You are on page 1of 5

Convergent minds: the evolution of

cognitive complexity in nature


rsfs.royalsocietypublishing.org Russell Powell1, Irina Mikhalevich2, Corina Logan3 and Nicola S. Clayton4
1
Department of Philosophy and Center for Philosophy of Science, Boston University, Boston, MA, USA
2
Berlin School of Mind and Brain, Humboldt University, Berlin, Germany
3
Department of Zoology, and 4Department of Psychology, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, UK
RP, 0000-0002-9893-1721; CL, 0000-0002-5944-906X; NSC, 0000-0003-1835-423X
Introduction
Cite this article: Powell R, Mikhalevich I,
Logan C, Clayton NS. 2017 Convergent minds: Stephen Jay Gould [1,2] argued that replaying the ‘tape of life’ would result in
the evolution of cognitive complexity in nature. radically different evolutionary outcomes. Gould’s ‘radical contingency thesis’
Interface Focus 7: 20170029. focused primarily on animal morphology, and in particular on the specific par-
http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rsfs.2017.0029 ameters of animal body plans, which, he argued, reflect but a small fraction of
the larger set of equally functional morphological possibilities that for historically
contingent reasons were never actualized. Were the tape replayed from different
One contribution of 12 to a theme issue crucial junctures in the history of life, Gould contended, animal evolution would
‘Convergent minds: the evolution of cognitive be channelled into radically different pathways, its topography would assume a
complexity in nature’. markedly different shape, and many properties associated with extant animal
life would never have arisen. Imagine how the history of animal life would
have unfolded, for example, were it not for the improbable survival of ancestral
Subject Areas:
chordates like Pikaia, which gave rise to all modern vertebrates, or for the fortui-
biocomplexity, systems biology tous persistence of the lobe-finned fish that would eventually give rise to
tetrapods, or for the asteroid-induced extinction of the non-avian dinosaurs
whose emptied niches permitted the unlikely radiation and macro-faunal
dominance of mammals. These examples suggest that the radical contingency
thesis is best interpreted as a ‘modal’ thesis, that is, as a claim about the instabi-
lity of certain evolutionary outcomes across possible evolutionary worlds. More
Author for correspondence: precisely, it is a claim about the causal dependency of evolutionary outcomes
Russell Powell on small changes in initial conditions, such as quirky survival, extinction or
e-mail: rpowellesq@gmail.com mutation events, particularly in the early stages of the evolution of higher taxa
like phyla, classes and orders [3,4]. This sensitive dependency explains other
features commonly attributed to the Gouldian view of macroevolution, such as
unpredictability [5,6], stochasticity [7] and path-dependency [8].
Although the radical contingency thesis was aimed at the morphological
features of life, it is particularly provocative for the implications it might have
for the emergence of sophisticated forms of cognition. Is the evolution of mind
a historical accident, unlikely to be replicated across alternative histories of life,
much as Gould argued about animal body plans? Or do we have reason to
think that mind and its associated cognitive competencies is a robustly replicable
feature of the evolutionary process? Given that we are privy to only a single
history of life, how can we even begin to adjudicate such questions? One promis-
ing avenue for investigating evolutionary contingency in general is to examine
patterns of convergent evolution—the independent origination of similar biologi-
cal forms and functions [5,6,9–11]. Under certain conditions, convergence may
constitute natural experimental replications that provide evidence for the robust-
ness, predictability and/or path-independency of the iterated outcomes observed
[4]. Although the term ‘convergence’ is typically reserved for descriptions of mor-
phological character states, the concept can usefully be extended to functional
properties such as cognition [12]. We may therefore investigate the replicability
of cognitive capacities of varying degrees of complexity, as well as the develop-
mental and ecological conditions under which particular cognitive forms
are likely to arise, by establishing the extent and phylogenetic distribution of
cognitive convergence [12,13].
If patterns of cognitive convergence are to serve as evidence for robust evol-
utionary replicability, however, it is critical that the iterated evolution of similar

