You are on page 1of 10

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

Natural history and the formation of the human being: Kant on active
forces
Anik Waldow
Department of Philosophy, School of Philosophical and Historical Inquiry, Main Quad, University of Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: In his 1785-review of the Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit, Kant objects to Herder’s
Available online 25 June 2016 conception of nature as being imbued with active forces. This attack is usually evaluated against the
background of Kant’s critical project and his epistemological concern to caution against the “meta-
Keywords: physical excess” of attributing immanent properties to matter. In this paper I explore a slightly different
Kant; reading by investigating Kant’s pre-critical account of creation and generation. The aim of this is to show
Active forces;
that Kant’s struggle with the forces of matter has a long history and revolves around one central
Matter theory;
problem: that of how to distinguish between the non-purposive forces of nature and the intentional
Mechanistic explanations;
Cosmology;
powers of the mind. Given this history, the epistemic stricture that Kant’s critical project imposes on him
Anthropology no longer appears to be the primary reason for his attack on Herder. It merely aggravates a problem that
Kant has been battling with since his earliest writings.
Ó 2016 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

In his 1785 review of Herder’s Ideen zur Philosophie der


Geschichte der Menschheit (1784),1 Kant objects to Herder’s specu- In this passage Kant cites the invisibility of occult powers as the
lative method. More precisely, he claims that Herder is entirely reason for rejecting Herder’s account. The fact that he uses this
unjustified in conceiving of the power to reason as a force that has strategy is surprising. Kant was well aware of the debate on living
evolved out of the principle of life that is common to all animate forces surrounding the publications of Georges-Louis Leclerc, the
beings. The problem with this conception is, he continues, that the Comte de Buffon and Albrecht von Haller’s works between 1740
existence of life forces is dubitable, which means that they cannot and 1780.3 This debate focused on the question of whether life can
be cited in order to explain what reason is: develop gradually as a consequence of a self-organising principle in
matter, as the so-called epigenesists claimed, or whether it must be
Yet what is one to think in general about the hypothesis of
understood as having come into existence through an act of divine
invisible forces, effecting organization, hence about the endeavor
creation at the beginning of history. Importantly, defenders of both
to want to explain what one does not comprehend from what
positions were committed to careful experimentation and
one comprehends even less (8:53-4, emphasis mine).2
observation.
Given Kant’s familiarity with this debate, his charge against
Herder seems to be exaggerated: it ignores that it was part of the
E-mail address: anik.waldow@sydney.edu.au.
1
References to this work will be given in the text after the relevant quotes as observation-based science of his day to claim that living forces
Ideen, page number. Quoted passages are taken from the edition Johann Gottfried exist. Moreover, in recent years scholars have argued that Kant was
Herder (1989) Werke in Zehn Bänden, vol. 6. Edited by Martin Bollacher. Frankfurt
am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag.
2
All references to Kant’s writings will be made in the body of the text and are as
3
follows: AA: Immanuel Kant (1900), Gesammelte Schriften. The English translation is Wubnig (1969); Genova (1974); Zöller (1988); Müller-Sievers (1997), pp. 45-64;
taken from Immanuel Kant (1995-), The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Roe (2002), pp. 50-88; Zammito (2002), p. 305; Riskin (2015).
Kant, indicated by page numbers after the reference to the Akademieausgabe.

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2016.03.005
0039-3681/Ó 2016 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
68 A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76

not only familiar with this debate, but also deeply influenced by reason as a power that develops out of a general force in nature is
it.4Thus, Phillip Sloan claims that in the Kritik der Urteilskraft (1790) only one step away, which is problematic as Herder’s account
Kant defends a quasi-epigenesist account by conceiving of pre- dynamises the structures of reason in relation to a world that
formed “Anlagen. as dynamic, purposive predispositions that perpetually evolves.10 It thereby dissolves the fixity and necessity of
function in relation to. [Blumenbach’s] Bildungstrieb.”5 Sloan the Kantian Apriori, on which the possibility of objective knowledge
qualifies this claim by adding that Kant did not think of the Bil- depends.11
dunsgtrieb as operating in the noumenal realm. Yet he attributes to By working from Kant’s pre-critical acceptance of forces of
Kant the view that “reason as well as experience suggests matter to the threat that this position poses for him during his
[epigenesis] as the most defensible account.”6 On this epistemo- critical phase, we not only understand the vehemence of his
logical reading, Kant objects to Herder primarily because of response to Herderdwhich is absent from his earlier critique of
Herder’s ontological commitment to the principle of life. Sloan’s mind-like forces in naturedbut we can also better comprehend
interpretation thus conforms to the standard account, according to Kant’s decision to abandon the concept of active matter shortly
which Kant’s attack on Herder is driven by his attempt to caution after the review. According to the account developed here, Kant’s
against “metaphysical excess”, which occurs when we ascribe struggle with the forces of matter has a long history.12 The Ideen can
“immanent properties to matter,” as John Zammito has put it.7 Yet therefore not be seen as having pointed Kant to an entirely new
in a later article Zammito goes further than this, arguing that Kant problem, namely that through Herder’s active forces it becomes
himself was not entirely neutral in this regard as he “tacitly possible to derive reason from nature. Instead, the Ideen only made
admitted the objective actuality of forces throughout physical sci- clear to Kant that in order to achieve his long-held goal of keeping
ence.”8 And this, he adds, is the position Kant also embraces in the the realm of matter free of mind-like agency, he had to dispense
Opus postumum. with the notion of active matter altogether. In what follows I will
In this essay I want to explore what it could have meant for Kant sketch this development in Kant’s thoughts.
to accept that processes of generation involve forces, that is, not just
at the level of the phenomena but at the noumenal level as well. 1. Creation, generation and supernatural causes
Instead of focussing on the late Kant, however, I will offer an
analysis of his pre-critical account of creation and generation.9 The From the start of his career Kant took a strong interest in
aim of this is to show that the epistemic stricture that Kant’s critical questions of creation and generation. Thus, A Universal Natural
philosophy imposes on him is not the primary reason for his attack History and a Theory of the Heavens (1755) presents an account that
on Herder. It merely aggravates a problem that Kant has been sees comets, planets and solar systems as forming through the
struggling with since his earliest writings. This is the problem that influence of forces that perpetually drive creation forward form the
on the one hand we must distinguish forces operative in the realm centre point of the universe to its periphery:
of nature from the intentional powers of the mind, while on the
other hand it is not clear how such a distinction can be established. Millions and whole mountain ranges of millions of centuries will
As we will see, this problem becomes particularly pressing after pass within which ever new worlds and world-orders will from
the critical turn. Now Kant can no longer engage in those meta- and attain completion one after another in the remote distances
physical manoeuvres that once served him to specify what the form the centre point that has become the first point of for-
activity of matter consists in and how it differs from that activity we mation and the centre of creation by the attractive capacity of its
attribute to free agents who act in accordance with their reason and pre-eminent matter. (1:314, 266)
will. Yet at the same time much more hinges on the possibility of
establishing such a difference. Without it, Herder’s conception of Original particles of matter are here conceived as endeavouring
and striving towards the formation of greater lumps of matter,
while the forces of attraction and repulsion organise this formation
4 in concentric circles around the centre point of the universe (1: 313,
Zammito (2003); Mensch (2013); Riskin (2015).
5
Sloan (2002), p. 249. 265-6).
6
Sloan (2002), pp. 249-50. Despite Kant’s frequent use of language that presents nature as
7
Zammito (2002), p. 302. Also see Beiser (1987), p. 152, for a similar interpre- an active agent of an orderly production that pursues a certain
tation. The standard account is closely related to the question of the status of purposedsuch as the replacement of one maladapted species by
teleological judgement in Kant. What crops up in this discussion is the question of
the production of better ones (1: 317, 26913)dhe is clear that all
how to judge nature and more specifically the fact that organisms exist without
attributing teleological causes to nature. McLaughlin (1990), Ginsborg (2001), creative forces follow general laws of motion, and in this sense
Zuckert (2007) argue that for Kant teleological principles are heuristic tools count as determined and blind, rather than as initiated by some
employed in judging organisms; and they all claim that these principles do not purpose-pursuing intentional forces (1:222, 194). The distinction
inform us about the causal structure of the organism in re. between blind forces bound by the laws of nature and those which
8
Zammito (2003), p. 82, emphasis added.
9 are freely unfolding in accordance with self-chosen purposes ulti-
See for instance Lord (2009) for Kant’s critique of Herder’s Spinozism after the
publication of the review of the Ideen. Also see Boehm (2014), for the claim that mately goes back to Kant’s physicotheology.14 During his pre-
Spinoza is one of the main targets of Kant’s critical philosophy. critical phase Kant conceives of God as a supreme intelligence
10
Beiser (1987), p. 154; Zammito (1992); Sloan (2002). See Zöller (1988) and who acts in line with understanding and will, and for specific
(1989), especially pp. 231-232, for the view that the success of the critical project purposes when creating the universe in a specific way. However,
depends on the conception of reason as being productive of its own principles and
the related claim that Kant had to oppose the idea (which Herder embraced) that
nature is able to generate reason out of its own accord.
11 12
Although arguing that for Kant intuitions and categories are acquired by being For other accounts that also stress continuities in Kant’s thinking about forces
produced through spontaneity and receptivity, Zöller (1989) stresses that the see Watkins (2001) and (2003).
13
formal aspects of this productive process are fixed. See Falkenstein (1990) for an Within Kant’s pre-critical and critical framework organisms assume a special
anti-nativist interpretation that also stresses the productive character of the status, since he believes that their existence is neither exhaustively explicable
structures of time and space and yet acknowledges the fixity of these structures through the mechanism of nature nor through the presence of a purposive, mind-
once they have been produced. See Kitcher (1990), especially pp. 35-39, for a like force. I will say more about this presently when turning to the discussion of
detailed analysis of the various component parts of productive processes and the Kant’s critique of the so-called naturalists.
14
fixity of the “laws of mind” operative in such processes. Waschkies (1987), pp. 562-578; Zammito (2006).
A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76 69

