You are on page 1of 5

and computation; it leaves learning

Special Section as an unexamined primitive.

The Four Causes of Behavior


ARISTOTLE’S FOUR CAUSES
Peter R. Killeen1
Department of Psychology, Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona Aristotle (trans. 1929) described
four kinds of explanation. Because
of mistranslation and misinterpre-
Abstract reduction of information to dis- tation by “learned babblers” (San-
Comprehension of a phe- position. Automata theory pro- tayana, 1957, p. 238), his four “be-
nomenon involves identifying vides a grammar for models of causes [aitia]” were derogated as
its origin, structure, substrate, conditioning and information an incoherent treatment of causal-
and function, and representing processing in which that con- ity (Hocutt, 1974). Although an-
these factors in some formal sys- straint can be represented. cient, Aristotle’s four (be)causes
tem. Aristotle provided a clear provide an invaluable framework
specification of these kinds of Keywords for modern scientific explanation,
explanation, which he called ef- associations; automata; causal- and in particular for resolution of
ficient causes (triggers), formal ity; explanation; models the current debate about learning.
causes (models), material causes In Aristotle’s framework, effi-
(substrates or mechanisms), and cient causes are triggers, events that
final causes (functions). In this bring about an “effect.” This is the
Judging whether learning is bet- contemporary meaning of cause.
article, Aristotle’s framework is
ter explained as an associative or Philosophers such as Hume, Mill,
applied to conditioning and the
computational process requires and Mackie have clarified the crite-
computation-versus-associa-
that we clarify the key terms. This ria for identifying various efficient
tion debate. The critical empiri-
essay provides a framework for causal relations (e.g., necessity, suf-
cal issue is early versus late
discussing explanation, association, ficiency, insufficient but necessary

Downloaded from cdp.sagepub.com at University of Texas Libraries on June 4, 2015


CURRENT DIRECTIONS IN PSYCHOLOGICAL SCIENCE 137

events in the context of otherwise possible to speculate about under- ary pressures and varieties of strate-
sufficient events). Efficient causes lying mechanisms, and to generate gies adequate for that function),
identify the early parts of a se- formal models of them; but with- even though the wings are not ho-
quence that are essential for the out direct data on those mecha- mologues (i.e., are not evolved from
later parts; they tell us what ini- nisms, the models are unverifiable the same organ in an ancient for-
tiates a change of state. Jachmann conjectures and typically subject to bear). Analogical-functional analy-
and van den Assem’s (1996) change as fads come and go—they ses fall victim to “the analogical fal-
“causal ethological analysis” of the are occult. lacy” only when it is assumed that
courtship behavior of a wasp ex- Final causes are functional expla- similarity of function entails simi-
emplifies this meaning of cause. nations. “To recognize an actual larity of efficient (evolutionary his-
Material causes are substrates. machine, we have to have some tory) or material (physiological)
These are the most common kinds idea of what it is supposed to do” causes. Such confounds can be pre-
of causal explanation in use today, (Minsky, 1967, p. 4). Questions like vented by accounting for each type
exemplified by most of neuro- “What is it for?” and “Why does it of cause separately.
science and brain-imaging re- do that?” call for functional (final) Efficient causes, then, are the
search. Once the machinery has causes; survival of the fittest, opti- initial conditions for a change of
been identified, many people con- mal foraging theory, and purposive state; final causes are the terminal
sider the phenomenon explained. explanations in general provide rel- conditions; formal causes are mod-
Exclusive focus on machinery is evant answers. Most of modern els of transition between the initial
known as reductionism. physics can be written in terms of and terminal conditions; material
Formal causes are models. New- functions that optimize certain vari- causes are the substrate on which
ton’s great achievement was to give ables, such as energy. All laws these other causes act.
credibility to such models absent stated in terms of such optima con-
material causes: For him, there were cern final causes. Common exam-
no “hooks and eyes” to gravity— ples are light rays following paths
“Hypothesis [concerning underlying that minimize transit times, animals EXPLAINING CONDITIONING
mechanism] is no part of my de- behaving in ways that maximize ge-
signe”—just naked math. This was a netic representation in succeeding Skinner (1950) railed against for-
difficult position for Newton to generations, and humans behaving mal (“theorizing”), material
adopt, for as a mechanical philoso- in ways that maximize the benefits (“neuro-reductive”), and final
pher he abhorred occult (and thus ad for a population. Final causes were (“purposive”) causes, and scien-
hoc) accounts. Newton would gladly given a bad name (teleology) because tized efficient causes as “the vari-
have equipped his theory with they were treated as errant formal, ables of which behavior is a func-
hooks and eyes—material causes— material, or efficient causes. A rea- tion.” He was concerned that
but could devise none sufficient to son giraffes have long necks is to let complementary causes would be
hold the planets in their orbits. them browse high foliage; this final used in lieu of, rather than along
Formal causes are logical maps. cause does not displace formal with, his functional analysis. But of
Aristotle’s favorite form was the syl- (variation and natural selection) all behavioral phenomena, condi-
logism, just as the modern physi- and material (genetic) explanations; tioning is the one least able to be
cist’s favorites are differential equa- nor is it an efficient cause (Lamarki- comprehended without reference
tions. Such equations describe the anism). But none of those other to all four causes: The ability to be
course of change from one state to causal explanations make sense conditioned has evolved because
another; in concert with initial condi- without specification of the final of the advantage it confers in ex-
tions (efficient causes), they describe cause. Biologists reintroduced final ploiting efficient causal relations.
the complete trajectory of change. causes under the euphemism “ulti-
No matter how successful for- mate mechanisms,” referring to the Final Causes
mal models are, they are not ma- efficient and material causes of a be-
chines: Mathematical equations de- havior as “proximate mechanisms.” Conditioning shapes behavioral
scribe the trajectories of baseballs Two systems that share similar trajectories into shortest paths to
and planets, but those bodies do final causes may have quite dissimi- reinforcement (Killeen, 1989).
not solve equations to project their lar substrates. Analyses of evolu- When a stimulus predicts a biologi-
moves. The formal models of the tionary analogues—such as wings cally significant event (an uncondi-
contributors to this Special Section in insects, birds, and bats—provide tioned stimulus, US), animals im-
are mute concerning efficient useful functional information (con- prove their fitness by “learning
cause, substrate, and function. It is cerning, e.g., convergent evolution- associations” among external

