1948): 42.
3 "Plato and the Poets," JAAC 25 (1966): 167. 35See Arnold Toynbee, Civilization on Trial (New
4 G. M. A. Grube, Plato's Thought (London, 1935), York, 1958), pp. 47-54.
p. 189. 36 Gilbert Murray, Greek Studies (Oxford, 1946),
5 Rucker, p. 167. p. 37.
6 See Republic V, 487-91. 37Friedlander, p. 118.
7 Theaetetus 174. 38
Havelock, p. 5.

This content downloaded from 193.255.248.150 on Thu, 8 Jan 2015 14:13:15 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like