You are on page 1of 12

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/240236180

Knowledge and Appraisal in the Cognition-Emotion Relationship. In:


Cognition and Emotion 2(4): 281-300

Article  in  Cognition and Emotion · October 1988


DOI: 10.1080/02699938808412701

CITATIONS READS

335 3,550

2 authors, including:

Craig A Smith
Peabody College of Vanderbilt University
102 PUBLICATIONS   14,493 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Emotion, Stress, Motivation, Coping, and Adaptation View project

Organization of Physiological Activity in Emotion View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Craig A Smith on 26 March 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


COGNITION AND EMOTION, 1988, 2 (4), 281-300

Knowledge and Appraisal in the


Cognition-Emotion Relationship

Richard S. Lazarus and Craig A. Smith


University of California, Berkeley, U.S.A.

Recently there has been considerable theoretical and empirical work attemp-
ting to identify specific cognitive dimensions that shape the emotional
response. However. this work has almost universally neglected an important
theoretical distinction between two types of cognition relevant to emotion:
knowledge and appraisal. Knowledge has to do with the facts of an adapta-
tional encounter, whereas appraisal defines the personal significance of an
encounter for well-being. In the shaping of an emotion, knowledge is a distal
variable which requires an additional process of appraisal to produce an
emotion: appraisal is a proximal variable which directly intluences whether
an emotion will be generated. and if so. its kind and intensity.
In this article we examine the distinctions between knowledge and apprai-
sal that arc relevant to the emotion process. and how the failure to consider
them muddies theoretical and empirical work. We examine a number of
putative appraisal dimensions prominent in current theoretical systems.
examine why they often constitute knowledge rather than appraisal, and
discuss some of the appraisal dimensions in the emotion process. In addition.
the major techniques used to study the cognition-emotion relationship arc
examined and their potential for providing evidence of appraisal rather than
knowledge is evaluated.

.-
INTRODUCTION
Although interest in the relationship between cognition and emotion has
been stimulated by recent interchanges (e.g. Baars, 1981; Ellis. 1985;
Kleinginna & Kleinginna. 1985: Lazarus, 1981, 1982. 1984: Scheff, 1985:
Slife. 1981; Zajonc. 1980, 1984), the nature of this relationship has been

Requests for reprints should he sent to Richard S. Lazarus. Department of Psychology.


University of California. Berkeley. CA 94612. U.S.A. Preparation of this article was
supported in part bv National Institute of Mental Health Grant MH09445 to the second.
author. We wish to thank Phoebe Ellsworth. Philip Tctlock. and Daniel Weinberger for their
helpful comments and suggestions. -

© 1988 Lawrence Erlhaum Associates Limited


CE ~/4-A
282 LAZARUS AND SMITH KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION 283
and remains a very important and unresolved issue (see also Bolles. 1?74; cognition, to use a well-known metaphor. Appraisals, in contrast, involve
Hilgard, 1980). There is currently an extraordinary volume of w~1t.mg such stakes and reflect how adequately we are managing the encounter.
about cognition-emotion relationships and some brand new empmcal They are therefore warm or hot. Although the distinction has been made
research. · . often (cf. Abelson, 1963; Kreitler & Kreitler, 1976; Lazarus & Folkman,
A number of attempts have been made to theorise about emotion which 1984), and can even be traced to classical writings, the two kinds of
centre on the process of cognitive appraisal. Some, such as those of Arnold cognition are commonly confused for obscure reasons.
(1960), Epstein (1983), Lazarus (1966; Lazarus & Folkm~n, 1984), ~nd
Leventhal (1984), conceptualise emotion from the standp?mt of a~pra1sal Knowledge in Emotion
without systematically attempting to detail the appraisals involved m each Much that can be said about knowledge is outside the scope of this article.
kind of emotion. Others, such as Frijda (1987), Roseman (1984), Scherer However, certain distinctions between it and appraisal are fundamental to
(1984a,b), Smith and Ellsworth (1985), and Weiner (1985, whose wmk on our arguments. As we are using the term. knowledge consists of our
attribution and emotion is partly derived from earlier analyses by He1d~r' understanding of both the way things are and work in general. and the way
1958), have attempted to link specific kinds of cogn~tive activit.y to specific things are and work in a specfiic context. Thus we can speak of general
kinds of emotion. And if we included analyses of smgle emotions such as knowledge and contextual knowledge: General knowledge includes estab-
guilt. fear, anger, or hope, the number of citati?ns relevant. to the lished attitudes. beliefs, and intuitive theories about ourselves (including
cognition-emotion relationship would overwhelm this mod.est article. our self-concepts) and the world (cf. Epstein, 1983; Ross, 1977); contex-
To advance the argument beyond assumption and assertion a~out h~w tual knowledge concerns the who, what, where. when, and how of any
cognitive activity shapes emotion. there must also be program~at1c empir- particular encounter. and is directly derived, in part. from the perceptual
ical efforts to identify the chapter and verse of the appraisal facto~s information presented to us by our immediate situation. However. in
necessary and sufficient for each emotion. Such efforts, alt~oug.h st1.ll constructing contextual knowledge we also draw on general knowledge
infrequent. now appear to be underway, some of them .appeanng m. ~his through a diverse array of attributional and inferential strategics (Heider,
Journal (e.g. Conway & Bekerian, 1987; Ellsworth & Smith, 1988a; Fn1da. 1958; Nisbett & Ross, 1980).
1987). - . Sometimes knowledge is verbalisable, but it can also be tacit (cf.
However, a troubling feature of this research is widespread confusion Polanyi. 1966), and even unconscious, either in the less controversial sense
about what is meant by appraisal, and about the differenc~s b~twe~n t~o of simply being unnoticed or unnoticeable, or in the Freudian sense of
kinds of cognition: knowledge and appraisal. The confusion 1s pnma~1ly being kept out of awareness in defence of the psychological system.
theoretical but it also has methodological ramifications. The theoretical Knowledge. both general and contextual, can be elemental. concrete, and
confusion arises because both kinds of cognition, and the way they limited. or complex, abstract, and broad; it can also be accurate or
influence emotions, are different, yet in practice these cognitive constructs inaccurate.
tend to be regarded as interchangeable. For example, "appraisal" and To the extent that theories postulate that emotion is sometimes (or
"attribution" (which is a form of knowledge) are often ~re.ate~ as the same. always) a reaction to the significance (e.g. harm or benefit) of what is
Our purpose in this article is to examine t.he d1stmct1ons betw~en happening for well-being, knowledge is a necessary factor. Only if we
knowledge and appraisal from both a theoretical and methodological comprehend how things work in general. and in a particular context, can
perspective. and to explain why the~ are ~mportant to a proper understand- we appropriately evaluate the significance of encounters with the environ-
ing of the cognition-emotion relat1onsh1p and the design of research. ment for our well-being and. therefore, react with specific emotions based
on this significance. However. knowledge. per se, does not result in
THE THEORETICAL CONFUSION emotion. Another process. called appraisal. is required. which consists of
an evaluation of whether and how what is happening is personally harmful
In a nutshell, knowledge, whether concrete and primitive or abstract and or beneficial. Whereas knowledge. although necessary, is not by itself
symbolic. consists of cognitions about the way things a~e and h?~ they sufficient to produce an emotion, the appraisal of the personal significance
~ork. In contrast, appraisal is a form of personal meanmg cons1stmg of of the encounter. based on this knowledge, is both necessarv and sufficient.
evaluations of the significance of this knowledge for well-being. If pe.rsonal Each positive emotion reflects a particular kind of apprai;ed benefit, and
stakes are not implicated in an adaptational encounter. knowledge is cold each negative emotion reflects a particular kind of appraised harm.
284 LAZARUS AND SMITH

