You are on page 1of 17

THE THOMIST®

A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW


OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY

ISSN 0040-6325 OCTOBER, 2012 Vol. 76, No. 4

ARTICLES
Arabic.iblami<.: Philo~ophy in Thomas Aquinas's Conception of the Bc~nific
Vi~ion in IV Sent., D. 49, Q. 2, A. 1 . . . . . . . . . . . RICHARD C. TAYLOR 509

i\taking Something out of Nothing: Privation, Po~~ibility, and Potentiality


in Avicenn<.t and Aquinas . . . .... JON f\1C:Ci>:NI~ 551

Avicenna and Aquina~\. De principiis naturae, cc. 1-3 R. E. HOLT~ER 577

Vis aestirnatiua and vis cogitat1ua in Thomas Aquinas's Con11ner1tary un the


Sentences ............ j0RG ALEJA::--JDRO TELLKA.\11' 611

REVIEWS
Uwe \1ichacl Lang, ed., Tf1e Genius of the Ro1nun Rite: Historical,
Theologicul. and Pastorul Perspectives on Catholic l.iturgy
TR['.\JT P0:>1PLl'N 641

Thon1a~ Joseph \X'hite, ().P., ed., The /\n.ilogy of Being: lnuention of the
Antichrist or the \X'isdon1 of(;od? ........ PAJC,E E. l-IOCH~CHJLD 645

Ulrich C. Leinsle, /11trod11ction to Scholastic Theology .. COR~.'r L. B,\RNF~ 649

Garth Hallett, Theology U'ithin the Bounds of Langu.ige: A 1Vlethodolugical


Tour..... ............... TFRRANCF '\/./.KLEIN 653

~lichaclBannvell, The Problem of 1"v.'eg!tge11t ()rnissions: ;\fedieval Action


Theories to the Rescue ...... jA.\1IE A"!\"NE SP!ERll\"C 657

Georg CJ.sser, ed., Personal Identity and Resurrection: I-Jou' Do \X1e Surviue
()ur Death? . . . BRY ..\>J KROi\IHOl I z, ().r. 661

Piotr LichJ.cz, O.P., Did Aquinas Justify the Fransition fron1 'ls' to
'Ought'? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . BRL.\C\" CHRZASTEK, l).P. 665
'the Ihornist 76 (2012): 611-40

VIS AESTIMATNA AND VIS COCITATNA IN THOMAS


AQUINAS'S COMMENTARY ON THE SENTENCES

jORG ALEJA~DRO TELLKAMP

U1uversidad AutUno1na A1etroµolitana


lvfexico Ctty, Alcxico

N THOMAS AQUINAS'S MATURE WORK, for instance in

I the Summa Theologiae or in the commentaries on De anima


and De sensu et sensato, we find an elaborate discussion of the
mechanisms of perception. In agreement with the Aristotelian
tradition, AqLiinas distinguishes five external senses, whose task it
is to grasp and discern the essential sensibles, such as color and
sound (sensihilia propria) and size, shape, and movement
(sensibilia communia). 1 Since this information about an object's
qualitative and quantitative features docs not yet yield complete
knowledge of the individual object, he posits according to the
Aristotelian-Arabic tradition that animals have inner senses, which,
based on the actual perception achieved by the external senses,
compose and divide the information grasped. Aquinas calls this
information intentiones, which roughly stands for those aspects of
material, individual objects which are not directly apprehended by
the external senses, as when a bird identifies a straw as a suitable
object for building a nest.
In addition to the five external senses, Aquinas distinguishes
four different inner senses, which describe different ways in which
sensible forms can be grasped. (1) The common sense (sensus
communis) unifies the stimuli of external senses, while (2)
imagination or fantasy (imagination seu phantasia) composes,
• divides, and stores those forms. (3) Memory and reminiscence
1

On the topic of extern.1! ~ensation, ~ce the still \·aluable ankle of G. van Ricr, "L:i th Corie
thorni~re de la ~ensarion exrerne," Revue µhilosophique de f_ou11ai11 5 J (1953): _)74-408.

611
,I

r
612 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AESTIMATNA AND VIS COGITATNA 613

(memoria et reminiscentia) have the function of storing sensible what a given object means for a perceiving subject. 3 Hence, when
forms insofar as they belong to the past and (4) vis cogitativa or vis a sheep sees a wolf as dangerous, it apprehends relevant aspects
aestimativa grasps the intentional content of those forms. The vis that are not seen directly, but that are apprehended on the basis of
cogitativa is found exclusively in human beings, whereas the vis sensory stimuli together with the activity of the vis aestimativa.
aestimativa of higher animals has an analogous function and The most important feature of intentiones is (1) that they point
occupies the same physiological space in the brain as the vis at what an object means for a proper recipient, and (2) that they
cogitativa. The latter is permeated with reason, but the former is allow one to distinguish mere natural processes, like the heating
not. The vis aestimativa explains the sensory processes achieved of a stone, from processes that involve a cognitive change in the
by higher animals, such as sheep and dogs, in virtue of the organic, perceiving subject. 4 For Aquinas, intentiones are not only
material composition of their brain. The vis cogitativa, in contrast, apprehended by the mind; they are also properties of material
is a cognitive function exclusive to human sensation, which has an objects, which are neither accidental nor substantial and which are
organic component as well as an "immaterial" one, because it in need of a proper faculty in order to be grasped as such. 5 This
somehow participates in intellectual processes. This means that faculty is the vis aestimativa in the case of higher animals, such as
although both powers (vis aestimativa and vis cogitativa) are dogs and birds, and the vis cogitativa in the case of human beings.
rooted in roughly the same part of the brain, that is, in the middle Because of its resemblance with Aquinas's own point of view it
ventricle, they point at distinct forms of sensory experience, might be useful to outline what intentionality amounts to based on
mainly because in human beings the participation with the intellect Fred Dretske's naturalized theory of the mind. According to this
adds a rational ingredient which animals lack. Therefore, in approach, intentional content has (1) the power to misrepresent,
Aquinas's mature theory the vis aestimativa of higher animals and very much like when someone wrongly says that a tower, when
the human vis cogitativa are essentially different powers, which seen from afar, is round, when it really is square. 6 (2) The
grasp sensible intentions either under the aspect of their practical aboutness of intentional experiences relates to other states
relevance (vis aestimativa) or as particular instances that are regarding certain properties; for example, when seeing an orange,
perceived as being part of universal notions (vis cogitatzva). one can think that it is round, one may desire it because it is sweet,
Since the inner senses grasp aspects of material objects that are and so on. (3) The aspectual shape an object takes in our
not perceived properly, that is, intentiones, a basic and brief experience stems from the acknowledgment that it can generate an
account of this notion is required. 2 Although it has a wide range experience of itself under one aspect rather than another, for
of meanings in Aquinas's thought, in the context of his discussion instance, when a pie is seen as good for eating as opposed to being
of perception and knowledge intentio stands, broadly speaking, seen as adequate for smashing into someone's face. (4) Intentional
for the cognitive content attached to an object, which encompasses experience is, finally, directed at objects; in the case of Aquinas's

1
A thorough discussion of Aquinas's theory of intentionality with regard to perception can
be found in D. Perler, Theorien der Tntentionalitiit im Mittelalter (Klo~tern1ann: Frankfurt,
2002), 42-60.
2 4
Although the notion of intentio is primarily introduced into the thirteenth-century Aquinas, STh J, q. 78, a. 3.
philosophical discussion about perception and knowledge rhroughAvicenna'sDeanima, I will ' for a n1ore detailed account of the role of intentio in Aquinas's causal theory of
not dwell on the Av1cennian antecedent given the wealth of publications on this topic. See D. perception, see J. A. Tellkamp, "Aquinas on Intentions in the Medium and in the h.1ind,"
Ha~se, Avicenna's De anima in the Latin West (London: The Warburg Institute; T urin:Nino Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80 (2006): 275-89.
Aragno Editore, 2000), 127-53; D. Black, "Estimation (wahm) in Avicenna: The Logical and 1
' F. Dret'ike, Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, t\1ass., and London: MIT Press, 1995),

Psychological Dimensions," Dialogue. Canadian Philosophical Review 32 (1993): 219-58. 28-34.


