You are on page 1of 7

Art Education

ISSN: 0004-3125 (Print) 2325-5161 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/uare20

Problems Confronting Visual Culture

Arthur D. Efland

To cite this article: Arthur D. Efland (2005) Problems Confronting Visual Culture, Art Education,
58:6, 35-40, DOI: 10.1080/00043125.2005.11651567

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/00043125.2005.11651567

Published online: 21 Dec 2015.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 124

View related articles

Citing articles: 9 View citing articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=uare20
VIS B ~ R1 H U R D.

A new movement has app eared Lntil the advent of this movement, th e fine arts were
deemed the cen tral CO il' of the visual arts cu rricul um,
recommending, in part, that the field of art an d indwd. there haw been times in the history of art
ed ucation sho uld lessen its tradition al ties education w ben nn e art w a.s offered as the social
remedy prot ecting th e young from the It'SSsa\"(1)' influ -
to drawing, painting, and the study of master- ences of the po pular c ulture (Tavin, 2005). Ho w eve r, the
pieces to become the study ofvisual culture. recent advance ohisual cult ural st udies seemingly
standspoised to displa ce th e nne arts. If th e fine arts
(Freedman. (l)!17;Tavin, 2001; Duncur n, 200(2)' '.'jsll tl!
co mprise a s mall fract ion or the total ity covered by
('ultuml ,<iflll/./l re fers to an an-e ncompasstng category of
vi sual cultural s tu dies, s hould it co ntinue 10 re main th e
cultural prac tice t hat includes the lim' arts bUIalso
central foc us ortnstmcnon? Dot'S ft conti nue to have a
deals with the s tudy c rvariou, forms of popular cult ure:
role in educat ion and what might that he?
the folk tradit ions ofartmaking; industr ial, interior,
pa ckage and graphic design; photography; commercial So me proponents of visual culture advocate that
illustration; andthe entertainment media incl udi ng more time and reso urces s hould be expended to st udy
cinema, television, and their electro nic exterus io ns vta the arts of evel)' day life ( Duncu m. 200l) ra ther than 10
the co mput er and th e Internet. It th e fine arts. Freedman an d Stuhr, though rec ogruztng
includes th e design o f bu ilt the impo rtance o f Ilne art as a carrier -of
e nvironments in public spaces In particular, till' histo rical and co nte mporary cu lt ure,
s uch , L'O theme parks, fa.'>I. food neve rtheless conclude, "Fine art
rest aurants . and s hopping malls.
hierarchy that placed objects and 'good tast e' can no longer
The presence of these po tent fine art at the top of be seen as the only \i s ua1 cult ural
sources ohi...uaI imagt'ry has capital to servE'ele mentary, secondary,
challl{ed Anwrican culture and
the heap and popular o r- college level students," (2()()..I, p.
the li\,{'So ( r-hildn-n gru ",ing up in culture at the bollom 8 17). Hthe Iine arts no longer should
the midst ortht'Sl' innlH'n("t'S. play th e principal role in de termining
has largely been the content of lnstruetion, w hal takes
Ilo w ever.uw fit·ld of art
ed ucation has done liu lt' to abandoned. The its place and to .....hal purpose? Before
prepare children (0 deal wi th \his d('aling wi th th ese questions, I revie w
curriculum 0 IW I1pd some problems that mak e-the st udy of
on....laught. (Freedman & Stuhr;
2(X).I; Duncum. 2(02) its elf to a broader the vt sual arts difficult at \his moment,
array of co ntent,
especially as the
boundary line
separating the high
from the low became NOVEIIB ER 200S I U T ED UCA TI ON ..
less clear.
The Problem with Art and characterized by political neutrality. The fact that the
The problem with art is how to come to terms with its nature modernist avant-garde once had a radical agenda of its own
as a human endeavor, including how to identify its bounds. What seems to have been forgotten, and this despite the fact that its
purpose does it serve as a domain of practice especially when agenda was very much like that promoted by many proponents
the boundaries, which separate it from the everyday life-world, of visual cultural studies, today.'
are fading? In his book Beyond the Brillo Box, the philosopher
and critic, Arthur Danto (1992), describes the cultural landscape The Problem with Modernism
as a map that shows many regions bounded by various zones. Since the end of World War II new technological advances
One zone is the art world where the fine arts serve as its main were at work busily creating today's mass culture. The
preoccupation, while other regions include the mass media and modernist avant-garde threw itself into opposition' and champi-