the created world itself is taken to lack all mind-like attributes, so particles (1:346, 291-2), as much as it opposes the conception of a
that the forces operative within this world must be seen as blind divine being who remains actively involved in the created world.16
and unable to give their actions a self-chosen direction. It does so by making two related claims: first, that order and beauty
Kant’s understanding of mind-like forces in opposition to blind can in fact come into existence through ordinary processes in na-
forces becomes most explicit in The Only Possible Argument in ture; and, second, that this is possible only if we think of these
Support of the Demonstration of the Existence of God (1763). He here processes as being organised by divinely ordained natural laws. In
considers the question of “whether the properties of understanding quintessence, this means that on Kant’s view the moment the
and will are to be found in the Supreme Being as determinations universe was created natural laws and the workings of blind forces
inhering in it, or whether they are to be regarded merely as con- took the place of intentional divine action, that is, action that un-
sequences produced by it in other things” (2:89, 133, emphasis folds in line with understanding and will and follows the principle
mine). He rejects the second option for the reason that it depicts of choice, rather than determined patterns of cause and effect.
God as “possessing neither cognition nor choice” which turns him Clearly, keeping intentional actions out of the realm of created
into a “blindly necessary ground of other things and even of other matter enables Kant to secure the explanatory value of mechanistic
minds” (2:89,133 emphasis mine). physics. However, one problem that emerges within this context is
Kant offers this argument to reveal the absurdity of the mate- the question of animal generation. In the Only Possible Argument
rialism he associates with Spinozism and the Epicureans.15 Con- Kant concedes precisely this point, stating that with respect to or-
trary to this position, Kant argues that the “universe is no accident ganisms and the question of their original formation mechanistic
of God” (2:90, 134); it is designed and because of its order, beauty explanations are entirely useless: “It would be absurd to regard the
and perfection “presupposes relation to a being endowed with initial generation of a plant or animal as a mechanical effect inci-
cognition and desire” (2:90, 134). This argument in principle leaves dentally arising from the universal laws of nature” (2:114: 156). Due
enough room for a conception of created matter as endowed with to this absurdity, it would be common to assume that an “artificial
powers that are similar in kind to those of its designer, the divine arrangement” (2: 98, 141) made for a specific purpose is the cause
being (Kant for instance mentions minds, which are typically of an organism’s existence. Here as already in the Universal Natural
endowed with understanding and will). Yet we will see below that History (1:346, 291), Kant thinks of “special arrangements” as the
Kant’s attack on occasionalism shows the contrary, namely that he purposive actions of a freely choosing agent who introduces con-
was strongly opposed to any attempt to conceive of the realm of tingencies into the otherwise lawful mechanism of nature (2:96,
matter as being pervaded by mind-like forces. Before turning to this 139-40).
discussion, the point that deserves our attention however is that for Despite the problems that organisms pose for a strictly mech-
Kant something counts as blind when its lacks “understanding and anistic explanatory framework, Kant does not think that this jus-
will” and cannot act in line with “cognition and choice”; and, vice tifies the belief in supernatural causes. Kant raises this issue when
versa, that for a force not to count as blind is to be mind-like, in the objecting to the practice of the so-called natural philosophers who
sense that it actually has understanding and will and is able to “toy around with the problem. of gradual propagation” (2:115,
choose a specific course of action. 157). He writes:
Although Kant acknowledges the existence of a supreme intel-
[W]hether the supernatural generation occurs at the moment of
ligence as the ultimate “ground” of the universe, he deems it ille-
creation, or whether it takes place gradually, at different times,
gitimate to conclude from the fact that the universe is orderly and
the degree of the supernatural is no greater in the second case
beautiful that “the direct hand of God” (1:347, 292) remains
than it is in the first. The only difference between them relates
involved in this universe after its creation. The temptation to
not to the degree of the immediate divine action but merely to
embrace this view is particularly strong whenever we discover
the when. (2:115, 157)
“arrangements in the constitution of the world that redound to the
reciprocal advantages of creatures” (1:347, 292). Kant finds this
view intolerable, as it turns free choice and intentional By temporalizing the concept of creation in this way, Kant treats
actiondnamely those of the divine beingdinto major explanatory natural philosophers as occasionalists, as for him these philoso-
principles that leave little room for the rigid order of nature that phers too seem to believe that a certain effect, namely the emer-
acts in line with necessary laws. For this reason one of the major gence of life, is produced by something that is not part of nature
argumentative goals of Kant’s Universal Natural History is to itself. Since for Kant this supernatural cause can only be a divine
establish that the first cause of the universe is strictly “mechanical”. being that remains actively involved in its creation, natural phi-
Setting up the theoretical foundations for his subsequent inquiry in losophers turn into occasionalists.
the preface to this work, Kant programmatically states that the Kant’s occasionalist take on the so-called natural philosophers is
“order and beauty” of the universe need to be understood as a mere interesting, as it reveals that establishing the mechanical origin of
“effect of matter left to its general laws of motion” (1:221, 194). And the universe pursues a rather limited aim. Instead of ruling out that
in the concluding remarks Kant reemphasises that “the first cause there could ever be activity in created matter, he merely wants to
[of the universe] was tied to the mechanical rules of motion and did make sure that we do not conflate the activity of matter that is
not act by free choice” (1: 344, 290). necessarily bounded by the laws of nature with the activity char-
Kant’s own account thus sits in the middle of two extremes. It acteristic of a being who is able to act out of choice and in line with
dispenses with the Epicurean chaos view, according to which his intentions and for specific purposes. That this is the direction in
beauty and order count as the products of randomly colliding which he wanted to push the debate also seems to follow from the
specific way in which he here engages with Maupertuis.
As Zammito has argued, Kant directly lifted his critique of the
15
For Kant, Spinozism is a more sophisticated version of Epicureanism, as the so-called natural philosophers from Maupertuis’ System de la Na-
second half of the quoted passage indicates: “and it would differ from the eternal ture that “set[s] about elaborating a general theory of active matter,
fate postulated by some ancient philosophers in nothing except that it had been
more intelligently described” (2:89, 133). Kant articulates a similar view in the
Critique of the Power of Judgement (1790) where Spinozism is presented as the
16
position that conceives of “the supreme ground for the objectively purposive forms In the Only Possible Argument and in the third Critique Kant refers to this view as
of matter without conceding an understanding to it” (5:421, 289, emphasis mine). occasionalism (5:422-3, 291), as we will see further down.
70 A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76

