You are on page 1of 13

The Behavior Analyst 1984, 7, 83-95 No.

2 (Fall)

Observational Learning from a


Radical-Behavioristic Viewpoint
Hikaru Deguchi
Keio University
Bandura (1972, 1977b) has argued that observational learning has some distinctive features that set it
apart from the operant paradigm: (1) acquisition simply through observation, (2) delayed performance
through cognitive mediation, and (3) vicarious reinforcement. The present paper first redefines those three
features at the descriptive level, and then adopts a radical-behavioristic viewpoint to show how those
redefined distinctive features can be explained and tested experimentally. Finally, the origin of obser-
vational learning is discussed in terms of recent data of neonatal imitation. The present analysis offers a
consistent theoretical and practical understanding of observational learning from a radical-behavioristic
viewpoint.

According to social-learning theory, a through observation; (2) delayed perfor-


new behavior can be acquired symboli- mance mediated by cognitive processes
cally at a cognitive level simply through whose need, history, and autonomy are
the perception of a modeled behavior. not analyzed; and (3) the importance of
The acquired behavior can then be stored vicarious rather than direct reinforce-
as a symbolic representation and per- ment. Among radical behaviorists and
formed much later under the guidance of social-learning theorists, however, these
that representation (Bandura, 1971 a, conflicts seem to lie not in the empirical
1971b, 1972, 1977b). Thus, acquisition data, but rather in their interpretation and
is clearly different from performance. The in where to look for a more complete
acquisition of new behavior via an ob- analysis.
server's exposure to the modeled behav- Some behavior analysts have attempt-
ior is called "observational learning." ed to explain the phenomena of obser-
This perspective emphasizes the per- vational learning within their behavioral
ceived reinforcement of the modeled per- systems (Gewirtz, 197 la, 197 lb; White-
formance (vicarious reinforcement) rath- hurst, 1 978). Gewirtz (1971 a, 1 971 b; Ge-
er than current or historical direct wirtz & Stingle, 1968) presented an early
reinforcement of any of the observer's behavioral view of observational learn-
behavior. Vicarious reinforcement is said ing using operant conditioning princi-
to play informative and motivational ples. Whitehurst (1978) has attempted to
roles for future performance by creating define and classify types of observational
expectations about the results of later im- learning and to identify some variables
itation. Thus, imitation can occur even that influence it. These attempts have ad-
if it is not reinforced directly at that time. vanced the behavioral understanding of
This view of observational learning has observational learning, although not al-
some distinctively inefficient or short- ways from the standpoint of radical be-
sighted features from a radical-behavior- haviorism (see Day, 1983; Skinner, 1974).
istic viewpoint: (1) acquisition simply Gewirtz, for example, apparently saw no
roles of private events or of phylogenic
The author deeply thanks Dr. Donald M. Baer, contingencies in his analysis of obser-
my mentor, for his help, valuable suggestions, and vational learning. Whitehurst intention-
encouragement in preparing this manuscript. The ally avoided integrating variables that can
author also would like to express his sincere thanks control and influence observational
to Dr. Edward K. Morris for his valuable comments learning into a minimal set of behavioral
and criticisms on this manuscript.
Reprints may be obtained from the author, De- principles. The purpose of this paper is
partment of Psychology, Keio University, Tokyo, to establish a minimal set of consistent
Japan. functional explanations from a radical-
83
84 HIKARU DEGUCHI
behavioristic viewpoint. The present One-Trial Learning
analysis shows how radical behaviorism
and social-learning theory interpret ob- The first component of the descriptive
servational learning and attempts to re- definition is the one-trial demonstration
solve major conflicts between the two of relatively novel behavior following an
paradigms and to put in perspective the exposure to the modeled behavior with-
origin of observational learning. out any direct manual guidance, prompt-
ing, or external reinforcement. Even if
social-learning theory insists that the ac-
DESCRIPTIVE DEFINITION quisition of such behavior occurs at the
The first step toward resolving con- cognitive level, the behavior must be per-
flicts between radical behaviorists and formed at least once to assure us (its re-
social-learning theorists is to redefine the searchers) of its acquisition. The term
three distinctive features of observation- "one-trial" is more descriptive than the
al learning at the level of description. term "acquisition," except at the cogni-
Radical behaviorists and cognitive psy- tive level, which is not observable, and
chologists speak different languages, even our purpose now is description.
when they are talking about the same For some social-learning theorists, ob-
thing (Catania, 1972). Thus the use of servational learning is a primary category
only one language may fail to distinguish of behavior process: New behavior is ac-
what they share from how they differ. quired through stimulus contiguity and
The descriptive definition of the three cognitive mediation simply by observa-
distinctive features of observational tion (Bandura, 1977b; Bower & Hilgard,
learning allows us to examine whether 1981). Indeed, in a typical social-learning
what can be said in the language of social- paradigm, normal children show the ac-
learning theory can also be said in the quisition of relatively new behavior
language of radical behaviorism and per- through a single exposure or repeated ex-
haps said better. The three features can posures to a modeled response even when
be summarized descriptively as follows: external reinforcement is impossible (e.g.,
Bandura, 1965; Bandura, Ross, & Ross,
(1) One-trial learning: Relatively new behavior 1963). Interestingly, most radical behav-
can be imitated following a single exposure to the iorists would not be surprised by this ob-
model without any direct physical assistance or ex-
ternal reinforcement. servation ofone-trial learning. They have
(2) Delayed performance: That behavior can be seen relatively new models of behavior
performed later and in the absence of the model imitated on the initial trial (or trials)
whether or not it is performed at the time of mod- without external reinforcement or phys-
eling. ical assistance, as long as other imitations
(3) Observed consequences: A modeled response
producing contingent reinforcement to the model are reinforced (Brigham & Sherman,
is more likely to be imitated than a modeled re- 1968) or after enough imitation training,
sponse that does not produce contingent reinforce- in the cases of initially nonimitative per-
ment to the model. sons (Baer, Peterson, & Sherman, 1967;
Metz, 1965). Most behaviorists still sup-
BEHAVIORAL INTERPRETATION pose, however, that the origin of that
ability lies in the subject's conditioning
The second step is to interpret and ex- history, although they sometimes differ
amine these three features, now redefined subtly in postulating the ways that rein-
at the descriptive level, in the language forcement histories influence that ability
of radical behaviorism. Conflicts un- (see Baer & Deguchi, in press, for a con-
veiled through this behavioral interpre- ditioned-reinforcement thesis, and Ge-
tation can then be analyzed at method- wirtz, 197 la, for a conditional-discrim-
ological and philosophical levels to ination thesis).