& 2017 The Author(s) Published by the Royal Society. All rights reserved.
cognitive capacities be demonstrated in taxonomically distant The independent evolution of complex cognition in the 2
groups of animals. This is because the evolutionary distance many millions of years since these groups separated from a

rsfs.royalsocietypublishing.org
of converging lineages serves as a natural experimental control cognitively simpler common ancestor is putative evidence
for conserved (homologous) developmental variables that of the power of natural selection to drive convergent cogni-
could potentially undermine the independence of iterations tive evolution from highly disparate initial conditions [24],
and thus restrict the generalizability of any regularities and thus provides a forceful counterexample to the radical
observed. If convergence is phylogenetically deep, then contingency thesis as it relates to some complex forms of
shared developmental constraints are unlikely to be respon- cognition. Some have argued that certain types of cognition
sible for the observed repetitions. For instance, if we observe are uniquely human, such as shared intentionality, moral
certain complex cognitive properties in lineages whose norm acquisition, and other cognitive abilities that underpin
common ancestor in all probability lacked complex brain struc- ultra-cooperation [25] and cumulative cultural transmission
tures or even a centralized nervous system—then this indicates [26] in humans—which, if truly singular, could indicate the

Interface Focus 7: 20170029


the evolutionary replicability of these properties across tem- highly contingent origins of these cognitive forms. Gould
porally deep replays of the tape of life (e.g. across alternative himself made a case for the radical contingency of human-
histories of animal life), and in some cases could indicate specific cognition, while withholding judgement on the evol-
their law-like necessity in any complex multicellular world. utionary replicability of more general forms of intelligence
Convergence across great taxonomic distances is also crucial [27]. Yet the fact that there is currently little evidence of
for establishing the ecological causes and evolutionary conse- these particular cognitive abilities in nonhuman animals
quences of cognitive evolution, as well as the developmental does not indicate that they are entirely absent in nonhuman
substrates that facilitate and constrain the emergence of clades, since very little testing has been conducted and the
complex cognitive forms. By controlling for many (though efficacy of experimental probes has been limited. In addition,
perhaps not all) phylogenetic constraints, the taxonomic the interplay of biology and culture in the development of
breadth of convergent iteration increases our confidence that such capacities is unclear, and the extent of culture in nonhu-
any regularities observed will hold up across disparate initial man animals is itself the subject of intensive investigation
conditions and phylogenetic contexts. In essence, convergence [28]. We must therefore keep an open mind in asking: What
can indicate that certain cognitive forms are less sensitive do patterns of convergence in the history of life on Earth
to boundary conditions, less path-dependent, and less unpre- tell us about the nature of mind, its evolution and its place
dictable than the radical contingency thesis might have us in the universe?
believe. Do patterns of cognitive convergence support a This themed issue brings together an international group
‘robust replicability thesis’ of mind? of leading researchers and theorists from across the natural
It is crucial that any study of cognitive convergence that sciences and from the philosophy of biological and cognitive
aims to draw broad lessons about the evolution of mind— science to explore the iterated evolution of cognitive complex-
