You are on page 1of 10

Topoi

DOI 10.1007/s11245-015-9336-1

Giving Reasons Does Not Always Amount to Arguing


Lilian Bermejo-Luque1

 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Abstract Both because of the vagueness of the word characterized argumentation as a practice of giving rea-
‘give’ when speaking about giving reasons, and because we sons. This approach has widened the traditional concep-
lack an adequate definition of ‘reasons’, there is a harmful tions of argumentation and argumentation goodness, which
ambiguity in the expression ‘giving reasons’. Particularly, has enabled, in turn, an account of non-verbal forms of
straightforwardly identifying argumentation with reasons arguing and a non-semanticist conception of justification.
giving would make of virtually any interplay a piece of However, both because of the vagueness of the word
argumentation. Besides, if we adopt the mainstream defi- ‘give’ when speaking about giving reasons, and because we
nition of reasons as ‘‘considerations that count in favour of lack an adequate definition of ‘reasons’, there is a harmful
doing or believing something’’, then only good argumen- ambiguity in the expression ‘giving reasons’. Particularly,
tation would count as argumentation. In this paper, I defend straightforwardly identifying argumentation with reasons
a qualified characterization of argumentation as reasons giving would make of virtually any interplay a piece of
giving that is shown to be fruitful for shedding light on the argumentation. Besides, if we adopt the mainstream defi-
practice of giving reasons, and an inferentialist conception nition of reasons as ‘‘considerations that count in favour of
of reasons that makes room for speaking of ‘‘bad reasons’’ doing or believing something’’, then only good argumen-
and, consequently, makes it possible to talk of argumen- tation would count as argumentation.1 Should we then give
tation as reasons giving even if we are talking about bad up the characterization of argumentation as reasons giving?
argumentation. In this paper, I defend a qualified characterization of
argumentation as reasons giving. This proposal is shown to
Keywords Argumentation  Reasons  Giving reasons  be fruitful for dealing with non-verbal argumentation, as it
LNMA  Inferring  Argumentative speech-acts provides a rationale for its interpretation, analysis and
evaluation while overcoming the problem of finding non-
verbal argumentation all over the place. In turn, I defend an
1 Introduction
1
Actually, this is the standard definition for normative reasons—as
The pragmatic perspective that characterizes Argumenta-
opposed to motivating reasons. In discussing how to understand
tion Theory underlines the interactional dimension of argumentation as a practice of giving reasons, I will be considering
argumentation and its significance for developing adequate only normative reasons, that is, reasons that justify an individual in
normative models for argumentation appraisal. In order to believing or acting as she does. Motivating reasons—that is, reasons
that explain why an individual believes, or acts, as she does—will be
accommodate this view, argumentation theorists have
kept out of our discussion. For, not in vain, argumentation is not an
explanatory but a justificatory device: the reasons that we give in
arguing are meant to justify that for which we offer such reasons.
& Lilian Bermejo-Luque They are not meant to explain it because, in the linguistic-pragmatic
lilian.bermejoluque@gmail.com; lilianbl@ugr.es context of arguing, that for which we offer reasons is not taken for
granted—which is a linguistic-pragmatic condition for explaining it—
1
Department of Philosophy I, University of Granada, Campus but quite the opposite: it is precisely taken to be in need of
de Cartuja, 18071 Granada, Spain justification (see McKeon 2013, p. 300, for a defence of this view).

123
L. Bermejo-Luque

inferentialist conception of reasons that makes room for persuade in the name of what seems actually right to
speaking of ‘‘bad reasons’’ and, consequently, makes it believe or do.
possible to talk of argumentation as reasons giving even if Both the justificatory and the persuasive roles of arguing
we are talking about bad argumentation. are idiosyncratic of this type of communication, and a
In Sect. 3, I consider whether an account of argumen- suitable account of argumentation is prima facie committed
tative reasons giving as an ‘‘invitation to inference’’ (Pinto to dealing with them and to making sense of the way they
1995) could do the work. I underline the rewards of this relate to each other. This was the ancient—mainly Aris-
account, but I explain that, despite the communicative totelian—conception of argumentative discourse as an art,
connotations of the idea of inviting inferences, it still does which deemed that speaking the truth is useless unless we
not manage to exclude non-argumentative forms of reasons manage to make it evident to others.
giving that may count, nevertheless, as proper invitations to Unfortunately, this conception of argumentation as both
inference. In Sect. 4, I explain that argumentation must be a justificatory and a persuasive practice is something that
characterized as a particular type of communicative rea- philosophers had renounced since Descartes’ epistemo-
sons giving, and I defend a conception of argumentation as logical turn until the second half of the last century. Under
a second order speech-act complex. In this account, the the assumption that a man in his solitude could arrive at
kind of reasons giving that counts as arguing can also be justified beliefs just by the power of his reasonings, modern
seen as a certain communicative way of inviting infer- philosophers, and a consistent tradition of logicians after
ences. Following this view, in Sect. 5, I explain the rela- them, focused on argumentation as a justificatory device,
tionship between argumentation—i.e., a communicative dismissing argumentation’s communicative and interactive
process—and reasoning—i.e., a mental process—by con- nature. They were interested in argumentation mostly as a
sidering that reasons as speech-acts have as their mental means to ‘‘test’’ our beliefs. This narrow interest resulted in
counterpart the cognitive inputs that trigger acts of indi- the abandonment of the inquiry on the conditions and
rectly judging. In this account, arguments are not seen as properties of argumentation as a particular form of com-
the contents of reasonings or of acts of arguing, but rather munication, and to a straightforward identification between
as representations of the semantic and syntactic properties argumentation and reasoning. The focus now was argu-
of both types of inferential processes. ments, understood as abstract objects, i.e., sets of propo-
sition. And although such sets of propositions were taken to
be the contents of both reasonings (that is, certain type of
2 The Pragmatic Hallmark of Argumentation mental process) and pieces of argumentation (that is, cer-
Theory tain type of communicative process), the main goal was not
to tell good reasonings or argumentations from bad ones,
Argumentation is a tool for the interplay between indi- but to determine support relations among propositions.
viduals, a means to influence people. By arguing, we can Actually, under the influence of Frege’s aversion to psy-
persuade others of what we say. In this respect, however, chologism, ‘reasonings’ became a synonym for ‘argu-
arguing is not different from, for example, merely assert- ments’ and arguments were seen as instances of formal
ing: by saying ‘‘my name is Alex’’ or ‘‘it’s going to rain’’ in structures. This is how philosophy reduced argumentation
adequate circumstances, I can also manage to persuade my to its formal and semantic properties. The pragmatic con-
addressees that this is my name or that it’s going to rain. straints of arguing were banished from the mainstream
Communication, in general, enables individuals to induce account of argumentation goodness: good argumentation
beliefs and attitudes in others. Actually, almost anything was conceived just as argumentation consisting of true
we do can be pursued as a means for inducing beliefs and premises and (formally) valid inferences, as Black (1964)
attitudes. Is it because almost anything we do can be made manifest by coining the expression ‘‘sound
argumentation? argument’’.
Characteristically, argumentation is also a tool for jus- The rise of Argumentation Theory can be seen as par-
tifying: by arguing, we may show that we are right, that it tially stemming from the need to fight this semanticist
is not up to our audience to accept what we say or not. The conception of argumentation and argumentation goodness.
fact that argumentation is a means to justify explains not As pointed out by many argumentation theorists, the
only its widespread use as a means to persuade—because, semanticist approach faced inescapable difficulties in
fortunately, our rational fellows tend to be persuaded when dealing not only with the analysis and interpretation of real
we offer good reasons for what we say, and we are argumentation in natural language, but also with the nor-
instrumentally rational in pursuing good means for our mativity of argumentation as a communicative activity.
ends—but also its legitimacy—because trying to persuade Thus, for example, authors like Hamblin (1970), Walton
of what we say by giving good reasons for it is trying to (1989) or van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992) pointed