resolve or clarify the conflicts between Thus, one conflict lies in the historical
radical behaviorists and social-learning role of reinforcement for the emergence
theorists. and control of one-trial learning. This
BEHAVIORAL ANALYSIS OF OBSERVATIONAL LEARNING 85
conflict appears to be due partly to the Thomas, 1981). Thus, social-learning
length or levels of observation that so- theorists should be open to the possibility
cial-learning and behavioral approaches ofdirect but eventual reinforcement con-
have adopted in their analyses of the phe- trol. Although the origin of observational
nomenon. To observe the role of rein- learning is unknown and may be expect-
forcement in already generalized imita- ed to be difficult to prove (this issue is
tions, behavior should be observed over discussed later in depth), reinforcement
extensive time because behavior can be control of observational learning is al-
controlled by very sparse intermittent re- ready empirical fact. Given that, we can
inforcement schedules (Ferster & Skin- then inquire further into the operant
ner, 1957; Gewirtz, 1971b). In behav- characteristics of observational learning.
ioral research, continuous assessment of Perhaps this direction of research will
behavior typically is used to collect data contribute to the further development of
over time and with individual-analysis "modeling therapies" based on social-
designs. Through this continuous anal- learning theory (see Kirkland & Thelen,
ysis, imitation has been observed to in- 1977; Rosenthal & Bandura, 1978).
crease or decrease over time by manip-
ulating its consequences, even its very Delayed Performance
intermittent consequences (cf. Baer &
Deguchi, in press). In most social-learn- The second component of the descrip-
ing research, however, behavior is ob- tive definition is that the observer can
served for relatively short times and with perform an imitative response much lat-
between-group designs. Data for each er and in the absence of the model.
subject are usually collected only over Cognitive mediation. To explain de-
one or two sessions of pre- and post-test- layed performance, some social-learning
ing: Their reliability is analyzed statis- theorists (e.g., Bandura, 1971a, 1971b,
tically. Especially in normal children, ob- 1977b) emphasize the role of represen-
servational learning or imitation has been tational processes said to mediate sub-
likely to be reinforced at least intermit- sequent behavior. Once a representation
tently outside the laboratory. Then how of behavior has been acquired, it is pre-
could the effects of intermittent rein- sumed to be stored and to guide later
forcement in the natural environment be performance of the observed behavior.
validated with such short term synchron- From a behavioral viewpoint, however,
ic observation in the laboratory? Differ- hypothesizing about supposed cognitive
ent conclusions may well be reached de- mediators may not be necessary to ex-
pending on how long or when the plain delayed performance. Delayed per-
behavior is sampled; that is, absent con- formance can be explained as a phenom-
tinuous assessment of observational enon on the same continuum with
learning, researchers may well miss the immediate imitation-a delay always oc-
long-term role of reinforcement. curs between the modeled behavior and
One-trial observational learning is the so-called immediate imitative re-
negatively defined, if its definition relies sponses (Gewirtz & Stingle, 1968). Why
on observing an absence of reinforce- is a different level of explanation needed
ment for only a short time (also see Baer, for phenomena continuously distributed
1982b, and Beach, 1955, on negative def- on a simple continuum of time?
initions). The definition may stand only Still, Bandura (1971 a) has argued that
until we observe some longer-term re- this kind of explanation can be possible
inforcement control of observational only when the delay is short but that con-
learning. Ample evidence exists that an siderably delayed imitation in the ab-
imitative response class can easily be sence of the model is too difficult to ex-
controlled by its intermittent contingent plain without a concept of cognitive
consequences (Baer & Deguchi, in press; mediation. However, if the emergence of
Baer & Sherman, 1964; Baer et al., 1967; delayed performance can be traced to the
Brigham & Sherman, 1968; Furnell & reinforcement history of the individual
86 HIKARU DEGUCHI

and can be controlled by environmental control group. These results were inter-
manipulation, then delayed performance preted as empirical support for the sig-
could be attributed to and thus explained nificant role of cognitive operations in
by describing those historical conditions observational learning and delayed per-
without hypothesizing a mediating cog- formance, and for the usefulness of the
nitive process that is not independently acquisition-performance distinction.
manipulable. For example, Garcia ( 1974) Descriptively, however, these data show
trained three initially somewhat imita- only a close correlation between certain
tive retarded children and one nonimi- verbal instructions and subsequent overt
tative retarded child to imitate both im- behavior. This correlation may not jus-
mediately and after delays. The tify any causal relationship between cog-
nonreinforced delayed imitations in- nitive operations and behavior. In ad-
creased only when reinforcement was dition, what was manipulated, at the level
contingent on other delayed imitations. of description, were not cognitive events
Also, when reinforcement was contin- but types of instructions.
gent on some immediate imitations, non- This need not mean that private events
reinforced immediate imitations in- are irrelevant to the analysis of obser-
creased, and nonreinforced delayed vational learning. Most radical behav-
imitations decreased. iorists do not deny the existence of pri-
Thus, delayed imitation can be creat- vate events and do recommend analyzing
ed, controlled, and eliminated by rein- them thoroughly as physical, behavioral
forcement contingent on the timing of events (Day, 1969; Johnston & Penny-
imitations. Describing conditions under packer, 1980; Moore, 1980, 1984; Skin-
which delayed performance is shaped and ner, 1945, 1953, 1957, 1972, 1974). The
generalized to new instances when those scientific analysis of private events is one
conditions are basic procedures in an ex- of the distinguishing characteristics of
planatory system in itself forms a con- radical behaviorism (Skinner, 1974). In
vincing behavioral explanation within this paradigm, private events are as-
that system. Making more complex sys- sumed to be capable of playing a role in
tems is not parsimonious. behavior as mediators (Skinner, 1972, p.