the popular culture. But this map reveals an unusual cultural oned the ideal of high culture as the redeeming purpose of art.
situation, namely that the boundaries that once kept these zones Modem art was the high art of the future whereas the lower
apart have either disappeared or are in the process of erasure. forms of popular culture were labeled "kitsch," but by the late
The lines that once separated fine art from popular culture have 1970smodem art began losing its lofty sense of purpose. Its
either become imperceptible, or register as disputed territories optimism was replaced by exhaustion and irrationality (See
or sites of contestation. 2 Gablik, 1984). It began to lose its sense of entitlement and
privilege and was characterized as an elitist project by cultural
As Danto explained, starting in the 1960s,this series of
critics like Pierre Bourdieu, (cited in Johnson 2002, p. 112).In
erasures has all but eliminated these borders. Pop art eliminated
fact, the cultural relation of the "high arts" to the rest of society
the boundary between high art and low art; minimalism erased
had become one of the topics of inquiry that typified
the distinction between fine art and industrial process. The
postmodern discussions of the arts. In particular, the hierarchy
border separating mass-produced things from the images of fine
that placed fine art at the top of the heap and popular culture at
art housed in museums has disappeared from the landscape.
the bottom has largely been abandoned. The curriculum opened
Another is the distinction between objects appreciated as
itselfto a broader array of content, especially as the boundary
exemplars of cultivated taste and the objects of the ordinary
line separating the high from the low became less clear.
person's life-world, including comic strips, soup cans, and
cheeseburgers. No longer does art have to be beautiful or to Yet,with all the changes in culture brought on by the
resemble nature; indeed there is no longer any difference postmodern moment, the teaching of art still continues to be
between works of art and what Danto called "mere real things." guided by a modernist aesthetic orientation. The movement to
transform traditional art education into visual cultural studies is
Even more telling was his observation that "Youcannot tell
an attempt to align the teaching of art in school settings with
when something is a work of art just by looking at it, for there is
what is happening in the culture as a whole.
no particular way that art has to look" (Danto, p. 5, 1992). One
can no longer teach art simply by looking at examples. And so Visual Culture and Postmodernism
the question becomes, how does one teach the arts and what Visual cultural study became a curriculum movement within
does one teach? If fine art is indistinguishable from the rest of
professional art education with the onset of postmodernism as
the material culture, how does one define the limits of instruc- the last century was ending. The ternlpostmodemism is an
tional content? academic category concerned with develop-
Though proponents of visual culture ments in the arts in the late decades ofthe last
acknowledge the existence of fine art as a century. It soon became a descriptive term for
practice, they also describe it as a product all sorts of proposed shifts and changes in
from a bygone era (modernism) and are contemporary society and culture. With faith in
generally unconcerned with the task of progress seen as belonging to a modernist
teaching art as fine art in all its separate- period (1900-1960), the term "postmodernist"
ness and remoteness. Rather, the task is to began to describe the successor period as one
teach students to become critically of change, often characterized by disillusion-
attentive to the cultural meanings that ment. As long as modernist optimism
visual images convey for the purpose of prevailed, the advance of "fine" or "high" art
understanding society and culture, was deemed an unquestioned good. Many, like
including how these images help create myself, once saw modernist practices like
the shared meanings we call culture. abstraction as progressive. Modernist architec-
Critical citizenship rather than the appreci- ture with its clean lines and its "less is more"
ation of a "stale canon of masterpieces" aesthetic felt like a breath of fresh air that
has become the objective (Tavin, 2001, transformed our cities with shiny new
p. 133). Modernism has become a term of buildings made of glass and steel. It is only in
opprobrium, a synonym for the status quo, retrospect that these gleaming skyscrapers