123
Giving Reasons Does Not Always Amount to Arguing

out that the pragmatic constraints of arguing were the key Certainly, in order to accommodate these widening
for dealing with most informal fallacies. conceptions of arguing, it seemed crucial to characterize
In order to counterbalance the hegemony of the argumentation, in general, as a practice of giving reasons.
semanticist approach, Argumentation Theory developed a For, as we have pointed out, unless we were ready to deem
pragmatic perspective stressing the fact that argumentation as argumentation almost anything we do (like, for example,
is, first and foremost, a particular sort of interaction. This merely asserting), it is necessary to integrate the justifica-
perspective promoted a new change in focus from argu- tory dimension of argumentation with its bare ability to
ments as abstract objects (i.e., sets of propositions) to induce beliefs. In thinking of argumentation as reasons
arguments as pieces of argumentation, and a corresponding giving, the idea would be that this integration is a matter of
conception of arguing as the activity of giving, or argumentation’s ability to make rational those beliefs and
exchanging, reasons. Most argumentation theorists attitudes that we are able to induce in others by giving
assumed that the only way to overcome the shortcomings reasons for them.
of the semanticist approach was to develop models able to
establish the conditions that arguers should meet in giving
or exchanging reasons. 3 Giving Reasons as Inviting Inferences
Unfortunately, there was just a small step from this view
to the identification of argumentation goodness with some But, what is ‘‘giving reasons’’ for a belief or an attitude? In
kind of legitimate argumentative success.2 As a conse- ‘‘You can leave your hat on’’, Joe Cocker said to his
quence of thinking of argumentation as a communicative addressee ‘‘you give me a reason to live’’. Because the song
process connected to and normatively determined by is fresh and sexy rather than melancholic or ‘‘intellectual’’,
speakers’ behaviour, main approaches within Argumenta- we assume that Cocker isn’t talking about a piece of
tion Theory promoted a new conception of argumentative argumentation by his addressee for the view that Cocker’s
value according to which argumentation goodness was a life is worthy to live, or anything in these lines… Instead,
matter of argumentation’s ability to achieve the ends that we guess that he is talking about his lover’s ability to make
would allegedly be characteristic of the practice of arguing. him happy. Cocker is celebrating that, by being thus and
This is how the pragmatic perspective gave rise to a new so, his lover gives him a reason to live. Yet, being thus and
account of the normativity underlying argumentation, so is not arguing. Actually, Cocker might have also sung
namely, a conception shifting from criteria to decide on the ‘‘it gives me a reason to live’’ in order to praise the virtues
semantic and formal properties of arguments to criteria to of friendship, Scottish whisky, a cosy cottage or whatever
decide on the value of acts of arguing as means to achieve could make him think or feel that life is worthy to live. No
certain legitimate goals, like the persuasion of a universal doubt, things can give us reasons for adopting all kind of
audience (the new rhetoric approach), the rational per- doxastic and non-doxastic attitudes; but we wouldn’t say
suasion of an addressee (the informal logic approach), or that things could argue.
the resolution of a difference of opinion on the merits So, giving reasons does not always amount to arguing.
(Pragma-dialectics). Arguing, we have seen, is a communicative activity: the
Importantly, thinking of arguing as a practice of giving type of reasons giving that amounts to arguing must
reasons enabled the recognition of non-verbal forms of involve some kind of communicative interplay.
argumentation. For example, Birdsell and Groarke (1996) Yet, which type of communicative reasons giving is
argued for the possibility of recognizing visual argumen- arguing? Noteworthily, by saying that my name is Alex in
tation, that is, argumentation put forward by means of adequate circumstances, I can not only persuade my
images instead of words. And, according to Gilbert’s addressees that this is my name, but also give them a
account of coalescent argumentation (Gilbert 1997), doing reason to believe so by communicative means. Moreover,
things like looking approvingly, turning serious or giving a we may say both that persuading my addressees that my
nudge might also count as arguing, as they may be means name is Alex by saying so is a rational way of persuading
to overcome disagreement by fostering the ‘‘coalescence’’ them, and that my addressees are rational in being so
of different points of view. Moreover, in Gilbert’s view, persuaded when told, in normal circumstances, that my
some types of arguments, like emotional ones, would name is Alex. Yet, if we don’t want to say that mere
require fundamentally different criteria of assessment than assertions count as argumentation, it seems, again, that we
arguments as traditionally conceived. will need something else, a further feature to define argu-
mentation as reasons giving.
2 In ‘‘The relation of argument to inference’’, Pinto (1995)
In Bermejo-Luque (2011, chap. 2), I explain that one of the main
problems of this type of instrumentalism is that it is unable to provide defended the view that arguing is, first and foremost, an
a rationale for normative models of argumentation. invitation to inference.3 I would like to explain the rewards