Environmental antecedents. Other 325), or as parts of causal chains of be-
cases, however, exist where cognitive havior (Baer, 1982a; Moore, 1984).
functioning has been supposed to play an However, merely hypothesizing cog-
important role. For example, certain types nitive processes-and only cognitive
of instructions are seen as manipulations processes-is limited in utility. How can
of functional cognitive events by some we manipulate one's cognitive events in-
social-learning theorists (Bandura & Jef- dependently of manipulating types and
fery, 1973; Bandura, Jeffery, & Bachicha, histories of instructions and experience?
1974; Gerst, 1971). In the Gerst study The ultimate cause of behavior, from an
(1971), college students were exposed to experimenter's viewpoint, should be
filmed modeling stimuli. One group of found outside the organism, partly in the
students was instructed to memorize sense that only environmental events' are
them by vivid imagery, a second group directly accessible and effectively manip-
by verbal coding, and a third group by ulable (Skinner, 1974, p. 10; Blanshard
labeling them concisely. A fourth group & Skinner, 1967, p. 331). For analysis, it
was the control group; they were required
to count the beats of a metronome to
prevent their engaging in cognitive pro- ' Environmental and private events, however, are
cesses. All three coding groups were sta- not in any way dichotomous. Dr. Lawrence E. Fra-
tistically superior to the control group in ley, a reviewer of this paper, points out that one's
an immediate-reproduction test. In a de- private events sometimes are directly accessible and
layed-reproduction test (15 min period), manipulable when analyzers deal with their own
private events, which are unconcerned about a proof
the summary-labeling group was better of another audience. Thus, for them, those private
than the other two coding groups and the events are environmental.
BEHAVIORAL ANALYSIS OF OBSERVATIONAL LEARNING 87

is crucial to know of what the private its final causes that should be pursued.
events are a function and how to manip- What should be questioned is why those
ulate those events for the control and pre- immediate antecedents come to predict
diction of observational learning. Atten- or influence observational learning,
tion should then be directed not only to probably at the level of environmental
types of instructions manipulated in the history. At that level, those immediate
immediate case but also to how those antecedents can acquire discriminative
instructions come to influence the emer- functions (controlling power) for the ob-
gence of observational learning, not at server or the person who attempts to pre-
the cognitive but at the environmental, dict, probably because it is in association
historical level. Otherwise, individual dif- with the predecessors of those relevant
ferences in the effects of types of instruc- antecedents that observational learning
tions are difficult to explain (other than has been reinforced, extinguished, or
tautologically) and to modify. A thor- punished.
ough experimental analysis of private Private events as history. The difficulty
events cannot be made unless we identify of knowing someone's entire history does
their immediate and historical environ- not mean that we cannot analyze the rel-
mental antecedents. When private events atively small parts of it operating in a
are a cause, they might best be assumed given case or that intrinsically tautolog-
to be questioned as potential formal ical cognitive processes are the necessary
causes (Moore, 1984), that is, as mo- alternative, and thus sufficient. As Baer
mentary, local causes operating as parts (1 982a) has argued, a series of studies by
of a behavioral chain. If so, their expla- Meichenbaum and his colleagues (e.g.,
nation cannot be complete until their im- Meichenbaum & Goodman, 1969, 1971;
mediate and historical antecedents are Asarnow & Meichenbaum, 1979) shows
specified. that teaching certain self-instruction pro-
Some cognitive psychologists point out cedures can offer a useful experimental
that the entire history of an individual is model for this issue. (It should be noted
unknowable, and, known or unknown, that Meichenbaum's interpretation of the
affects current behavior only by con- procedure and its results are not always
structing cognitive processes that operate similar to the present analysis.) In their
in the current situation (see Bandura, procedure (especially, Meichenbaum &
197 la; Wessells, 1981). As a result of this, Goodman, 1971), children are taught
the social-learning approach has not paid through modeling and instructions to say
much attention to histories (e.g., Ban- a series of corrective statements to them-
dura, 1977a, 1977b). Their experimental selves intended to regulate their own
inquiries have been about immediate en- problem-solving behaviors, initially at an
vironmental antecedents that interact overt level but fading gradually to a co-
with supposedly already existing cogni- vert level. Children with such training in
tive processes and that thereby influence self-instruction show certain changes in
observational learning, such as types of their performance relative to children
instructions, characteristics of the model without that training. A behavioral anal-
and the observer, and consequences to ysis of this procedure acknowledges that
the model (see Akamatsu & Thelen, 1974; self-instructive behavior can be made part
Rosenthal & Zimmerman, 1978; Thelen of a behavioral chain controlling other
& Rennie, 1972). For behavior analysts, behavior and that this can be made to
these immediate antecedents are at best happen through direct teaching of self-
considered as predictors of observational instructive behavior, that is, as a function
learning or as social or physical condi- of certain prior environmental histories.
