You are on page 1of 6

Deflating Psychiatric Classification

Claudio E. M. Banzato

Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, Volume 16, Number 1, March 2009,


pp. 23-27 (Article)

Published by Johns Hopkins University Press


DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.0.0213

For additional information about this article


https://muse.jhu.edu/article/316643

Access provided by UFF-Universidade Fed Fluminense (16 Jun 2018 21:29 GMT)
Deflating
Psychiatric
Classification
Claudio E. M. Banzato

Keywords: nosography, comorbidity, utility, prag- By working well, classifications eventually tend
matism to become invisible. They end up looking just
natural, as if they were carved by nature itself. But
indeed purpose is the touchstone here. Even if a

S
ystems of classification bring order into given class of objects fully qualifies as a ‘natural
the world. They are a key part of the infor- kind’ and necessary and sufficient criteria for class
mational working infrastructure of the world membership can be definitely established, it does
we inhabit (Bowker and Star 1999). Thus, much of not entail that it constitutes the best way to clas-
the human interaction hinges on these ordering— sify these objects irrespective of the context. Peter
pattern identifying and creating—systems. Formal Zachar (2002) offers a compelling example from
or informal, standardized or ad hoc, visible or natural sciences, the utmost practical importance
invisible, enforced or optional, there are a myriad of distinguishing between hydrogen and its iso-
of classifications we necessarily live by. topes (hydrogen, deuterium, and tritium). In this
Typically, classifications convey representations case, the classificatory thrust stretches beyond the
of states of affairs to make interventions on them shared atomic number. In his words, “A crucial
feasible and, to some extent, predictable. In other factor in recognizing them as distinct is that they
words, classificatory systems and schemes try to are used in distinct activities and practices. We
confer intelligibility to the world. By succeeding get a better neutron bounce with heavy water or
in such task, they may provide rational grounds D2O. Deciding what aspects of internal structure
to human operation on reality (toward the most are important therefore cannot be isolated from
diverse ends). This account fully applies to medical external factors.” (p. 220)
classifications, which struggle to sort out all kinds In contemporary psychiatry, diagnostic classi-
of diseases, ailments, complaints, and sufferings fication has been center stage for several reasons.
that can possibly be targeted by medical interven- But before addressing them, however, a brief his-
tions. This means classifications are instrumental torical detour is necessary. Back in the nineteenth
to the ends pursued by medicine, quintessential century, putting forward a new classification of
modificatory activity. In sum, classifications are mental diseases was taken somewhat as a token
cognitive tools devised to build up knowledge by of psychiatric proficiency according to the witty
making relevant distinctions, which may prove remark by the French physician and publicist
helpful to guide human action. Philippe Buchez: “Upon believing that they have