Appraisal in Emotion
Thus, although knowledge is a vital part of the cognitive stuff of which
personal meaning is made, it does not constitute an appraisal until its
implications for personal well-being have been drawn. Kreitler and
I
I
KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION

emotional reaction is more likely than a negative one. If, however, the
285

then the encounter will be appraised as benign or beneficial, and a positive

person is uncertain about the possibilities of coping effectively, the encoun-


ter will be appraised as a threat and an emotion relevant to this appraisal,

I
for example, anxiety, will ensue. And if coping resources suggest helpless-
Kreitler (1976, p. 78) have described the types of issues that when evalu-
ness or hopelessness in the face of threat, the resulting emotion will accord
ated provide the essence of personal (and hence emotional) meaning:
with this evaluation, as in, for example, sadness or depression. Particular
... meaning generation is regulated by two focal questions: 'What does it I' combinations of primary and secondary appraisal, based on knowledge,
mean?' and 'what does it mean to me and for me?' Whereas the first question is f provide the emotional significance of any encounter and lead to appropri-
an elaborate form of the central question 'What is it?' that guides meaning ate kinds and intensities of emotion.
action, the second question is new and specific to meaning generation. It raises An important feature of appraisal is that the personal meaning which
the issue of personal relevance, but only insofar as action is concerned. For the underlies the emotional reaction refers to a particular relationship between
sake of clarifying this question it seems advisable to present it also in some the person and the environment. Personal meaning cannot be defined
rephrased forms, such as, 'Does it affect me at all?', 'In what way does it affect without simultaneous reference to both the person and the environment.
me?', 'Am I concerned in any way?', 'Should I be involved?', 'Is any action Thus, in any adaptational encounter, the process of appraisal must recon-
required on my part?', 'Am I to act or not?' Foreshadowing concepts and cile two often contradictory sets of forces: The goals and beliefs (to which
processes explained and discussed later, we venture to introduce yet another
one is committed) that are brought to the encounter by the person; and the
more technical rephrasing of the same question: "In which sense(s) does it or
environmental realities affecting the outcome. This reconciliation cannot
may it affect (or concern) my goals, my norms, my beliefs about myself. and
my beliefs about the environment or any of its aspects?' Evidently, the go overboard in either direction, because to overemphasise personal
formulation 'What does it mean to me or for me?' is merely a label agendas is autism and to overemphasise environmental realities is to
summarizing these different variants of the question. abandon one's personal commitments. Survival or well-being is en-
dangered when appraisal fails to fit the environmental requirements or fails
Personal meaning as discussed by Kreitler and Kreitler is closely related ~to take personal agendas into account (Lazarus, in press).
to the concept of appraisal. Lazarus and his colleagues (e.g. Lazarus, 1966; In emphasising the distinctions between contextual knowledge and
Lazarus, Averill, & Opton, 1970; Lazarus & Folkman, 1984) have written appraisal. and the dependence of appraisal upon knowledge, we arc in no
about primary appraisal, which addresses whether and how the encounter sense implying that the appraisal process follows predefined sequences or
is relevant to the person's well-being, and is similar to Kreitler and stages (as does, for example, Scherer, 1984a, in his concept of ev~luation
Kreitler's question about whether the situation affects one at all. Primary checks). Nor do we imply that the cognitive processes involved are
appraisal is "primary" not because it necessarily comes first in the appraisal necessarily conscious, verbally accessible, deliberate, or rational (cf.
process; it often does not. It is primary because it provides the "heat" in a Lazarus. 1982, 1984). We assume that emotions are elicited quickly,
transaction, based on personal relevance, which is what makes knowledge automatically, and concretely, in ways often outside of consciousness,
potentially emotional. An appraisal that an encounter touches upon goal which is akin to what Leventhal (1984; Leventhal & Scherer, 1987) has
commitments provides personal relevance and hence the potential for termed "schematic processing". That is, the personal significance of an
emotion. encounter is often appraised automatically, and nearly instantaneously, on
However, primary appraisal is not sufficient by itself to determine the basis of past experiences with similar encounters.
whether and in what ways harm or benefit is involved. Secondary appraisal In automatic or schematic processing, it is not necessary to view apprai-
of coping resources and options further defines the adaptational signi- sal as following in a temporal sense the knowledge upon which the appraisal
ficance of is happening and, therefore, the specific emotions to be experi- might depend. If knowledge has been consistently appraised in particular
enced (Lazarus. Kanner, & Folkman, 1980). It is similar to Kreitler and ways by an individual, perhaps as a result of experienced positive or
Kreitler's question about whether action is required and if so. what kind. negative outcomes. some connections between knowledge and appraisal
For example, when a person has a personal stake in a transaction. if that may become functionally inseparable and seemingly fused over the course
person's coping resources are evaluated as adequate to manage the poten- of development. What then might happen is that knowledge and appraisal
tial threat. or if the person believes that somehow things will work out, would seem to be aspects of one instantaneous process. Nevertheless.
286 LAZARUS AND SMITH
KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION 287
despite this seeming temporal fusion, the conceptual distinction between succeed in coming closer to personal meaning as intended by the appraisal
knowledge and appraisal remains inviolate because they are different kinds concept.
of cognition, with appraisal always involving an evaluation of what is
known or understood with respect to its implications for personal well-
being. Because people have different appraisal histories, they can make Perceptual or Sensory Information
quite different appraisals of the same knowledge base, leading to quite Scherer's concept of intrinsic pleasantness nicely illustrates the gap be-
different emotions despite common understandings of how things work. tween sensory information and appraisal. He (1984a, p. 307) defines it as
In addition to simple automatic or schematic processing, complex know- having to do "with the inherent pleasantness or unpleasantness of a
ledge structures and appraisals also shape emotions through abstract, stimulus, and is not dependent on the relevance to the goals of an organism
conscious, and deliberate cognitive processes, which Leventhal (1984) has at that particular moment". Included here are pleasant and unpleasant
termed "conceptual processing". Here, the appraisal process might follow sensations (e.g. being touched in a particular way or muscle fatigue).
pre.defined sequences, though this too may be problematic. For example, Precisely because this dimension is, in Schercr's own words, independent
dehberate secondary appraisal of coping options may occur even before of the organism's goals, it should be regarded as perceptual information to
primary appraisal of threat has occurred, as when we check hotel exits in be evaluated as to its personal significance rather than an appraisal.
the event of fire even when fire is not an imminent prospect and we do not Pleasure and pain are sensory states, not emotions; they lead to emotions
feel in danger.
when their significance is evaluated and the quality of the resulting emotion
In any case, we are saying that the elicitation of an emotion can occur on depends on the outcome of this evaluation. Muscle fatigue and pain, for
m?re than one cognitive processing level, and knowledge and appraisal example, are often appraised positively and lead to positive emotions for
might be separable in time or fused into one complex process. This view of the athlete who believes this is a desirable goal of exercise or practice (as in
n:iuiti~le levels of cognitive processing accords well with recent neurophy- the expression, "go for the burn") but are appraised quite negatively and
s1olog1cal approaches to the evaluative aspects of emotion such as Le lead to negative emotions when some other goal is involved, as when one is
Doux's (1986; see also Lazarus, 1986) in which evidence is provided for an struggling to finish a contest in the best position possible, or when pain or
evaluation process at the subcortical level of the amygdala. distress signifies physical impa~rment or illness to the person.