614 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AESTIMATIVA AND VIS COG/TAT/VA 615

theory of intentionality it is fair to assume that this directedness Dominican's account also has to be understood within his
has something to do with individual, material objects and not just contemporary context, where Albert the Great stands out as one
with intentional experience itself. of the most important sources.
The aim of this article is to show that Aquinas's distinction
between an exclusively human vis cogitativa and a vis aestimativa A) Avicenna
present in higher animals is the result of a process of clarification
that took place early in his career while he was working on the Avicenna's system of the inner senses, which are located in the
Commentary on the Sentences. In his scattered remarks on inner brain, comprises receptive and retentive powers. The common
sensation, he initially seems to endorse an Avicennian view insofar sense (sensus communis) receives forms, but does not retain them.
as the perception of intentions, animal as well as human, stands The formative imagination (imaginatio), however, retains them,
under the influence of estimation (aestimatio). As the Commentary because it has the adequate material composition in the frontal
progresses, however, Aquinas changes his view to lean towards ventricle of the brain after receiving the sensible forms grasped by
Averroes's tenets, that is, positing a human vis cogitativa or, as the common sense. 8 The middle ventricle houses the compositive
Aquinas describes it, ratio particularis. The shift from Avicenna to imagination (imaginativa) whose funcrion it is to divide and
Averroes explains how, for Aquinas, perception has to be seen in compose that which has heen transmitted by the formative
the broader context of his theory of cognition, which in its most imagination. It is important to note that when a human being is
perfect form is intellective. In his mature work, he still thinks that using the compositive imagination, it actually becomes an
the Avicennian model regarding animal perception of intentions instrument of thought (cogitans comparatione animae humanae).
is accurate, yet he takes an Averroistic stance when it comes to the The superior part of the middle ventricle houses the estimative
human grasp of sensible intentions. This insight into his earliest power, which "apprehends the non-sensed intentions, which are
account of these powers of the soul is a valuable contribution to in the particular sensible object" (apprehendens intentiones non
our understanding of his complex mature teachings. sensatas quae sunt in singulis sensibilibus). Finally, in the posterior
ventricle are memory and reminiscence, which retain the
I. AVICENNA, AVERRo~·s, AND ALBERT THE GREAT intentions grasped previously by the estimative power. 9
ON THE INNER SENSES It is clear that, in Avicenna's distinction between the virtus
..-t
aestimativa and the virtus cogitativa (mufakkira), only the latter is
The following brief survey requires a methodological caveat of present in human beings. 10 Yet it does not seem to completely
sorts, since only those texts of Arabic authors will be used which supersede the estimative power, insofar as human beings can also
were translated into Latin and which Aquinas read. - In fact, the grasp intentions with that power. The cogitative faculty, in
rather complex doctrine of the "middle powers" in Aquinas rests contrast, is rather the result of the relation between the com-
to a great extent on the Latin versions of Avicenna's De anima and positive imagination and human reason, the explanation of which
Averroes' Long Commentary on the De anima. Yet the encompasses physiological as well as cognitive elements:

- For a 1nore exhaustive account regarding the transmis5ion of Arabic texts into the Latin 8
Avicenna, I.iber de anirna seu sextus de naturalibus l, 5 (vol. Led. S. van Riet [Lou vain:
world, ~ee H. Daiber, "Lateinische Obersctzungen arabischer T exte zur Philosophie und ihre Peeters; Leiden: Brill, 1972J, 87-88).
Bedeutung fi.ir die Scholastik des Mittelalter5," ed. J. Han1esse and M. Fattori, Rencontres de ~Avicenna, De anima 1, 5 (van Riet, ed., 1:89).
10
cultures dans la philosophic rnedieval: Traductions et traducteurs de l'antiquitd tardiue au XIVe D. Black, "Imagination and Estin1ation: Arabic Paradigms and Western
siecle (Louvain-la-Neuve and Cas~ino: fJDEM, 1990), 203-50. Transformation~,'' 'fopoi 19 (2000): 60.
616 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AEST/MATNA AND VIS COGITATNA 617

[The estimative faculty] opens up the cerebellar vermis by removing what is Apart from abstracting intentions from images, the cogitative
between the two porous appendages (which [just] are the cerebellar vermis) and power plays a major part in the process of intellection. 15 Since
[the forn1 that is in the retentive imagination] conjoins with the pneuma
harboring the estimative faculty of the compositive imagination (which in humans
Averroes assumes that the material intellect is separate, and
is called the cogitative [faculty]). The form that is in the retentive imagination is because it is not a particular power, but one for all mankind, he
then imprinted onto the pneuma of the estimative faculty, and the faculty of the has to show how particular human beings can entertain particular
compositive imagination, which serves the estimative faculty, conveys what is in thoughts. This is where the cogitative power comes in, because
the retentive i1nagination to it. 11
"withont the imaginative power and the cogitative [power] the
intellect which is called material understands nothing." 16 As
B) Averroes Richard Taylor aptly puts it: "In this way the particular human
soul's cogitative power is responsible for the processing of the
The approach to the inner senses taken by Averroes is at first particular intentions then presented to the rational power properly
sight similar to that of Avicenna, insofar as Averroes locates those so called-namely, the material intellect and the agent intellect."
17

powers in the brain, thus stating, in agreement with Galen and the It seems, then, that for Averroes the workings of the inner senses
physicians, that they are organic and material in nature: "It was are most relevant when they are put into the context of the
said that the imaginative power is in the anterior part of the brain, acquisition of intellective knowledge. And this means that the
the cogitative in the middle, and the power of memory in the cogitative power has to be seen as a human faculty-unless, as
posterior." 12 It is, then, '"a particular material power," 13 whose Averroes intriguingly adds, animals exist that are superior to the
function it is to discern "the intention of a sensible thing from its 18
human being with the ability to think individually.
imagined image." 14 The main differences between Avicenna and Averroes, at least
11
Translation from the Arahic text in]. McGinnis, Avicenna (Oxford: Oxford University insofar as Aquinas is concerned, is not that Avicenna does not hold
Press, 2010), 110; it corresponds roughly to the following Latin text in Avicenna, De anima the existence of a properly human cogitative power, which is
3, 8, 270-71; "Deinde forma quae est in i1naginatio penetrat posteriorem ventriculum, cum
voluerit virtus aestimativa et elevaverit vcrmcm, et de duobus rnembris quae tenninantur
subservient to the compositive imagination, but rather that
penes vermem fecerit unum, et coniungetur forma cum spiritu qui gerit virtutem Averroes thinks that an account of human perception is relevant
aesti1nativa111, mediante spiritu qui gerit virtute1n imaginativam, quae vocatur in hominibus only insofar as it helps to understand intellective knowledge. This
virtus cogitatiuni~, et furma quae erat in irnaginativa in1primetur in spiritu virtutis
emphasis bears a strong resemhlance to Aquinas's own point of
aestimationis, et virtus irry~inationis <leservit virtuti aestimationis, reddens ei quad est in
imaginariva." See also 1-1. Sebti, Avicenne: L'!bne humaine (Paris: Presses Universitaires de
France, 2000), 64-65. Ji See Taylor, "Introduction," in A;·erroes, Long Commentary on the De anima of
12
Averroes, Commentarium rnagnum in Aristotelis de anima libros 3, 6 (ed. F. Stuart Aristotle, lxix-lxxvi.
10
Crawford [Ca1nbridgc, t-.1ass.: Medieval Academy of America, 1953],415): "Dicitur quod Averroes, Co1nmentarium 1nagnum in De anima, 3, 20 (Crawford, ed., 450): "Sine
virtus ymaginativa est in antcriori cerebri, er cogitariva in media, et rememorativa in virrute yn1aginativa et cogitativa nichil intelligit intellectus qui dicitur marerialis."
1
posteriori" ("It was said that the imaginative power is in the anterior of the brain, rhe - Taylor,"Introduction," in Averroes, Long Co1nmentary un the De anima of Aristotle,

cogitative in the middle, and the po\ver of memory in the posterior" [translation in Averroes, lxix.
Long Commentary on the De anima of Aristotle, trans. and intro. R. Taylor with Th.-A. H Averroes, Curnmentarium magnu1n in De anima, 2, 29 (Crawford, ed., 172-73): "Idest,

Druart (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2009), 33 t ]). et ponamus etiam pro manifesto quad virtus cogitativa et intellectus existunt in aliis modis
13
Averroes, Commentarium magnu1n in De anima, 3, 3 (Crawford, ed., 476). ani1nalium que non sunt homines, et quod proprie sunt in aliquo genere, ur in bominibus, aut
14
Averroes, Commentarium magnum in De ani1na, 3, 6 (Crawford, ed., 415): in alio gcnere, si den1onstratio surgat quod alia sunt huiusmodi; et hoc erit si fuerint equales
"Dcdaratum est enim illic quod virtus cogitativa non est nisi virtus que distinguit intentionem hominibus aut me1iores eis" ("That is, let us also assert [itJ as clear that the cogitative power
rei sensibilis a suo idolo ymaginato" ("For it was explained that the cogitative power is only and the intellect exist in other kinds of ani1nals which are not human beings and that they are
a power which discerns the intention of a sensible thing: fro1n its imagined image" [Taylor, properly in some genus, as in [that of] human beings, or in a differeut genus, if a
trans., 331J). demonstration arises that there exist different things of this sort" [Taylor, trans., 137]).
618 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AEST/MATIVA AND VIS COGl1ATIVA 619