not only about its replicability, but also about the specific ity. Conceptual problems loom large in this discussion. For
developmental and ecological conditions under which it is starters, what counts as evidence for the evolutionary replic-
likely (and unlikely) to occur—must look to convergence ability of mind will depend on how we define the relevant
across higher taxa, both within chordates and between chor- explanandum (or ‘reference class’). This poses a particular
dates and other phyla in Bilateria, especially arthropods and challenge in the case of cognition, a phenomenon about
molluscs. On prevailing phylogenetic reconstructions, arthro- which there is no widespread agreement regarding its defi-
pods and molluscs share a common ancestor with vertebrates nition, its typology, or in virtue of which properties some
that in all probability did not possess a centralized nervous types of cognition may be said to be more complex than
system or even vision, both of which are thought to have others. On ‘big-tent’ accounts of cognition, such as infor-
evolved independently in these groups after their divergence mation processing accounts, minimal cognitive processes
over 500 million years ago in the Cambrian (notwithstanding are present in nearly all forms of life including prokaryotes
conserved genes and embryonic patterning mechanisms and other unicellular organisms, with cognitive processes
involved in the ontogeny and evolution of all known nervous greying into metabolic ones [29]. Other more restrictive but
systems) [14]; but see [15]. A growing body of comparative still biologically broad-based accounts of cognition hold
cognition research on molluscs (in particular, cephalopods; that minimal cognition consists in sensorimotor mechanisms
e.g. [16]) and arthropods (especially insects and arachnids; that are organizationally decoupled from metabolic processes
e.g. [17–19]) suggests that complex cognition did not arise and thus support faster sensorimotor information flows—a
solely in the vertebrate clade—and thus, contra Gould, function paradigmatically realized by nervous systems. Yet
would not have gone un-actualized had Pikaia and its ilk there are functionally analogous sensorimotor systems in
been less fortunate. Similarly, certain bird and mammal plants, in unicellular eukaryotes, and even in bacteria—all
clades, which share a common ancestor that lived over of which exhibit functional memory and flexible stimulus –
300 million years ago in the Carboniferous, exhibit convergently response pairing mechanisms that are distinct from metabolic
enlarged brain structures [20] and a convergent cognitive tool processes [30]. Both bacteria and plants have been shown to
kit that includes capacities such as causal reasoning, flexible exhibit complex behavioural repertoires with a degree of
problem solving and imagination [12,21,22]. Similar patterns flexibility that was long presumed to require a functional ner-
of convergence can be seen at finer grains of taxonomic resolu- vous system. According to ‘bottom-up’ accounts of cognition,
tion, including between numerous mammalian lineages whether glossed in terms of general information processing
such as cetaceans, primates, elephants, and carnivores [23], or more specific sensorimotor information flows, cognition
indicating predictability and path-independency across is not restricted to complex nervous systems or even to ner-
shallower—though still quite substantial—replays of the tape vous systems at all—and thus it can be expected to be a
of life. universal feature of life wherever it evolves.
This bottom-up approach is championed by Keijer [31] arachnids [35], despite recent evidence to the contrary 3
who argues that the nature of cognition is to be discovered [36,37]—though the status of cognitive maps and other forms