RECENT THEORY ANO RESEARCH ON Features of the Emotional Response


APPRAISAL
Quite distinct from the intrinsic pleasantness of a stimulus, a second more
Having set forth the theoretical distinction between knowledge and global dimension of pleasantness is found in the work of Frijda (1987) and
appraisal, we draw upon this distinction in a critical analysis of recent Smith and Ellsworth (1985). This dimension has had a considerable
resea~ch and thought on the cognitive dimensions that result in particular research history (e.g. Frijda & Philipszoon, 1963; Osgood, 1966; J. A.
emotions. Recent research has, without a doubt, successfully identified a Russell. 1980; Schlosberg, 1952) as reviewed in Smith and Ellsworth
number of cognitive dimensions that are causally relevant to the emotional (1985). Using Ellsworth and Smith's (1988b) definition and measure-
reactions studied. However, for both theoretical and methodological ment strategy, global pleasantness refers to "how pleasant or unpleasant [it
reasons many of these dimensions have to do with knowledge, and the was] to be in the situation'', and thus appears better to describe subjective
consequent neglect of appraisal leaves us without an adequate anchor for affect. a feature of the reaction itself, than to describe the process of
understanding and predicting emotion.
appraising the significance of what is happening for personal well-being.
In order to illustrate concretely the nature and extent of this confusion it Similarly, attentional activity is concerned with attempts to attend to or
will be instructive to examine some of the best known cognitive dimensions think about the ongoing situation, which is also part of the emotional
recently proposed and studied empirically. Some of these are, in our view, response rather than an antecedent of it. These reactions can provide
perceptual information, which is an aspect of knowledge, not appraisals; important information which, in turn, is available for subsequent appraisal.
some are features of the emotional reaction itself rather than being From this standpoint, level of activation/arousal and depth of experience
antecedent cognitive processes shaping emotion; some refer to knowledge are also best regarded as features of the emotional response rather than
rather than appraisal: and some are, we think, appraisals, or at least appraisals.
288 LAZARUS AND SMITH

Knowledge
I KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION 289

it is more threatening to have control than not to have it. If, for example,
we can choose to have a radical mastectomy, a modified radical, or a
The vast majority of cognitive dimensions studied by emotion researchers lumpectomy, we are also in the unenviable position of having to take the
deal with causal attributions about the encounter, or contextual know- blame for the negative consequences of that decision. Many people would
ledge, instead of appraisals. These include Weiner's (1985) attribution rather have someone else decide because, for them, control is appraised as
dimensions of locus of causality, stability, controllability, intentionality, a double-edged sword.
and globality, as well as analogous ones such as causal agency (Roseman, Finally, Scherer (1984a) has proposed a cognitive dimension, novelty,
1984; Scherer, 1984a), locus of responsibility (Smith & Ellsworth, 1985), which seems similar to the so-called orienting response. Although he
the probable motives of the causal agent (Scherer, 1984a), perceived regards it as a dimension of appraisal, we consider novelty to have few or
fairness or legitimacy (Roseman, 1984; Scherer, 1984a; Smith & Ellsworth, no clear significations for well-being. It operates at a very low level of
1985). and locus of control (Smith & Ellsworth, 1985). All refer to cognitive functioning, and serves to call our attention to anything that is
knowledge or beliefs about the causation of events. Bv themselves. these sudden. different, or unexpected, to enable the further appraisal of its
belids do not have the same implications for well-bei~g for everyone. relevance for well-being and action. This cognitive dimension might be
Consider. for example, the locus of causality, which clearly has rele- important as a first step in the appraisal process, as suggested by Kreitler
vance for the emotion process. and for the type of emotion generated. In and Kreitler ( 1976). However, by itself it contributes little to the personal
several studies (e.g. Ellsworth & Smith, 1988b; Weiner, Graham, & meaning, and hence the emotion. that may be generated by further
Chandler, 1982). attributing causality to someone else has been linked to cognitive exploration.
anger. whereas attributing causality to oneself has been linked to guilt.
However, the locus of causality is not directly responsible for these
Components of Appraisal
emotions without an accountability judgement about who is to be blamed,
if anyone, for harm or threat, or who deserves credit for a benefit. A number of cognitive dimensions appear to us to represent true appraisal
Although locus of causality and accountability are closely related con- processes. These have to do with specific molecular questions concerning
structs, they are by no means identical, as recently demonstrated by the person-environment transaction, the answers to which combine to
McGraw (1987) and Shaver (1985). produce the molar personal meanings that lead directly to specific emo-
For adults at least, many additional knowledge dimensions, including tions. In ongoing research we have identified six: two related to primary
intentionality. legitimacy, and controllability, are often combined with appraisal. four to secondary appraisal. Most of these can also be found in
locus of causality in complex ways to determine accountability or blame. one form or another in the cognitive dimensional analyses of Frijda ( 1987),
For example. under conditions of harm people are held less accountable to Roseman (1984), Scherer (1984a.b) and Smith and Ellsworth (1985, 1987).
the extent that their harmful actions are perceived as unintentional, just, The two primary appraisal dimensions are importance or motivational
and/or unavoidable (Shaver. 1985; Weiner, Amirkhan, Folkes, & Verette, relevance. and motivational congruence. Motivational relevance refers to
1987). In the 1950s and 1960s a host of studies of frustration, intentionality, the extent to which the encounter touches on personal goals and concerns.
and arbitrariness in the generation of anger made a similar point (cf. that is. issues the person cares about or has a stake in (see Frijda. 1987;
Pastore. 1952). A judgement of blame, which often contains more than a Scherer, 1984a; and Smith & Ellsworth. 1987). Motivational congruence
trace of resentment, is much closer to what we mean by appraisal than a refers to the extent to which a transaction is consistent or inconsistent with
mere attribution of causality; attributing causality is often cool, but blame what the person wants. that is. either thwarts or facilitates personal goals.
implies one has been harmed. and that the person doing the harm could It corresponds closely to Roseman 's ( 1948) concept of motive consistency,
and should have acted otherwise. Yet attributional and appraisal theorists Scherer's ( 1984a) goal conduciveness, and Smith and Ellsworth's (1985)
(e.g. Roseman. 1984; Smith & Ellsworth, 1985: Weiner, 1985) tend to use perceived obstacle. In combination, motivational relevance and motiva-
the two constructs interchangeably, producing theoretical confusion. and tional congruence define the encounter as one of potential harm or benefit.
leading to difficulties in the interpretation of research results. The four cognitive components of secondary appraisal -are accowztabi-
Folkman (1984) has made the same type of analysis with the concept of lity, which we discussed earlier. problem-focused coping potential. emotion-
controllability in pointing out that although being in control is often focused coping potential. and future expectancy. In contrast with locus of
appraised as favourable for well-being, there are numerous occasions when control. which determines the person's knowledge of who or what is