a plausible theory of hylozoism.”17 However, although Kant did not 2. Active forces
hesitate to employ Maupertuis’ argument in order to show that
there is no room for divine intervention in the created universe and In the Universal Natural History Kant writes: “The basic matter
that for this reason the natural laws have to play a more funda- itself, the properties and forces, of which underlie all changes, is a
mental role in the generation of organisms, he firmly rejected direct consequence of a divine existence” (1:309, 263). And he adds
Maupertuis’ vital materialism that was supposed to solve the that
problem that the mechanism of nature fails to explain the emer-
[I]t is true that the formation, the shape, the beauty, and
gence of organised life-forms. This position, as Kant argues in the
perfection are relationships of the building blocks and of the
third Critique, illegitimately infuses matter with “a property (hy-
substances that constitute the material of the universe; and we
lozoism) that contradicts its essence” (5:375, 246). This property, as
observe it in the measures that the wisdom of God is still taking
we can glean from the passages leading up to Kant’s critique of the
all the time; and it is most appropriate to it that they evolve by
natural philosophers, is something mind-like that enables matter
an unforced succession from these universal laws implanted in
to have memory, cognition and desire. Maupertuis intended his
them.” (1:309, 263)
language to be metaphorical, but Kant clearly ignored this.18 Thus
he writes:
It is difficult to say what it precisely means when Kant says that
The internal forms proposed by Buffon, and the elements of
God has implanted the universal laws in the original particles of
organic matter which, in the opinion of Maupertuis, join
matter. Michael Friedman’s interpretation of Kant’s pre-critical
together as their memory dictate, and in accordance with the
concept of space as developed in the New Elucidations of the First
laws of desire and aversion, are either as incomprehensible as the
Principles of Metaphysical Cognition (1755) might help us to shed
thing itself, or they are entirely arbitrary inventions. (2:115, 157,
further light on this question. According to Friedman, Kant thinks of
emphasis mine)
space as being constituted by the interaction of substances.19 These
substances are different from Leibniz’s monads in that they interact
Rejecting this approach, Kant moves on to considering that with one another and through this interaction constitute space
“either the formation of the fruit is to be attributed immediately to (1:415, 43). Importantly, the laws structuring their interaction exist
a divine action, which is performed at every mating, or, alterna- in the “scheme of the divine understanding” (1:413, 41). God’s mind
tively, there must be granted to the initial divine organisation of thus becomes the common cause of the substances and the laws, as
plants and animals a capacity, not only to develop their kind both come into existence by “conceiving their existence as corre-
thereafter in accordance with a natural law, but truly to generate lated with each other” (1:413, 41).
their kind” (2:115, 157). Kant concludes this section by flagging that It thus would appear that it is somewhat imprecise to say that
“the purpose of these considerations has simply been to show that substances that constitute space through their interactions abide
one must concede to the things of nature a possibility, greater than by the laws of nature in the sense that they passively follow
that which is commonly conceded, of producing their effects in something external to them. Kant’s substances have been placed in
accordance with universal laws” (2:115, 157, emphasis mine). relation to one another by God’s conceiving of them in precisely
Kant here explicitly states that it is a genuine possibility to this way.20 This means that the laws that structure the interaction
conceive of organic matter as capable of producing its own kind if of substances come into being at the same time and through the
the relevant activity is thought of as complying with the laws of same divine act of conceiving that is also responsible for the
nature. Moreover, I have argued above that acting in accordance emergence of the substances themselves. Furthermore, Kant claims
with the laws of nature is a formula that Kant typically uses to that the interaction of substances manifests itself in the attractive
describe an activity that is not governed by intelligence, cognition, and repulsive forces through which material bodies are formed.21
will and the principle of choice, and for this reason counts as blind. On this account, the motion of matter becomes the outer appear-
Taken together these two claims suggest that Kant did not object to ance of the lawful interaction of metaphysical forces that span from
Maupertuis’ vital materialism simply because it conceives of matter one physical monad to another.22
as active. Rather, what Kant found objectionable was that, accord- Against this background, it emerges that for Kant natural laws
ing to his interpretation, Maupertuis attributed to matter an ac- do not exist externally to the first particles of matter whose
tivity that is mind-like, which, as we have seen above, meant for attractive and repulsive forces account for the creation of the
him that matter can act in line with understanding and will and out
of the principle of choice. However, if such elements enter the
concept of matter, he reasoned, the prospect of naturalising phi-
losophy is entirely lost, as something that is not bound by the laws
19
of nature becomes acknowledged as a regular cause in natural Friedman (1992), pp. 27-34.
20
processes. Yet Kant claims that “there could be if God so willed, a number of. substances,
free from any connection with our universe” (1:414, 42). This might suggest that
I will say more about what precisely it means to be a force that is
substances can be created without being placed in relation to one another that is
not mind-like and yet able to produce life presently, when dis- specified by a law. To refute this claim, one only needs to consider that even in this
cussing the difference between the forces of organic and inorganic specific passage Kant stresses that substances, while not necessarily related to “our
matter. Before this, however, I want to engage more closely with universe”, are nevertheless “linked with each other to produce place, position, and
Kant’s account of how the original particles of matter came into space” (1:414, 42, emphasis added). Kant thus stresses what I have claimed above,
namely that substances that constitute a material world (ours or another one) do in
existence. This will put us in a position to understand how it is fact relate to one another.
possible for Kant to do both, avoid occasionalism and hold on to the 21
Kant claims that attraction and repulsion are external expressions of in-
idea that intelligent design plays a role in preparing matter in such teractions of substances; on this account, Newtonian gravity tracks the movement
a way that organised beings can be formed. of substances that, as Kant puts it, gravitate towards one another “throughout the
whole realm of space” (1:415, 43).
22
Attraction here still counts as “a quality of matter”, as Kant stresses in the
Universal Natural History, while simultaneously explaining that “attraction is pre-
17
Zammito (2006), p. 334; also see p. 343. cisely that universal relationship that unites the parts of nature in one space” (1:
18
See Zammito (2006), p. 334, and Terrall (2002), p. 328. 308, 262).
A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76 71