tional discriminative stimuli that set the In this view, private events are not in-
occasion for observational learning to be ferred substitutes for the reinforcement
reinforced, extinguished, or punished. But history because they are demonstrably
they are neither explanatory of all the products of it and demonstrably func-
variability of observational learning nor tional. Those events are parts of the chain
88 HIKARU DEGUCHI
that follows the immediate environmen- Private events, like other operations
tal antecedents whose functions have been that may interact with subsequent ob-
created by their historical interactions servational learning, can be analyzed into
with reinforcement contingencies. behaviors at an overt level. Their validity
The experimental analysis of historical is tested by teaching them to naive or-
reinforcement contingencies can be a log- ganisms and then observing the effects of
ical substitute for merely constructing that teaching. The generality of that
hypothetical cognitive processes. What teaching and of the behaviors taught
may be going on at a cognitive level can should be examined in terms of the ex-
be analyzed and taught at the overt level tent to which they work powerfully and
before allowing the behavior to become in many situations, especially in non-
covert as parts of the chain. Such analyses teaching situations. For some behavior-
of private events into workable behav- ists, at least, it is not the postulation but
ioral skills to be taught might be very rather the experimental analysis of pri-
important to applied behavior analysis vate events-by transforming them ef-
(Baer, 1982a, 1983). Can we not analyze fectively at a procedural level as in-
private operations (events) that possibly structions or teaching-that is of great
follow different types ofinstructions used importance.
in observational learning research into One theoretical problem is still un-
effective teaching procedures? For ex- solved: How can we be sure of the on-
ample, can we not teach how to describe going function of those newly taught
the modeled response verbally to chil- events after they become covert and
dren who do not respond well to the in- unobservable? Probably, we cannot. The
struction to memorize the model by co- only recourse is to be pragmatic. Once
vert verbal coding and observe its effects possible private events are analyzed into
in the children's later reproduction of the an effective instructional or teaching pro-
model? cedures, theorizing about their subse-
Then how can we analyze private quent function may no longer be useful.
events?2 Sometimes we can deduce their It is better to analyze private events by
nature: We can ask what private process learning how to teach them and see what
could control the public behavior in difference that makes; then we should be
question (see Baer, 1 982a, for an example satisfied with knowing those effects and
of the logical analysis of an experimen- their procedural antecedents, and should
tally teachable, initially public square- recognize as speculation any further
root algorithm that eventually becomes knowledge of their later, ongoing func-
private). Verbal reports about private tion within the behavioral system (D. M.
events may sometimes be a source of hy- Baer, personal communication, April 12,
potheses for the subsequent experimental 1984). This strategy may be seen as rad-
analyses of those events (Skinner, 1953, ical behaviorism in that the analysis of
p. 282). Note, however, that verbal re- private events as environmentally con-
ports are not dependable as a measure of trolled potential mediators can play an
"efficacy expectation" (e.g., Bandura, important role in the study of observa-
1977a) nor should they be conceptual- tional learning. Yet some analysts may
ized as a metacognition (e.g., Meichen- consider only privately the role that pri-
baum & Asarnow, 1981; also see Lowe vate events might play in their subjects'
& Higson, 1981, for a discussion of me- behavior. If they make that analysis real
tacognition from a radical-behavioristic by constructing observable teaching cur-
viewpoint). ricula and do not publicize their deduc-
tions about the private events that the
public curriculum is to teach, they will
2 General tactics to
private events have been dis- appear to be methodological behavior-
cussed elsewhere (see Johston & Pennypacker, 1980; ists. In other words, it may require some
Skinner, 1945). radical-behavioristic research to analyze
BEHAVIORAL ANALYSIS OF OBSERVATIONAL LEARNING 89
a radical-behavioristic function in some history. If so, the therapeutic and edu-
methodological behaviorism! cational use of vicarious reinforcement
alone is not a good strategy for the reli-
able maintenance and generalization of
Observed Consequences its outcomes.
Reinforcement control of vicarious
The final component of the descriptive learning then becomes an important ex-
definition is the observation that a vi- perimental issue, one for which the typ-
cariously reinforced modeled response is ical procedures used in past observation-
more likely to be imitated than a non- al-learning research are probably
reinforced one (cf. Arem & Zimmerman, insensitive (for example, Bandura, 1965;
1976; Bandura, 1965; Kazdin, 1973; 01- Rice, 1976). As pointed out earlier, data
lendick, Shapiro, & Barrett, 1982; Thelen for each subject in the observational-
& Rennie, 1972). Bandura (1971b) also learning paradigm are usually collected
notes that the effects of vicarious rein- in only one or two sessions of pre- and
forcement may be short-lived. One of his post-testing. Therefore, the time course
examples is, "One would not recom- of behavior change cannot be recorded.