123
L. Bermejo-Luque

of this approach for our inquiry by recalling a distinction I my neighbour upstairs has plants on his balcony, which
made in Bermejo-Luque (2011, pp. 72–80) between direct may better explain these drops of water).
and indirect judgments. Directly judging does not necessarily involve judging
A direct judgment is a judgment that has not been the plausibility, acceptability or truth of a given represen-
caused by any other judgment. Self-knowledge and many tation: after all, in order to judge that things are thus and so,
kinds of empirical knowledge are usually the result of this it is not necessary for a given representation of this state of
kind of judging: I come to believe that there is a book on the world to pre-exist (either in our minds or put forward
the table just by seeing it, or I come to believe that I have a by someone else). On the contrary, such a representation
pain in my back just by feeling it.4 Similarly, I can directly can be brought about by the very act of judging: the world
judge that it is raining, not only by looking through the may simultaneously cause our representation—for exam-
window and seeing drops of water falling down, but also by ple, the idea of the book on the table—and our judgment
hearing my son coming in and saying so. The falling of that this representation holds—i.e., the judgment that the
drops of water and my son saying that it is raining can also book is on the table.
be reasons that would eventually justify my judgment that In turn, an indirect judgment would be a judgment
it’s raining. But in my act of directly judging, they just caused by other judgment(s) or belief(s) that are related to
count as events that cause my judgment.5 Of course, this judgment in an inferential way.6 For example, I indi-
pointing at these events is also a means to justify the cor- rectly judge that Elizabeth must have finished off the
responding judgments; but we must distinguish between Cheerios last night, when I consider that we are run out of
the causes and the reasons for a judgment. For, we can Cheerios this morning (Harman 1986, p. 1). When we
think of circumstances in which, as a cause, the event is indirectly judge, we make a judgment prompted by a
sufficient for generating a mental state that did not exist cognitive input like a belief or judgment—e.g., my judg-
previously (e.g., the judgment that it is raining), whereas, ment that we are run out of Cheerios this morning. This
as a reason, the same event may be insufficient to justify cognitive input counts as a reason for our cognitive output
the corresponding judgment (for example, if (I know that) by virtue of its association with another conditional judg-
ment or belief whose meaning is that of a warrant for this
cognitive output, provided that the input is true—in our
3
Actually, Pinto says that it is arguments, not argumentation, what example, the conditional judgment that if we are run out of
constitutes an invitation to inference. Yet, because he says that an Cheerios this morning, then Elizabeth finished them off last
argument is ‘‘a set of statements or propositions that one person offers
night. Let me call this conditional belief or judgment the
to another in the attempt to induce that other person to accept some
conclusion’’ (Pinto 1995, p. 271), whereas argumentation is ‘‘an inference-motivation of the act of indirectly judging.
interactive social process involving two or more people, in which the Despite their normative function, inference-motivations
principal goal is to induce belief or agreement through the presen- also depend on our acquaintance with the world and how it
tation of arguments’’ (1995, p. 271), I would rather say that it is
affects us in particular circumstances. After all, they are
argumentation (as an activity), not arguments (as abstract entities),
what amounts to an invitation to inference. supposed to in fact motivate the inferences that we make: it
4
In literature, this kind of judgment is usually called ‘‘non- is because my belief or judgment that ‘‘if ci then co’’ is
inferential.’’ However I would rather call it ‘‘direct’’ because I would salient for me in this particular case that, in having the
like to leave aside the question of whether, in the end, a judgment cognitive input ci, I come to indirectly judge that co,
must be inferentially articulated for it to have any content at all. In
instead of indirectly judging that co’, co’’, etc. For exam-
fact, I am willing to say that direct judgments depend upon previous
inferences. For example, I usually directly judge that it’s time for a ple, in facing that a fungus in the test-tube has killed the
coffee when I hear a familiar sound from a bell in a nearby church. bacteria culture, I may make the judgment, among many
Such a judgment is caused by this sound having that impact on me: others, that the experiment has gone bad, that the test-tube
when I hear it in normal circumstances, I come to believe that it’s
was contaminated, that I need a new axenic culture, or, as
time for a coffee. Yet, the fact that the sound has this impact on me
depends on my having associated it, one way or another, with being Fleming did, that there is a powerful antibiotic in it.
time for a coffee when it sounded in normal circumstances. This Importantly, however, inference-motivations do not
association is something that certainly depends on many inferences have to be pre-existing beliefs: sometimes, in drawing a
that I have made over time. Yet, despite its inferential articulation, my
conclusion, we do not follow a belief that we already have,
judgment counts as a direct judgment because I didn’t make these
inferences in order to judge in this particular case that it’s time for a but endorse the corresponding conditional in the very act of
coffee. Rather, I merely heard a sound that triggered the judgment
‘‘now it’s time for a coffee’’. 6
Consequently, the distinction between direct and indirect judgments
5
I leave aside the question of whether or not a judgment caused by is not meant to be exhaustive regarding the possible ways of coming
an event that could not justify it at all (like a drug, a mental disorder to believe new things. For there may be judgments prompted by other
or a blow to the head) is a real judgment after all. If we think that it is, judgments in a non-inferential way. This would be the case, for
then judging that there is a pink elephant in front of you because of a example, of associations of ideas and processes like remembering
drug would also be a case of directly judging. something by noticing something else, etc.