universe.23 Rather, he regards these laws as the conditions neces- which could dispense with all natural explanation” (5:423, 292). To
sary for matter to constitute itself. So when Kant says that God has ensure that nature is able to act out of itself and without the help of
implanted the universal laws of nature into the first particles of supernatural divine action can thus be seen as a strong motive that
matter, he quite literally seems to mean this, instead of just using an drives Kant’s attempt to carve up the conceptual landscape of the
awkward expression for saying that matter is externally con- eighteenth-century life sciences in his own particular way.
strained by the laws of nature. I have argued above that in the case of inorganic matter the
One way of capturing this aspect of Kantian matter would be to forces that make it possible for nature to act out of itself are best
say that matter has been programmed to follow the laws of nature. conceived as blind in the sense that they lack understanding, will
This way of putting it stresses that matter is not externally con- and the ability to give their actions a self-chosen direction. Being
strained, but internally configured to actively behave the way it bound by nature thus seems to stand for the absence of those mind-
does. Yet, while being active in this sense, it still holds that matter is like powers that are characteristic of divine action. When dealing
deprived of mind-like forces characteristic of the freedom and with organic forces, Kant adopts a slightly different stance. In The
choice Kant attributes to the divine being: after all, matter follows Dreams of a Spirit Seer (1766) Kant remarks, “all life is based on the
the universal laws of nature, thus driving out the divine plan, and inner capacity to determine itself voluntarily” (2:328n, 315). This
lacks the power freely to initiate actions of its own choice. suggests that Kant thinks of life as a force that enables living beings
The question that emerges here is how the existence of organ- to perform spontaneous action at will.
isms fits into all of this. As discussed in the previous section, Kant To be sure, with this reference to “natures whose own power of
considers it a genuine possibility that “there must be granted to the will is capable of spontaneously determining and modifying itself”
initial divine organisation of plants and animals a capacity, not only (2:328n, 315) something mind-like enters Kant’s concept of force.
to develop their kind thereafter in accordance with a natural law, Yet Kant seems to back-pedal immediately after having articulated
but truly to generate their kind” if this capacity is thought of as this thought, stating “those immaterial beings which contain the
“producing [its] effects in accordance with universal laws” (2:115, ground of animal life are different from those which comprise
157, emphasis mine). Kant states this point as part of his critique of reason in their spontaneous activity and are called spirits” (2:328n,
the so-called natural philosophers who smuggle into their 315). Kant thus suggests that there is a clear line to be drawn be-
explanatory framework supernatural causes when thinking of tween the spontaneity of animals and that of human beings, who
“immediate divine action” (2:115, 157) as responsible for the gen- are endowed with reason and for this reason also capable of per-
eration of life. Importantly, in this particular context divine action is forming intentional action in line with their will and
seen as a cause that stands against and supersedes ordinary natural understanding.
causes that figure in mechanistic explanations. Kant’s occasionalist If we abstract from this rather specific context, however, it be-
critique thus leaves untouched the status of divine action that es- comes clear that it is not the contrast between the ability to act at
tablishes the natural laws themselves and the particles of matter will and the ability to act in line with reason that matters to Kant’s
that then act in line with these laws. For strictly speaking such an conception of animal life. Rather, it is the manner in which the
actiondeven if it included the “initial organisation of plants and concept of spontaneity becomes embedded in a structure that
animals” (2:115, 157) e does not interfere with the order of natural limits the freedom of organic forces. Evidence for the claim that
causation, but renders possible precisely the kind of framework Kant thinks of organic forces as constrained is provided by his use
through which we can understand nature in mechanistic terms. of the concepts of “Keime” and “Anlagen”. Both concepts, as Sloan
If we approach the question of species generation from this has shown, essentially structure Kant’s intellectual trajectory from
angle, we can see that for Kant it was rather important to think of a more rigid conception of fixed predispositions and germs that
nature as active. This is because only if nature is seen as able to constrain organisms in their capacity to propagate the species (as in
generate change and development out of its own resources can we Kant’s three essays on race from 1775, 1785 and 1788) to a more
avoid the explanatory gap that invites reflections on the activity of a flexible conception that stresses the productive and purposive
divine being as a supplementary supernatural cause. The belief that character of organic forces in the third Critique. A figure that
we must leave enough conceptual space for an activity of nature is crucially influenced this trajectory was Blumenbach. Sloan writes:
not only the message of Kant’s occasionalist critique in the Only “In the wake of the Blumenbach encounter, what we see is that
Possible Argument; it also ultimately informs Kant’s engagement Kant dramatically weakened his appeal to the preformation of
with the problem of animal generation in the third Critique. germs. This is immediately evident when we examine the word
Kant here writes that “if one assumes occasionalism of the frequencies of the Kritik der Urteilskraft of 1790.” The concepts of
production of organic beings, then everything that is natural is “Anlage and Naturanlage. have now taken on a new dynamic role.
entirely lost” (5:422, 291). On this position, God is seen as imme- No longer are they static structural relations of parts. Anlagen have
diately involved in “commingling in every impregnation” (5:422, become ‘inner purposive predispositions’ [inneren zweckmässigen
291). An alternative position, Kant explains, is prestabilism, which Anlagen]. Kant also has now deemed his new account of develop-
can be subdivided into two groups: “the system of generatings as ment a theory of epigenesis.”24
mere educts” that he calls “individual preformation” and the Despite this move towards more flexibility concerning the
“system of generatings as products” that he labels “generic pre- specific manner in which organic forces can articulate themselves
formationism”. While for Kant the first position, similar to occa- in their pursuit of specific purposes, it is important to note that
sionalism, attributes to the divine being an overly active role each even in the account of the third Critique organic activity remains
time life is formed, he positively acknowledges that the second “left essentially constrained. Commenting on the virtues of Blu-
something to nature in order not to fall into complete hyperphysics, menbach’s conception of a “formative drive”, Kant points out that
the “self-preserving purposiveness” of organic forces stands under
“the guidance and direction” of the “inscrutable principle of an
original organisation” (5:424, 292-3). What this means is that the
23
Eric Watkins stresses that for Kant the sphere occupied by a physical body is
constituted by relational properties of intrinsically active substances; see Watkins
(2003), p. 24. Kant’s natural laws, as I conceive them, are the expressions of the
activity of monads and for this reason count as having their roots in a monad’s
24
intrinsic properties. Sloan (2002), p. 248.
72 A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76