mend to employers, for example, that they The possibility of reinforcement control
maintain the productivity of their em- of vicarious reinforcement could be as-
ployees by having them witness a small sessed adequately only with longer term,
group of workers receiving paychecks at continuous observation of the phenom-
the end of each month" (p. 235). This ena. For example, Ollendick, Dailey, and
example implies that vicarious reinforce- Shapiro (1983) assessed the long-term
ment would not work unless the observ- durability of the effectiveness of vicari-
ers experienced some direct reinforce- ous reinforcement for normal children's
ment (paychecks), too. As analyzed behavior. Pairs of children performed a
previously, the construction of cognitive task in which one child received direct
processes need not be a substitute for his- social reinforcement; the other child could
tory, theoretically or pragmatically. Ban- only observe those consequences. Other
dura, however, did not describe the role pairs of children engaged in the same task
of direct reinforcement in the definition without reinforcement or with intermit-
of vicarious reinforcement. tent reinforcement. As trials proceeded,
Vicarious reinforcement is negatively the directly reinforced children im-
defined in terms of an absence of direct proved. The vicariously reinforced chil-
reinforcement to the observing subject, dren improved initially, but then their
who is observed for only a short period performance decreased. However, vicar-
of time. From a behavioral viewpoint, iously reinforced children who also re-
the modeled consequences of the mod- ceived intermittent direct reinforcement
eled behavior probably function as dis- came to perform as well as the directly
criminative cues for extrinsic reinforce- reinforced children over time. These re-
ment for an observer's later imitation; sults support a discriminative-stimulus
that function may be hypothesized to interpretation of vicarious reinforce-
have been established in the observer's ment: Its discriminative function is to set
earlier reinforcement history (Gewirtz, the occasion for imitation that can be
1971 a, 1971 b). The effects of vicarious maintained directly by (intermittent) re-
reinforcement may then be examined as inforcement of the observing child's be-
control by direct reinforcement in a his- havior. To analyze further reinforcement
torical context. If vicarious reinforce- control in vicarious learning, the effects
ment is a discriminative stimulus for the of observed consequences should be
observer, its effects should decrease over studied over time in more detail. Direct
time in the absence of reinforcement of reinforcement of the observer's behavior
the observer's behavior, the amount of can be manipulated in various ways to
time necessary being a function of prior examine its control of vicarious learning
90 HIKARU DEGUCHI
over time within individual-analysis de- whether neonatal imitation could be a
signs. procedural artifact. Their second exper-
iment demonstrated that the type of
THE ORIGIN OF mouth movement evoked at one mo-
OBSERVATIONAL LEARNING ment by a pacifier (also used in the Melt-
zoff
So far, discussion has emphasized the dictor and Moore study) was a reliable pre-
operant characteristics of observational the kindofused subsequent infant responses of
to define imitation. Ifthese
or vicarious learning that may be devel- types of movements with the pacifier in-
oped and controlled by its consequences fluenced the experimenter's timing in
under relevant social and physical stim- presenting the model to be imitated,
ulus conditions over time. Still another purely coincidental "imitation" woulda
controversy remains between social- result. Also, Jacobson (1979) has shown
learning and radical-behavioristic para- that imitation in young infants can be
digms: Is observational learning a pri- elicited nonspecifically by events other
mary given category of behavior or a than facial modeling stimuli-stimuli Ja-
totally learned behavioral process? Is its cobson called
development shaped from a zero baseline ample, infant"incentive events." For ex-
tongue-protrusion oc-
or only modified in detail from a given curred in response to a pen moved
non-zero baseline? If imitative ability is towards the infant's face just as often as
innate, is it not sufficient for us to find a tongue-protrusion model. Similarly,
the conditions that modify and control to ring before the infant's hand
it? For this issue, the neontatal imitation was asdangled
a
effective as a hand-movement
reported recently by Field, Woodson, model in producing
Greenberg, and Cohen (1982) and Melt- ments. These results infant hand-move-
suggest possi-
zoff and Moore (1977, 1983a) becomes bility of artifactually imitative the responses
an important case. This controversial is- elicited by particular stimulus aspects that
sue is considered in terms of methodol- the modeled responses may contain. The
ogy, conception, and pragmatics. Meltzoff and Moore (1977, 1983a) and
Methodological Considerations Field et al. (1982) studies did not exper-
imentally rule out the possibility of these
Meltzoff and Moore (1977) reported artifactually imitative responses.
that 12- to 21-day-old infants can imi- Thus, the possibility of already existing
tate tongue-protrusion, lip-protrusion, imitation in newborn infants remains
mouth-opening, and hand-movements. ambiguous and still to be proven. A well-
Later, Meltzoff and Moore (1983a) used designed procedure will be needed to
an improved procedure to demonstrate avoid the problems inherent in neonatal
imitation of mouth-opening and tongue- imitation (also see Meltzoff & Moore,
protrusion by newborn infants ranging 1983b, for a discussion). One basic prob-
from 0.7 to 71 hours of age. Field et al. lem is that the infant behaviors to be
(1982) also reported imitation of mouth- tested are not discrete and well formed
opening, mouth-widening, and lip-pro- each time that they occur (Meltzoff &
trusion in infants averaging 36 hours of Moore, 1977), thereby creating problems
age. These results, however, should be in response definition and hence in reli-
considered tentative; they contain meth- able measurement. A second, related
odological difficulties peculiar to neo- problem is that the experimentally useful
natal imitation. Some of these problems infant behaviors are very restricted in
were indicated by the Hayes and Watson number and form (e.g., Meltzoff& Moore,
study (1981) of these behaviors in neo- 1983a). The few useful facial expressions,
nates. The first Hayes and Watson ex- for example, are difficult to differentiate
periment failed to replicate the Meltzoff from arousal or nonmodel-elicited re-
and Moore experiment (1977), despite a sponses. A third problem is the difficulty
careful attempt to reproduce their pro- of keeping the infant's attention on the
cedures. Hayes and Watson then asked model, leading to varied numbers and
BEHAVIORAL ANALYSIS OF OBSERVATIONAL LEARNING 91
times of model presentation, some of fying both as products of the same origin.
which might be matched only inadver- Even if neonates have an innate ability
tently by the infant's responses (see Field to imitate a few specific models, that does
et al., 1982; Hayes & Watson, 1981; Ja- not mean that all other imitations in later
cobson, 1979). life need not be externally reinforced. In-
Even if neonatal imitation is shown to deed, many studies have demonstrated
be reliable, the origin of imitation or ob- that imitation can be developed, elabo-
servational learning is not necessarily rated, modified, attached to specific cues
clarified. Skinner (1984, p. 220) argues and setting events, and maintained by its
that only a first instance of behavior can consequences, and that it decreases with-
be considered as essentially innate, and out those contingencies (see Baer & De-
that first instances are difficult to specify. guchi, in press).
An experimentally sound demonstration In summary, a behavioral analysis can
of neonatal imitation would at best be an interpret neonatal imitation as a product
implausible case of learning and a more of phylogenic contingencies but also of-
plausible case of innate (or unknown) or- fers a possible and useful distinction be-
igin. tween neonatal imitation and imitation
later in life.