view. Unlike Avicenna, in the Long Commentary on the De anima Albert's basic notions on perception and, in general, on the
Averroes does not discus animal cognition as a proper field of processes in the natural world could have influenced Aquinas. 23
research. In contrast, Avicenna does so under the heading of the In De homine Albert explains (1) how sensible forms are
virtus aestimativa, which is present in animals as well as human acquired and (2) how mental representations of particular objects
beings. But according to Aquinas the virtus cogitativa is an are formed. In order to come to terms with the different forms of
exclusively human faculty which supersedes the estimative power, inner apprehension, he sets out to analyze each inner sense
and it is precisely this point which he owes to Averroes. regarding its nature (quid est), object (quid obiectum), organ (quid
organum), and act (quid actus). He assumes that the notion of
C) Albert the Great sensus interior is not a univocal concept. This can clearly be seen
in his characterization of phantasia, which can be conceived of in
The first half of the thirteenth century saw a host of a broad (large) sense and a narrow (stricte) sense:
commentaries and treatises written on the soul. 19 While most of
them take Avicenna as a point of departure, like that of John of la We say that fantasy is predicated in two ways, that is, in a broad and in a narrow
Rochelle, there are also some works that focus on Averroes, such sense. It i~ broad insofar as it enco111passcs imagination, fantasy and estimation.
... In its narrow sense it i~ understood as a plnvcr that gathers images through
as the anonymous commentary on De anima edited by R.-A. con1position and division . . . . Therefore says Ghazali that some called it a
Gauthier. 20 Thus when Albert the Great (ca. 1200-1280) started thinking power rpotentiam cogitativam], as Avicenna called it. But only in human
to write on issues related to the nature of the soul and its powers, beings it is properly thinking [cogitativa]. 24
as, for instance, in his monumental De homine (finished ca. 1245),
there was already a lively discussion underway, which, although Albert thinks that there are only small organic differences between
mostly Avicennian in tone, also had ample room for discussing these inner senses; he also says that their respective objects are
notions from Averroes' Long Commentary on the De anima. In the similar. The main criterion for establishing them as inner senses is
formative years before his work on the Commentary on the that their activity has to be the same: they produce mental
Sentences and De ente et essentia, Aquinas was Albert's pupil, first representations (phantasmata) of objects which do not need to be
from 1245 to 1248 in Paris and afterwards as his assistant in physically present, although they might be present. 25
Cologne until 1252. 21 Since book II of the Commentary on the
Sentences was pr~bably written around 1252-54 and book IV
n j.-P. Gauthier, "Preface," in Thomas Aquinas, Sententia Libri De anima (editio Leonina
4511 fR01ne: Co1nmissio Lconina; Paris: Vrin, 1.984J, 222*0.
probably finished hefore 1256,22 it is fair to assume that some of 24
Albertu'i Magnus, De ho1nine, "De partibu~ animae scnsibilis, quae sunt apprehensivae
deintus," 2.1 (editio Colonicn~is 27/2 [Mlinster: Aschendorff, 2008], 289): "Dicimus quod
phantasia dicirur duobus modis, scilicet large et stricte. Large, secundum quod comprehendit
19
See again Hasse, Avicenna's De anima in the Latin West. imaginationem et phantasiam ct aestimatione1n . . . . Stricte autem accipitur pro potentia
Saine of the treatise~ and commentaries worth mentioning that were written prior to
lo collativa imaginum per co1npositione1n et divisionem, er sic diffinitur ab Algazele, et ideo
Albert and Aquinas are the anonyn1ous Lectura in librum de anima a quodam discipulo etiam dicit Algazel quod qufdam appellant cam potentiam cogitativam, sicut appellat earn
reporlata, ed. R.-A. Gauthier (Crottaferrata: Collegii S. Bonaventurac ad Claras Aquas, 1985), Avicenna; sed tamen cogitativa non est proprie nisi in hominibus .., The translations of Albert's
written around 1245-50; the as yet unpublished In de anima Aristotelis of Richard Rufus (ca. texts here cited are mine. It has been noted that Ghazali's text is a rather free interpretation
1236-37), currently being edited by Rega Wood; John of la Rochelle, Su1nn1a de anima, e<l. of of Aviccnna'sDiinesh-Niimeh; see, e.g., J. Janssens, "Le Diinesh-Niimeh d'lbn Slnli: un texte
J. G. Bougerol (Pari~: Vrin, 1995), written ca. 1235-36; Pseudo-Peter of Spain, Expositio libri a revoir?", Bulletin de philosophie medievale 28 (1986): J 63- 77.
de anima, Obras fi!os6ficas III, ed. M. Alonso (~1adrid: C.S.LC, 1950), written around J 240. 25
Albertus ~lagnus, De homine 2, 1.1 (Cologne ed., 283): "Dicitur quandoque imaginatio
21
j.-P. Torrell, Initiation asaint Thomas d'Aquin: Sa personne et son oeuvre (Pari~: Cerf; omnis virtus sensibilis animae, quae operatur super sensibilc acceptun1 a sensibus sine
Fribourg: Editions Universitaires du Cerf, 1993), 480. pracsentia materiae ct sine ratione praeteriti te1nporis, ct sic comprehendit imaginationem et
22
Ibid., 485. phantasiam et aestimatione1n" ("Son1erimes imagination is said to be every power of the
620 ]ORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AESTIMATIVA AND VIS COGITATIVA 1'21

By the time Albert wrote on the inner senses he already had to and which are located in the brain. 31 This is one reason why they
deal with various approaches to the subject, which led to different are apprehensivus ab intus. 32
classifications. 26 Hence he takes into consideration the accounts of But what does it mean to sense something from within? Why
Nemesius of Emesa and Qusta ibn Luga. According to both are the inner senses called senses at all? In opposition to his theory
authors, there are three inner senses, which correspond exactly to of the proper senses, Albert thinks that the brain, in itself, is not
one brain ventricle each: the imaginative faculty is located in the a sense organ. The reason for this is that sensation generally is
frontal ventricle, the excogitativum in the middle, and memory in related to the flow of blood stemming from the heart. 33 Without
the posterior ventricle. 27 Following the wording proposed by blood there is no sensation at all, but in the brain there is no blood
Nemesius, Albert relates the division of the brain ventricles to the and hence there is no heat which sensation generally requires.
proper function achieved by each one: "there are three cells in the Sense knowledge has, then, a necessary physiological counter-
head, i.e., the anterior, the posterior and the middle. The authors part that helps to explain the meaningful grasp of a particular
call the first fantastic [phantastica], the second is logical [logistica], object (intentiones), in the sense that the imaginatio and virtus
and the third is memory." 28 This threefold distinction also echoes aestimativa only function as faculties rooted in the brain. This
Averroes' position: "It was said that the imaginative power is in meaningful grasp is achieved by the inner senses putting a certain
the anterior of the brain, the cogitative in the middle, and the emphasis on practical issues, such as desiring, fleeing, and so on.
power of memory in the posterior."'" Although it appears that This is the way Aquinas sees the role of estimation in book II of
Albert is keen to maintain Nemesius's and Qusta ibn Luqa's the Commentary on the Sentences. And hence it is plausible to
classification of three ventricles, he moves closer to Avicenna with think that he follows the Avicennian interpretation of the inner
regard to the number of the inner senses. 30 In fact, he consistently senses.
states that there are five inner senses, which are organic in nature
II. AQUINAS

sensible soul, which operates on the sensible object grasped by the senses ·without a present A) Aquinas's Standard Theory: "Summa Theologiae" and
matter and with the aspect of a past tense; and in this sense it encon1passes imagination, "Commentary on De anima"
fantasv, and estimation").
2" Cf.N. Steneck, "Albeft the Great on the Classification and Localization of the Internal
Senses," Isis 65 {1974): 193-211.
In order adequately to show the process of development
P See Ncmesius, De natura ho1ninis: Traduction de Burgundiu de Pise 11.86 (ed. G. Aquinas's theory underwent in the Commentary on the Sentences,
Verbeke and]. R. Moncho [Leiden: Brill, 1975], 59-67); also Costa ben Luca (Qusta ibn it will be helpful to present a broader picture of what can be
Luga), De differentia animae et spiritus (ed. C. S. Barach [Innsbruck: Verlag der Wagner'schen
considered his standard view of the distinction between vis
Univcrsitaetsbuchhandlung, 1878], 124-30); and Averroes, Commentarium magnum in De
anima 3, 20 (Crawford, ed., 449). aestimativa and vis cogitativa, such as we find it mainly in the
H Albertus .Magnus, De homine 2, 2.4 (Cologne, ed., 291): "Dicendum quod tres sunt Summa Theologiae and the Commentary on De anima. Generally
ccllulae capitis, scilicet anterior et posterior ct media. Et prima dicitur phantastica ab speaking, the inner senses as a whole, and the distinction between
auctoribu~, secunda logistica et tertia n1en1oriali~."
29
See Averroes, Commentarium magnum in De anima, 3, 6 (Crawford, ed., 415): "Dicitur n See G. Klubertanz, The Discursive Power: Sources and Doctrine of the Vis cogitativa
quad virtus ymaginativa est in anteriori ccrebri, et cogitativa in media, et rememorativa in according to St. Thomas Aquinas (Saint Louis: The Modern Schoolman, 1952), 134ff.; and
posteriori" (Taylor, trans., 331). H. A. Wolfson, "The Internal Senses in Latin, Arabic, and Hebrew Texts," The Harvard
10 Tt might be noted that Avicenna himself uses the threefold distinction of the ventricles, Theological Review 28 (1935): 116-20.
\vhich had been canonical since Galen, yet Albert does not appeal to him in order to establish l l Avicenna, De anima I, 5 (van Riet, ed., 83).