-------------- ~ -----------·-
290 LAZARUS AND SMITH KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION 291

currently controlling events in the encounter, problem-focused coping both the necessary and sufficient core relational themes as well as the
potential has to do with evaluations of whether and how the person is able appraisal components that combine to produce them. Each emotion de-
to manage the demands of the encounter and actualise the personal pends on how one evaluates several cognitive-relational components hav-
commitments that are brought to it. Emotion-focused coping potential has ing to do with benefit, harm (or loss), threat, coping potential. and blame.
to do with the prospects of regulating the emotional state which harmful or Negative emotions are characterised collectively by primary appraisals of
threatening consequences generate (cf. Folkman & Lazarus, 1980, 1985; high levels of motivational-relevance (or stakes) and motivational incon-
Folkman et al., 1986; Lazarus & Folkman, 1984). Problem-focused coping gruence. Secondary appraisal components, however, are necessary to
potential is closely related to the concepts of power as discussed by distinguish one from another. When someone else is blamed (other-
Roseman (1984), and control and power as discussed by Scherer (1984a). accountability), for example. anger is more likely; when self is blamed
Emotion-focused coping potential appears closely related to Scherer's (self-accountability), guilt is more likely; when nothing can be done (low
concept of adjustment, which he defines as "the potential for adjustment to coping potential; helplessness), sadness is more likely; when one's ability
the final outcome via internal restructuring" (Scherer. 1984b, p. 39). to prevent or ameliorate an actual or potential negative outcome is
Future expectancy refers to the possibilities for changes in the psychologi- uncertain (uncertain coping potential and/or future expectancy), anxiety is
cal situation, which could make the encounter more or less motivationally more likely. Each cognitive component contributes to the production,
congruent. explanation, and prediction of the emotional state. Thus, consideration of
appraisal in terms of both molecular components and molar themes
provides a clearer perspective on appraisal-emotion relationships than
Core Relational Themes either would yield in isolation.
Considered separately, the components of appraisal identified above are
not sufficient to define the personal meanings about harmful and beneficial
THE METHODOLOGICAL PROBLEM
relationships with the environment that distinguish among the disparate
emotions. The level of analysis is, in our view, too molecular to stand by Researchers have a limited number of ways to study the relationships
itself. Molar cognitive constructs are also needed, which combine the between cognition and emotion, and quite apart from the theoretical
molecular primary and secondary appraisal components into basic rela- confusions we examined earlier, it is not always clear whether appraisal or
tionships between the person and environment having emotional signi- knowledge is being studied with these research methods. The available
ficance. These relationships correspond to the diverse emotions such as methods, as well as the strengths and limitations of each from the perspec-
anger. anxiety, shame, guilt, happiness, pride, and so forth. tive of what we have been saying, are addressed later.
The term we suggest, core relational themes, expresses a very old idea in In the research literature we have examined, roughly seven types of
which each emotion category is considered to be a reaction to distinctive method are used, which are briefly described below. However, it is worth
kinds of harm or benefit. Thus, anger can be said to involve an offence noting that methods other than these can also be found, but tend not to be
against the person or those with whom the person is identified. Aristotle's used by psychologically oriented emotion researchers with whom we are
concept of anger as reaction to the thought that the person has been familiar. For example, content analyses of literary and historical docu-
insulted, demeaned, or slighted, illustrates this theme. For anxiety, the ments can be made to trace the contextual and cognitive antecedents of
core relational theme is potential or future harm. especially of a vague and emotion. One can also make systematic analyses of emotion terms in
perhaps symbolic sort (Lazarus & Averill, 1972). For sadness it is unavoid- ordinary language. illustrated perhaps by Lakoff and Kovecses' (1983)
able and irrevocable loss. For happiness or satisfaction it is personal gain in model of anger as inferred from American English usage.
the context of an overall sense of security. As implied above, this approach In the seven types of method examined here, researchers ask subjects to:
treats the emotions as relational categories, each of which not only (1) judge the similarities among the meanings of emotion words such as
describes a different kind of psychophysiological reaction. but also defines sadness. anger. and anxiety (e.g. Conway & Bekerian. 1987, Study 2); (2)
a different person-environment relationship implying a particular kind of judge the cognitive properties of such words (e.g. Frijda. 1987, Studies 1
harm or benefit. and 2); (3) reveal their understanding of the cognitive properties of
Extending this argument further. for each negative emotion the cogni- emotion words through the use of priming tasks (e.g. Conway & Bekerian,
tive-relational research questions to pose have to do with understanding 1987, Studies 5. 6, and 7); (4) guess the reactions of hypothetical characters
292 LAZARUS AND SMITH KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION 293