Conceptual Considerations
The possibility of imitation as a prod- Pragmatic Considerations
uct of phylogenic contingencies of sur- If either all imitations or later-life im-
vival need not be denied. Skinner (1966, itations are ontogenically established and
1974, 1984) has argued that imitation modified, then discovering the environ-
may well have survival value for a species mental conditions under which imitation
as well as be a product of ontogenic con- develops, differentiates, and is discrimi-
tingencies of reinforcement: nated and generalized will be of primary
Since phylogenic and ontogenic contingencies act concern for understanding imitation as a
at different times and shape and maintain behavior socializing process. Even ifthe imitations
in different ways, it is dangerous to try to arrange of neonates are phylogenically formed and
their products on a single continuum or to describe later-life imitations are on the same con-
them with a single set of terms. (1966, p. 121 1)
tinuum with neonatal imitation, simply
Consider an analogous example. Ag- pointing to its possibly innate character
gressive behavior in animals or humans does not actually further its analysis. En-
can be either elicited by antecedent stim- vironmental conditions are known to in-
ulus events (Azrin, Hutchinson, & Hake, fluence its development very powerfully
1966; Kelly & Hake, 1970; Ulrich & Az- in that many behavioral studies have
rin, 1962) or developed and controlled demonstrated that imitation can be de-
by consequential stimulus events (Azrin veloped, modified, and thoroughly con-
& Hutchinson, 1967; Azrin, Hutchinson, trolled by its consequences. An analo-
& Hake, 1967). Elicited aggression is typ- gous instance is seen in other reflexive
ically accompanied by autonomic, emo- behaviors that can be modified by their
tional, vocal, and facial responses; op- consequences. For example, Ulrich,
erant aggression usually is not Wolfe, and Dulaney (1967) and Azrin
(Hutchinson, 1973). Perhaps these two (1970) have demonstrated that the class
classes of aggressive behavior are fun- of shock-elicited aggression can be de-
damentally different in terms of their creased by contingent punishment (shock)
controlling variables. If so, they may not in squirrel monkeys.
belong on the same continuum. Thus in either the phylogenic or on-
Similarly, not all imitative behavior togenic case and in either the operant or
may come from a single phylogenic or respondent (reflexive) case, what should
ontogenic origin. Topographical similar- be done is virtually identical. The only
ities between neonatal imitation and im- difference is in our interpretation of the
itation later in life do not justify identi- origin of imitation or observational
92 HIKARU DEGUCHI
learning. Of course, we should know fective and reliable use of observational
whether imitative ability is genetically and vicarious learning for therapeutic and
endowed and whether all imitations educational practice.
through the developmental course are Another disagreement lies in the treat-
controlled by the same variables. At pres- ment of private events. The present ar-
ent, however, these inquiries may be ex- guments do not negate the analyses of
tremely laborious, difficult to prove ex- private events and their immediate en-
perimentally, and, indeed, have relatively vironmental antecedents. Studies of pri-
low logical and pragmatic priority. vate events and their environmental an-
Thus, in a pragmatic sense (cf. James, tecedents can have considerable
1907), the origin of imitation or obser- predictive value. Experimental under-
vational learning may not be critical, even standing of only the immediate anteced-
in theory. An explanation consisting of ents, which will lead tautologically to
the complete exploration of the environ- cognitive processes, however, contrib-
mental functions involved may prove to utes to only a gross level of prediction
be satisfactory if it allows the develop- and control of observational learning. The
mental and behavioral problems that we present analysis argues that the effects of
face to be solved sufficiently (Baer & De- those variables, and their variability may
guchi, in press). The question of origin originate in historical events such as con-
may become less urgent if the analysis of tingencies of reinforcement. Under-
environmental functions and conditions standing that history, sometimes through
should prove to confer a powerful control analyzing (teaching) private events,
over imitation or observational learning. should produce more precise prediction
The achievement of such powerful con- and control ofobservational learning. The
trol of observational learning may give proper goal is to analyze private events
an explanation by ontogenic contingen- by realizing them effectively at a proce-
cies not only its own place but a major dural level (see Johnston & Pennypacker,
role in the theories of imitation. 1980, for a related discussion).
From a methodological point of view,
CONCLUSION these two disagreements may derive
partly from the way that the social-learn-
When the three major distinctive fea- ing approach has dealt with variability in
tures of observational learning are rede- its data. Social-learning theorists always
fined at the descriptive level, they prove use group designs, unlike behavior ana-
to be explainable in behavioral terms. lysts who use individual-analysis de-
One of the most significant disagree- signs. In group designs, variability in data
ments between many behaviorists and typically is analyzed statistically. When
social-learning theorists seems to be the concepts of observational learning are
issue of reinforcement control of obser- validated statistically, they are not likely
vational and vicarious learning. This dis- to be pursued further for control of vari-
agreement appears to derive largely from ability within individuals: Observational
the length of observation of the phenom- learning remains a statistical or actuarial
ena. Extended observation may be cru- outcome. Yet the real needs are for con-
cial in resolving this controversy. In fu- tinuous assessment and the analysis of
ture research, the control of observational sometimes idiosyncratic historical ante-
and vicarious learning should be studied cedents, both of which require further
by manipulating direct reinforcement of control of variability within individuals.
the observer's behavior over extensive The origin of observational learning
time to see whether observational or vi- and imitation was also discussed from
carious learning could be a function of methodological, conceptual, and prag-
their consequences in a modified obser- matic viewpoints. Although the origin of
vational-learning as well as an operant imitation will be difficult to prove, a rad-
paradigm. Perhaps this direction of re- ical-behavioristic view can systematize
search can lead to developing a more ef- the origin of imitation in both its phy-
BEHAVIORAL ANALYSIS OF OBSERVATIONAL LEARNING 93
logenic and ontogenic cases. The present on behavior and the demolition of behavioral
analysis, however, emphasizes explana- structures. In D. Bernstein & H. Howe (Ed.), Ne-
braska symposium on motivation (Vol. 29, pp.