it. n See Qusta ibn Luqa, De differentia animae et spiritus (Barach, ed., 130).
622 jORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AEST/MATNA AND \ITS COGTTATIVA 62.1

the vis cogitativa and the vis aestimativa in particular, play a This passage highlights several points. Aquinas establishes a
crucial role in explaining how, in the context of a causal theory of distinction between vis cogitativa and vis aestimativa on the basis
perception, meaningful (i.e., intentional) knowledge of particular of their cognitive scope: the vis cogitativa grasps intentions as
objects is acquired. Aquinas holds that only the activity of the vis standing under a common nature and the vis aestimativa grasps
aestimativa or respectively of the vis cogitativa leads to the intentions only insofar as they yield passions and actions. Since
apprehension of intentions. Yet the reason these faculties are only sensory processes of human beings participate in reason, it
essentially distinct resides in the fact that human beings are can be concluded that only human beings have vis cogitativa. In a
rational and higher animals are not. In fact, in order to describe way reminiscent of Averroes, Aquinas calls this faculty ratio
the vis cogitativa Aquinas uses the concept of ratio particularis particularis, whereas the vis aestimativa stands for the instinctive
which, while grasping individuals, already recurs to universal reaction of animals in the presence of certain stimuli.
notions (rationes). This is made possible because the vis cogitativa That the vis cogitativa is ratio particularis means that a given
participates in intellectual activities. 34 To clarify further the state of affairs or experience is seen as pertaining to general
distinction between vis aestimativa and vis cogitativa Aquinas notions, so that someone can, for instance, see "this human being"
explains that because he or she possesses the universal concept of "human
being" (i.e., rational animal), which includes at least a vague idea
rhe cogitative and estimative powers stand differently in this regard li.e. to of how human beings are: two legs, arms, a head, and so on.
apprehending intentions]. For the cogitative power apprehends an individual as
Animals, however, only grasp the intentional content an ex-
existing under a common nature [sub natura communi]. It can do this insofar as
it is united to the intellective power in the sa1ne subject. Thus it cognizes this perience entails insofar as it produces an action or emotional
human being as it is this human being, and this piece of wood as it is this piece reaction. In this sense Aquinas argues that in human beings the vis
of wood. But the estin1ative power apprehends an individual, not in terms of its cogitativa replaces the vis aestimativa of higher animals. l6
being under a common nature, but only in terms of its being the end point or The vis aestimativa 's apprehension of states of affairs relevant
starting point of son1e action or affection. It is in this way that a sheep recognizes
the lamb not inasmuch as it is this lamb but inasmuch as it can nurse it. It to behavior is a prerequisite for adequate reactions, since the sheep
recognizes this grass inasmuch as it is its food. Thus its natural estimative power is not concerned with the wolfs essence; its reaction is instinctive.
in no way apprehends any individual to which its acting or being affected does No animal grasps rhe intentional content of the world it perceives
not extend. For the natural estimative power is given to animals so that through because it hopes to gain a significant knowledge of it; it
it they are directed·~toward the proper actions or affections that should be
apprehends the intentiones quas sensus non apprehendit so it can
pursued or avoided. H
survive and live adequately. 17
14
Aquinas, II De anima, 13 (Leonine ed., 121-22). See also Caurhier, Preface, 225* on the Aquinas's theory of the inner senses has much in common with
Averroistic origin of the of the ratio particularis in Aquinas's conunenrary on De anima.
15
Aquinas, [J De ani1na, 13 (Leonine ed., 122): "Differenter tamen circa hoc se habet
Albert's, but it also differs from it in various respects. The first is
cogitatiua ct estimatiua: na1n cogitatiua apprchendit indiuiduum ut existente1n ~ub natura that Aquinas posits a faculty proper to human beings that
communi, quad contingit ei in quantum unitur intel!ectiue in eodem subiecto, undc cognoscit substitutes for the vis aestimativa proper of higher animals. Albert
hunc homine1n prout est hie homo ct hoc lignum prout est hoc lignum; csti1natiua autem non still thought that what makes human sensation properly human is
apprehendit aliquod indiuiduum secundum quod est sub natura comn1uni, set solum
~ccundum quod est terminus aut principiu1n alicuius action is ucl passion is, sicut ouis eognoseit
hunc agnum non in quantun1 est hie agnus, set in quantun1 est ah ea lactabilis, et bane herbam
in quantum est eius eibus; unde illa indiuidua ad que se non extend.it eius actio uel passio, trans. Robert Pasnau (Nev.' Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1999), 208.
nullo modo apprchcndit sua estin1atiua naturn.li: naturalis enim estimatiua datur animalibus ;(, STh l, q. 81, a. 3: ''Loco aute1n aestimativac virtutis est in homine ... vis cogitativa."
1
ut per earn ordinentur in aetiones proprias uel passioncs prosequendas uel fugiendas." The -Thon1as Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae De anima, q. 13 (editio Leonina 24/1 [Rome:
translation has been taken fron1 Tho1nas Aquinas, A Commentary on Aristotle's De anima, Commi~~io Leonina; Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1996], 117-18).
624 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AESTIMATIVA AND VIS COGITATIVA 625

the fact that aestimatio works under the guidance of reason. 38 In the fact that some sensory faculties, which are localized in the
contrast one may consider the following text from Aquinas's brain, realize quasi-rational processes of distinction and judgment
thirteenth disputed question De Anima: about the material world.
The main issue at stake appears to be the following. Human
Certain intentions, which the senses do not grasp, are required, such as .. harmful" sense perception relates essentially to the knowledge of
or "useful" and the like. And man achieves knowledge of them researching and individuals, and yet the proper function of the vis cogitativa
gathering; other animals, however, [know themJ through a certain instinct, like
consists in representing individuals sub natura communi, which,
the sheep that naturally flees fron1 the wolf as something harmful. Therefore, in
other animals natural estimation is ordered to those [intentions]; in man, as Aquinas explains, sterns from the fact that the cogitative power
however, it is the vis cogitativa, which gathers particular intentions, due to which has a close relationship with the intellect. The fact that he also uses
it is called particular reason and passive intellect.'~ the terms ratio particularis and intellectus passivus to describe the
cogitative power indicates that reason is effectively at work in the
What makes the vis cogitativa a quasi-rational faculty is that it realm of the senses. As will be shown below, this terminology is
"researches" and "gathers." Although it is accurate to say that derived from Averroes' Long Commentary on De anima. 41
Aquinas posits a sharp distinction between sensory and rational Given that the vis cogitativa is an inner sense located in the
powers,4° there remains a puzzle about how to reconcile the brain, whose function is to grasp individual states of affairs, how
assumption that human beings have an immaterial intellect with does it relate to the intellect, so that it can grasp an individual sub
natura communi? Put differently: how is the knowledge of the
.H Albertus Magnus, De anima 3, 1.3 {editio Coloniensis 7/1 lMiinster: Aschendorff,
individual sub natura communi accomplished, considering that the
1968], 168): "Est autem adhuc advertendum, quod ista virtus animae in homine, sicut et
ceterae, aliquando coniungitur rationi, et tune iuvatur a ratione et suadetur ad imitandum,
intellect itself only grasps universals? 42 Also, if there is a faculty of
quod aestimat, vel fugiendum. Et propter hanc similitudinem sui in homine ad opinionem the brain that grasps individuals, why does the intellect somehow
quidam philosophorum, sicut Plato, earn opinionem quandam esse asserebant et non differre achieve the sarne? 43 By definition, the intellect's proper object is a
in homine et in brutis nisi per magis esse obumbratam in bruris et minus in hominibus. Sed
See, e.g., Thomas Aquina~, Summa contra Gentiles TI, c. 80 (ed. C. Pera [Turin and
41
falsum est, quod dicunt, quia opinio est de communi, prout est in pluribus, aestimatio autem,
secundum quad huiusmodi, non recedit ab hoc individuo, secundum quod est hoc, et ideo in Rome: Marietti, 1961J, 233): "[Anima] nihil intdligit sine intellectu passivo, quern vocat
homine iuvata ratione non iuvatur, nisi prout est circa hoc vel illud, et rune dicitur proprio virtutem cogitativam" ("[The soul] understands nothing without the passive intellect, which
nomine aestimatio" ("One must bear in mind that this power of the soul [i.e., estimation], like is called cogitative power") See also STh I, q. 79, a. 2, ad 2: "Secundum alios autem
the others, in man someti~s conjoins reason. In that case it is helped by reason, and it is inrellectus passivus dicitur virtus cogitativa, quae nominatur ratio particularis" ("According
convinced to imitate what it estimates or flee from it. Because in man it is similar to opinion, to other lauthors] the passive intellect is called cogitative power which obtains the name of
some philosophers such as Plato stated that it is a certain opinion and that it only differs in particular reason"). See also R. Taylor, "Cogitatio, Cogitativus and Cogitare: Remarks on the
man and in anin1als in that it is more overshadowed in animals and less in men. But what they Cogitative Power in Averroes," in J. Hamesse and C. Steel, eds., L 'ilaboration du vocabulaire
say is false, because opinion is about what is common inasmuch as it is in many; estimation philosophique aux Mayen Age (Turnhout: Brepols, 2000), 123.
42
as such, however, does not withdraw from this individual inasmuch as it is this. Therefore in STh I, q. 86, a. 1: "Unde intellectus noster directe non est cognoscitivus nisi
man when it is supported by reason it is only supported when it is about this or that; in that universalium."
43
case its proper name is estimation"). Ibid.: "Indirecte au tern, et quasi per quandam reflexionem, potest cognoscere singulare,
39 quia, sicut supra dictum est, etlam postquan1 species intelligiblles abstraxir, non potest
Q. D. De anima, q. 13 (Leonine ed., 117-18): "Quarto autem requiruntur alique
intentiones qua~ sensus non apprehendit, sicut nociuum et utile, et alia huiusmodi; et ad hec secundun1 eas actu intelligere nisi converrendo se ad phantasmata, in quibus species
quidem cognoscenda peruenit hon10 inquirendo et conferendo, alia uero animalia quodam intelligibiles intelligit, ut dicitur in III de anima. Sic igirur ipsum universale per specien1
naturali instinctu: sicut ouis naturaliter fugit lupum tamquam nociuum; uncle ad hoc in aliis intelligibile1n direcre intelligir; indirecte autem singularia, quorum sunt phantasmata. Et hoc
animalibus ordinatur estimatiua naturalis, in homine autem uis cogitatiua, que est collatiua modo fonnat hanc propositionem, Socrates est homo" ("Indirectly, however, and by means
intentionum particularium; unde et ratio particularis dicitur, et intellectus passiuus." of a certain reflexion, it can understand the singular, because ... even after it has abstracted
40
R. Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature: A Philosophical Study of Summa the intelligible species, it cannot under~rand them in act unless it turns it~clf to the phantasms
theologiae 1 a 75-89 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 267. in which it understands the intelligihle species. . Thi~ is, therefore, how it directly
626 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AESTIMATIVA AND VIS COG/TAT/VA 627