ultimate direction and scope of the changes produced by the forces of organic and inorganic matter as endowed with an active force.
of organic life are preconfigured. And this explains why, according Indeed, it is precisely this combination that enables him to offer an
to Kant, experience has so far not given any evidence of the capacity account of creation that dispenses with divine interaction, on the
of a species to morph into another (generatio heteronyma); all that one hand, and avoid the chaos view of the Epicurean materialists, on
could be observed is that racial variation occurs within the confined the other. This is because it is the activity of matter, and not the
limits of one species (generatio homonyma).25 presence of a divine or any other mind-like force, that explains how
If we now return to the task of specifying what kind of forces processes of creation are continuously driven forward to realise the
Kant is ready to grant to organisms, we can say that these forces are order and beauty that Epicureans would be hard-pressed to explain.
spontaneous and productive in that they are able to produce racial Although Kant’s middle position successfully combines the
variations in line with the demands of a given environment. Yet concept of orderly creation with a mechanistic account of nature,
these forces are ultimately constrained: they act to preserve the one problem remains. If it is Kant’s intention to provide an account
species as a whole despite all racial variations within that species. of generation that keeps the realm of created matter free of mind-
The reason for this is that organic matter has originally been like agency, Kant’s account of monadic interaction as the meta-
configured to behave this way. Since this is so, the forces operative physical ground on which his concept of matter rests makes it hard
in organic nature cannot be considered as mind-like in the sense in to see how this can be achieved. Monads are as immaterial as souls,
which I have defined this term above. What counts as mind-like is which makes it at least conceivable that they are organised upon
associated with the creative actions of a divine being endowed with the same principles and exhibit the same kind of forces.28 Kant
understanding and will; and, most importantly, with the manner in himself concedes this point in the Inquiry Concerning the Distinct-
which this being acts, namely in line with the principle of choice ness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality (1764), where
which gives it freedom to realise its intentions at will. Organic he explains that without further proof it cannot be ruled out those
matter lacks all of this, even though it might appear purposive in its physical monads are different in kind from the monads that
goal directedness to preserve its own kind.26 Most significantly, it constitute souls:
has no ability to choose its course of action, which is manifested by
I admit that the proof that we have that the soul is not material
its inability to produce variations that take it beyond the confined
is a good one. But take care that you do not infer from this that
limits of its own species. What guides its activity instead is fixed
the soul is not of a material nature. For this latter claim is uni-
through the “inscrutable principle of original organisation”. Of
versally taken to mean not merely that the soul is not matter,
course, the fact that Kant invokes this principle straightforwardly
but also that it is not a simple substance of the kind which could be
points us to an agency external to organic matter itself, which, if it
an element of matter. (2:293, 267)
did not organise organic matter in a specific way, would make it
impossible for this matter to perform its reproductive purpose.27
With this conception of a hidden agency in place, we once again To achieve this proof, two things would need to be shown: first,
come very close to the kind of occasionalism that Kant attacked in that a spirit “does not exist in space” and, second, that “when
his adaptation of Maupertuis’ argument. Yet, as has been suggested combined with other thinking beings” it fails to “constitute some-
above, Kantdat least during his pre-critical phasedcould counter thing extended, a conglomerate” (2:293, 267). However, according
this objection by thinking of original configuration as the ground to Kant, such a proof does not exist.29
that makes it possible for the universe to emerge. Original config- Only three years after this statement, Kant engages more pro-
uration then need not be seen as an intervention in the course of foundly with the question of how to distinguish material and
nature, but as something that enables organic matter to behave in immaterial substances. In The Dreams of a Spirit Seer (1766) he ex-
line with the laws of nature, once its first particles have been plains that a fundamental problem of dealing with spirits is that “the
created with the capacity to produce life within the confined limits influence of incorporeal beings. can at best be acknowledged to
of the relevant species. exist” (2:331, 319), while “the nature” of the operation that the in-
Here, then, it turns out that for Kant there is no contradiction fluence of incorporeal beings exerts “and the extent of its effects.
involved in thinking of the blind mechanism of nature as the gov- will never be explained” (2:331, 319). For Kant the aim of the Dreams
erning principle of the universe, while at the same time conceiving is therefore not to provide a positive account of the nature of spirits
and the principles upon which their interactions are organised, but
to illustrate what happens when we conceive of the soul’s actions in
analogy to the “universal activity of matter” (2:331, 319).
25
See 5:419n, 288. In his first essay on race Of the Different Races of the Human Two things are interesting about this approach. First, Kant’s use
Beings (1775) Kant expresses the point like this: “This care of Nature to equip her
creature through hidden inner provisions for all kinds of future circumstances, so
of the method of analogy is mainly negative: far from trying to
that it may preserve itself and be suited to the difference of the climate or the soil, is establish that activity in the spirit realm is similar to the kind of
so admirable. In the migration and transplanting of animals and plants it creates the activity governing the realm of matter, Kant tells us that they are
semblance of new kinds; yet they are nothing other than variations and races of the distinguished by a fundamental difference. Thus he claims that, for
same species the germs and natural predispositions of which have merely devel-
all we can tell, the forces of spirits are organised in accordance with
oped on occasion in various ways over long periods of time” (2:434, 89).
26
As mentioned before, for Kant animals are endowed with the ability for free “moral impulses” (2:335, 322) that follow the rule of the general
spontaneous, voluntary action. So it might be argued that for Kant animals do in will (2:335, 322), while the activity of matter is conceived in rela-
fact have mind-like forces. Yet it is clear that animals cannot perform the same kind tion to the natural law.30
of voluntary actions as humans: animals follow their instincts and in this sense
merely follow the laws of nature rather than act out of the principle of choice and in
line with their intentions and beliefs. So if having a “mind-like” force essentially
28
means to be able to choose one’s actions (in line with practical reason), there is no Cf. Friedman (1992), p. 28.
29
problem here. See Redding (2009), especially chapter 5, for the claim that Kant’s difficulties to
27
It is interesting to note that in the first Critique Kant stresses that when we think of the soul in substantial terms finally led him to develop a quasi-functionalist
ascribe to “some organs of an animal’s body an end” (A688/B716, 615), as some account of mind.
30
anatomists would do, it is the idea of an intelligent creator God that enables us to Thus, Kant asks: “Are we, then, to suppose that it would not in the same way be
see purpose in nature (A687/B717, 615). Having reason and being able to act on possible to represent the phenomenon of the moral impulses in thinking natures,
purpose (which are here identified as attributes of God) thus become enabling who are reciprocally related to each other, as the effect of a genuinely active force, in
conditions for the possibility of attributing purpose to nature. virtue of which spirit natures exercise an influence on each other?” (2:335, 322).
A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76 73