rsfs.royalsocietypublishing.org
by examining the biological world, rather than decided of spatial cognition in arthropods remains unsettled [19].
a priori by appealing to anthropocentric intuitions. Drawing Moore [38] meanwhile, makes the case that animal com-
on recent findings demonstrating the complex behavioural munication bears a much stronger resemblance to human
repertoires of protists, plants, and fungi, Keijer proposes a language-mediated communication by reinterpreting the
notion of ‘biologically embodied cognition’, which combines demands of the prevailing theory of successful communi-
biology’s bottom-up approach to cognition with an embodied, cation. According to Moore, the ability to direct a message to
rather than a computational-representational and brain-bound, an intended audience ‘in pursuit of a communicative goal’ is
view. Van Duijn [32] does not take a stand on whether cogni- found in many nonhuman animals and is likely to have
tion is essentially computational or embodied, but he too evolved many times in the history of life. Finally, Clayton &
draws on evidence from both unicellular and multicellular Wilkins [39] draw simultaneously on Clayton’s extensive

Interface Focus 7: 20170029


aneural organisms to challenge what he sees as the ‘cerebro- body of work on episodic-like memory in jays and on Wilkins’s
centrism’ of cognitive science and, by extension, comparative literary exploration of the relation between memory and iden-
psychology. Evidence suggests that these aneural organisms tity to make the case that the ability to remember past events to
exhibit basic forms of learning and possess complex molecular plan future events likely evolved to aid in prospection rather
mechanisms of information transfer, which undermines the than recall. If they are correct, then evidence of episodic-like
assumption that cognition requires nervous systems, let alone memory in jays may simultaneously constitute evidence of
brains. Trewavas [33] a leading authority on plant cognition, future-oriented cognitive abilities, such as planning. Moreover,
offers a wide-ranging exploration of the mechanisms of infor- they suggest that engaging science with narrative art may
mation transfer that underwrite ‘intelligent’ behaviour in present a novel method for exploring questions about the
plants. He concludes that all organisms whose survival depends unobservable phenomena that are the subject of study in
on coping with a complex environment must evolve ‘intelli- comparative cognition.
gence’, by which he means a set of sophisticated cognitive A central research question in comparative cognition
capacities that underwrite flexible responses to environmental concerns the evolutionary and ecological circumstances that
contingencies. Cognition, on each of these ‘bottom-up’ accounts, give rise to complex forms of cognition. Under what conditions
can be expected to be biologically ubiquitous and modally does complex cognition tend to evolve and what is it used for?
robust (i.e. stable across alternative evolutionary histories). The prevailing theory is that cognitive evolution is an adaptive
Other cognition theorists opt for a ‘top-down’ approach response to environmental complexity. Several contributors to
that conceives of the replicability of mind more narrowly to this issue build on or test elements of this hypothesis in an
refer to the robustness not simply of cognition, but of cognitive effort to explore the ecological and evolutionary correlates of
capacities that are canonically deemed complex—such as plan- cognitive evolution. Dunlap et al. [40] investigate whether
ning, insight, imagination, causal reasoning, metacognition, bumblebees modify their information-seeking behaviour
intentionality, self-recognition, consciousness, and the like— in response to a changing and unstable foraging ecology.
capacities that are not present, even in rudimentary forms, in Holekamp & Benson-Amram [41] investigate the source
the vast majority of organisms on Earth (only a tiny fraction of spotted hyaenas’ social intelligence by evaluating the
of which are multicellular organisms). With a top-down ‘cognitive buffer hypothesis’. According to this hypothesis,
approach, questions regarding the contingency and predict- domain-specific cognition such as social intelligence is a
ability of mind become in a sense more interesting and more by-product of the selection for general intelligence, which is
pertinent, but also more difficult to evaluate. Research in the required to cope with a changing environment. The cognitive
expanding field of comparative cognition purports to identify buffer hypothesis challenges the social intelligence hypothesis,
numerous instances of convergence on these more demanding according to which gregarious animals acquired their social
cognitive properties. intelligence (and correspondingly larger brains) in response
A number of researchers from disparate disciplines have con- to the demands of social living. If general intelligence has its
tributed to this theme issue on convergent minds, and several of casual-etiological roots in the demands of ecological complex-
these authors follow this top-down tradition in probing for the ity, then we should expect to find elements of intelligence in
presence of sophisticated cognitive capacities such as imagin- all organisms that face such demands, barring constraints or
ation, proto-linguistic communication, and counting abilities in contingencies to the contrary.
lineages as phylogenetically disparate as birds, primates, and Studies of cognitive convergence, though compelling, are
arachnids. Cross & Jackson [34] detail an experimental test for fraught with conceptual and methodological difficulties that
numerical cognition in the Portia jumping spider, from which often make their findings difficult to interpret. For instance,
they conclude that these arachnids appear to represent the quan- how precisely should we delineate the cognitive traits that
tities ‘1’ and ‘2’ as discrete numerical categories; moreover, they are putatively converged upon, and at what level of description
likely discriminate among these through a method other than, are they convergent? Additionally, it is widely acknowledged
for example, relying on discriminating between the timing of that convergence judgements are relative to hierarchical
different sets of events. Their experimental set-up relies on the level—a trait may be convergent at the level of macro-
spiders’ well known ability to select the most effective path morphology but homologous at the level of tissues, proteins,
(which is not necessarily the most direct one) in pursuit of or genes. Likewise, complex cognition can be convergent at
prey, which is itself suggestive of the possession of a cognitive the level of cognitive mechanisms, while arising from diver-
map, or an internal representation of the relationship among gent neuroanatomical structures (e.g. the cortex in mammals
objects in an environment. Numeric cognition, cognitive maps and the telencephalon in birds) that are comprised of homolo-
and other complex representations are often thought to be gous neural substrates and formed by conserved patterning
beyond the reach of tiny-brained animals such as insects and mechanisms. McShea [42] aims to pick apart the cognitive
traits that are convergent, making a Humean case for the con- take up the question as to how sources of evidence beyond 4
ceptual decoupling of motivational and affective faculties the behavioural experimental setting—in particular, evolution-