© 2009 by The Johns Hopkins University Press


24  ■  PPP / Vol. 16, No. 1 / March 2009

completed their studies, rhetoricians will compose tions, many of which have a valuable function in
a tragedy and alienists a classification” (Ber- research and administration. Such classifications
rios 1999, 152). By the middle of the twentieth may stimulate the study of new relationships and
century, many psychiatric classifications (based thus advance knowledge. The only proviso to be
on diverse principles and underlying theoretical made for such classifications would be that they
orientations) were still used across the world. should be readily convertible into the international
The British psychiatrist Erwin Stengel (1959), in system” (Stengel 1959, 618–619). His caution-
his influential report on classification of mental ary motto about any international classification
disorders, pointed out that the issue of difficulty thus read: “It must be a servant of international
of communication was then the order of the day communication rather than its master” (Stengel
for psychiatry, because it was widely perceived as 1959, 618).
one of the most serious obstacles to the progress The realm of psychiatric classification changed
in the field. considerably within the last few decades. In some
The broad, worldwide survey carried out by key respects, Stengel did foresee several develop-
Stengel made it clear that classifications of all ments that eventually took place and brought
shapes were used in different contexts, but they us here, such as the move toward a descriptive
were seldom appealing outside the boundaries of (minimally inferential) and symptom-based classi-
the respective centers that generated them. Such di- fication, first materialized in American Psychiatric
versity of classifications reflected not only different Association (APA)’s Diagnostic and Statistical
functions or purposes they were meant to serve, Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM)-III (1980),
but also the role played by the history of a given a rule-based classification with explicit inclusion
problem within a particular medical tradition and and exclusion criteria for class membership. This
cultural background. Thus, Stengel’s aims for an approach had a massive, worldwide impact and
acceptable statistical international classification proved to be decisive for the internationalization
were relatively modest: it should simply ground of psychiatry. The DSM-III and its successors not
epidemiological work. only enjoyed a great acceptance (in the United
Stengel’s stance on classification was frankly States as well as in many other countries), but
pragmatic and utilitarian. He understood well the also ended up influencing the very development
difficulties posed by the ‘disease entity’ assump- of Chapter V (concerning mental and behavioral
tion in psychiatry and asked the straight question: disorders) of the official international classifica-
“Firstly, what do we classify in this field? Are we tion, the World Health Organization (WHO)’s
classifying diseases or people?”, to which he of- International Classification of Diseases (ICD)-10
fered a compromised answer: “It may be said that (1992). Although the implementation of the ICD-
the material the psychiatrist has to classify consists 10 is still rather incomplete and little is known
neither of diseases nor of people but of a variety about its everyday use by psychiatrists and other
of disorders or reactions, a material which does mental health workers—and its actual impact on
not readily lend itself to classification” (Stengel the quality of clinical care delivered across the
1959, 612). For him, the pursued agreement on world—it seems reasonable to acknowledge that
the interpretation of psychiatric concepts for the psychiatry has achieved its long-awaited ‘com-
sake of diagnosis and classification should basi- mon language,’ even if with two quite distinctive
cally serve the purpose of communication. accents—the APA’s and the WHO’s.
A key aspect of Stengel’s recommendation, It is likely that the current prominence of diag-
surprising as it may sound nowadays in this age nostic classifications would surprise Stengel. In a
of global psychiatry, is that an international clas- way, his best expectations in the late 1950s were
sification should not impose itself and replace all surpassed, but such a complete reversal of trends
the others in use: “It should not be the purpose of raised problems of its own. Indeed, it was not all
an international psychiatric classification to oust about gains. So one should ask how did we get
and to take the place of regional or local classifica- here and at what costs? Addressing these issues
Banzato / Deflating Psychiatric Classification   ■  25

should help to clarify the centrality of psychiatric However, several objections may be construed
classifications nowadays. against his account. First, the controversy around
In the 1960s and 1970s, the problem of lack nosography of mental disorders has never ap-
of reliability of the diagnostic concepts continued peased; despite the huge success of such enterprise,
to vex psychiatrists. Clearly, this also contributed the DSM has had to face its many foes along
to fuel the antipsychiatric criticism (from varied the way. Thus, it may be argued that the DSM
extraction and degrees of sophistication) both of represented just a compromised pragmatic agree-
social and medical legitimacy of such specialty. ment about the next steps among psychiatrists
In response to this long-standing controversy, the who otherwise had little in common; so at best
DSMs operated an empiricist turn, making a move it should count as a surrogate for a disciplinary
toward grounding classifications on scientific matrix. Second, it is doubtful whether there was
empirical evidence, so diagnostic categories could a period of ‘normal’ science within DSM frame-
function as working testable hypotheses. There work in the last three decades. For instance, has
was an explicit bet that ensuring reliability would psychiatry since the 1980s actually undergone
pave the way for validating diagnostic concepts. a period of scientific stability? Third, although
Thus, the underlying hope was that provisory the adoption of rule-based classifications and the
conventional criterial definitions would eventu- agreement on explicit diagnostic criteria led to a
ally give way to independent invariants, taken definite research program, the DSM’s utter rejec-
as ‘core’ or ‘essential property’ of the nosologic tion of theory makes it a bit far fetching to use
unities, such as some sort of ‘causal bedrock’ ‘paradigm’ in the Kuhnian technical sense of the
(etiology or pathophysiological pathways), by term. After all, which was the prevailing theory
means of which a sufficiently robust explanation that worked well in the recent past but now is
of a given class of objects could then be provided. failing? Fourth, comorbidity is widely recognized
Within this framework, diagnostic categories were as a byproduct of the DSM’s predominantly split-
expected to end up mirroring natural and discrete ting taxonomic strategy. And it may well be an
morbid entities. Therefore, a scientific classifica- undesirable feature for many reasons, especially
tion of mental disorders was bound to become a when the rates of comorbidity empirically found
naturalistic nosologic map. are considered too high. But, again, that does not
Because the DSM-III proved to be very influ- mean it is a truly Kuhnian ‘anomaly,’ because it
ential and created great expectations about the is actually an anticipated side effect of the initial
prospective empirical validation of diagnostic setup, not some unexpected discovery that might
categories, it seems fair to take the DSMs (since challenge an otherwise successful account of the
the 1980s) as a sort of disciplinary matrix of behavior of objects. In sum, the comorbidity is-
psychiatry, which means they embodied a set of sue may indeed be irresolvable given the DSM
underlying assumptions, beliefs, and values even- premises and commitments (according to the case
tually shared by most psychiatrists (for an in-depth made by Aragona), but it is hardly an ‘anomaly’ in
analysis of DSM value commitments, see Sadler the sense of a violation of the paradigm-induced
[2005]). The fact is that DSM-informed practice expectation. It strikes me as inconsistent and odd
became mainstream psychiatry for the purpose to treat comorbidity at the same time as artifactual
of research and clinical care. Thus, perhaps one byproduct and as anomaly.
may treat, like Aragona actually does in this issue Nevertheless, irrespective the word chosen to
of PPP, the DSM as a ‘paradigm’ in the Kuhnian qualify it, Aragona aptly frames the comorbidity
sense. Aragona even takes a step further and issue by outlining its several intertwined concep-
suggests that this ‘DSM paradigm’ has entered a tual underpinnings and by convincingly showing
period of scientific crisis, for reasons he addresses that such problem cannot be solved merely by
in his article, namely the comorbidity issue vis-à- means of the usual empirical research. The very
vis the conflicting philosophical commitments of ‘disease entity’ assumption is deeply implicated in
DSM authors. the discussion of ‘intraparadigmatic’ and ‘revolu-
26  ■  PPP / Vol. 16, No. 1 / March 2009