The second interesting point about Kant’s approach is that matter, is already present in the final chapter of the Universal
through his use of the method of analogy, he in principle does Natural History. Kant here experiments with the idea that human
exactly what he later criticises in his reviews of Herder’s Ideen. As life could have emerged in other parts of the universe. Although
we have seen, Kant here objects to Herder’s attempt to explain this thought experiment is apparently intended to offer an inte-
what reason is by invoking invisible powers that can nowhere be grated account of the place of human beings in the world of created
observed to exist. This objection is followed by the consideration matter, Kant never goes as far as to claim that human reason could
that “at least with respect to the former [that is, forces affecting have evolved out of the bare movements of matter. He writes that
organisation] we can become acquainted with its laws through there is an “infinite distance between the capacity to think and the
experience, although their causes will remain unknown” (8:54, motion of matter, between the reasoning mind and the body”
132). In the Dreams Kant himself becomes guilty of overstepping (1:355, 298).
the boundaries set by the realm of experience. Based on vague The reason for this distance has to do with the process through
analogies and deprived of the possibility to study the principles of which humans come into existence, which, according to Kant,
interaction of invisible spirits, he claims that these principles are as happens when God joins the immortal soul to a particular lump of
lawful as those organising the interaction between physical bodies matter. Through this joining, the soul is not only bound to a certain
in that they follow the rule of the general will.31 place within the space-time coordinates of the universe, but also
Certainly, Kant takes himself to be ironic when speculating constrained in how well it can exercise its rational powers. He
about the interactions of spirits. As mentioned before, his professed writes: “The powers of the human soul are restricted and hemmed
aim is to reveal the absurdity of a dualist conception of body and in by the obstacles of the coarse matter to which they are most
mind (2: 327, 314), which, according to Kant, is based on the intimately bound” (1:358, 300).32
mistaken form of analogical reasoning that he himself employs in Since in the Kantian universe the quality of matter varies in
the Dreams. More precisely, the problem would be that by extrap- proportion to its distance to the sundwhich in turn determines the
olating from the behaviour of matter to the actions of the mind, it forces of attraction and repulsion through which bodies with a
becomes impossible to “recognise with certainty any distinctive specific density are formeddthis account suggests that the “ability
characteristic mark of the soul, which distinguishes it from the raw to think rationally” (1:355, 298) is regulated by environmental
elementary matter of corporeal natures” (2:326-7, 314). conditions, namely those in which the human body finds itself
Kant here clearly returns to the problem that he already artic- when being attached to the soul (1:358, 300). Interestingly, Kant’s
ulated in the Inquiry, that is, the problem that we cannot rule out analysis here already relies on the principles taught in his course on
that souls are composed of the same metaphysical material that physical geography (regularly taught from 1756 until his retirement
also constitutes matter. However, without being able to establish in 1796), parts of which were later recast as the lectures on an-
such a difference, Kant warns, “the idea jokingly proposed by thropology (between 1772 and 1773).33 Thus he regards climate,
Leibniz that in drinking our coffee we may perhaps be swallowing soil, light conditions, and in this specific case the density of matter,
atoms destined to become human souls” is no longer “a laughing as shaping influences on human beingsdnot only on their physical
matter” (2:327, 314). This is because the “I” becomes “subject to the constitution, but also their mental powers due to the constraints
common fate of material nature” (2:327, 314). For Kant this not only that the body imposes on the soul’s functioning.
means that the immortality of the soul can no longer be defended, For our purposes, this account matters as it clearly historicises
but also that we can no longer understand how we have come into human reason in relation to the space-time coordinates of the body.
existence in the first place: “Just as [the “I”] had by chance been Of course, this historicisation operates within well-defined limits,
drawn from the chaos of all the elements in order to animate an since the environment of a given human being only determines
animal machine, why should it not in some time in the future, when how well reason functions, but not that a particular lump of matter
the contingent combination has been dissolved, return once more can think rationally.34 In this way, Kant’s account groups flexible
to that chaos of the elements?” (2:327, 314). elements around the fixed kernel of a soul that, by God’s provi-
Despite all irony, this passage clearly shows that Kant is serious dence, has been placed into specific spatiotemporal conditions
about one thing: he does not want the mind to be absorbed into the which in turn set the parameters for the development of the power
realm of matter, because this would engender a conception of hu- to think.
man beings as having evolved out of contingent chaos. Note that in It is well known that Kant’s Universal Natural History served
this context contingency and chaos are not simply invoked in order Herder as a model for his This too a Philosophy of the History of
to criticise the Epicurean view, which according to Kant fails to Formation (1774), which is commonly seen as a condensed version
acknowledge the lawfulness of the created universe. Rather, the of the Ideen, that is, the very work that Kant criticises for the claim
problem for the conception of the “I” is constituted by the fact that that reason has evolved from a force present in all animate and
it is not organised by an ordering principle that is specifically inanimate objects of the universe. As we can now see, in the Uni-
different from the organisational principle of matter. versal Natural History Kant himself experimented with the thought
that the power of to think rationally can be enhanced by environ-
3. Formation of the human being mental conditions. However, as has been pointed out, for him
environmental conditions can only regulate the powers of the soul
The same thought, namely that it is wrong to see the existence in that they determine the properties of the human body, but they
of human life as a mere product of the organisational principles of fall short of enabling rationality as such.
In the Ideen Herder approaches the relationship between body
and mind from the opposite direction. While suggesting that nature
31
It is true that the critical Kant changed his mind about the manner in which we
can reconstruct the laws that govern the use of reason and will. Yet what he keeps
arguing is that there are these laws. Thus in the first Critique he suggests that reason
follows the so-called “laws of freedom” (A802/B830, 675-6), which tell us “what
32
ought to happen” (A 801/B829, 675) rather than what actually happens. He therefore Also see 1:355, 298.
33
seems to remain committed to the dual realm conception of the Dreams that This account also figures in Determination of a Concept of a Human race (1785).
34
conceives of the laws structuring human mental activity in analogy to the laws of Kant’s historical account of reason in his Conjectural Beginning of History
nature. (1786) offers a slightly different story.
74 A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76

formed humans after everything else had been created (Ideen, 115), In Kant’s “Review of Moscati’s Of the Corporeal Essential Differences
35
he stresses that this last act of creation was completed only at the between the Structure of Animals and Humans” (1771) we find impor-
moment that nature commanded, “Stand up on the Earth! Left to tant parallels to Herder’s account of the Ideen. Similar to Herder, Kant
yourself, you would be a beast among beasts; but through my claims that our posturedKant here refers to our two-footednessdhas
special aid and care, walk erect and be the God of beasts” (Ideen, important implications for our lives in nature and society. However,
115).36 different from Herder, Kant argues that the fact that humans have
Although this myth of creation purports to tell us that human reason cannot be explained through a change in their posture alone,
beings come into existence by design and all at once, that is, but must be seen as a result of the presence of a specific germ:
without gradual developments taking place after their first for-
The first foresight of nature was that the human being as an an-
mation, it is crucial to note that Herder describes nature as creating
imal be preserved for himself and his kind; and for that the position
human beings out of precisely those materials out of which it had
for which is most suited to his internal build, the situation of the
already formed all other beings. This, as well as the temporal
fetus and the preservation in dangers is the four-footed one; but
dimension invoked when comparing the not-yet reasonable ape to
that there also has been placed in him a germ of reason through
the already rational human being, indicates an important conti-
which, if the latter develops, he is destined for society, and by
nuity (Ideen, 128-9). Rather than suggesting that one act of creation
means of which he assumes permanently the most suitable po-
carried out at one point in time is responsible for the division of the
sition for society, viz. the two-footed one. (2:425: 80-1)
species, Herder insinuates that matter can continue to form itself,
and thereby ultimately give way to something as unique as the life
of rational agents.37 With this conception of reason as a germ, Kant in principle
The claim that continuities between humans and the rest of denies those continuities Herder is keen to stress. Since beings
creation play a major role in Herder’s thinking is supported by the come into existence with or without the relevant germ, there is no
consideration that for Herder it is not the upright posture itself that way for them to develop out of themselves and by way of a reor-
renders “humans human”, but the “new organisation of forces” ganisation of an already present force the power of reason, which
(Ideen, 115). Implied in this account is that even before humans then enables them to live a life in society.
stood up, their existence was governed by forces similar to those Furthermore, by invoking germs, Kant gestures towards a model
found in other animals: after all, what changes with the ability to of development that we have already encountered in the Universal
walk upright is the organisation of forces, and not that there are Natural History. As we have seen, he here thinks of development
such forces.38 and change as effects of the motion of matter that has been
For Herder, forces are “organisational principles” (Ideen, 115) of configured in such a way that it only drives out determinations in
nature that, similar to Caspar Friedrich Wolff’s vis essentialis, line with the divine plan. The point of this account is, as I have
constitute the so called “Lebensprinzip”.39 Importantly, for Herder argued, to make sure that activity that resembles the purposive,
this principle of life is observable not only in organic matter but in free action of a divine creator mind cannot enter into the realm of
the entire universe as it actively drives forward on-going creation created matter.
(see for instance Ideen 21-32 and 166).40 And even though he Now, the same logic seems to underlie Kant’s account of reason
stresses that the principle of life is different from the force of as a germ. Germs, similar to Kant’s programmed parcels of matter,
reason, Herder is clear that all forces connect and communicate ensure a development that unfolds in accordance with the de-
with one another [in Verbindung stehen] (Ideen, 273). This once terminations that God has originally implanted in the human body.
again stresses that in the Ideen Herder thinks of reason in conti- The conception of reason as a germ therefore ensures that reason
nuity with the forces of matter and organic life rather than in op- can emerge only in those creatures that God has chosen, but cannot
position to them. evolve out of the forces of nature itself.41 Kant’s germ of reason thus
contributes to the conception of the species borders as having been
established once and for all at the beginning of history, namely
when all the relevant germs were originally distributed among the
35
In the preface to the Ideen Herder specifies that “Natur” is not distinct from God various parcels of matter. It thereby blocks the possibility that
but that “Gott ist Alles in seinem Werken,” Ideen 17. See Lord (2009), especially pp. animalsdwhich, as we have seen in the previous section, also
55-58, for an analysis of Herder’s concept of God as an active dynamic being received a specific kind of germ that makes it possible for them to
immanent in nature. reproduce life within the confined limits of their own spe-
36
My own translation. Here is the original: “Steh auf von der Erde! Dir selbst
ciesdcould morph into human beings due to unforeseeable cir-
überlassen, wärest du Tier wie andere Tiere; aber durch meine besondere Huld und
Liebe gehe aufrecht und werde der Gott der Tiere.” cumstances produced by freely unfolding dynamics of generation.42
37
The contrast to Kant’s position here becomes most apparent, as Reinhard To be sure, humans endowed with the germ of reason infuse
Brandt notes: “Kant all through his life rejected the effort in the sphere of natural into the realm of created matter precisely the kind of activity that
history to discern a natural transition from merely mechanical to organic nature,” Kant’s argument for the mechanical origin of the universe is
Brandt (1980), p. 81.
38 intended to rule out. This is because reason enables free action in
In Herder’s 1772-account of the origin of language, he claims that humans are
endowed with a special kind of innate awareness that then evolves into fully- line with one’s intentions and in this sense resembles the agency
fledged reason through the acquisition of language. Herder here also denies the characteristic of a divine being that acts on the principles of
continuity between animal expressions and the human use of linguistic signs; cf.
DeSouza (2012) and Lifschitz (2012), pp. 1-6 and chapter 7. The early Herder thus
seems to be much closer to Kant who understands reason as an innate principle (or
germ) implanted in us by God than the Herder of the Ideen who gestures towards a
41
conception of reason that evolves out of the general forces of nature. Kant makes the same point in his lectures on metaphysics, stressing that God is
39
See Roe (2002), pp. 46-50, and Zammito (2003), p. 87, for an analysis of Wolff’s the creator of the soul: “All generation of substance is produced ex nihilo, creation;
influence on Herder. because before the substance there was nothing. A creature itself, however, does
40
As Sloan notes, this is a crucial difference between the HerdereWolff version of not itself have a creative, but only a developmental [bildende] force, i.e., [the ability
epigenesis and the version Blumenbach puts forth when restricting the efficacy of to divide or compound things that are already given. There is no alternative,
the Bildungstrieb to the living domain; see Sloan (2002), p. 248. See Wolff (1764) for accordingly, but to assume the soul is preformed [praeformiert], however it may be
an account of the vis essentialis as capable to produce organic matter out of inor- with the creation of the body,”(29:760-1).
42
ganic matter. Cf. Zammito (2003), p. 79; Sloan (2002), p. 245.
A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76 75