123
Giving Reasons Does Not Always Amount to Arguing

inferring; in these cases, the very act of inferring involves conveys and triggers reasonings. Would then be ok to say
the act of making the corresponding conditional judgment.7 that argumentation is reasons giving that invite inferences
The latter is what we do when we make novel inferences, in this sense? Unfortunately, again, we need something
that is, when we do not follow a pattern of inference, but else. Because, for example, by replying that there is a gas
come to infer in unexpected ways. The typical ‘‘eureka’’ station around the corner at your observation that we’re out
moments of scientific discovery would be a good example of petrol, you’re invited to infer that it will be open, and my
of this phenomenon of inferential but unexpected reason- saying so gives you a reason to believe it. But implicating,
ing. At any rate, the inferences that we make from a given despite being a means to invite inferences by giving rea-
piece of evidence depend not only on our beliefs and sons, is not arguing either.
judgments about the world—as they provide the condi- At this point, we could try to say, as Pinto himself points
tionals that we endorse in inferring, but also on our cog- out, that arguing is inviting inferences ‘‘through the pre-
nitive styles, our interests, constrains, etc. sentation of arguments’’ (Pinto 1995, p. 271). But this
Now, one of the most salient features of argumentation, response only shows the real dimension of our problem, for
in contrast with other kinds of communication, is that when we do not have a suitable definition of ‘‘arguments’’. If
we argue we convey not only our beliefs, but also our arguments are conceived either as pieces of argumentation
reasonings. But, what does this mean? I think we may or as the product of argumentation, then appealing to
understand Pinto’s account of argumentation as an invita- arguments cannot be of help for characterizing argumen-
tion to inference in the following way: by arguing, we tation in turn. Alternatively, if we think of arguments as
invite our addresses to infer, in the sense of inviting them abstract entities, we still have to explain what their rela-
to make indirect judgments. On this view, a mere assertion tionship to argumentation is. For Pinto himself, an argu-
of ‘‘my name is Alex’’ would not count as argumentation ment is ‘‘a set of statements or propositions that one person
because, normally, it would not involve any invitation to offers to another in the attempt to induce that other person
make an indirect judgment, but only to make a direct to accept some conclusion’’ (1995, p. 271), but, again, this
judgment, namely, that my name is Alex. Furthermore, if I is not going to take us too far in our attempt at character-
hit my head and cry in pain, I would give you a reason to izing argumentative reasons giving either.
believe that I am in pain, but I would not be inviting you to Actually, there is a deeper concern with the very defi-
make that inference; rather, you would do it on your own. nition of arguments as abstract entities. According to Copi
This way, Pinto’s account of argumentation as an invitation and Cohen, ‘‘an argument, in the logician’s sense, is any
to inference incorporates not only the communicative ele- group of propositions of which one is claimed to follow
ment of proper arguing, but also a straightforward expla- from the others, which are regarded as providing support
nation of the twofold dimension of argumentation as a or grounds for the truth of that one (Copi and Cohen 1990,
persuasive and a justificatory practice: in this account, p. 6, my italics). Notice that if we don’t want to identify
argumentation has the power to induce beliefs and the arguments with good arguments, we have to say that the
power to justify them, because a justified induced belief conclusion ‘‘is claimed to follow’’, not that if actually
can be characterized as a belief prompted by a reason that follows. Of course, we could also say that an argument is
is true and sanctioned by an inference-motivation that is just a set of propositions; but, obviously, as a definition, it
also true. Besides, this account can also explain the dif- is too vague, and it cannot be of help for defining argu-
ference between a justified induced belief and a belief that mentation in turn. As Copi and Cohen’s definition suggests,
has been adopted rationally by the addressee: the latter in order to give an account of arguments that makes room
would be a belief prompted by a representation that the for bad arguments and goes beyond the mere idea of an
subject takes to hold and sanctioned by an inference-mo- unstructured sets of propositions, we need to characterize
tivation that she also takes to hold, whether or not they them by reference to some communicative activity in
actually hold—that is, whether or not the reason actually which some proposition ‘‘is claimed to follow’’ and others
justifies the belief. ‘‘are regarded as providing support or grounds’’.8 This is
Pinto’s conception of argumentation as an invitation to precisely the main intuition behind the following proposed
inference may be seen as an attempt to preserve the dis- account.
tinction between argumentation and other ways of per-
suading by characterizing argumentation both as a
justificatory device and as a persuasive practice that
8
Simard Smith and Moldovan (2011, p. 256) also understand that the
7
I think this distinction corresponds, in the realm of reasonings, to illative relation between propositions that structures sets of proposi-
the Toulmian distinction between warrant-using and warrant-estab- tions as arguments ‘‘is created by an agent when the agent intends that
lishing arguments. a conclusion follows from a set of premises in a certain way.’’