• ART EDUCATION / NOVEMBER 2005


becam e an architecture that grew to symb olize corporate A visual culture curriculum purports to place all objects on an
dominance. When I became an art teacher in the mid-1950s, I equal footing without favoritism and that to do otherwise leaves
struggl ed to teach an appreciation for modem art even though the educator open to the charge of an elitism that favors certai n
many deemed it a hoax or a communist conspiracy. kinds of art above the rest. The probl em is that many cultures in
Of course , mod emi sm was not without its flaws, and one was their collective judgment do take ce rtai n works to be more
its tendency to define the vario us dom ains of kno wledge as important than oth ers . The reasons for these judgments might
autonomous disciplines. Each discipline had its expertise, its vary, might include their religious, civic, or aesthetic values and
community of scholars, and methods for procuring knowledge. may involve issues of power, as many who favor visual culture
This was especially tru e in the sc iences but the arts and litera- insist.
ture followed this path as well. Each disciplin e promised to offer Because the study of works of art has for its central purpose
univers al knowledge, that is, knowledge not bound to any the critical understanding of the cultures or societies wherein
particular culture. such works originated, it is quite possible that one could very
However, unlike the sciences, the arts are bound to their well teach children to interpret cultures through a critical
cultures of origin. Typical talk about works of art or their reading of images from the mass medi a, without ever referring to
stylistic class ification cannot proceed without reference to such works from the genre of the fine arts of the sort traditionally
ethnic or cultural descriptors as "Japane se" prints , "Fre nch" encountered in museum s. In my view this is an unfortunate
Impressionist paintings , German romantic compose rs, the poss ibility.
"Italian Renaissance," "Pers ian" miniatures , or "Navajo" pottery.
Discussion of the cont ent of such works is also closely bound up Fine Art and its Continuing Importance
with the social context where thes e works have arisen. Looked Histori cally, fine art always stood for something extraordi-
at from this persp ective, the atte mpt to characte rize the arts as nary, so mething that transformed the world of the everyday and
freestand ing disciplines culminated in the movement known as the mundane. More than 30 years ago, the educational philoso -
Discipline-Based Art Education (DBAE) (Efland, 1988). The pher Maxine Greene presented a pap er on the topi c of popular
visual arts were set apart from the cultural influences that gave culture and the fine arts in education.' Her term for them was the
rise to them, and this was a grave error. Visual cultural studies "serious arts," a term that in my judgment is unfortunate since
in large part atte mpts to remedy this tend ency. the fme arts are not always serious. She included literature,
theatre, dan ce, and music as well as the visual arts in her discus-
Problems Affecting Visual Culture sion . In her view, if we teachers try to ignore or demean the
However, visual cultural studies as a movement has so me popul ar culture, if we insist on pr esenting se rious art to students
vexing att ributes that may limit its effectiveness as a new as the only respectable culture, our efforts will be received with
paradigm. No movement can arise without expe riencing some blank looks or cries of irrelevanc e.
difficulties or what might be called "grow ing pains" and visual Like Maxine, I know better than to argue that the fine arts ar e
culture is no exce ption. Two such difficulti es are its excessive better than the arts conveye d by the mass media and pop ular
breadth since the numb er of genres covered by programs in culture. However, they ar e different in purpose, and it is with
visual culture can become so enormous as to become unman- these ideas in mind that the case for their continued presence
ageable in the time allotted for teaching the arts. The she er can be made. Let me paraphrase a portion of Green e's argument.
numb er of topics available for coverage confounds the selection She claims that serious art opens up more possibilities of feeling,
process. If everyone agreed on the choices of conte nt to meet und erstanding, aIld pleasure than the popular arts . They perm it
these objectives, which is far from the case, the assessment of a unique enrichment of existence, a diversification (indee d, all
such objectives would still become a major so urce of difficulty. expansion) of consciousness beyond the scope of the popular.
(Freedman & Stuhr, 2004, p. 823) To be sure, these are practical It is because serious art-Beethoven 's, Flaub ert's, Hemingway's,
difficulties rath er than conce ptual ones, but they are difficulties, Cezanne's, DeKoonin g's, Ibsen's, and others- if actively and
nevertheless. perceptively encountered , has the capacity to move human
Asecond difficulty I call its leveling tend ency-the belief that beings into themselves , to releas e them into their own subject-
there is no pre-established hierarchy that accords privileged ivities, to illuminate their particular life worlds. Engagement
standing to ce rta in objec ts such as the objects of "fine art." with works of serious art , difficult as they are to recognize and