freedom and purpose.43 However, on Kant’s account, it is not nature state. Now we know no other internal principle in a substance for
but God that gave humans the ability to reason and act freely, such changing its state expect desiring, and no other internal activity at
that he can still maintain that nature is devoid of the particular kind all except thinking, together with what depends on it, the feeling
of activity that can produce out of its own accord human reason.44 of pleasure and displeasure, a desire or willing. (4:544, 251-2)
By referring to germs rather than forces that arise independently of
such germs, Kant is thus able to explain how it is possible that
Importantly, activity is now quite generally taken to stand for
humans are capable of an activity that is very different from any
mind-like, voluntary activity that follows one’s own desires and
other kind of activity in the universe, however without thereby
thoughts. This is precisely the kind of activity that Kant was already
attributing free agency that is organised around intentions and the
at pains to rule out as a cause of creation in the Universal Natural
principle of choice to nature itself.45
History and the Only Possible Argument. Yet in contrast to his earlier
Bearing these connections in mind, we can now see that in
writings, Kant no longer allows for a second kind of activity, that is,
Kant’s review of the Ideen more is at stake than the complaint that
an activity that blindly unfolds as a result of the fact that matter has
Herder believes in life forces, although such forces are invisible.
appropriately been configured by a divine creator. After all, for the
Kant seems to be particularly concerned about the fact that Herder
Kant of the Foundations all matter is dead, and for this reason
conceives of forces as freely creating agents. Herder’s account thus
cannot act, not even in the sense that it drives out the programme
directly counteracts Kant’s sustained attempt to keep the forces of
that the divine being has implanted in it. He writes: “The inertia of
matter locked in the general dynamics of the mechanism of nature
matter is, and means, nothing else than its lifelessness, as matter in
by conceiving of them as gaining their determination from a divine
itself” (4: 544, 251).
being the moment they were created. So strictly speaking, Kant’s
The reason for this change might well be, as Eric Watkins has
forces do not determine themselves; and this crucially distin-
argued, that Kant’s conception of internal magnitude challenges
guishes them from Herder’s forces. As we have seen, Herder argues
the claim that space is infinitely divisible.46 A further reason might
that forces produce out of their own accord, and without having
be, as Beiser has claimed, that through Kant’s engagement with
been configured to do so, lifedand even the capacity for rational
Herder’s Ideen, he could no longer ignore the “thorny issue of
thought when they enable humans to adopt an upright position.
teleology”47, since Herder’s forces are able to freely create for
certain purposes. These two interpretations can be connected if we
4. The death of active matter return to the worry that Kant articulated in the Inquiry and
repeated in the Dreams. That is, the worry that we cannot establish
The problem with Kant’s account of course is that we cannot that there is a fundamental difference between physical monads
know whether, metaphysically speaking, the activity of matter is and souls, and that we therefore cannot rule out that in drinking
really different in kind from the activity we find in humans, who in our coffee we “swallow atoms destined to become human souls”
virtue of having reason and will can act for certain purposes and in (2:327, 314). This possibility emerges because, by being composed
a self-determined way. In order to establish this difference, it could of the same kind of material, it is conceivable that something
perhaps be argued that there are two different kinds of substance physical can generate out of itself the features we take to be char-
that, as Kant claims in the Dreams, accord with two different sets of acteristic of souls. 48
laws: that of the general will and that of nature. However, Kant Approached from this angle, the pressing problem is not to rule
himself denounces this argument as an absurd outgrowth of the out that nature is purposive per se; nor merely to explain how the
attempt to think of the soul in analogy to matter. He thus remains internal magnitude of something unextended like the physical
with next to nothing in his hands to defend the claim that the ac- monad can constitute infinitely divisible space. On the reading
tivity of matter is of an entirely different nature than the activity developed here, both accounts have a deeper motivation, namely to
characteristic of free, purposive agency. block a conception of reason, rationality and the ability to act freely
Kant’s decision to drop the concept of active matter in The and for certain purposes as having evolved out of the dynamics of
Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (1786) removes this matter. After all, if souls and physical monads are granted the same
problem. He now defines matter as movable in space and unable to kind of internal magnitude, they are granted the same kind of force.
determine its own motion and rest. On this account, activity and life And this renders it possible to think that the purposiveness and
go together, while desiring, thinking, and feeling pleasure and rationality characteristic of human action have developed out of
paindas well as having representations more generallydare something which is perhaps not yet a fully-fledged principle of
invoked to specify what this activity is: rationality and purposiveness in itself, but which already contains
the seeds of it.
Life is the faculty of a substance to determine itself to act from an As we have seen, Kant’s early writings already show a good deal
internal principle, of a finite substance to change, and of a material of determination in ruling out that mind-like, intentional forces that
substance [to determine itself] to motion and rest, as change of its operate upon the principle of choice are at work in created matter.
Such forces would introduce contingencies into nature that would
render it as unpredictable and chaotic as the Epicurean universe. For
43
Reinhard Brandt calls this capacity for free agency “the vocation (Bestimmung) the critical Kant, the need to rule out the possibility of freely acting
of the human being” to emancipate itself “from nature through self-determination
forces that pervade nature becomes even more pressing. If reason
(Selbst-Bestimmung),” Brandt (1980), p. 94.
44
As we have seen, in his essay On the Use of Teleological Principles (1788) (also see developed out of the universal dynamics present in the realm of
Determination of the Concept of a Human Race from 1785 and On the Different Races
of the Human Species from 1775) Kant also invokes “Keime” to explain the purpo-
siveness of organisms and their ability for variation and adaptation. However, since
46
for Kant “Keime” are divinely ordained and cannot be seen as the products of an See Watkins (2001), p. 142-145.
47
evolving nature, here too nature is seen as unable to produce out of itself the ability Beiser (1987), p. 153.
48
to pursue ends. Of course, Kant cannot accept an account that leaves open the possibility of
45
C. Zumbach characterises Kant’s account of the causality of reason as a play of inanimate matter continuously evolving to become organic and eventually human.
free, teleological causes, and he contrasts this system of causality with “the me- Zammito notes: “Nothing was more important to him, metaphysically or method-
chanical conception of nature which lacks this idea of a free cause,” Zumbach ologically, than to police the boundaries between the organic and the inorganic,
(1984), p. 83. and, again, between man and animal,” Zammito (2002), pp. 306-307.
76 A. Waldow / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 67e76