Copyright © 2001 American Psychological Society


Downloaded from cdp.sagepub.com at University of Texas Libraries on June 4, 2015
138 VOLUME 10, NUMBER 4, AUGUST 2001

events, and between those events Formal Causes ditionals—such as the probability
and appropriate actions. Stable of becoming ill after experiencing a
niches—those inhabited by most Models are proper subsets of all particular taste—often start small,
plants, animals, and fungi—neither that can be said in a modeling lan- so that one or two pairings greatly
require nor support learning: Tro- guage. Associationist and computa- increase the conditional probability
pisms, taxes, and simple reflexes tional models of learning are formu- and generate taste aversions. Ear-
adequately match the quotidian lated in the languages of probability lier pairings of the taste and health,
regularities of light, tide, and sea- and automata, respectively. Their however, will give the prior condi-
son. However, when the environ- structures are sketched next. tionals more inertia, causing the
ment changes, it is the role of learn- conditional probability to increase
ing to rewire the machinery to more slowly, and possibly protect-
exploit the new contingencies. Bet- Associative Models ing the individual from a taste
ter exploiters are better repre- aversion caused by subsequent as-
sented in the next generation. This Material implication, the suffi- sociation of the taste with illness.
is the final—ultimate, in the biolo- cient relation (if C, then E; symbol- More common stimuli, such as
gists’ terms—cause of condition- ized as C→E), provides a simplistic shapes, may be slow to condition
ing. Understanding learning re- model of both efficient causality because of a history of exposure
quires knowing what the learned and conditioning. It holds that that is not associated with illness.
responses may have accomplished whenever C, then also E; it fails Bayes’s theorem provides a formal
in the environments that selected whenever C and E. When the pres- model for this process of updating
for them. ence of a cue (C, the conditioned conditional probabilities. This ex-
stimulus, or CS) accurately predicts emplifies how subsets of probabil-
a reinforcer (E, the US), the strength ity theory can serve as a formal
of the relation C→E increases. The model for association theory. Asso-
Efficient Causes
conditional probability of the US ciative theories continue to evolve
given the CS—p(E|C)—generalizes in light of experiments manipulat-
These are the prototypical kinds
this all-or-none relation to a proba- ing contextual variables; Hall
of causes, important enough for sur-
bility. Animals are also sensitive to (1991) provided an excellent his-
vival that many animals have
the presence of the US in the ab- tory of the progressive constraint
evolved sensitivity to them. Parame-
sence of the CS, p(E|ⵑC); only if of associative models by data.
ters that are indicators of efficient
this probability is zero is a cause
causes—contiguity in space and
said to be necessary for the effect. Computational Models
time, temporal priority, regularity of
Unnecessary effects degrade condi-
association, and similarity—affect
tioning, just as unexpected events Computers are machines that
both judgments of causality by hu-
make an observer question his associate addresses with contents
mans (Allan, 1993) and speed of con-
grasp of a situation. (i.e., they go to a file specified by
ditioning (Miller & Matute, 1996).
Good predictors of the strength an address and retrieve either a da-
of learning are (a) the difference tum or an instruction). Not only do
between these two conditional computers associate, but associa-
Material Causes probabilities and (b) the diagnostic- tions compute: “Every finite-state
ity of the CS, p(E|C)/p(E), which is machine is equivalent to, and can
The substrate of learning is the the degree to which the cause (CS) be ‘simulated’ by, some neural net”
nervous system, which provides an reduces uncertainty concerning the (Minsky, 1967, p. 55). Computers
embarrassment of riches in mecha- occurrence of the effect (US). As is can instantiate all of the associative
nisms. Development of formal and the case for all probabilities, mea- models of conditioning, and their
efficient explanations of condition- surement of these conditionals re- inverses. For the computational
ing can guide the search for opera- quires a defining context. This may metaphor to become a model, it
tive neural mechanisms. In turn, comprise combinations of cues, must be restricted to a proper sub-
elucidation of that neural architec- physical surroundings, and his- set of what computers can do; one
ture can guide formal modeling, tory of reinforcement. Reinforce- way to accomplish this is via the
such as parallel connectionist mod- ment engenders an updating of the theory of automata (Hopkins &
els—neural nets—that emulate conditionals; speed of conditioning Moss, 1976). Automata theory is a
various brain functions. Each of the depends on the implicit weight of formal characterization of compu-
four causes is a resource for under- evidence vested in the prior condi- tational architectures. A critical
standing the others. tionals. The databases for some con- distinction among automata is