123
L. Bermejo-Luque

4 Argumentation as a Speech-Act: Non-verbal In principle, we can make explicit the variety of ways in
Argumentation which we can put forward a certain semantic content p in a
constative speech-act by saying things like ‘‘p is true,’’
‘Persuading’ or ‘trying to persuade’ or ‘trying to rationally ‘‘p is (more or less) probable,’’ ‘‘p is (more or less)
persuade’, ‘giving reasons’, ‘inviting inferences’, ‘giving acceptable,’’ ‘‘p is (more or less) plausible,’’ ‘‘p is neces-
reasons that invite inferences’… none of these expressions sary,’’ ‘‘p is possible,’’ etc. I named ontological modals to
seems to be a synonym for ‘arguing’. Argumentation the- the modals by means of which we can make explicit the
orists have provided a variety of characterizations of type and degree of pragmatic force of any of the consta-
arguing, but we still don’t know what does it mean to say tives constituting the act of arguing (including the infer-
that arguing is ‘‘giving reasons’’. As we have seen, ence-claim): after all, constatives are speech-acts meant to
appealing to arguments as sets of premises that constitute communicate how the world is. In making explicit the
the contents of those pieces of communication in which we pragmatic force of such constatives, we make plain asser-
‘‘give reasons’’ does not seem to be of help either. So, how tions in turn—such as the plain assertion that p is true, or
should we think of arguing as reasons giving? that it is (more or less) probable, or possible, or plausible,
As most argumentation theorists, in Bermejo-Luque or necessary, etc. When we put forward a propositional
(2011), I adopted a pragmatic approach to argumentation. content with the pragmatic force that such propositional
Yet, I did so by characterizing argumentation as a lin- content actually deserves as a representation of the world,
guistic-pragmatic practice. I defined argumentation as a we make first order constatives that are semantically cor-
communicative activity involving acts of arguing, and I rect. Contrastingly, the modal that expresses the pragmatic
proposed a linguistic normative model, LNMA, that fol- force with which we draw our conclusion in the act of
lows Bach and Harnish’s (1979) Speech-Act Schema in arguing is an epistemic modal. This modal is meant to
order to characterize acts of arguing as second order communicate our credentials for concluding, i.e., the type
speech-act complexes. Particularly, I provided an account and degree of support that our reasons are supposed to
of acts of arguing as speech-acts consisting of a speech-act confer on our target-claims because of our inference-
of adducing and a speech-act of concluding. claims. In concluding that a claim holds truly, necessarily,
In this account, acts of adducing and acts of concluding possibly, plausibly, probably, presumably, etc. (i.e., that
are constatives—whether directly or indirectly performed, likely p, that it might be the case that p, that certainly p,
literal or non-literal; but they are second order because they that presumably p, etc.), we are saying something about the
can only be performed by means of first order speech-acts. status of this claim as knowledge, about the confidence that
According to this view, a performance of, for example, ‘‘I we may put on it, or our epistemic entitlement to it. In this
promise I’ll take care, don’t worry’’—which, in principle, account, epistemic modals are meant to express how good
just involves two first order speech-acts, i.e., a promise and our reasons for our claims are; and, as we are going to see,
a request—turns into a speech-act complex of arguing they are a function of the ontological modals that corre-
because these first order speech-acts turn into the consta- spond to the implicit inference-claim and to the speech-act
tive speech-act of adducing that the arguer commits herself of adducing.
to take care and the constative speech-act of concluding Very roughly, the idea is that, illocutionarily, acts of
that the addressee should not worry, correspondingly. arguing, so characterized, count as attempts at showing a
Two speech-acts become an act of adducing R (for target-claim to be correct. To the extent that they succeed
reason) and an act of concluding C (for target-claim) in this—which means that the target-claim has been cor-
because of their relationship to an implicit inference-claim rectly qualified by a certain epistemic modal (semantic
whose propositional content is ‘‘if R, then C.’’ In a few conditions) and that the act of arguing is a good means for
words, it is by attributing to the speaker the implicit showing this (pragmatic conditions)—they will be deemed
inference-claim ‘‘if (it is true that) I commit myself to take good argumentation—that is, argumentation providing
care, then (it is plausible that) you should not worry’’ that justification.9
we interpret her utterances of ‘‘I promise I’ll take care’’ and
‘‘Don’t worry’’, as a single speech-act—namely, an act of
arguing. Normally, the fact that the speaker has used some 9
On this account, it is one thing to determine argumentation
epistemic modal (like ‘‘probably,’’ ‘‘necessarily,’’ ‘‘pre- goodness—that is, to determine whether or not a given speech-act of
sumably,’’ ‘‘plausibly,’’ etc.) or an illative expression like arguing succeeds in showing its target claim to be correct—and
‘‘so,’’ ‘‘therefore,’’ ‘‘since,’’ ‘‘consequently,’’ etc. is what another thing to determine whether or not the addressee of that act of
arguing will take it to be a good one. In Bermejo-Luque (2011,
authorizes us to interpret the speaker’s performance as a pp. 159–162), I contend that something like Grice’s Cooperative
speech-act of arguing. Principle is a good starting point to settle the pragmatic conditions
that determine whether a speech-act is a good act of showing.