matter, it would be formed by a world that could have been different, DeSouza, N. (2012). Language, reason and sociability: Herder’s critique of Rousseau.
Intellectual History Review, 22(2), 221-240.
so that reason could have been different too. Moreover, given that
Falkenstein, L. (1990). Was Kant a nativist? Journal of the History of Ideas, 51(4), 573-
the Kantian universe perpetually evolves, reason’s structure would 597.
never stop changing in its communication with the particular space- Friedman, M. (1992). Kant and the exact sciences. Cambridge/Mass: Harvard Uni-
time coordinates of the ever-evolving universe within which it finds versity Press.
Genova, A. C. (1974). Kant’s epigenesis of pure reason. Kantstudien, 65, 259-273.
itself. Reason would thus turn into a contingent product and could Ginsborg, H. (2001). Kant on understanding organisms as natural purpose. In
no longer serve as a fixed point of reference, thereby undermining E. Watkins (Ed.), Kant and the sciences (pp. 231-254). Oxford: Oxford University
the supposedly necessary structure of the Kantian Apriori on which Press.
Herder, J. G. (1989). Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit. In
the possibility of objective knowledge depends.49 M. Bollacher (Ed.), Werke in Zehn Bänden (Vol. 6, pp. 1784-1791), Frankfurt am
With these considerations in mind, it looks like Kant is not Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag.
exaggerating when claiming in the Foundations that hylozoism is Kant, I. (1900). Gesammelte Schriften (Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaft, Ed.).
Berlin: de Gruyter.
“the death of all natural philosophy” (4:544, 252). This position Kant, I. (1995-). The Cambridge edition of the works of Immanuel Kant, edited by
admits of internal forces as constituents of matter, thereby leading P. Guyer, & A. Wood, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
straightforwardly into the problem that ultimately undermines the Kitcher, P. (1990). Kant’s transcendental psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lifschitz, A. (2012). Language and enlightenment: The Berlin debates of the eighteenth-
plausibility of Kant’s entire critical project.50 Given this funda- century. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
mental threat, it seems less troublesome indeed to let go of the idea Lord, B. (2009). Against the fanatism of forces: Kant’s critique of Herder’s Spino-
that there are such things as active forces in nature. All the more so zism. Parallax, 15(2), 53-62.
McLaughlin, P. (1990). Kant’s critique of teleology in biological explanation: Antinomy
at a point in Kant’s career when the principles of his critical phi-
and teleology. Lewiston: E. Mellen Press.
losophy prevent him from invoking a divine being in order to flesh Mensch, J. (2013). Kant’s organicism. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
out what it means for something to be active and yet to lack the Müller-Sievers, H. (1997). Self generation. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
capacity for free purposive agency. Redding, P. (2009). Continental idealism, from Leibniz to Nietzsche. New York:
Routledge.
Riskin, J. (2015). Striving machinery: The romantic origins of a historical science of
life. Intellectual History Review, 25(3), 293-310.
5. Conclusion Roe, S. (2002). Matter, life and generation: 18th-Century embryology and the Hallere
Wolff debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
In the literature this last point is well acknowledged: that for the Sloan, P. (2002). Performing the categories: Eighteenth-century generation theory
and the biological roots of Kant’s a priori. Journal of the History of Philosophy,
critical Kant in order to prevent the collapse of his epistemological
40(2), 229-253.
project it is of utmost importance to rule out that reason could have Terrall, M. (2002). The man who flattened the Earth: Maupertuis and the sciences in
its origin in nature.51 Yet what is often overlooked is that there is an the enlightenment. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
important continuity between Kant’s pre-critical efforts to keep Waschkies, H. J. (1987). Physik und Physikotheologie des jungen Kant. Amserdam: B.
R. Güner.
nature free of mind-like, intentional powers and his later claim that Watkins, E. (2001). Kant’s justification of the laws of mechanics. In E. Watkins (Ed.),
nature is devoid of active forces and purposes. This essay has tried Kant and the sciences, 136-15, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
to bring into focus this continuity, while acknowledging that Kant’s Watkins, E. (2003). Forces and causes in Kant’s early pre-critical writings. Studies in
History and Philosophy of Science, 34, 5-27.
critical stance complicates his position. What is gained by this Wolff, C. F. (1764). Theorie von der Generation. Stuttgart: G. Fischer.
interpretation is that we can better understand why it is, as Zam- Wubnig, J. (1969). The epigenesis of pure reason. Kantstudien, 60, 147-152.
mito has put it, that even the critical Kant “tacitly” accepted the Zammito, J. H. (1992). The genesis of Kant’s Critique of judgement. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
existence of forces in nature. Based on the analysis of his early Zammito, J. H. (2002). Kant, Herder, and the birth of anthropology. Chicago: Chicago
writings we can say that Kant typically attacks the conception of University Press.
one specific kind of force: a force that behaves as an active, pur- Zammito, J. H. (2003). ‘This inscrutable principle of an original organization:’ Epi-
genesist and ‘Looseness of Fit’ in Kant’s philosophy of science. Studies in History
posive agent. Forces that operate within the fixed patterns of nat- and Philosophy of Science, 34, 73-109.
ural causation thus emerge as principally unproblematic and Zammito, J. H. (2006). Kant’s early views on epigenesis. In J. Smith (Ed.), The problem
therefore can be accepted in the non-committal way that is of animal generation (pp. 317-355). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zöller, G. (1988). Kant on the generation of metaphysical knowledge. In H. Oberer, &
compatible with Kant’s critical stance.
G. Seel (Eds.), Kant: Analysen-Probleme-Kritik (pp. 71-90). Würzburg: König-
shausen & Neumann.
Zöller, G. (1989). From innate to ‘a priori’: Kant’s radical transformation of a
References Cartesian-Leinizian legacy. Monist, 72, 222-235.
Zuckert, R. (2007). Kant on beauty and biology: An interpretation of the Critique of
Beiser, F. (1987). The fate of reason. Cambridge/Mass: Harvard University Press. judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Boehm, O. (2014). Kant’s critique of Spinoza. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Zumbach, C. (1984). The transcendent science: Kant’s conception of biological meth-
Brandt, R. (1980). “Kant e Herder e Kuhn.” Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 5, odology. The Hague: Nijhoff.
27-36.

49
If reason’s organisational structure were dependent on external circumstances,
it could no longer be seen as being productive of its own intuitions and categories;
see Zöller ([1989], p. 231f) for this argument and the claim that it is the productivity
of the understanding that ensures the objective necessity of the Kantian Apriori. See
Zöller ([1988], 77-9), for an analysis of Kant’s rejection of the conception of God as
an external constraint on human rationality for its potential to undermine the
possibility of knowledge.
50
Cf. Beiser (1987), p. 154.
51
Zöller (1988) and (1989); Beiser (1987); Zammito (1992); Sloan (2002); Mensch
(2013).

You might also like