to experimenter-supplied emotional vignettes (e.g. Roseman, 1984; (e.g. Bower, 1981). However. the issues being examined in both these
Weiner, Russell, D., & Lerman, 1979, Experiment 2): (5) state their own literatures are quite different from those concerning how personal mean-
likely or imagined reactions (imagery/role playing) to such vignettes (e.g. ings (appraisals) produce emotional reactions. In order to study actual
McGraw. 1987, Experiment 1; Russell D., & McAuley, 1986, Study 1; appraisals and the emotions they generate, in contrast to generalised
Smith, 1987; Weiner et al., 1982, Experiment 2); (6) provide retrospective knowledge. it is necessary to question subjects about appraisals and
memories about how they thought, felt, and acted in real-life adaptational emotions in specific encounters and to test, when possible, whether more
encounters (e.g. Ellsworth & Smith, 1988a. 1988b; Folkman & Lazarus, than detached or abstract thought (that is, personal or involving meaning)
1988; Lazarus & Folkman, 1987; McGraw, 1987, Experiment 2; Smith & about emotions is involved.
Ellsworth, 1985; Weiner et al., 1979, Experiment 1; Weiner et al.. 1982, In our view the final four methods listed above (4, 5, 6, and 7) come
Experiment 1); and (7) report current thoughts and feelings during an closer to the process of appraisal in specific life encounters than the first
ongoing encounter (e.g. Folkman & Lazarus, 1985; Lazarus et al., 1970; three. Whether or not past studies have used these methods effectively, the
D. Russell & McAuley, 1986, Study 2; Smith & Ellsworth, 1987). theoretical confusion between appraisal and knowledge could more easily
Several of these methodologies (methods 1, 2, and 3 above) study be avoided in the future by explicitly questioning subjects about their
cognitive-emotional relations in an abstract (that is, knowledge) sense. For appraisal components and core-relational themes.
example, Conway and Bekerian (1987, Study 2) asked subjects to rate how These four methods are not equal, however, in the probability that
similar in meaning each of several emotion words was to other emotion subjects' answers reflect personal meanings and involvements. We think
words. and Frijda (1987, Studies 1 and 2, p. 119) had subjects indicate that the weakest in this respect is to ask subjects to predict likely reactions
whether particular cognitive components (e.g. pleasant, unpleasant. ex- of hypothetical others to experimenter-supplied vignettes (method 4)
pected, unexpected. etc.) "usually applied to the conditions leading to., a because the focus is on the reactions of someone other than the subject
number of emotions. As implied by J. A. Russell (1987), when questions giving the report. As they are not speaking for themselves personally,
like these are asked in the abstract, it is unlikely that appraisal, as we have subjects will almost certainly derive their answers from abstract knowledge
defined it, is being examined. At best. such questions reveal subjects' or intuitive theories about emotion instead of from personal meanings. It is
generalised knowledge or intuitive theories about cognition-emotion rela- possible. of course, that subjects will sometimes take the role of the
tions. And with global similarity ratings. such as those used by Conway and hypothetical other and convert the abstract task into one of personal
Bekerian (1987, Study 2), even more doubt about what is being measured imagery/role-playing, and thus might respond on the basis of what the
exists because there is no a priori way to know on which features of vignette means to them personally. However. without direct checks on the
emotion knowledge (i.e. antecedents, sensations. action tendencies, etc.) actual cognitive pr:_ocesses. and on what the vignette means to them
the judgements are based. personally, the method is quite ambiguous with respect to the theoretical
If one agrees that the abstract judgement tasks used by Frijda (1987) and confusion.
Conway and Bekerian (1987) reveal the contents of generalised knowledge Although our judgement could be controversial. we think that imagery/
about emotion, the priming tasks used by Conway and Bekerian (1987. role-playing methods, retrospective reports of actually experienced emo-
Studies 5, 6. and 7) seem to reveal formal or structural ways in which tional encounters. and reports of ongoing emotional encounters (methods
generalised knowledge about emotion is organised and stored in memory. 5, 6, and 7) have the best potential for studying the appraisal process.
For example. when they examined how priming by an emotion word Nevertheless, if the question asked in the imagery/role playing method is to
influences the latency of images of emotional encounters, they established "say how you would probably feel in this situation" rather than "how you
that emotional concepts in memory are closely associated with common did, or do feel", or "respond to the situation ... as strongly and as deeply
situational antecedents. as you can" (cf. Smith. 1987). the findings are apt to draw more on
The contents of generalised knowledge about emotion, and the organisa- ~eneralised. abstract knowledge than on personal meaning. Role-playing
tion of this knowledge in memory, are interesting research topics in their mstructions probably elicit more than intellectual responses. and engage
own right. There is an emerging developmental literature on what children the emotions to some degree. as evidenced by patterned physiological and
of different ages know about emotion and social relationships (e.g. Gnepp. facial expressive responses to imagery (e.g. Carroll. Marzillier. & Merian,
Klayman. & Trabasso. 1982), and there is a separate cognitive psychology 1982; Fridlund. Schwartz. & Fowler. 1984: Lang. 1979; Smith. 1987:
literature that examines the organisation of emotion knowledge in memory Smith. McHugo. & Lanzetta. 1986). A drawback. however, is that there is
294 LAZARUS AND SMITH KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION 295