123
Giving Reasons Does Not Always Amount to Arguing

Like many other activities, the activity of arguing is argumentation is a communicative activity, then we can
constrained both constitutively and regulatively. The reg- think of its ‘‘product’’ in many ways: it may be particular
ulative constraints of argumentation determine the speech-acts, or the meaning that is conveyed by them, or
achievement of certain goals that we pursue when we even their effects on their addressees, etc.
argue.10 Thus, they provide rules and criteria for evaluating For my part, I think of arguments as particular abstract
argumentation from one or another point of view. In turn, objects, namely, the representations of the inferences that
the constitutive constraints of argumentation determine the supervene on acts of arguing and acts of reasoning (i.e.,
identification of certain objects of the world as argumen- particular indirect judgments, as characterized in Sect. 3).
tation proper, whether good or bad. In LNMA, the con- And, in contrast with acts of arguing and acts of reason-
stitutive and regulative constraints of argumentation turn ing—which are, so to speak, ‘‘objects of the world’’—ar-
out to be linked to each other in the following way: argu- guments would be just theoretical constructions. We obtain
mentation is communication determined by those prag- arguments by representing the semantic (and, eventually,
matic conditions that make a given piece of behavior count also the syntactic) properties of acts of arguing and acts of
as an attempt at showing a target-claim to be correct. In reasoning, and this is something we can do by following a
turn, good argumentation is argumentation actually show- variety of models, like those of the different formal sys-
ing its target-claim to be correct. Thus, to the extent that a tems, informal argumentative schemas or, for example, by
piece of non-linguistic communicative behavior may count adopting Toulmin’s model of argument. Actually, in my
as an attempt at showing a target-claim to be correct, view, the latter is the most accurate representation of acts
LNMA finds no problem in acknowledging non-verbal of arguing as characterized in LNMA, because of its
argumentation, which, in turn, will be good argumentation underlying material conception of inferential
if it succeeds in such attempt. Our extension of Bach and normativity.11
Harnish’s speech-act schema will then be the ground for In adopting Toulmin’s model of argument for repre-
interpreting and analyzing such non-verbal forms of senting the inferences that supervene in acts of arguing and
arguing. acts of reasoning, we will take that the constitutive ele-
On the other hand, as van Eemeren and Grootendorst ments of arguments, so conceived, are: premises (corre-
(1984) had already pointed out, characterizing argumenta- sponding either to the speech-acts of adducing, R, or to the
tion as a speech-act enables us to make sense of argumen- cognitive input in the act of reasoning, CI), conclusion
tation as an activity aimed at certain perlocutionary goals, (corresponding either to the speech-act of concluding, C, or
such as persuading an addressee or audience or resolving a to the cognitive output in the act of reasoning, CO), war-
difference of opinion. This way, another advantage of our rant (corresponding either to the inference-claim in the act
approach is that it enables us to integrate the justificatory and of arguing or to the inference-motivation in the act of
persuasive dimensions of argumentation as two sides of the reasoning) and the representation of the epistemic and
same coin: after all, the illocutionary and the perlocutionary ontological modals, em and om, of the speech-acts con-
descriptions of a speech-act apply to the same communica- stituting the act of arguing (corresponding to the pragmatic
tive event. Regarding acts of arguing, whereas justification force with which each constative of the act of arguing has
would be the constitutive goal of arguing—i.e., the goal that been put forward, either implicitly or explicitly) or of the
conventionally renders any piece of communication argu- judgments and beliefs constituting the act of reasoning
mentation—persuading could be seen as the purpose we (corresponding to the type and degree of assent to each
normally use argumentation for. In fact, as an invitation to propositional content constituting the act of reasoning).12
inference, argumentation is a very special means to persuade, Thus, an ascription of both epistemic and ontological
as we are going to see. modals (eventually, the ascription made by the arguer or
the reasoner herself) is part of the layout of arguments, and
the semantic evaluation of an act of arguing or reasoning
5 Reasoning, Argumentation and Arguments would be the process of determining the right ascription of

Within Argumentation Theory, it is commonplace to define 11


For Toulmin, argument goodness is a matter of the warrant that
arguments as ‘‘the product of argumentation.’’ But, to be sanctions the inference, not of accordance with formal rules of
true, this definition is too vague. If we agree that inference. See Bermejo-Luque (2011, pp. 88–101) for a defence of
this conception of logical normativity.
12
Because Toulmin does not deal with argumentation from a
10
Or, rather, the goal that we pursue in arguing: as I have explained linguistic-pragmatic perspective, his account of qualifiers is quite
in Bermejo-Luque (2011, pp. 23–40), our normative models for different from the one presented here. Particularly, Toulmin does not
argumentation must focus on the constitutive goal of arguing, which distinguish between epistemic and ontological qualifiers, because he
is justifying, if their normative status is to be justified in turn. is not concerned with the differences between the pragmatic force of