rsfs.royalsocietypublishing.org
(‘wants-preferences-cares’), on the one hand, and intellectual ary and ecological theory and data—can inform hypothesis
faculties (‘logic-calculation-problem-solving’), on the other. choice and experimental design in comparative cognition.
He argues that both are crucial yet distinct causal components Rejecting a blanket preference for simple explanations,
of the behaviour typically associated with cognition, and he they propose an evolutionary–ecological model according to
points out that the evolutionary histories of these two distinct which the repeated emergence of trait-clusters including
faculties can be dissociated. (i) flexible behaviours, (ii) complex neuroanatomy and
Establishing convergent cognitive mechanisms is an (iii) heterogeneous selective environments can be used to infer
especially challenging task, because unlike other phenotypic complex cognitive abilities because they comprise a non-acci-
traits such as morphological or even behavioural characters, dental convergent regularity. This convergent regularity, in
cognition implicates unobservable processes and hence must turn, may be used to support the inference to one trait (e.g. com-

Interface Focus 7: 20170029


be inferred from behavioural observations. Some convergent plex cognition) whenever lineages exhibit two or more of the
behavioural traits, such as the ‘agriculture’ phenotype in ants other traits in the cluster. On this view, while, for example,
and humans, are unlikely to be underpinned by similar cogni- the jumping spider may possess just a few hundred thousand
tive mechanisms, even if some prominent discussions of neurons, its behavioural flexibility, heterogeneous ecology
convergence have loosely described such outcomes as conver- and comparatively encephalized neuroanatomy collectively
gent minds (e.g. [5]). However, many observed animal speak in favour of the convergent complexity of its cognitive
behaviours can be explained equally well by simpler and toolkit. A direct prediction of this model is that complex cogni-
more complex cognitive mechanisms, and thus the logical tive capacities will begin to degrade under relaxed selection in
structure of the inference from observed behaviours to the less informationally demanding environments—which agrees
presence of particular cognitive mechanisms remains under- with Cartmill’s reminder that convergences include convergent
specified. In some cases, a preference for simpler cognitive losses, such as decreased encephalization in response to relaxed
explanations may be justified by additional sources of evidence predation pressures, and that these, too, deserve our theoretical
(e.g. neuroanatomy) conjoined with background theoretical and empirical attention.
assumptions (e.g. about the relation between neuroanatomy In sum, the time is ripe for a conceptually rich, multi-
and cognition). For example, Cartmill [43] argues that disciplinary investigation into the evolution of cognition in
behavioural convergence need not be evidence of cognitive its multiplicity of forms. It is only by examining cognitive con-
convergence for animals whose neurophysiology is unlikely vergence—and the lack thereof—in clades as phylogenetically,
to sustain intentionality and consciousness—two features of developmentally, and ecologically disparate as corvids,
mind that he takes to be of particular interest in the quest to whales, carnivores, primates, cephalopod molluscs, jumping
discover cases of convergent cognition. Thus, the tiny brains spiders, insects, green plants, fungi, and unicellular organisms,
(in terms of total number of neurons) of jumping spiders rule that we can begin to map out the phylogenetic distribution of
them out as plausible contenders of cognitive convergence cognition as well as its evolutionary drivers, constraints and
even though, as Cartmill notes, their predatory behaviour, consequences. As this broad-based picture begins to resolve,
which involves alternating among attack strategies such it will illuminate the interplay of contingency and necessity
as stalking, ambushing, and frontal attacks, is as flexible as in the evolution of cognitive worlds.
those of large cats. For similar reasons, Cartmill urges scepticism
in evaluations of cephalopod behaviour (e.g. puzzle-solving Competing interests. We declare we have no competing interests.
behaviours of octopuses) given the radically alien organization Funding. R.P. is grateful to Templeton Foundation grant no. 43160 and
and developmental history of cephalopod brains. C.L. thanks the Leverhulme Trust and Isaac Newton Trust for a
Cognitive models, neuroanatomy and broader evolution- Leverhulme Early Career Research Fellowship, which supported
this research.
ary–ecological considerations may therefore be drawn upon
Acknowledgements. We would like to thank the contributors to this
to strengthen or weaken inferences of cognitive complexity; theme issue for their fascinating and provocative papers, as well as
but precisely how these respective lines of evidence should the editors of Interface Focus, especially Tim Holt, for invaluable
be weighted and integrated is unclear. Mikhalevich et al. [44] editorial support.