universal. But knowing an individual qua individual has to include This passage highlights the terminological troubles Aquinas faces.
the knowledge of some, if not all, particular features that The fact that the inner senses somehow participate in the
constitute it. And in fact Aquinas stresses that the intellect is intellective powers suggests that both are somehow conjoined
unable to grasp particular objects directly and primarily (directe et (coniungitur). With conjunction, however, arises the problem of
primo). This limitation is due to the fact that the intellect cannot interaction between the inner senses and the intellect, because
grasp things materially, because, by definition, intellectual there is no ready way to explain how they are conjoined. On the
knowledge is immaterial in all of its aspects. Hence, the intellect other hand, Aquinas insists that the intellect and the senses have
knows only the universal. 44 virtually nothing in common: the intellect is immaterial, the vis
This leaves, however, plenty of room to debate whether and cogitativa is organic. Even if the intellect's performance diminishes
how the intellect achieves knowledge of particular things. In this due to reduced sensory activity, this does not indicate the
regard, Aquinas says that the intellect can grasp individuals existence of a connection between the two. It only shows that, in
indirectly, as through a process of reflection. 41 The agent intellect the process of abstraction, the intellect can only operate to the
not only directs itself actively towards mental representations of extent the outer and inner senses do. 48
individuals (phantasmata), it also actively reaches out to the
individual in order to know it as such. Hence this form of reflexio B) "Vis aestimativa ·· and "vis cogitativa" in Aquinas's "Com-
allows the knowing subject to understand that a particular object, mentary on the Sentences"
for example, Socrates, falls under a certain universal concept, a
species or genus. 46 In the preceding remarks I laid out the broader context of
Aquinas himself points out that the relationship between the Aquinas's theory of the inner senses. When it comes to the
intellect and the vis cogitativa has to be understood in terms of the scrutiny of his treatment of sense knowledge, and especially of his
latter's participation in the former: notion of the inner senses, his early works seem to be an unlikely
place to look for full-blown discussions on the topic. In fact, the
This sort of apprehension in a human being is produced through the cogitative Commentary on the Sentences contains only a few scattered
po\·Ver. This is also called particular reason, because it joins universal concepts remarks on sense knowledge in books II, III and IV, all in
[rationumj. But all the same, this power is in the soul's sensory part. For the
theological contexts. However, I will argue that one of the most
sensory power, at its higQ~st level, participates some¥.rhat in the intellective power
in a human being, in wii6'n1 sense is connected [coniungitur] to intellect.
47 striking features of those texts is that they show how Aquinas finds
his way to his standard theory through his first encounter with
understands the universal through the intelligible species, yet indirectly runderstanding] the Avicenna's and Averroes' psychological theories.
singular about which are the phantasrns. And in this way it fonns this proposition: 'Socrates While Aquinas uses notions derived from Avicenna's De anima
is a n1an "').
44 STh I, q. 86, a. 1: "lntellectus autcm noster . . inrelligit abstrahendo specie1n in order to understand how higher animals grasp and react to their
inrelligibilcm ab huiusmodi 1nateria. Quod autem a materia individuali abstrahitur, est
univcrsale." hec uis est in parte sensitiua, quia uis sensitiua in sui suppremo participat aliquid de ui
4
' Ibid.: "Indirecte autem, et quasi per quandam reflexioncm, potest [intellectus nosterl intcllecriua in homine, in quo scnsus intelkctui coniungitur" (Pasnau, trans., 208). See also
cognoscere singularia." Averroes, Comnientariun1 magnum in De a11i11za 3, 39 (Crawford, ed., 506).
4
46
On this particular point see Averroes, Commentarium magnum in De anima 3, 33 ~ ScG 11, c. 79 (Marietti ed., 231 ). Al~o ScG TT, c. 80 (Marietti ed., 233): "lndiget etiam
(Cra\.vford, ed., 476). anirna ad i11telligendun1 virtutibus praeparantibus phantas1nata ad hoc quod fiant intelligibilia
4
- II De aninia, 13 (Leonine ed., 121 f.): "Huiusmodi quidcm apprehensio in homine fit per actu, scilicet virtute cogitativa et 111en1orativa" ("ln order to understand, the soul also needs
ui1n cogitatiuam, qJe dicitur etiam ratio particularis eo quod est collatiua intentionum powers that prepare the phantasms to become intelligible in act, namely, the cogitative power
indiuidualium sicut ratio uniuersalis est collariua rationum uniuersalium, nichilon1inus tamen and rbc memory").
628 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VISAESTIMATNA AND VIS COGITATIVA 629

environment, the focus changes in his discussion of the vis Avicenna's model of inner sensation, which is based on a detailed
cogitativa, which appears to be influenced by Averroes in that it account of estimation: it explains how animals apprehend
points to a human faculty that plays a crucial role in the intentions based on an instinctive grasp of relevant features as well
acquisition of intellective knowledge. as the way human beings rationally process information obtained
Book I of the Commentary on the Sentences already shows that through the senses. In both cases the inner sense at work is
Aquinas depended on Avicenna and Averroes in many issues, but aestimatio.
the references to both philosophers are limited to theology, Yet in books III and IV Aquinas formulates a slightly different
metaphysics, and physics; references to their psychology are theory of inner cognition, insofar as he shifts his attention from
absent. From the very beginning of his career Aquinas was well estimation to an account of the vis cogitativa as the inner sense
aware of the explanatory power provided by both philosophers. that allows human beings to grasp individual objects under
Their works, metaphysical as well as psychological, had already universal aspects. The reasons for acknowledging the existence of
been widely read and commented on; they can be understood as a genuine human and rational way of inner sensation that allows
a part of an already established tradition that had started in the the apprehension of particular objects under universal considera-
early thirteenth century. 49 tions (rationum) are not altogether clear, since in book II Aquinas
Aquinas's Commentary on the Sentences is theological in already displays an expert interpretation of Averroes' theory of the
nature, and the constraints of the literary genre forced him into intellect and he could have used his theory of inner sensation as
discussing the topics proposed by Peter Lombard. Hence, we do well. 50 But he did not. In any case, the available textual evidence
not find here a philosophical anthropology properly speaking, but does allow us to pinpoint a shift from Avicenna to Averroes.
a series of elucidations on human nature within a theological In order to establish this change, I will discuss the texts
framework. Yet it is noteworthy that when Aquinas discusses chronologically. 51 In book II (d. 20, q. 2, a. 2, ad 5) we find a
man's nature and powers, he consistently uses philosophical terms discussion of whether newly born children have perfect
to do so-including the philosophical terminology introduced by knowledge. The answer is that they do not, because they are not
the Latin translations of Avicenna and Averroes. able to use their cognitive functions properly, since their bodily
This is especially true regarding his remarks on sense complexion is still underdeveloped; this cognitive deficiency,
perception and the workings of the inner senses. In book II of the however, calls for a substitute that enables children to react
Commentary on the'Sentences Aquinas describes inner sensation properly to their surroundings.
in terms of what is suitable or unsuitable. Inner sensation has,
thus, primarily a practical scope, insofar as harm is to be avoided To the fifth argument the answer is that other animals do not seek the suitable
and what is suitable has to be pursued. This characterization of and avoid the harmful by rational deliberation, but by the natural instinct of the
inner sensation in the context of adequate reactions to stimuli is
one of the salient features of Avicenna's account of aestimatio. In
book II Aquinas does not use the expression vis cogitativa or ratio 11
' Thomas Aquinas, Scriptum super libros Sententiarum, lib. 2, d. 17, q. 2, a. 1 (ed. R. P.