123
L. Bermejo-Luque

modals to each represented claim or judgment/belief (that would be the reasons that we give in arguing. On this view,
is, whether or not the ascription made by the arguer or the argumentation is communicative reasons giving because
reasoner is correct after all). This model of argument can argumentative reasons amount to speech-acts of adducing.
thus be outlined as follows: As we have seen, in this account, what makes of a
cognitive input or of a speech-act a reason is its relation-
(omr/ci)Premise _________therefore___ (emx)(omc/co) Conclusion ship to an inference-claim or an inference-motivation that
| sanctions the inferential step from it to that for which this
since cognitive input or speech-act is a reason indeed. In contrast
(omi)Warrant: “if R/CI, then C/CO”
with the mainstream definition of reasons as ‘‘considera-
tions that count in favour of doing or believing something’’,
(Noticeably, the content of the antecedent, R, and the our conception of reasons as the sort of thing a premise can
consequent, C, is the content of the corresponding first represent enables us to talk about argumentation as reasons
order constatives, R and C, joint with their corresponding giving even if we are not talking about good argumentation
pragmatic forces in the act of arguing or, alternatively, the at all. Let us then briefly consider the consequences of this
content of the corresponding cognitive input and output, CI view with respect to our understanding of the practice of
and CO, with their corresponding type and degree of assent giving reasons.
in the act of reasoning). In our proposed model, the constitutive elements of
Let u represent the function that assigns, for each arguments correspond to the pragmatic elements of the
ontological modal of a conditional, the epistemic modal speech-act of arguing as an attempt at justifying and to the
that must be used in drawing a conclusion having this cognitive elements that constitute an act of indirectly
conditional as its warrant—or, in other words, the term that judging. This way, we can also easily make sense of
must be used for expressing either the pragmatic force of argumentation as an invitation to inference by thinking of
any speech-act of concluding having a conditional so its characteristic perlocutionary effect as that of triggering
qualified as its inference-claim or the type and degree of certain acts of indirectly judging in the addressee: namely,
assent to the cognitive output having a conditional so mental processes that have as their cognitive input the
qualified as its inference-motivation. reasons adduced by the speaker and as their cognitive
uðomi Þ ¼ emi output the conclusions that she put forward. Arguing is a
way to achieve this because, as pointed out at the begin-
In this account, an argument is valid if and only if ning, mere assertions may have persuasive power: by
emi = emx and omi is correct—in the sense that it is the putting forward the constatives that constitute an act of
ontological modal that actually corresponds to the infer- arguing, we can trigger the direct judgments that play as
ence-claim as a constative or to the inference-motivation as cognitive inputs, cognitive outputs and inference-motiva-
a belief/judgment. That is, the argument will be valid if and tions, correspondingly. Yet, in indirectly judging as invi-
only if the epistemic modal that the speaker or reasoner has ted, the addressee takes the implicit inference-claim put
used for concluding or coming to believe the cognitive forward by the speaker as an inference-motivation for
output is the epistemic modal that u assigns to the onto- himself. What does this mean?
logical modal of her implicit inference-claim or inference- As we have seen, the conditional judgment or belief that
motivation and this ontological modal is the one that this lies behind any act of indirectly judging is the element that
inference-claim or inference-motivation actually deserves, makes a judgment or belief input a proper reason for a
given the state of the world. cognitive output. If it didn’t make sense to attribute such
conditional judgment or belief to the subject, then it
wouldn’t make sense to think of the cognitive input as a
6 Argumentation as Reasons Giving reason for her cognitive output. Instead, her input–output
cognitive process would count, at best, as an association of
LNMA’s characterization of argumentation as a second ideas or something like that. Such is the sense in which
order speech-act complex provides a straightforward cognitive inputs as reasons are normative for the subject
account of argumentation as reasons giving: arguing is who indirectly judges: for a mental process to count as an
performing speech-acts of adducing as a means to show a act of indirectly judging, it has to be rational; that is to say,
target-claim to be correct. Such speech-acts of adducing we have to view the subject as taking the cognitive input to
be a good reason for the cognitive output, which is some-
thing that the subject does by taking the cognitive input ci
Footnote 12 continued
ordinary constatives and the characteristic pragmatic force of the and the inference-motivation i to be true, which is, in turn,
speech-act of concluding.

123
Giving Reasons Does Not Always Amount to Arguing

what she does when she judges or believes that ci and that already had. After all, in putting forward the reason of our
i.13 act of arguing, we can make our addressee believe it just
In my view, this is what goes on when, as addressees, we because we say so, because, as pointed out before, mere
follow an argument. And it is also the sense in which the assertions do also have persuasive power: they are a means
reasons that we are given in argumentation are normative to induce direct judgments. And more importantly, in
over us: following an argument is counting as inferring making the implicit inference-claim of our act of arguing,
ourselves, i.e., as adopting the reasons adduced by the we can make our addressee believe it thereof. This is what
speaker as reasons for us. In this respect, following an happens, for example, if a chef says to the cook trainee
argument—as opposed to merely agreeing with, or coming ‘‘you have to whisk the mixture steadily; otherwise, it
to believe, the speaker’s conclusion—counts as being won’t rise’’ and the trainee didn’t already know that the
rationally persuaded. mixture should rise: by following the chef’s argument, the
Importantly, following an argument is not evaluating the trainee will learn not only that he has to whisk the mixture
act of arguing that the argument represents, but accepting steadily (the chef’s target-claim), but also that if the mix-
the invitation to inference that this act of arguing amounts ture won’t rise if not whisked steadily, he must whisk it
to. As we have seen, indirect judgments proceed by rea- steadily (the chef’s inference-claim)—which, in fact, is
sons, but they are not the output of judging that a given also a way of learning that the mixture should rise.
representation (a judgment, belief, or claim) is justified. In Argumentation’s ability to prompt indirect judgments
other words, indirectly judging does not involve positively this way explains the worry that Campolo (2005) and
evaluating a reason for a conclusion, but making an Turner and Wright (2005) express about giving reasons in
inference prompted by a cognitive input that counts for us context of deep disagreement. For, in facing argumenta-
as a reason because a suitable motivation to infer is at play. tion, addressees confront a difficult choice: either adopting
Contrastingly, in order to judge that a given representation a non-natural attitude towards the reasons given—namely,
is justified by such and such reason, we have to evaluate that of evaluating the corresponding argument—and being
the corresponding argument having the propositional con- accused of being uncooperative, or being cooperative and
tent of this representation as its conclusion and the follow the argument, which amounts to inferring as invited
propositional content of this reason as its premise. So doing by coming to believe both the claim adduced as a reason
involves reconstructing the corresponding inference-moti- and in the implicit inference-claim.
vation as the argument’s warrant, and to take the correct-
ness of these representations as something in question. In a
few words, whereas indirectly judging involves endorsing 7 Conclusions
beliefs and judgments as reasons and inference-motiva-
tions, judging a representation to be justified involves The pragmatic approach that currently characterizes the
adopting a reflexive attitude, i.e., that of determining that field of Argumentation Theory focuses on the activity of
the representations corresponding to the premise, conclu- arguing in two respects. On the one hand, it takes into
sion and warrant of an argument are correct. account the constraints of communicative rationality
Thus, in our account, argumentative persuasion pro- regarding argumentative exchanges in order to deal with
ceeds by reasons, but it is not necessarily the output of argumentation’s interpretation and analysis. On the other
judging that the speaker’s target-claim is justified. Most of hand, it aims at providing a normative framework for
the times, being persuaded by the reasons adduced does not argumentation based on the assumption that it is a practice
involve positively evaluating the corresponding piece of that characteristically aims at certain ends, such as the
argumentation; it simply involves coming to believe a rational persuasion of an addressee, the resolution of a
target-claim—as qualified by the arguer in her argumen- difference of opinion or the persuasion of a universal
tation- because of our acceptance of the reason that she has audience.
put forward—and consequently, of the corresponding I have tried to show, however, that this pragmatic per-
inference-claim, now playing the role of an inference- spective is bound to neglect the distinction between argu-
motivation for ourselves. ing and other types of reasons giving and, therefore, to
In this account, argumentation’s persuasive power is not inadequately distinguish between argumentation and other
a matter of merely ‘‘recalling’’ beliefs that the addressee types of communication. Of course, this does not mean that
argumentation theorists confuse reasons giving that is
13
argumentation with reasons giving that it isn’t. My only
In my view, this is the sense in which motivating reasons, as
claim is that, so far, we lack both a proper account of
opposed to merely explanatory ones, do also have normative force
(see Álvarez 2010 for a defence of the view that normative reasons argumentation as reasons giving and a characterization of
are different from explanatory ones). the sort of thing a reason, in the argumentative sense, is.