tion through the ontogenic environmen- 217-254). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
tal conditions that develop and modify Baer, D. M. (1983). What is an attribution, that
observational learning and imitation, to thou art mindful of it? In J. M. Levine & M. C.
see if doing so offers a sufficient solution Wang (Eds.), Teacher and student perceptions:
to current developmental and behavioral Implications for learning (pp. 271-278). Hills-
dale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
problems. Baer, D. M., & Deguchi, H. (in press). Generalized
An approach to observational learning imitation from a radical-behavioral viewpoint.
or imitation should not be criticized or In S. Reiss & R. R. Bootzin (Eds.), Theoretical
justified only by its level of explanation issues in behavior therapy. New York: Academic
Press.
or its suitability to pre-existing models Baer, D. M., Peterson, R. F., & Sherman, J. A.
of human nature. An approach should be (1967). The development of imitation by rein-
judged in terms of its contribution to a forcing behavioral similarity to a model. Journal
science and a technology of human de- of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 10,
velopment. In this regard, many behav- 405-416.
Baer, D. M., & Sherman, J. A. (1964). Reinforce-
iorists and social-learning theorists seem ment control of generalized imitations in young
to agree with each other (see Bandura, children. Journal of Experimental Child Psy-
1 977b, p. 4). The present analysis argues, chology, 1, 37-49.
however, that a further theoretical and Bandura, A. (1965). Influence of model's rein-
forcement contingencies on the acquisition of im-
practical understanding of observational itative responses. Journal of Personality and So-
learning will be achieved best by a be- cial Psychology, 1, 589-595.
havioral account that stubbornly pursues Bandura, A. (Ed.). (1971a). Psychological mod-
the ontogenic environmental conditions eling: Conflicting theories. Chicago: Aldine-Ath-
erton.
under which imitation and observational Bandura, A. (1971b). Vicarious and self-rein-
learning develop and are modified. forcement processes. In R. Glaser (Ed.), The na-
ture ofreinforcement (pp. 228-278). New York:
Academic Press.
REFERENCES Bandura, A. (1972). Modeling theory: Some tra-
ditions, trends, and disputes. In R. D. Parke (Ed.),
Akamatsu, T. J., & Thelen, M. H. (1974). A re- Recent trends in social learning theory (pp. 35-
view of the literature on observer characteristics 61). New York: Academic Press.
and imitation. Developmental Psychology, 10, 38- Bandura, A. (1977a). Self-efficacy: Towards a
47. unifying theory of behavior change. Psychologi-
Arem, C. A., & Zimmerman, B. J. (1976). Vicar- cal Review, 84, 191-215.
ious effects on the creative behavior of retarded Bandura, A. (1977b). Social learningtheory. New
and nonretarded children. American Journal of Jersey: Prentice-Hall.
Mental Deficiency, 81, 289-296. Bandura, A., & Jeffery, R. W. (1973). Role of
Asarnow, J. R., & Meichenbaum, D. (1979). Ver- symbolic coding and rehearsal processes in ob-
bal rehearsal and serial recall: The mediational servational learning. Journal of Personality and
training of kindergarten children. Child Devel- Social Psychology, 26, 122-130.
opment, 50, 1173-1177. Bandura, A., Jeffery, R. W., & Bachicha, D. L.
Azrin, N. H., & Hutchinson, R. R. (1967). Con- (1974). Analysis of memory codes and cumu-
ditioning of the aggressive behavior of pigeons lative rehearsal in observational learning. Jour-
by a fixed-interval schedule of reinforcement. nal of Research in Personality, 7, 295-305.
Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behav- Bandura, A., Ross, D., & Ross, S. A. (1963). Vi-
ior, 10, 395-402. carious reinforcement and imitative learning.
Azrin, N. H., Hutchinson, R. R., & Hake, D. F. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 67,
(1966). Extinction-induced aggression. Journal 601-607.
of the Experimental Analysis ofBehavior, 9, 191- Beach, F. A. (1955). The descent of instinct. Psy-
204. chological Review, 62, 401-410.
Azrin, N. H., Hutchinson, R. R., & Hake, D. F. Blanshard, B., & Skinner, B. F. (1967). The prob-
(1967). Attack avoidance and escape reactions lem of consciousness-a debate. Philosophy and
to aversive shock. Journal of the Experimental Phenomenological Research, 27, 317-337.
Analysis of Behavior, 10, 131-148. Bower, G. H., & Hilgard, E. R. (1981). Theories
Baer, D. M. (1982a). Applied behavior analysis. of learning (5th Ed.). New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.
In G. T. Wilson & C. M. Franks (Eds.), Contem- Brigham, T. A., & Sherman, J. A. (1968). An
porary behaviortherapy (pp. 277-309). New York: experimental analysis of verbal imitation in pre-
The Guildford Press. school children. Journal of Applied Behavior
Baer, D. M. (1982b). The imposition of structure Analysis, 1, 151-158.
94 HIKARU DEGUCHI
Catania, A. C. (1972). Chomsky's formal analysis means of developing self-control. Journal ofAb-
of natural languages: A behavioral translation. normal Psychology, 77, 115-126.
Behaviorism, 1, 1-15. Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). Imitation
Day, W. F. (1969). Radical behaviorism in rec- offacial and manual gestures by human neonates.
onciliation with phenomenology. Journal of the Science, 198, 75-78.