tionary’ solution strategies proposed by Aragona. an improper use of it. For instance, psychiatrists
Also, aesthetic and practical considerations seem quite often fail to apprehend the implications of a
to play a role in such choice: the underlying ideal criterial definition, which is conventional but not
of parsimony and neatness held by psychiatrists arbitrary. Furthermore, the caveat that diagnostic
must be taken into account. categories are just practical tools is frequently
It would be simply naïve to believe that a ignored in daily practice, to the dismay of the
DSM-like undertaking would suffice to provide nosologists who build these tools. Some examples
psychiatry with sound conceptual grounds. From and consequences of such inept handling of clas-
the fact that psychiatric classificatory systems sificatory systems follow.
reflect key conceptual issues, it does not follow First, it is way too common that psychiatrists
that any given classification should qualify as (often to their own professional benefit) speak
a replacement for psychopathological theory. about diagnostic categories as clearcut diseases
Bottom line, classifications perform a practical that have been fully elucidated, grossly overesti-
demarcatory role in psychiatry: the limits of pro- mating the existing knowledge about them. Sec-
fessional responsibility and the accountability for ond, in clinical routine, disorders are improperly
suffering depend to a large extent on the diagnostic taken as causes of symptoms (‘these symptoms
options available, as well as on the way diagnostic are due to that disorder’ [Scadding 1990]), which
constructs are conceptualized and classified. Thus, betrays deeply rooted ontological assumptions
their paramount pragmatic importance, echoing about the nature of mental disorders. Third, the
William James (1907) pragmatist formula: “There reification of diagnostic categories may hinder
can be no difference anywhere that doesn’t make research because alternative models are seldom
a difference elsewhere—no difference in abstract empirically tested; even though diagnostic catego-
truth that doesn’t express itself in a difference in ries can be legitimately thought of as hypothetical
concrete fact and in conduct consequent upon that constructs, they are ordinarily taken for granted
fact, imposed on somebody, somehow, somewhere, in most empirical studies, which means that they
and somewhen” (p. 144). count as part of the necessary background to test
The purpose of any classification: there is where other kind of hypotheses, but are rarely tested
the rub lies. So far, within the DSM framework, themselves against alternative options. Fourth,
a single classification should serve many masters clinical encounter may be significantly constrained
and purposes (clinical care, research, and teaching, when diagnosis is reduced to just subsuming pa-
to mention just those explicitly acknowledged in tient’s symptoms to the general types included in
the manual). But one may ask whether or not such the manual. After all, a classification should serve
ambition is attainable? If any given classification the diagnostic process, not the other way around.
is built out of the necessity of accommodating So the achievement of a psychiatric classification
very diverse end purposes, it would come to no must be measured by the benefits actually brought
surprise if the several assumptions and commit- to its diverse stakeholders: clinicians, researchers,
ments held in good faith by their authors could administrators, policy makers and, especially,
not be fully conciliated. Perhaps one might even patients and their families.
adapt (by replacing ‘truths’ by ‘purposes’) the Thus, regarding the discussion of the ‘third
piercing Jamesian adage to read ‘the greatest en- intraparadigmatic solution’ (the complete liber-
emy of any one of our purposes may be the rest alization of comorbidity), an important issued
of our purposes.’ is raised by Aragona: the diverse impact it might
Another key distinction concerns the intrinsic have on researchers and clinicians. In this scenario,
reach and limitations of a classification and the he foresees an eventual divorce of clinical practice
way it is actually used in practice. It is crucial from the DSM classification rules (an occurrence
to separate failures or dissatisfactions with a one may infer he disapproves of). What Aragona
given diagnostic system that are due to the faulty does not consider in his article, however, is the
instrument itself from those that are caused by very possibility of having separate classifications
Banzato / Deflating Psychiatric Classification   ■  27