References
1. Gould SJ. 1990 Wonderful life: the burgess shale and 5. McGhee G. 2013 Convergent evolution: 10. Conway MS. 2003 Life’s solution: inevitable humans
the nature of history. New York, NY: W.W. Norton & Co. limited forms most beautiful. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. in a lonely universe. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
2. Gould SJ. 2002 The structure of evolutionary 6. Beatty J. 2006 Replaying life’s tape. J. Philos. 103, University Press.
theory. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of 336 –362. (doi:10.5840/jphil2006103716) 11. Losos JB, Jackman TR, Larson A, de Queiroz K,
Harvard University Press. 7. Turner D. 2011 Gould’s replay revisited. Biol. Philos. 26, Rodrı́guez-Schettino L. 1998 Contingency and
3. Powell R. In press. Contingency and convergence in 65–79. (doi:10.1007/s10539-010-9228-0) determinism in replicated adaptive radiations of
macroevolution. Vienna series in theoretical biology. 8. Desjardins E. 2011 Reflections on path dependence and island lizards. Science 279, 2115–2118. (doi:10.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. irreversibility: lessons from evolutionary biology. 1126/science.279.5359.2115)
4. Powell R, Mariscal C. 2015 Convergent evolution as Philos. Sci. 78, 724–738. (doi:10.1086/662560) 12. Emery NJ, Clayton NS. 2004 The mentality of crows:
natural experiment: the tape of life reconsidered. 9. Vermeij GJ. 2006 Evolution and escalation: an convergent evolution of intelligence in corvids and
J. R. Soc. Interface Focus 39, 298–313. (doi:10. ecology history of life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton apes. Science 306, 1903–1907. (doi:10.1126/
1098/rsfs.2015.0040) University Press. science.1098410)
13. Seed AM, Emery NJ, Clayton NS. 2009 Intelligence 24. Powell R. 2012 Convergent evolution and the limits 35. Cruse H, Wehner R. 2011 No need for a cognitive 5
in corvids and apes: a case of convergent evolution? of natural selection. Eur. J. Philos. Sci. 2, 355– 373. map: decentralised memory for insect navigation.

rsfs.royalsocietypublishing.org
Ethology 115, 401–420. (doi:10.1111/j.1439-0310. (doi:10.1007/s13194-012-0047-9) PLoS Comput. Biol. 7, e1002009. (doi:10.1371/
2009.01644.x) 25. Tomasello M. 2014 A natural history of human journal.pcbi.1002009)
14. Erwin DH, Valentine JW. 2013 The Cambrian thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 36. Cheeseman JF et al. 2014 Way-finding in displaced
explosion: the construction of animal biodiversity. 26. Sterelny K. 2012 The evolved apprentice: how clock-shifted bees proves bees use a cognitive map.
Greenwood Village, CO: Roberts and Co. evolution made humans unique. Cambridge, MA: Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 111, 8949–8954. (doi:10.
15. Farris SM. 2015 Evolution of brain elaboration. Phil. MIT Press. 1073/pnas.1408039111)
Trans. R. Soc. B 370, 20150054. (doi:10.1098/rstb. 27. Gould SJ. 1985 SETI and the Wisdom of Casey 37. Camp E. 2009 Putting thoughts to work: concepts,
2015.0054) Stengle. In The Flamingo’s smile: reflections in systematicity, and stimulus-independence. Philos.
16. Grasso FW, Basil JA. 2009 The evolution of flexible natural history (ed. SJ Gould), pp. 403– 413. Phenomenol. Res. 78, 275 –311. (doi:10.1111/j.
behavioral repertoires in cephalopod molluscs. Brain New York, NY: Norton. 1933-1592.2009.00245.x)