Mandonnet [Paris: Lethiel!eux, 1929], 420-.10). On the impact of Avicenna and Averroes on
particularis, which is an indirect reason to think that he follows
discussions in the thirteenth-century Latin West see C. di Martino, Ratio parlicularis: La
doctrine des sens internes d'Avicenne a Thomas J-'Aquin (Paris: Vrin, 2008).
49
See C. Bazin, "13'h Century Commentaries on De anima: From Peter of Spain to 51 Book I of the Commentary on the Sentences does not contain any references to the inner

Thomas Aquinas," in G. Fioravanti, C. Leonardi, and S. Perfetti, eds., II commento filosofico senses and, therefore, it is not taken into consideration. As for the remaining parts, the
nell'occidente latino (secoli XIII-XV)-Philosophica/ Commentaries in the Latin West (13-lS'h translations I quote are taken from Klubertanz, The l)iscursive Power, 152-90. For the sake
centuries) (T urnhout: Brcpols, 2002), 119-84. of clarity I have modified Kluberranz's translation when necessary.
630 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AESTIMATNA AND VIS COGITATNA 631

estimative power, and such natural instinct exists also in children; and so they practical relevance. 56 Likewise, and in a way analogous to the texts
take the breast, and take other suitable things, without anyone teaching them. 52
from book II I will quote below, Aquinas does not here discuss
rational ways of perceiving intentions. This absence, however, is
Aquinas's dependence on Avicenna's theory of estimation in De
significant, because it explains why his early explanation of the
anima 4, 3 is obvious. There the Persian philosopher introduces inner senses omits the virtus cogitativa which is, as stated above,
the notion of instinct as the way estimation works in animals. 53 His
permeated by reason. This absence is underscored by an article in
concept of virtus aestimativa explains how animals, rational
which he discusses whether the knowledge acquired through the
animals included, acquire meaningful knowledge of the physical
sensory powers is adequately discussed in Scripture (utrum
world in order to react to it. This cognitive as well as appetitive
notificatio sensualitatis posita in littera sit conveniens):
reaction, says Avicenna, can be said to occur in various ways. 54
Therefore he distinguishes (1) the mere God-given reflex (cautela It rnust be said that sensualitv and sensibility differ. For sensibility comprehends
proveniens a divina clementia)-such as closing the eyes when an all the powers of rhe sensitiv:c part, those that apprehend from without lde foris]
object suddenly approaches-from (2) instinct properly speaking as well as those that apprehend fron1 within [de intusl, 5- and also the appetitive
(cautelas naturales). While the mere reflex does not imply [pov-.'erj. But sensuality more properly is the nan1c of that part alone by which the
animal is moved to seek or avoid sornething. . . . Now, the power that
cognitive processes, instinct does. Therefore the sheep flees from
apprehends such aspects of Vl-'hat is suitable or unsuitable seems to be t~e
the wolf, because it sees something to be afraid of; the sensory estimative power, by which the lamb avoids the \volf and follo\VS its mother._\x
stimulus of something gray and with such-and-such a shape
triggers that sort of "hard-wired" response:' 5 The sheep cannot but Here, again, Avicenna's influence is undeniable, not only because
run when seeing an object with the characteristics wolves usually it is probably the only occasion in his entire work on which
have (gray fur, large teeth, and so on). (3) On top of this Aquinas quotes him regarding the dichotomy of those powers that
instinctive reaction, there is room for the acquisition of new apprehend from without (de foris) and those that know from
responses to stimuli, for instance, when a dog learns to fear sticks. within (de intus), 5 ' but also because he emphasizes the role of the
All of this means that the virtus aestimativa not only allows for a virtus aestimativa in the process of grasping what is suitable
complex kind of cognition in sense perception, but that it also (conveniens) or unsuitable (inconveniens). It is worth noting that
limits this sort of intentional knowledge to practical purposes. this kind of language, linking the workings of the human inner
The use AquinJt!., makes of this distinction is that children, senses with practical concerns, does not appear in Aquinas's later
before reaching the active use of reason, and due to their bodily
'& This does not mean that Avicenna solely relates aestimativa and aestimatio to the
immaturity, can only instinctively reach out for objects that have assessment of practical issues, \vhich arc rather derived from establishing what is the case; see
Avicenna, De anima 4, 1 (van Rict, ed., 2:8).
2
' II Sent., d. 20, q. 2, a. 2, ad 5 (]\..landonnet, ed., 515): "Ad quintum diccndum, quod alia ,~Avicenna, De anitna 1, 5 (van Rict, ed., l: 83).
ani1nalia non prosequuntur convcniens et fugiunt nocivum per rationis deliberatione1n, sed 18
II Sent., d. 24, q. 2, a. 1 Uvlandonnct, ed, 601): "Respondeo diccndum, quod differt
per naturalem instinctun1 aestin1ativac virtutis: et talis naturalis instinctus est etiam in pueris; sensualitas ct scnsibilitas: sensibilitas cnim omnes vires scnsitivae partis co1nprehendit, tam
unde etiam niamillas accipiunt, et alia cis convenientia, etiam sine hoc quod ab aliis apprehensiva~ de foris, quarn apprehensivas de intus, qua1n etiam appetitivas; sensualitas
doceantur" (translation in Klubertanz, The Discursive l'ower, 159). autem magis proprie illa1n tantum partetn nominat per qua1n movetur an1ma . I in. ar1quo d
s_; Avicenna, Liber de ani1na seu sextus de naturalibus 4, 3 (vol. 2, ed. S. van Riet [Louvain: appetenduin vel fugiendwn. f... ] Vis autem apprehendens hujusmodi rationes convenie~tis
Peeters; Leiden: Brill, 1968], 38ff.). et non convenicntis, videtur virtus acstimativa, per quam agnus fugit lupum et sequitur
'~Avicenna, De anima 4, 3, (van Riet, ed., 2:3 7): "Dicemus igitur quod ip~a aestin1atio fit rnatrcm" (translation in Klubertanz, The Discursive Power, 154f.). The origin of the example
n1ultis n1odis." of the sheep and therefore of the e~timative's grasp of what is suitable or not is Avicenna, De
55
For a more detailed account of Avicenna's notion of instinct, sec Hasse, Avicenna's De aninw l, 5 (van Riet, ed., 1 :86); and 4, 3 (van Riet, ed., 2:38f.).
anima in the Latin West, 135-36. 9
' The relevant passage is Avicenna, De ani1na 1, 5 (van Rict, ed., 1:86).
632 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AEST/MATNA AND VIS COGITATNA 633

works. 60 Yet in the Commentary on the Sentences he explains this Avicenna alone. The shift indicates that between finishing book II
kind of desire stemming from estimation and imagination with an and working on book III Aquinas started to find Averroes' notion
analogy: insofar as choice and action are concerned, estimation is of the virtus cogitativa appealing, probably because it allows for a
like practical reason, while imagination resembles speculative more natural explanation of the link between perceptual and
reason: intellective processes. In book II, in contrast, his focus is either on
the intellect alone or on perception alone, without exploring their
In this way the sensitive apprehensive powers also belong to sensuality, although connection. 62 Hence he realized that it was necessary to posit a
regarding a certain order: because the estimative relates properly to it as the purely human faculty of inner perception, because otherwise it
practical reason to free choice, which also is a n1oving cause; but simple
imagination and the preceding powers have a more re1note relation, like the
would be difficult to explain how the grasp of intentions rests on
speculative reason to the will. 61 the paruc1pat1on in reason if-conceptually as well as
structurally-the inner senses of higher animals are identical to
Although it may not readily be understood this way, these few those of human beings. Only an essentially distinct inner sense, the
texts from book II show that, for Aquinas, human beings, mainly vis cogitativa, could explain that connection.
infants, grasp intentions instinctively through estimation, and that
the foundation for the sensitive grasp of intentions is similar across To the third argument: that power, which the philosophers [philosophiJ call
cogitativa, is at limit betv.'een the sensiti\i·e and the intellective part, where the
different animal species, including the human species. sensitive touches the intellective. It has something from the sensitive part, i.e.,
Yet, as will be shown, Aquinas's understanding of human that it reflects upon particular forms; it has something from the intellective [part],
sensation and the role of the inner senses that play a fundamental namely that it gathers. Therefore it only exists in human beings. 63
part in it changes in a few remarkable aspects in book III. While
in the passages I have quoted he uses the Avicennian notion of the Amongst the philosophi Aquinas reckons Averroes, although he
virtus aestimativa to characterize nonrational as well as rational might also have thought of Ghazali's Metaphysica and Avicenna's
perception, from book III on he starts using the concept of vis De anima. 64 There is, however, another peculiarity that confirms
cogitativa, although he does so to describe human perception. a turn towards Averroes: it is Aquinas's use of the expression ratio
This seems to be, at first sight, a mere terminological change particularis.
compatible with Avicenna's account of the virtus cogitativa. Yet
!,\
there are elements that do not seem to be the result of reading That the animal imagines the forms apprehended by the senses, pertains to the
nature of the sensitive apprehension in itself; but that it apprehends those
611
One might, of course, say that children start out having an estimative power which is
62
later replaced by the cogitative power when they reach the active use of reason. But this See again Gauthier, Preface, 225*. See also the notes on page 121 of the Leonine edition
would contradict the very process of creation by which God made every human being to his of Aquinas's Commentary on De anima. Cf. also Averroes, Commentarium magnum in De
image through rationes primordiales; cf. II Sent., d. 16, q. 1, a. 1 (Mandonnet, ed., 396-401). anima, 3, 20 (Crav.dord, ed., 449); see also ibid., 3, 33 (Crawford, ed., 476); and ibid., 3, 6
This means that God ultimately infuses the complete human soul-together with all its (Crawford, ed., 415).
63
faculties and powers-and that it is not handed down by the parents (traductio). See II Sent., Thomas Aquinas, Scriptum super libros Sententiarum, lib. 3, d. 23, q. 2, a. 2, qda. 1, ad
d. 18, q. 2, a. 1 {Mandonnet, ed., 459-60). Ir would therefore be difficult to explain how a 3 (ed. R. P. Mandonnet [Paris: Lethielleux, 19331, 727): "Ad tertium dicendum, quad ilia
power disappears and another comes into existence. potenria quae a philosophis dicitur cogitativa, est in confinio sensitivae er inrellectivae partis,
61
II Sent., d. 24, q. 2, a. 1, ad 2 (Mandonnet, ed., 603): "Er hoc modo etiam vires ubi pars sensitiva intellectivam attingit. Habet enim aliquid a parte sensitiva, scilicet quod
apprehensivae sensitivae pertinent ad sensualitatem, licet secundum quemdam ordinem: quia consideret forma~ particulares; et haber aliquid ab intellectiva, scilicet quod conferat; uncle
aesti1nativa proprie se habet ad ean1 sicut ratio practica ad liberum arbitrium, quae etiam est et in solis hominibus est" (my translation).
64
mavens; i1naginatio aute1n simplex et vires praecedentes se habent magis remote, sicut ratio Ghazali, Metaphysics: A Medieval Translation, ed. j. T. Muckle (Toronto: St. Michael
speculativa ad voluntatem" (translation in Klubertanz, The Discursive Power, 157). Medieval Studies, 1933), 170.
634 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AESTIMATNA AND VlS COGITATNA 635