no guarantee that subjects appraise the imagery/role-playing situations in self-report. Actually, no alternative methods are more reliable and demon-
the same ways they did or do when their adaptational encounters have real strably more valid than self-report, carefully used, in getting at the rich
personal consequences. panorama of mental activity involved in human emotion (see also
Retrospective reports of past encounters also probably reflect appraisal- Ellsworth & Smith, 1987; Lazarus & Folkman, 1984, 1987; and Leventhal,
relevant-hence emotional-processes, though one cannot be certain 1984; for extended discussions of this issue). Along with many others we
without other evidence. Although subjects are describing encounters that assume that multi-level and multi-method research will ultimately be
probably happened, there is always the danger of (often unintentional) needed to cope with the problem of method variance (cf. Smith, 1987).
retrospective falsification (cf. Owens, Bower, & Black. 1979; Shweder & However, using alternative measures fruitfully is not as simple as is often
D' Andrade, 1980), leaving room in the process for intuitive theories and assumed. We know so little about the behavioural (e.g. facial display) rules
abstract knowledge. Nevertheless. it would be an extreme and untenable (cf. Ekman & Oster, 1979; Fridlund, Ekman, & Oster, 1987) and physiolo-
position to argue that such memories are totally or even largely confabu- gical patterning in emotion that it is hazardous to use these types of data to
lated. a position that would preclude any use of retrospective reports. validate self-reports without serious qualification. To do so would be to try
Given the problems posed by all methods of studying cognitive-emotional to verify one response modality whose significance is obscure by means of
activity, retrospective reports, particularly of salient and recent encoun- another modality whose significance is equally, if not more, obscure.
ters, should be a valuable-some would say the richest-source of data on Given the necessary reliance on self-report, researchers can and should
appraisal and emotion (cf. Ellsworth & Smith, 1987; Lazarus & Folkman, take precautions to maximise the likelihood that reports will reflect actual
1987). appraisals and emotions rather than generalised knowledge. As detailed by
The strongest methodology for studying appraisal and emotion is, when Nisbett and Wilson (1977), a person is far more likely to have introspective
possible, to collect reports from subjects during an ongoing encounter, as access to the products of cognitive activity than to the processes them-
has been done, for example, at various stages of a college examination selves. In the current context this implies that subjects are better able
(e.g. Folkman & Lazarus, 1985; D. Russell & McAuley, 1986, Study 2; veridically to report what they are thinking and feeling than why they are
Smith & Ellsworth. 1987). However, this can only be accomplished with thinking and feeling this way, or how their thoughts are influencing their
"captive audiences" who are co-operative. Folkman and Lazarus (1985) feelings. Researchers questioning subjects about specific, personally in-
point out that they could not obtain assessments during the exam itself volving encounters (methods 5, 6, & 7; e.g. Folkman & Lazarus, 1985,
because subjects would not be willing to jeopardise their exam perform- 1988; Smith & Ellsworth, 1985, 1987; Weiner et al., 1979, 1982) have been
ance in order to answer research questions. To the best of our knowledge aware of this. In these studies subjects have been asked to report almost
the experimental variant of this method-namely to systematically "man- exclusively on the contents of their thoughts, actions, and feelings, and the
ipulate·· appraisal by controlling situational contingencies and to monitor researchers have used statistical/analytic techniques to-infer the underlying
the emotional consequences-has not yet been adequately exploited. The processes. Lazarus and Folkman (1987) make the same point about the
one exception is the earlier programmatic psychophysiological research of assessment of coping and ask subjects only to describe their thoughts and
Lazarus and his colleagues (cf. Lazarus, 1968; Lazarus et al., 1970). actions rather than to interpret them. There is reduced danger of distortion
However, this research was limited to the unidimensional stress reaction when the researcher, and not the subject, makes the interpretive infer-
and did not concern itself with emotion quality or content. Naturally, ences.
· ethical and practical considerations limit the potential strength and ecolo- When all is said and done, none of the methods used by investigators in
gical validity of such manipulations, but when theory driven the method their attempts to examine the cognitive activity in emotion is ideal or free
could prove valuable in testing specific causal hypotheses about the emo- from uncertainties. Some methods. however, are more likelv to reveal
tion process. knowledge about cognition and emotion, whereas others are m~re likely to
All of the above methods are dependent on self-report. However, we are reveal personally involving cognitive-emotional processes. Researchers
reluctant to criticise this dependence, not because there are no problems, I should use the methods most suitable to the purposes of the particular
but because we believe this criticism has been constant and overdrawn. investigation, keeping in mind the theoretical distinctions we have been

I
There exists a double standard in which the equal or often even greater making.
problems in making inferences from physiological and behavioural data are
constantly overlooked or understated compared with those inherent in

I
\....,___________....,.....,_______________ ,.
296 LAZARUS AND SMITH KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION 297

Recent research by McGraw (1987), who found that self-blame (an


CONCLUDING THOUGHT
appraisal-centred construct) is more strongly linked to guilt than are self
A final implication for theory and research strategy flows from the distinc- attributions of causality (a knowledge-centred construct), suggests that the
tions we have drawn between knowledge and appraisal. It is that know- distinctions we have been making are being taken to heart. Careful
ledge constitutes a somewhat distal variable with respect to emotion consideration of their data has also led both Roseman (1984) and Ellsworth
compared with appraisal, which is more proximal. The linkages between and Smith ( 1988b) to reconceptualise several of their cognitive dimen-
knowledge and the emotional reaction are looser and more variable than sions to more closely resemble appraisal concepts. For example, Roseman
those between appraisal and emotion (cf. House. 1981; lessor, 1981). has proposed a cognitive dimension of self-power (closely related to our
Thus, the distinction we have made between knowledge and appraisal is appraisal component of coping potential) to replace his original dimension
more than an intellectual curiosity and can be tested empirically. It should of legitimacy. Similarly, Ellsworth and Smith have reconceptualised their
be possible to demonstrate that the relations between appraisal and uncertainty dimension as uncertainty about coping ability to give it a
emotion arc necessary and more dependable as predictors than the rela- clearer personal relevance.
tions between knowledge and emotion. and, in fact, that appraisal medi- What is fundamental in our analysis-the bottom line, so to speak-is
ates the latter relations. We are saying. in effect, that the theoretical that an emotional reaction is always based on personal meaning, and the
linkages between appraisal and emotion are invariant, whereas there is specific meaning of an appraisal is the significance of what is happening for
considerable variation in the linkages between knowledge and appraisal, one's well-being. Appraisal is quite different from knowledge about what is
and hence between knowledge and emotion. going on in the encounter and the way things work. It is this personal
It is noteworthy that Weiner (1985, p. 564) acknowledges that attribu- meaning. inherent in the concept of appraisal, that must be studied to
tion-emotion relationships (i.e. knowledge-emotion relationships) can permit us to grasp how an emotion is brought about.
vary, thereby implying the essential role of individualised, therefore proxi-
mal, appraisals and their personalised determinants. He writes: "A word Manuscript received 12 January 1988
of caution ... is needed ... Given a causal ascription, the linked emotion Revised manuscript received 16 March 1988
does not necessarily follow .... Hence, the position being espoused is that
the attributional dimension-affect relations are not invariant, but arc quite
prevalent in our culture, and perhaps in many others as well".
Looking more deeply into what Weiner has implied, one realises too that REFERENCES
there are cultural as well as individual differences in the ways causal
attributions are appraised with respect to their personal significance for Abelson. R. P. (1963). Computer simulation of "hot cognitions". In S. Tomkins & S.
Messick (Eds), Computer simulation of personality: Frontier of psychological theory. New
well-being (cf. Ryff, 1987; Shweder & LeVine, 1984). For example, the
York: Wiley. pp. 277-298.
personal implications of attributing failure on a school exam to lack of Arnold. M. B. ( 1960). Emotion and personality (2 vols). New York: Columbia University
effort or ability by, say, Western and Japanese subjects, appear to be quite Press.
different. with consequent differences in the emotional response. Similar- Averill. J. R. (1980). A constructivist view of emotion. In R. Plutchik & H. Kellerman
ly, although many people within the same culture share a tendency to (Eds). Emotion: Theor~', research, and experience: Vol. /. Theories of emotion. New
York: Academic Press. pp. 305-339.
interpret one or the other of the attributions as damaging or supportive,
Baars. B. J. ((198I). Cognitive versus inference. American Psychologist. 36. 223-224.
there are probably substantial variations in the evaluation of their personal Bolles. R. C. (1974). Cognition and motivation: Some historical trends. In B. Weiner(Ed.).
significance. It is also likely that the personal implications of these attribu- Cog11iti1·e views of human motivation. New York: Academic Press. pp. 1-20.
tions will change in a given individual over the life-course. What we are Bower. G. H. (1981). Mood and memory. American Psychologist. 36. 129-148.
saying is. incidentally. compatible with social constructivist approaches Carroll. D .. Marzillier. J. S .. & Mcrian. S. (1982). Psychophysiological changes accompany-
ing different types of arousing and relaxing imagery. Psychophysiology. 19, 75-82.
(e.g. Averill. 1980) which emphasise diversity rather than universality of
Conway. Jl,f. A. & Bekcrian. D·. A. (1987). Situational knowledge and emotions. Cognition
emotional experience across cultures and individuals. To truly understand and Emotion. I. 145-191.
and predict the emotional response requires that we favour (proximal) Ekman. P. & Oster. H. (1979). Facial expressions of emotion. Annual Review of Psycho-
appraisals over (distal) knowledge. logy. JO. 527-554.