to serve different stakeholders and purposes. By deflating psychiatric classification it is meant


So a key question, and not just for the sake of that the conceptual framework of the discipline
handling comorbidity, is this: should we build should become less dependable on nosographic
one single classification or several? A potentially issues. Of course, alternative nosologic approaches
serious drawback of a ‘one-size-fits-all’ approach such as, for instance, those mentioned by Aragona
is that the interests and needs of the different in the concluding remarks of his article (spectrum,
stakeholders of classificatory systems may not fully dimensional diagnosis, and etiopathogenic classifi-
coincide. Actually, in that regard, WHO (ICD: cations) can and should be empirically tested, and
family of classifications) and APA (DSM: single not just for the sake of overcoming the problem
classification) have not adopted the same strategy. of comorbidity. But perhaps instead of taking
Again, pragmatic considerations play a key role. the competition between them as a ‘battle of
Arguably, part of the appeal of the DSM is that paradigms,’ it would be more accurate to describe
everything comes in a single volume. This certainly this simply as an attempt to do better justice to
enhances the chance of having its content known the highly complex task of conceptualizing psy-
and mastered. As a matter of fact, the several chopathology for a myriad of purposes, which in
versions of Chapter V of the ICD-10 family of itself does require methodological and explanatory
classifications (for research, for primary care, the pluralism; so combinations of models are to be ex-
multiaxial presentation for adults, the multiaxial pected. Theoretical openness is a condition for us
presentation for children and adolescents, etc.) to build on the gains brought by current systems.
launched successively after the inaugural volume Besides, I think full consideration of the diversity
(clinical description and diagnostic guidelines), of their several stakeholders’ real-life needs should
by different publishing houses, have not as yet inform the development of the next generation of
enjoyed widespread popularity. psychiatric classifications.
I suspect that issues such as ‘conciliating the
many purposes of a classification,’ ‘having one References
classification or several,’ and ‘addressing diverse Aragona, M. 2009. The role of comorbidity in the crisis
of the current psychiatric classification system. Phi-
needs of different stakeholders’ seldom receive
losophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 16, no. 1:1–11.
due attention in the literature because current Berrios, G. E. 1999. Classifications in psychiatry: A
diagnostic classifications have crystallized as the conceptual history. Australian and New Zealand
cornerstone of psychiatric practice. This situation Journal of Psychiatry 33:145–160.
is understandable given the difficulties of commu- Bowker, G. C., and S. L. Star. 1999. Sorting things out:
nication faced in the past and the recurrent attacks Classifications and its consequences. Cambridge,
on the medical identity of psychiatry. After all, it MA: MIT Press.
James, W. 1907. What pragmatism means. In Essays
is nice to have a neat document to display as a
in pragmatism, ed. A. Castell, 1959, 141–158. New
proof of the scientific maturity achieved by the York: Hafner Publishing Company.
discipline. But a classification is supposed to be a Sadler, J. Z. 2005. Values and psychiatric diagnosis.
tool, not a straitjacket. There are plenty of fasci- Oxford: Oxford University Press.
nating and challenging problems in psychiatry— Scadding, J. C. 1990. The semantic problem of psychia-
both theoretical and clinical—that, despite being try. Psychological Medicine 20:243–248.
germane to the classification of mental disorders, Stengel, E. 1959. Classification of mental disor-
ders. Bulletin of the World Health Organization
cannot be reduced to such aspect nor dealt with
21:601–663.
in a merely nosographic fashion. Hence, the claim Zachar, P. 2002. The practical kind model as a pragma-
that psychiatry would be better off if we started tist theory of classification. Philosophy, Psychiatry,
doing what is suggested in the title of this com- & Psychology 9, no. 3:219–227.
mentary.

You might also like