NOVEM BER 2005 I ART EDUCATI ON II


possess, is one way of achieving authenticity, the very authenticity critical appraisal is particularly well developed. Of course, the
that is required if our students are to maintain integrity under the various genres within popular culture are rapidly developing
onslaughts of technology and the seductions of media and their own modes of criticism relevant to their nature. For
kitsch. I have experienced the impact of such works throughout example, in the days following the 2005 Super Bowl there was
my life and these encounters tell me that Maxine's assessment of extensive critical commentary on the lackluster quality of the TV
their power is right; yet I know that it is difficult to make such a commercials shown during the game. One commentator on
case with individuals lacking such encounters. National Public Radio referred to a particular commercial made
for Apple Computers in 1984as meeting a standard that has
Problematizing The FineArts as Cultural Practices rarely been surpassed. But if the boundary lines between
In the West the term "fine" was often used to modify the term cultural genres are disappearing as Danto asserts, it might also
"art" to designate works where particular aesthetic features are be the case that the differences between critical practices are
present that raise them above the level of the merely useful. disappearing as well.
Many advocates for visual culture reject this concept. They resist
the idea of artistic value or the possibility that some works might To Look Beyondthe EverydayWorld
in some ultimate sense be aesthetically better than others. There is a more compelling reason why fine art has educa-
Questions about quality or excellence or what allows a partic- tional value, and it is based on the contrast between the experi-
ular work to be accorded recognition as a cultural achievement ences we have with objects in the everyday world and objects
are rarely, if ever, pursued as a bona fide line of investigation. traditionally categorized as fine art. I found Paul Duncum's
The idea of a canon of masterpieces repels enthusiasts for visual (2002) essay to be especially helpful in sorting out this problem.
culture since the act of listing forces one to exclude other works He draws a sharp distinction between "everyday aesthetic sites"
that might reveal important cultural or social factors. as opposed to art objects "which belong to the refined and the
If fine art as a cultural practice is acknowledged at all, it is special" (p. 5). The latter would be the kind of art that concerns
grudgingly and often mis-equated with upper class domination. the professional fine arts community whereas the average
Social critics like Pierre Bourdieu regard the high arts as no layman is more likely to be drawn to the popular culture.
more than sign systems designating social status (cited in Everyday cultural sites, then, are set apart from experiences
Johnson 2002,p. 5). Likewise, Tony Bennett, a British Marxist of art insofar as their appeal is to popular sentiment ... Their
describes fine art as "sheltering the world of privilege ... from references are familiar and together they help form the
unwelcome political distractions" (cited in Harpham, 1994,p. common culture. They directly address the present
128). Thus numerous academic types who once might have been moment. Unlike the art of the art-world, they are neither a
counted on to champion fine art, literature, and classical music, collection of sites that derive from the past, nor an attempt
stand less ready to support such offerings. to articulate the future. They represent neither a residue of
What gives the fine arts their special character is that within the past, nor what is emergent; rather they embody the
them is an ongoing practice of critical investigation that values and beliefs ofthe currently dominant form of
attempts to see which works should be recognized as art. This economic arrangement-global capital-and in this sense
happens with works in the popular culture as well, but it is they form what Williams (1977) calls the dominant culture.
within the fine arts where the tradition and expectation of (Duncum, 2002, p. 5)