CE 2/4-B
298 LAZARUS AND SMITH
KNOWLEDGE, APPRAISAL, AND EMOTION 299
Ellis, A. (1985). Cognition and affect in emotional disturbance. American Psychologist, 40,
471-472. Lazarus, R. S. (1966). Psychological stress and the coping process. New Y~r~: McGr~w-Hill.
Ellsworth, P. C. & Smith, C. A. (1987). Models and memories of emotion: A comparison of Lazarus. R. S. (1968). Emotions and adaptation: Conceptual and e~pmcal rel_at1o~s. In
their associated appraisals and facial expressions. Unpublished manuscript. Stanford W.J. Arnold (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, 1968. Lmcoln: Umvers1ty of
Universitv. Nebraska Press, pp. 175-266.
Ellsworth, P.· C. & Smith, C. A. (1988a). Shades of joy: Patterns of appraisal differentiating Lazarus. R. S. (1981). A cognitivist's reply to Zajonc on emotion and cognition. American
pleasant emotions. Cognition and Emotion, 2, 301-331. Psychologist, 36, 222-223. . .. .
Ellsworth, P. C. & Smith. C. A. (1988b). From appraisal to emotion: Differences among Lazarus, R. S. (1982). Thoughts on the relations between emotion and cogmt1on. American
unpleasant feelings. Motivation and Emotion. 12, 271-302. Psychologist. 37, 1019-1024. .
Epstein, S. (1983). A research paradigm for the study of personality and emotions. In M. M. Lazarus. R. S. (1984). On the primacy of cognition. American Psycholog1st, 39, 124-129.
Page (Ed.), Personality: Current theory and research. Nebraska Symposium on Motiva- Lazarus. R. S. (1986). Commentary. Integrative Psychiatry, 4. 245-247.
tion, 1982. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. pp. 91-154. Lazarus. R. S. (in press). Constructs of the mind in adaptation. In N. Stein. B. Cobler, B.
Folkman, S. (1984). Personal control and stress and coping processes: A theoretical analysis. Leventhal. & T. Trabasso (Eds). Psychological and biological approaches to emotion.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 46, 839-852. Hillsdale. N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc.
Folkman, S. & Lazarus. R. S. (1980). An analysis of coping in a middle-aged community Lazarus. R. S. & Avenll. J. R. (1972). Emotion and cognition: With special reference to
sample. Journal of Health and Social Behavior, 21, 219-239. anxietv. In C. D. Spielberger (Ed.), Anxiety: Current trends in theory and research,
Folkman, S. & Lazarus. R. S. (1985). If it changes it must be a process: Study of emotion Vol. 2". New York: Academic Press. pp. 242-282.
and coping during three stages of a college examination. Journal of Personality and Social Lazarus, R. S. & Folkman, S. (1984). Stress, appraisal, and coping. New York: Springer.
Psychology, 48, 150-170. Lazarus. R. S. & Folkman, S. (1987). Transactional theory and research on emotion and
Folkman. S. & Lazarus. R. S. (1988). Coping as a mediator of emotion. Journal of coping. European Journal of Personality, 1, 141-169. ..
Personality and Social Psychology, 54, 466-475. Lazarus. R. S., Averill. J. R., & Opton. J. R .. Jr (1970). Toward a cogmuve theory of
Folkman, S., Lazarus, R. S., Dunkel-Schetter, C., Delongis, A., & Gruen, R. (1986). The emotion. In M. B. Arnold (Ed.). Feelings and Emotions: The Loyola symposium. New
dynamics of a stressful encounter: Cognitive appraisal, coping, and encounter outcomes. York: Academic Press, pp. 207-232.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50. 992-1003. Lazarus. R. S., Kanner. A. D .. & Folkman, S. (1980). Emotions: A cognitive-
Fridlund, A. J., Ekman. P., & Oster, H. (1987). Facial expressions of emotion. In A. phenomenological analysis. In R. Plutchik & H. Kellerman (Eds), Emoti.on: Theory.
Siegman & S. Feldstein (Eds), Nonverbal behavwr and communication, 2nd edn. Hills- research. and experience: Vol. /. Theories of emotion. New York: Academic Press. pp.
dale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc, pp. 143-224. 189-217.
Fridlund, A. J., Schwartz. G. E., & Fowler, S. C. (1984). Pattern recognition of self- LeDoux, J. E. (1986). Sensory systems and emotion: A model of affectiye processing.
reported emotional state from multiple-site facial EMO activity during emotional Integrative Psychiatry, 4, 237-248.
imagery. Psychophysiology, 21, 622-637. Leventhal. H. ( 1984 ). A perceptual motor theory of emotion. In K. R. Scherer & P. Ekman
Frijda, N. H. (1987). Emotion, cognitive structure. and action tendency. Cognition and (Eds). Approaches to emotion. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc, pp.
Emotion, 1, 115-143. 271-291.
Frijda, N. H. & Philipszoon, E. (1963). Dimj!nsions of recognition of expression. Journal of Leventhal. H. & Scherer, K. R. (1987). The relationship of emotion to cognition: A
Abnormal and Social Psychology, 66, 45-51. functional approach to a semantic controversy. Cognition and Emotion. I. 3-28.
Gnepp, J., Klayman, J., & Trabasso, T. (1982). A hierarchy of information sources for McGraw, K. M. (1987). Guilt following transgression: An attribution of responsibility
inferring emotional reactions. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 33. 111-123. approach. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53. 247-256. . .
Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations. New York: Wiley. Nisbett. R. & Ross. L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcommgs of social
Hilgard, E. R. (1980). The trilogy of mind: Cognition. affection. and conation. Journal of judgment. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 16, 107-117. Nisbett. R. E. & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on
House. J. S. (1981). Social structure and personality. In M. Rosenberg & R.H. Turner mental processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231-259.
(Eds), Social psychology: Sociological perspectives. New York: Basic Books. pp. 525-561. Owens. J .. Bower. G. H., & Black. J. B. (1979). The "soap opera" effect in story recall.
lessor. R. (1981). The perceived environment in psychological theory and research. In D. Memory and Cognition. 7. 185-191.
Magnusson (Ed.), Toward a psychology of situations: An interactiona/ perspective. Hills- Osgood, C. E. (1966). Dimensionality of the semantic space for communication via facial
dale. N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc. pp. 297-317. expressions. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 7, 1-30.
Kleinginna, P. R. Jr & Kleinginna. A. M. (1985). Cognition and affect: A reply to Lazarus Pastore. N. (1952). The role of arbitrariness in the frustration-aggression hypothesis. Jour-
and Zajonc. American Psychologist, 40, 470-471. nal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 47. 728-731.
Kreitler. H. & Kreitler. S. (1976). Cognitive orientation and behavior. New York: Springer. Polanvi. M. ( 1966). The tacit dimension. Garden City, N. Y.: Anchor.
Lakoff, G. & Kovecses. Z. (1983). The cognitive model of anger inherent in American Rose~an. I. J. (1984). Cognitive determinants of emotion: A structural theory. In P.
English. Unpublished manuscript, Cognitive Science Program, Institute of Human Learn- Shaver (Ed.). Review of personality and social psychology: Vol. 5. Emotions, rela-
ing. University of California at Berkeley. tionships. and health. Beverly Hills. Calif.: Sage. pp. 11-36.
Lang, P. J. (1979). A bio-informational theory of emotional imagery. Psychophysiology, 16, Ross. L. (1977). The intuitive psychologist and his shortcomings: Distortions in the attribu-
495-512. tion process. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.). Advances in experimental social psychology. Vol. 10.
New York: Academic Press. pp. 173-220.
300 LAZARUS AND SMITH