ExperimentalAnalysis ofBehavior, 12, 315-328. Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1983a). New-
Day, W. F. (1983). On the difference between rad- born infants imitate adult facial gestures. Child
ical and methodological behaviorism. Behavior- Development, 54, 702-709.
ism, 11, 89-102. Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1983b). The
Ferster, C. B., & Skinner, B. F. (1957). Schedules origins of imitation in infancy: Paradigm, phe-
ofreinforcement. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall. nomena, and theories. In L. P. Lipsitt & C. Ro-
Field, T. M., Woodson, R., Greenberg, R., & Co- vee-Collier (Eds.), Advances in infancy research
hen, D. (1982). Discrimination and imitation (Vol. 2, pp. 265-301). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
of facial expressions by neonates. Science, 218, Metz, J. R. (1965). Conditioning generalized im-
179-181. itation in autistic children. Journal of Experi-
Furnell, J. R. G., & Thomas, G. V. (1981). Be- mental Child Psychology, 2, 389-399.
havior Analysis Letters, 1, 117-122. Moore, J. (1980). On behaviorism and private
Garcia, E. E. (1976). The development and gen- events. The Psychological Record, 30, 459-475.
eralization of delayed imitation. Journal of Ap- Moore, J. (1984). On behaviorism, knowledge,
plied Behavior Analysis, 4, 101-112. and causal explanation. The Psychological Re-
Gerst, M. S. (1971). Symbolic coding processes cord, 34, 73-97.
in observational learning. Journal ofPersonality Ollendick, T. H., Dailey, D., &Shapiro, E. S. (1983).
and Social Psychology, 19, 7-17. Vicarious reinforcement: Expected and unex-
Gewirtz, J. L. (197 la). Conditional responding as pected effects. Journal ofApplied Behavior Anal-
a paradigm for observational, imitative learning ysis, 16, 485-491.
and vicarious learning. In H. W. Reese (Ed.), Ad- Ollendick, T. H., Shapiro, E. S., & Barrett, R. P.
vances in child development and behavior (Vol. (1982). Effects of vicarious reinforcement in nor-
6, pp. 273-304). New York: Academic Press. mal and severely disturbed children. Journal of
Gewirtz, J. L. (1971 b). The roles of overt respond- Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 50, 63-70.
ing and extrinsic reinforcement in "self-" and Rice, M. E. (1976). The development of respon-
6'vicarious-reinforcement" phenomena and in siveness to vicarious reinforcement. Develop-
"observational learning" and imitation. In R. mental Psychology, 12, 540-545.
Glaser (Ed.), The nature of reinforcement (pp. Rosenthal, T. L. (1976). Modeling therapies. In
279-309). New York: Academic Press. M. Hersen, R. M. Eisler, & P. M. Miller, Progress
Gewirtz, J. L., & Stingle, K. G. (1968). The learn- in behavior modification (Vol. 2, pp. 53-97). New
ing of generalized imitation as the basis for iden- York: Academic Press.
tification. Psychological Review, 75, 374-397. Rosenthal, T. L., & Zimmerman, B. J. (1978). So-
Hayes, L. A., & Watson, J. S. (1981). Neonatal cial learning and cognition. New York: Academ-
imitation: Fact or artifact? Developmental Psy- ic Press.
chology, 17, 655-660. Skinner, B. F. (1945). The operational definition
James, W. (1907/1974). Pragmatism. New York: of psychological terms. Psychological Review, 52,
New American Library. 270-277.
Johnston, J. M., & Pennypacker, H. S. (1980). Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behav-
Strategies and tactics of human behavioral re- ior. New York: Macmillan.
search. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Asso- Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. New Jer-
ciates. sey: Prentice-Hall.
Kazdin, A. (1973). The effect of vicarious rein- Skinner, B. F. (1966). The phylogeny and ontog-
forcement on attentive behavior in the class- eny of behavior. Science, 153, 1205-1213.
room. Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis, 6, Skinner, B. F. (1974). About behaviorism. New
71-78. York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Kirkland, K. D., & Thelen, M. H. (1977). Use of Skinner, B. F. (1977). Why I am not a cognitive
modeling in child treatment. In B. B. Lahey & psychologist. Behaviorism, 5, 1-10.
A. E. Kazdin (Eds.), Advances in clinical child Skinner, B. F. (1984). The evolution of behavior.
psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 307-328). New York: Ple- Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behav-
num press. ior, 41, 217-221.
Lowe, C. F., & Higson, P. J. (1981). Self-instruc- Thelen, M. H., & Rennie, D. L. (1972). The effects
tional training and cognitive behavior modifi- of vicarious reinforcement on imitation: A re-
cation: A behavioral analysis. In G. Davey (Ed.), view of the literature. In B. A. Maher (Ed.), Pro-
Applications ofconditioning theory (pp. 162-188). gress in experimental personality research (Vol.
London: Methuen. 6, pp. 83-108). New York: Academic Press.
Meichenbaum, D., & Goodman, J. (1969). Re- Ulrich, R. E., & Azrin, N. H. (1962). Reflexive
flection-impulsivity and verbal control of motor fighting in response to aversive stimulation. Jour-
behavior. Child Development, 40, 785-797. nal of the Experimental Analysis ofBehavior, 5,
Meichenbaum, D., & Goodman, J. (1971). Train- 511-520.
ing impulsive children to talk to themselves: A Ulrich, R. E., Wolfe, M., & Dulaney, S. (1969).
BEHAVIORAL ANALYSIS OF OBSERVATIONAL LEARNING 95
Punishment of shock-induced aggression. Jour- Whitehurst, G. J. (1978). Observational learning.
nal of the Experimental Analysis ofBehavior, 12, In A. C. Catania & T. A. Brigham (Eds.), Hand-
1009-1015. book of applied behavior analysis: Social learning
Wessells, M. G. (1981). A critique of Skinner's processes (pp. 142-178). New York: Irvington
views on the explanatory inadequacy of cognitive Publishers.
theories. Behaviorism, 9, 153-170.

You might also like