intentions, which do not fall under the senses, like friendship, hate and the like,
And:
pertains to the sensitive part insofar as it touches reason. Therefore that part in
men, in whom it is more perfect because of its conjunction with the rational soul,
it is called particular reason, because it compares particular intentions; but in The intention of cogitation is nothing but this, namely, that the cogitative power
other animals, since [that part] does not compare, but apprehends those presents a thing absent form the sense as if it were a sensed thing. For this reason
intentions due to natural instinct, it is not called reason, but estimation. 65 things able to be apprehended by human beings are divided into these two,
namely, into the apprehensible which has as its principle sense and the
apprehensible which has as its principle cogitation. We have already said that the
Even if it is true that the expression itself-ratio particularis-is cogitative power i~ neither the material intellect nor the intellect which is in act,
being used by Aquinas and not by Averroes himself, its semantic but it is a particular nlaterial powcr.h 8
context strongly suggests that it had been derived from an accurate
reading of the Cordoban philosopher. According to Gauthier, The virtus cogitativa is, therefore, reason, hecause it judges and
Aquinas arrives at the concept of ratio particularis by reassembling discerns, but it does only do so with regard to particular images
the meaning of ratio and particularis as found in the Long and intentions. This juxtaposition of discerning and assembling
Commentary on De anima. 66 Thus Averroes himself establishes a particular and universal intentions is clearly adopted by Aquinas. 69
relationship between the cogitative power, reason, and the This notion of ratio particularis would, in fact, become a key
intentions of particular objects. Two short quotations highlight concept in Aquinas's mature discussions of the vis cogitativa. The
this point: explanation he offers for thinking that there is a rational influence
on the sensory level is based on the fact that human beings are
For this reason it vvas said there that when those three powers (i.e. the akin to ontologically superior beings, like angels. Therefore, their
imaginative, the cogitative and the memorative) assist each other, perhaps they
will represent the individual nature of the thing insofar as it is in its being, even aliqua ratio, et actio eius nichil est aliud quam ponere inrcntione1n forme ymaginationis cun1
though we may not sense it. He meant here by passible intellect the forms of the suo individuo apud ren1emorationem, aut distinguere earn ab eo apud formationcm et
i1nagination insofar as the cogitative power proper to hu1nan beings acts upon yn1aginationem" (Taylor, trans., 359).
1
them. For that power is a kind of reason and its activity is nothing but the placing 'H Averroes, Con1n1entarium magnutn in De Ii bros 3, 3.1 (Crawford, ed., 4 76): "Et intentio

of the intention of the form imagined in ils in<livi<luality in memory or the cogit;itionis nichil aliud est gua1n hoc, scilicct ut virtus cogitativa ponat rem abscnrc1n a scnsu
discerning of it from fthe individualJ in conception and imagination. 67 quasi rein sensatam. Et idco comprehensihilia humana dividuntur in hec duo, scilicet in
comprehensibile cuius principium c~t sensus, et comprchensibile cuius principium est
cogitatio. Ft iam dixin1us quad virtus cogitativa non est intellectus materialis neque intellectus
P> III Sent., d. 26, q. ~!t. a. 2: "Quod enim anin1al imaginetur fonnas apprehensas per
qui est in actu, sed est \'irtu~ particularis materia[is" (Taylor, trans., 3 7 9).
sensmn, hoc est de natura se·nsitivae apprehensionis secundun1 ~e; sed quod apprehendat illas
"~ See di Martino, Ratio particularis, 91-93. See also Averroes, Commentariu1n magnum
intentiones quam non cadunt sub sensu ~icut amicitian1, odium et hujusmodi, hoc est
in De anima, 3, 6 (Crawford, ed., 415): "Virtus cnim cogitativa apud Aristotelem est virtus
sensitivae partis sccundum quod aningir rationen1. Unde pars ilia in ho1ninibus, in quibus est
disrinctiva individualis, scilicet quod non distinguit aliquid nisi individualiter, non
perfccrior propter conjunctione1n ad animam rationale111, dicitur ratio particularis, quia
univers.lliter. Dedaranun est enim illic quod virtus cogitativa non est nisi virn1s que distinguit
confert de intentionibus particularibus; in aliis auten1 ani1nalibus, quia non confert, sed ex
intcntionem rei ~en~ibilis a suo idolo yrnaginato; et ista virtus est illa cuius proportio ad has
instinctu naturali habet hujusmo<li intentiones apprehendere, non dicitur ratio, sed aestimatio"
duas intcnriones, scilicct ad idolun1 rei et ad intentionem sui idoli, est sicut proportio sensus
(partial translation in Klubertanz, The Discursive Power, 152-54).
66 co1nn1unis ad intentiones quinque sensuum. Virtus igitur cogitativa est de genere virtutum
Gauthier, Pri(ace, 225 *.
6 existentium in corporihus" ("For the cogitative power according to Aristotle is an individual
- Averroes, Commentarium magnum in De anima 3, 20 (Crawford, ed., 449): "F.t sunt
discerning power, namely, hecause it discerns something only in an individual way, not in a
tres virtutes, quarum esse dcdaratun1 est in Sensu et Sensato, scilicet ymaginativa et cogitativa
univer~al way. For it was explained there that the cogitative power is only a power which
et rememorativa; iste enim tres virn1tes 5unt in homine ad presentanda1n formam rei discerns the intention of a sensible thing from its imagined image. That po\ver is one which
ymaginate quando fuerit sensus absens, et ideo dictum fuit illic quod, cum iste rres virtutes is such that its relation to those t;vo intentions, namely, to the image of a thing and to the
adiuverint se adinvicem, forte representahunt indivi<luu1n rei sccundum quod est in suo esse, intention of its image, is just as the relation of the common sense to the intentions of the five
licet autem non sentiamus ipsuni. Et intendcbar hie per intellcctum passibilem formas senses. The cogitative power, therefore, is of rhe genus of powers existing in bodies" [Taylor,
ymaginationis secundun1 quod in eas agit virtus cogirativa propia homini. lsta enim virtus est trans., 331 ]).
636 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VISAESTIMATNA AND VIS COGITATNA 637

perception of the physical world has to reflect this superiority, Avicenna, in contrast, seeks to account for animal cognition,
which nonrational animals do not have. This notably leads him to not because it is as perfect as intellectual knowledge, but because
set animal cognition apart from human sense knowledge, because its grasp of intentions is similar to human perception. However,
human beings do not possess a virtus aestimativa, but a vts given that the inner senses grasp only individuals together with
cogitativa. 70 So, while in book !I the explanation of the mner their particular attributes, for Avicenna it seems necessary to
senses is Avicennian, in book III Aquinas displays a more explore their organic foundation. Nothing of this can be found in
Averroistic approach. Aquinas, and the increasing shift toward Averroes might be a sign
Another indication for this shift lies in the fact that Aquinas, that he thought that a functional analysis of inner perception, that
generally speaking, does not show a profound interest in the is, an explanation of what the apprehension of intentions amounts
physiological aspects of outer and inner perception. This has to, is sufficient for its portrayal. Physiology does not play a
probably to do with his interest in explaining human cognition, significant role as long as we can explain what the inner senses,
which culminates in intellectual knowledge. Like Averroes, mainly the vis cogitativa, do. This amounts to saying that, while
Aquinas considers that a full account of knowledge is possible only the organic substratum of the vis aestimativa of higher animals and
if the immateriality of the intellect is taken into account. It is the vis cogitativa of human beings is comparable, it is their
telling that Averroes' indications regarding the organic structure functions that essentially differ.
of the inner senses are not very abundant either; instead he limits Aquinas might also have taken Averroes' stance on inner
himself to saying that the vis cogitativa is located in the middle perception because of its subservient role regarding intellectual
ventricle of the brain. 71 Aquinas seems, then, to have Averroes on knowledge; therefore, Averroes' term virtus cogitativa is fitted to
his mind when establishing this particular point. underscore Aquinas's view that the vis cogitativa is an exclusively
70
human faculty. 72 While it is true that Avicenna accounts for a
See also III Sent., d. 35, q. 1, a. 2, qcla. 2, ad 1: "Ad primum igitur dicendum, quod
homo, inquanrum est co_ntemplativus, est aliquid supra hominem: quia in intellectus simplici typically human kind of inner perception, he also explores inferior
visione continuatur homo superioribus substantiis, quae intelligentiae vel Angeli dicunrur, animal knowledge without reference to rational knowledge.
sicut animalia conrinuantur hominibus in vi aestimativa, quae est supremum in eis, secundum Considerations of animal cognition can hardly be found in
quam aliquid simile operibus rationis operantur" ("Man, inasmuch as he contemplates is
Averroes. Aquinas's shift from Avicenna to Averroes indicates an
something above man, because in the understanding of simple vision man is connected to
superior substances whichi.:~re called intelligences or angels; in the san1e way animals are increased interest in the cognitive aspects of human perception, as
connected to man in the estifnative power, which is their highest [power], in which operations opposed to the analysis of the practical cognition higher animals
sin1ilar to that of reason are brought about"). achieve. A passage from book IV of his Commentary on the
" 1 Aquinas, IV Sent., d. 50, q. 1, a. 1, ad 3 (Thomas Aquinas, Commentum in quatuor