.. ART EDUCATION / NOVEMBER 2005


Duncum argues compellingly that the aesthetics of everyday everyday life. However, it is equally the case that on some
encounters are offered by sites such as shopping malls, televi- occasions we should look beyond the everyday! This is where my
sion, theme parks, and fast-food restaurants and should not be view differs from his. Moreover, his assumption that the fine arts
overlooked by contemporary art educators as legitimate sources only provide "calm, reflective sites," or that they are politically
of content in contradistinction to the experiences provided by neutral is just plain wrong.
the arts of the museum. The latter are more likely to emphasize The proponents for a visual culture orientation have a valid
the one-of-a-kind, unique aspects of aesthetic experience. point when they say that too many oftoday's art educators teach
"Everyday life," in his view, involves the mundane world which about works of art as though such works are politically neutral
he characterizes as being unrelated to the major events of and above controversy. In my opinion, the problem is not the
history. "It involves the reproduction and maintenance of life, fine arts but how they are represented in instruction.
not the production of new ways of thinking and acting"
In my view, a visual culture curriculum should represent the
(Duncum 2002, p. 4).
arts on both ends ofthe genre continuum and to do otherwise is
When Duncum turns his attention to fine art, he describes it as to constrain the freedom of cultural life. The same might be said
a genre that "focuses exclusively on certain privileged forms of of a curriculum that deals only and exclusively with the fine arts
the visual. Its focus is on works that are considered spiritually and that presents such works as exceptional moments of human
elevating. Art is said to take us out of ourselves. Aesthetic appre- achievement-as the only legitimate content. No valid educa-
ciation is thus an especially heightened, even consummatory tional purpose is served by limiting the range of visual culture
experience" (Duncum 2002, pp. 6-7). "Creating calm reflective either to the realm of the everyday or to arts that transcend the
sites, separate from the overt, dynamic of a materialistic society everyday, but if each has the other to serve as a basis for compar-
was for this tradition the point of both fine art and the aesthetic" ison, then the special attributes of each genre can become clear.
(p. 7). By contrast, the aesthetics ofthe everyday world
emphasize "the present moment, an immersion in the Implications for the Future of Art Education
immediacy of current experiences and activities" (Duncum, The movement toward visual cultural studies is a step in the
2002, p. 4). He would have today's students focus attention on right direction by identifying it more closely with the whole of
the aesthetic experiences of the everyday world rather than social life. But it is also a movement that runs the risk of
those offered by the so-called higher realms of the fine arts. In becoming blinded by a kind of shortsightedness. In its zeal to
effect, Duncum accepts the reality of an aesthetic hierarchy problematize aesthetic or hierarchical distinctions as undemoc-
except that he asks educators not to neglect the everyday end of ratic, it loses sight of the fact that many cultures develop hierar-
the continuum rather than concentrate upon the so-called higher chies often based on aesthetic attributes and these often do
realms of experience offered by the fine arts. However, a more than serve as the markers differentiating social class. Left
reversal ofthe hierarchy does not eliminate it; he merely asks us to its own devices, each flies in the face of democratic aspira-
to allow one set of values to take precedence over another. tions to constrain the freedom of inquiry, including the freedom
The musicologist Julian Johnson takes an opposing view. His to explore various forms of cultural life. But freedom entails
little book Who Needs Classical Music? reads like a reply to more than art style or life style choices.
Duncum though, of course, this was not its purpose. There is also a second sense in which I use the termfreedorn.
But sometimes art is not obviously concerned with the It is the particular role of the arts to traniiform the culture of
everyday. It is concerned with the extraordinary, the outer which they are part. This happens with the creation of novel,
limits of our experience ... it is the source of art's unique imaginative works of art. This happens in the popular culture,
value as a means of articulating areas of experience beyond perhaps more so, but it is principally in the practices ofthe fine
everyday linguistic discourse, and at the same time, it is a arts where the human imagination has its greatest degree of
means of becoming fantasy, more or less unrelated to the freedom to cultivate, explore and express novel meanings
concerns ofthe everyday. (Johnson, 2002, p. 49) relatively free" of social repression or censorship. Fine art
And Johnson continues: fosters "an experience of freedom" that can serve the broad
social purposes favored by the advocates of visual culture if in
Art's apparent refusal of the everyday is not a refusal of the
human cognition they create a space for imagination and under-
"human" as such: it is a refusal of the idea that the sum of
standing to entertain and rehearse social and moral ideas
what it is to be human is found in the everyday. (Johnson,
without immediate social or political consequences. Cultures
2002,p.49)
and societies which allow this in their arts (and many do not) are
So, if we adopt Duncum's orientation we would emphasize the ones where there is likely to be evolutionary change and adapta-
aesthetic encounters of everyday life. Ifwe take Johnson's view, tion of cultural practices over time. Thus the fine arts as a
we would look to the fine arts for a realm of experience that category of cognitive activity within human experience provides
extends beyond the everyday, to enter perhaps, that spiritual a space where human beings have the freedom to create new
world alluded to earlier. Duncum has a point in asking students forms of cultural life, providing a means of social invention and
to become critically attentive to the aesthetic dimensions of critique.'