Interface Focus 7: 20170029


Behav. Evol. 74, 231–245. (doi:10.1159/ 28. Laland KN, Janik VM. 2006 The animal cultures 38. Moore R. 2017 Convergent minds: ostension,
000258669) debate. Trends Ecol. Evol. 21, 542–547. (doi:10. inference and Grice’s third clause. Interface Focus 7,
17. Chittka L, Niven J. 2009 Are bigger brains better? Curr. 1016/j.tree.2006.06.005) 20160107. (doi:10.1098/rsfs.2016.0107)
Biol. 19, R995–R1008. (doi:10.1016/j.cub.2009.08.023) 29. Godfrey-Smith P. 1996 Complexity and the function 39. Clayton N, Wilkins C. 2017 Memory, mental time
18. Raine NE, Chittka L. 2012 No trade-off between of mind in nature. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge travel and The Moustachio Quartet. Interface Focus
learning speed and associative flexibility in University Press. 7, 20160112. (doi:10.1098/rsfs.2016.0112)
bumblebees: a reversal learning test with multiple 30. van Duijn M, Keijzer F, Franken D. 2006 Principles 40. Dunlap AS, Papaj DR, Dornhaus A. 2017 Sampling
colonies. PLoS ONE 7, e45096. (doi:10.1371/journal. of minimal cognition: casting cognition as and tracking a changing environment: persistence
pone.0045096) sensorimotor coordination. Adapt. Behav. 14, and reward in the foraging decisions of
19. Hesselberg T. 2015 Exploration behaviour 157 –170. (doi:10.1177/105971230601400207) bumblebees. Interface Focus 7, 20160149. (doi:10.
and behavioural flexibility in orb-web spiders: 31. Keijer FA. 2017 Evolutionary convergence 1098/rsfs.2016.0149)
a review. Curr. Zool. 61, 313–327. (doi:10.1093/ and biologically embodied cognition. Interface 41. Holekamp KE, Benson-Amram S. 2017 The evolution
czoolo/61.2.313) Focus 7, 20160123. (doi:10.1098/rsfs. of intelligence in mammalian carnivores. Interface
20. Lefebvre L, Nicolakakis N, Boire D. 2002 Tools and 2016.0123) Focus 7, 20160108. (doi:10.1098/rsfs.2016.0108)
brains in birds. Behaviour 139, 939–973. (doi:10. 32. van Duijn M. 2017 Phylogenetic origins of biological 42. McShea D. 2017 Logic, passion and the problem of
1163/156853902320387918) cognition: convergent patterns in the early convergence. Interface Focus 7, 20160122. (doi:10.
21. Emery NJ, Clayton NS. 2005 Evolution of avian brain evolution of learning. Interface Focus 7, 20160158. 1098/rsfs.2016.0122)
and intelligence. Curr. Biol. 15, R946 –R950. (doi:10.1098/rsfs.2016.0158) 43. Cartmill M. 2017 Convergent? Minds? Some
(doi:10.1016/j.cub.2005.11.029) 33. Trewavas A. 2017 The foundations of plant questions about mental evolution. Interface Focus 7,
22. Clayton NS, Emery NJ. 2015 Avian models of human intelligence. Interface Focus 7, 20160098. (doi:10. 20160125. (doi:10.1098/rsfs.2016.0125)
cognitive neuroscience: a proposal. Neuron 86, 1098/rsfs.2016.0098) 44. Mikhalevich I, Powell R, Logan C. 2017 Is
1330–1342. (doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2015.04.024) 34. Cross FR, Jackson RR. 2017 Representation of behavioural flexibility evidence of cognitive
23. Marino L. 2002 Convergence of complex cognitive different exact numbers of prey by a spider-eating complexity? How evolution can inform comparative
abilities in cetaceans and primates. Brain Behav. predator. Interface Focus 7, 20160035. (doi:10.1098/ cognition. Interface Focus 7, 20160121. (doi:10.
Evol. 59, 21 –32. (doi:10.1159/000063731) rsfs.2016.0035) 1098/rsfs.2016.0121)

You might also like