librus Sententiarum [Parma: Perri Fiaccadori, 1858], 1248): "Ad tertium diccndum, quod
passivus inrellectus, de quo philosophus loquitur, non est inrcllectus possibilis, sed ratio
2
particularis, quac dicitur vis cogitativa, habens determinatum organum in corpore, scilicet - Averroes, Comtnentarium lnagnum in De anima 3, 6 (Crawford, ed., S30): "Deinde

rnediam cellu!am capitis, ut Co1nmentator ibidem dicit; et sine hoc anima nihil modo dixit: non enim hahet cogitationcm, etc. Idest, et preter ani1nal rationale nullun1 habet
intelligit; intc!liget au rem in futuro, quando a phantasmatibus abstrahere non indigebir" ("The cogitationem, quia non habet rationcm; ct motus anin1alium est propter ddcctationem, et est
passive intellect of which the philosophers speak, is not the possible intellect, but a particular n1otus sin1plex, non diversus, quia non habet virtutem cogitativam cum appetitu ita quad hee
reason which is called cogitative power. It has a specific bodily organ, i.e., the middle ventricle due virtutes dominarcntur sibi adinvicem adeo quod moveretur animal quandoque proptcr
of the head as the Commentator says ... without it the soul does not understand anything; voluntatcm sicut in animali rationali" ("Next he said, 'for it does not have cogitation,' etc.
it would however understand in the future if no abstraction from the phantasms were That is, aside fron1 the rational animal, none has cogitation because none has reason. The
needed"). Sec al50Averroes, Commentarium magnum inDeanima 3, 6 (Crawford, ed., 415): motion of the animal is due to pleasure and it is sin1ple 1notion, not complex [motion I. This
"Et quidam dubitavcrunt in hoc quod fuit dictum (scilicet quod intellectus non haber is because it does not have the cogitative power together with the appetite in such a way that
instrumentum) ex hoc quo<l dicitur quad virtus ymaginativa est in antcriori cerebri, et the two powers con1n1and one another to the extent that the animal is n1oved sometimes on
cogitativa in nlcdio, et rememorativa in posteriori." account of will as [is the case] in regard to the rational animal" [Taylor, trans., 428]).
638 jORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP VIS AEST/MATIVA AND VIS COG/TAT/VA 639

Sentences that looks almost like a commentary on De anima instance when a sheep sees a wolf as its natural enemy, requires
418a8-25 calls attention to this differentiation: the presence of an adequate recipient, that is, the vis aestimativa
or, if a human being perceives a wolf, the vis cogitativa.
That what is sensed per accidens does not induce a change [passio] in the sense, But while according to later writings the vis aestimativa
neither inasmuch as it is a sense, nor inasnn1ch it is this sense, but it is conjoined
apprehends the intentio of a thing under the aspect of desire or
with what per se induces a change in the sense, such as Socrates, the son of
Diares, being friend and such. Those things are kno\vn per se by the intellect as
avoidance, the vis cogitativa goes beyond the mere practical
universals, but 1nan knows them as particulars \Vith the cogitative power and relevance of sense-knowledge. It is in the Commentary on the
1
other ani1nals with the esti1native pcnver.' Sentences that we first see Aquinas setting forth the notion of vis
cogitativa as analogous to practical reasoning, which somehow
As discussed above, Aquinas uses the same terminology in his arrives at a conclusion similar to that of a practical syllogism. 76
Commentary on De anima. There he says that accidental This is a view he apparently found in Averroes, who characterized
perception can be derived from the intellect's involvement in the this inference-like action as a result of the involvement of the
inner senses. This means that when a human being perceives a passive intellect in perceptual processes.r
particular object, it is concomitant with the proper object of the From the Avicennian perspective the perception of intentional
intellect; the inner senses grasp, as it were, universals as part of the aspects is rooted in the physiological as well as in the mental
perceptual experience of particular objects. Hence, when seeing constitution of higher animals, such as human beings, wolves, and
that someone moves, it immediately seen that she lives. 74 Aquinas sheep. The perception of the external object's intention is (1) an
also speaks of sensation per accidens when something is event that does not simply arise within the context of natural
apprehended as an individual (in singulari), that is, that by seeing causes and has to be placed (2) within a theory of cognitive powers
05
one colored object "I perceive this man or that animal." For that (3) help explain how, for example, the sheep "judges" the
instance, when seeing something white, it is also seen that it is wolf to be an enemy of its nature, or that someone sees the son of
Diares's son who has the particular qualitative characteristic of Diares. Although without spelling it out in great detail, the passage
being white. That it is Diares's son, however, is not seen per se, but from book IV quoted already contains Aquinas's mature
it is construed with basic sensory information and a rational
0
background knowl\'dge about people and their general features. - IV Sent., d. 50, q. I, a. 3, ad s.c. J (Parma ed., 1251): '"Ad tcrtium diccndum, quod
intelkctus practicus ad hoc quod de "ingularihus di~ponat, ut dicitur in 3 de anima, indiget
This means that the perception of intentions is not a natural event
ratione p:irticulari, qua 1ncdiante, opinio quae est LmiH:rsalis (quae est in intdlectu) ad
that automatically arises with the perception of sensible qualities parriculare opus applicetur: ut sic quidem fiat syllogis1nus, cujus n1ajor est universalis, quae
and quantities, but that the grasp of sensible intentions, for est opinio intellectus practici; minor vero singulari~, quae est aestimatio rationis particularis,
quae alio nornine dicitur cogitativa: conclusio vero consistit in dcctione opcris" ("The
-, IV Sent., d. 49, q. 2, a. 2 (http://www.corpusthomisticu1n.org): "Per accidens autem practical intellect inasnuich as it reaches out to particular things ... needs the particular
sentitur illud quod non infert passionem sensui neque inquantun1 est scnsus, neque inquantum reason hy me:ins of which the opinion, which is univers.:d (which is in the intellect) is applied
est hie sensus; sec conjungitur his quae per sc sensui infrrunt passionerr1; sicut Socrates, et to the particular action. [This isl like when someone makes a sy1logisn1, whose major premise
filius Diarii, et amicus, ct alia hujusmodi: quae per se cognnscuntur in universali inrellectu; is universal, >vhich is an opinion of the practical intellect; the minor ho-...vever is particular
in particu!ari auter:1 in virtute cogitativa in homine, aesti1nativa autetn in aliis animalibus" (my which i~ the estimation of the particular reason, \vhose other n:irne is cogitative power: the
translation). conclusion consist~ in the choice of an action").
-4 lIDeanima, 13 (Leonine ed., 121): "Non ra1nen omne quod intellectu apprehendi potest Averroee~ explains the n:lat1on bet\\ecn 1rnagmat1on, cogttanon, and practical JOtellect
in re sensata, potest dici scnsibik per accidens, set quod statim ad occursum rei sensate in Averroes, Com1nentari1an magnu1n in De anima 3, 48-50 (Crawford, ed., 515-19). He
apprchenditur intellectu, sicut statirn cum uideo aliquem loquente1n uel moucn: se ipsun1, suggests that whenever the practical intellect does not operate, such as in animals, the
apprehendo per intellectum uita1n eius, unde possu1n dicere quod uideo eum uiuere." imaginanon functions very much like it only that it is based on particular images and not on
75
II De anima, 13 (Leonine ed., 121): "Percipio hunc hominem uel hoc ani1nal." universal intentions.
640 JORG ALEJANDRO TELLKAMP

uuderstanding of sensation per accidens and, therefore, his


understanding of the role the vis aestimativa in animals and the vis
cogitativa in humans.

CONCLUSION

In his Commentary on the Sentences Aquinas is aware of the


relevant terminology regarding the inner senses proposed by
Averroes and Avicenna; in book II of the Commentary he follows
the Avicennian model of estimation, while in books Ill and IV he
draws a distinction between the grasp of intentions that animals
reach (vis aestimativa) and that achieved by human beings sub
natura communi (vis cogitativa). In the texts I have examined he
does not go into discussions about sensus communis or memoria;
his interest in phantasia is also rather underdeveloped. His
concern, then, consists in exploiting the Avicennian and
Averroistic terminology in order to explain how knowledge of
sensible intentions is acquired.
The textual evidence, however, does not render a systematic
theory of the inner senses, probably because composing a
commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard did not provide
the right occasion to explore in detail the physiological as well as
the psychological conditions of inner perception. Given that many
authors before Aquinas had already made extensive use of Arabic
sources, it would se1:m that his reference to those sources is neither
new nor original. ~ut, as I have tried to show, the shift from a
predominantly Avicennian reading of the virtus aestimativa to an
interpretation of the vis cogitativa in an Averroistic fashion
conceptually prepares the separation of an animal vis aestimativa
and a human vis cogitativa, a distinction that wonld become one
of the hallmarks of Aquinas's mature theory of the inner senses. 78

08
Draft~ of this paper \Vere rt:ad at Marquette University in the fall of 2008 and in May
2010 at the Commissio Leonina in Paris. I greatly bcncfitted fro1n commentaries and criticism
by Kevin White, Richard Taylor, Luis Xavier LOpez, Leo White, and two anonymous
reviewer~.

You might also like