Russell, D. & McAuley, E. (1986). Causal attributions, causal dimensions, and affective
reactions to success and failure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 50.
1174-1185.
Russell, J. A. (1980). A circumplex model of affect. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology. 39, 1161-1178.
Russell, J. A. (1987). Comments on articles by Frijda and by Conway and Bekerian.
Cognition and Emotion, 1, 193-197.
Ryff. C. D. (1987). The place of personality and social structure research in social psycho-
logy. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53, 1192-1202.
Scheff. T. J. (1985). The primacy of affect. American Psychologist, 40, 849-850.
Scherer. K. R. (1984a). On the nature and function of emotion: A component process
approach. In K. R. Scherer & P. Ekman (Eds), Approaches to emotion. Hillsdale. N.J.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc, pp. 293-317.
Scherer, K. R. (1984b). Emotion as a multicomponent process: A model with some cross-
cultural data. In P. Shaver (Ed.), Review of personality and social psychology: Vol. 5.
Emotions. relationships, and health. Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage, pp. 37-63.
Schlosberg. H. (1952). The description of facial expressions in terms of two dimensions.
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 44. 229-337.
Shaver, K. G. (1985). The attribution of blame: Causality, responsibility, and blame-
worthiness. New York: Springer.
Shwedcr, R. A. & D'Andrade. R. G. (1980). The systematic distortion hypothesis. New
Directions for Methodology of Social and Behavioral Sciences, 4, 37-58.
Shwedcr. R. A. & Le Vine, R. A. (1984). Culture theory: Essays on mind, self, and emotion.
Cambridge University Press.
Slife. B. D. (1981). The primacy of affective judgments from a teleological perspective.
American Psychologist, 36, 221-222.
Smith. C. A. (1987). The informational structure of the facial expression of emotion.
Dissertation Abstracts International, 47, 4002B (University Microfilms No. 87-00,820).
Smith, C. A. & Ellsworth, P. C. (1985). Patterns of cognitive appraisal in emotion. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 48, 813-838.
Smith, C. A. & Ellsworth, P. C. (1987). Patterns of appraisal and emotion related to taking
an exam. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 475-488.
Smith. C. A .. McHugo, G. J., & Lanzetta, J. T. (1986). The facial muscle patterning of
posed and imagery-induced expressions of emotion by expressive and nonexpressive
posers. Motivation and Emotion, JO, 133-157.
Weiner. B. ( 1985). An attributional theory of achievement motivation and emotion. Psycho-
logical Review. 92. 548-573.
Weiner. B .. Amirkhan, J., Folkes, V. S., & Verette, J. A. (1987). An attributional analysis
of excuse giving: Studies of a naive theory of emotion. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology. 52, 316-324.
Weiner. B .. Graham, S., & Chandler. C. (1982). Pity, anger, and guilt: An attributional
analysis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 8, 226-232.
Weiner, B .. Russell, D., & Lerman. D. (1979). The cognition-emotion process in achieve-
ment-related contexts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37, 1211-1220.
Zajonc. R. 8. (1980). Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no inferences. American
Psychologist. 35, 151-175.
Zajonc. R. 8. (1984). On the primacy of emotion. American Psychologist. 39. 117-123.

View publication stats

You might also like