123
L. Bermejo-Luque

For my part, I have proposed a conception of argu- rational strategy for persuading. However, because argu-
mentation as communication aimed at showing a target- mentation is an attempt to show that our claims are correct,
claim to be correct—that is, aimed at justifying. Such aiming at persuading by arguing is, in the end, aiming at
characterization of the speech-act of arguing would enable persuading in a legitimate way.
us to distinguish between argumentation and other types of
communicative activities by stressing the fact that, when Acknowledgments I wish to thank Javier Rodrı́guez Alcázar and
the Topoi reviewers of this paper for their insightful comments and
we argue, we do not merely try to communicate our beliefs criticisms. The work presented in this paper has been financed by a
or persuade others of them, but we also try to show them to Ramón y Cajal Research Fellowship and by the research Project
be correct. This is something that we do by giving reasons FFI2014-54681-P of the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation.
for them, in the sense of ‘‘adducing’’, described above. And
it is precisely this appeal to reasons that confers on argu-
mentation a kind of legitimacy and force that makes it References
different from other persuasive devices—like suggestions,
Álvarez M (2010) Kinds of reasons: an essay in the philosophy of
advices, threats, or mere assertions. action. Oxford University Press, Oxford
This account of argumentative reasons giving as a jus- Bach K, Harnish RM (1979) Linguistic communication and speech-
tificatory practice does not exclude the idea that, by argu- acts. MIT Press, Cambridge
ing, people may also aim at coordinating actions and Bermejo-Luque L (2011) Giving reasons. A linguistic-pragmatic
approach to argumentation theory. Springer, Dordrecht
beliefs by persuading each other. Actually, my goal was to Birdsell D, Groarke L (1996) Introduction: argumentation and
provide a unitary account of argumentation as a justifica- advocacy. J Am Forensic Assoc 33:1–10
tory and as a persuasive device. Yet, I wanted to retain the Black M (1964) Critical thinking. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs
idea that the persuasive force of particular acts of arguing Campolo C (2005) Treacherous ascents: on seeking common ground
for conflict resolution. Informal Logic 25:37–50
need not be a consequence of their justificatory force—or, Copi IM, Cohen C (1990) Introduction to logic, 8th edn. Macmillan,
in other words, that good argumentation can fail to per- New York
suade whereas bad argumentation can succeed. In my view, Gilbert M (1997) Coalescent argumentation. Lawrence Erlbaum
the best way to deal with both intuitions, namely, that the Associates, Hillsdale
Hamblin C (1970) Fallacies. Methuen, London
justificatory and the persuasive powers of argumentation Harman G (1986) Change in view. MIT Press, Cambridge
are deeply connected to each other and yet that neither of McKeon M (2013) On the rationale for distinguishing arguments from
them need involve the other, is by dealing with justification explanations. Argumentation 27:283–303
and persuasion as different achievements of the same Pinto R (1995) The relation of argument to inference. In: van
Eemeren FH, Grootendorst R, Blair JA, Willard CA (eds)
activity, each of them having their own regulative condi- Perspectives and approaches. Proceedings of the third ISSA
tions. To this end, a characterization of argumentation as a conference on argumentation, vol I. SicSat, Amsterdam,
speech-act proves to be specially useful, since it enables us pp 271–286
to describe argumentation both as an illocutionary act that, Simard Smith P, Moldovan A (2011) Arguments as abstract objects.
Informal Logic 31(3):230–261
conventionally, counts as an attempt at showing a target- Turner D, Wright L (2005) Revisiting deep disagreement. Informal
claim to be correct and also as a perlocutionary act that, Logic 25:25–35
instrumentally, may be seen as an attempt at rationally van Eemeren FH, Grootendorst R (1984) Speech-acts in argumenta-
persuading an addressee or audience or at resolving a dif- tive discussions. A theoretical model for the analysis of
discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Foris,
ference of opinion, etc. by giving reasons for a target claim. Dordrech/Mounton de Gruyter, Berlin
In my view, persuading an addressee or audience is the van Eemeren FH, Grootendorst R (1992) Argumentation, communi-
most characteristic end that individuals pursue by giving cation and fallacies. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale
reasons for their claims. Of course, there are other means to Walton D (1989) Informal logic: a handbook for critical argumen-
tation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
persuade. Actually, argumentation is not always the most

123

You might also like