NOVEMBER 2005/ ART EDUCATION •


Social invention occurs in the popular culture as well, and ENDNOTES
there has its greatest impact because it reaches more people. 1For opposing views on the topic of visual cultural studios sep Dorn, C.
And hence the goal of enabling students to assess the impact of (2003), Sociology and the ends of arts education, Arts Educat ion Policy
these forms on their lives, including their understanding of Reoieu: 104(5) 3-1:3, and Smith, P..J. (200:3), Visual culturo studies versus
reality, gives the study of popular culture a level of importance it art education, Arts Education Policy Renicu: 104(4) pp. :J-H.
rarely had in the past. 2See Chapter Two in Efland, Freedman & Stuhr, Postmods-vn Al'l
However, popular culture, especially that which is dissemi- Education: An Approaeh to Curriculum (HJDG) for a discussion of
cultural boundaries and their disappearance.
nated by the mass media is inherently less free. It is constrained
by its very popularity to feature ideas and meanings chosen to :3See Andreas Huyssen's essay "Mapping tho Postmodern "in Nicholson
further the profitability of the culture industry. For the most part (Ed.) in Feminism/ posim otiern ism , New York: Routledge, pp. 2:34-277,
for his description of the modernist agenda.
its forms are assimilated uncritically into the lives of our
students. To increase the capacity for critical consciousness in 4Writings by Clement Greenberg typify the advocacy and defense of
modernism. Early in his career he attacked popular culture by rho term
our students is the main reason why visual cultural study is kitsch in an essay entitled "Avant garde and kitsch" Pa rt isa II Recicir. 6,
important. One develops such awareness through the play of pp. 4-49 (19:39).
contrasts of one cultural form with another including one genre
5Greene, M. (HJ71). "Popular Culture, The Arts and Education." Paper
with another. And this is where works of fine art play their presented at the fall conference of the Institute for the Study of Art in
principal role. They belong in the art education curriculum, not Education Department of Art, The City College, New York, November
to give us aesthetic experiences, though many such works do 1971.
that very well, but to remind us of our human potential. In the GCertainly not totally free.
final analysis, we are educators in the arts and it is our business
71obtained this term from Guyor, P. (HJUG) Ka lit a nil the Erpcricuc« q(
to keep doors ofthe human imagination open. Freedom. New York: Cambridge University Press.
8Since the Enlightenment this has been one of the functions of the arts
Arthur D. Efland is Professor Emeritus at The Ohio State in the cultures ofthe West.
University, Columbus. E-rnail: e:jland.l@osu.edu

REFERENCES
Danto, A. (1992). Beyond the Brillo Box: The visual arts in post-histor-
ical perspective. New York: Farrar Straus & Giroux.
Duncum, P. (2002). Theorizing everyday aesthetic experience with
contemporary visual culture. Visual Arts Research, 28(2), pp. 4-15.
Efland, A. (1988). How art became a discipline: Looking at our recent
history. Studies in Art Education. 2.9(3) 264-274.
Freedman, K. (1997). Critiquing the media: Art knowledge inside and
outside the school. Art Education, S.9(4), 46-51.
Freedman, K., & Stuhr, P. (2004). Curriculum change for the 21st
Century: visual culture in art education. In E. Eisner and M. Day
(Eds.), Handbook ofresearch and policy in art education (pp. SFi-
828). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum Associates.
Gablik, S. (1984). Has modernism.failed? New York: Thames & Hudson.
Johnson, J. (2002). Who needs classical music: Cultural choice and
musical value. New York: Oxford University Press.
Harpham, G. H. (1994). Aesthetics and the fundamentals of modernity.
In G. Levine (Ed.), Aesthetics and ideology. New Brunswick, NJ:
Rutgers University Press.
Tavin, K. (2001). Swimming up-stream in the jean pool: Developing a
pedagogy towards critical citizenship in visual culture. Journal. of
Social Theory in Art Education Vol. 21, pp. 129-158.
Tavin, K. (2005). Haunto1ogical shifts: Fear and loathing of popular
(visual) culture. Studies in Art Education, 46(2), 101-117.

.. ART EDUCATION I NOVEMBER 2005

You might also like