Published by Blackwell Publishers Inc.


Downloaded from cdp.sagepub.com at University of Texas Libraries on June 4, 2015
CURRENT DIRECTIONS IN PSYCHOLOGICAL SCIENCE 139

memory: Finite automata can dis- Consciousness of action permits correlated with early versus late re-
tinguish only those inputs (histo- adaptation, unconsciousness per- duction of information to action.
ries of conditioning) that can be mits speed. The challenge now is to identify
represented in their finite internal In traditional associative theory, the class and capacity of automata
memory. Representation may be information is reduced to a poten- that are necessary to describe the
incrementally extended with exter- tial for action (“strength” of associ- capacities of a species, and the ar-
nal memory in the form of push- ation between the CS and US) and chitecture of associations within
down stores, finite rewritable stored on a real-time basis. Such fi- such automata that suffice to de-
disks, or infinite tapes. These am- nite automata with limited memo- scribe the behavior of individuals
plified architectures correspond to ries are inadequate as models of as they progress through condi-
Chomsky’s (1959/1963) context- conditioning because “the nature of tioning.
free grammars, context-sensitive the representation can change—the
grammars, and universal Turing sort of information it holds can be
machines, respectively. Turing ma- influenced by [various post hoc op- Comprehending Explanation
chines are models of the architec- erations]” (Hall, 1991, p. 67). Rats
ture of a general-purpose com- have memorial access to more of Many scientific controversies
puter that can compute all the history of the environment and stem not so much from differences
expressions that are computable by consequences than captured by in understanding a phenomenon as
any machine. The architecture of a simple Bayesian updating of dispo- from differences in understanding
Turing machine is deceptively sim- sitions. Miller (e.g., Blaisdell, Bris- explanation: expecting one type of
ple, given its universal power; it is tol, Gunther, & Miller, 1998; see explanation to do the work of other
access to a potentially infinite also this issue) provided one com- types, and objecting when other
memory “tape” that gives it this putational model that exemplified scientists do the same. Exclusive
power. Personal computers are in such late reduction. focus on final causes is derided as
principle Turing machines, silicon If traditional associaters are too teleological, on material causes as
instruments whose universality simple to be a viable model of con- reductionistic, on efficient causes
has displaced most of the brass in- ditioning, unrestricted computers as mechanistic, and on formal
struments of an earlier psychology. (universal Turing machines) are causes as “theorizing.” But respect
too smart. Our finite memory for the importance of each type of
stores fall somewhere in between. explanation, and the correct posi-
The Crucial Distinction Automata theory provides a gram- tioning of constructs within appro-
mar for models that range from priate empirical domains, resolves
Memory is also what divides the simple switches and reflexes, many controversies. For example,
associative from the computa- through complex conditional asso- associations are formal constructs;
tional approaches. Early reduction ciations, to adaptive systems that they are not located in the organ-
of memory to disposition requires modify their software as they ism, but in our probability tables or
fewer memory states than late re- learn. The increased memory this computers, and only emulate con-
duction and permits faster—reflex- requires is sometimes internal, and nections formed in the brain, and
ive—responses; late reduction is sometimes external—found in contingencies found in the inter-
more flexible and “intelligent.” An- marks, memoranda, and behavior face of behavior and environment.
imals’ behavior may reflect compu- (“gesturing facilitates the produc- Final causes are not time-reversed
tation at any level up to, but not ex- tion of fluent speech by affecting efficient causes. Only one type of
ceeding, their memory capacity. the ease or difficulty of retrieving explanation is advanced when we
Most human behaviors are simple words from lexical memory,” determine the parts of the brain
reflexes corresponding to finite au- Krauss, 1998, p. 58). Context is of- that are active during conditioning.
tomata. Even the most complicated ten more than a cue for memory— Provision of one explanation does
repertoires can become “automa- it constitutes a detailed, content- not reduce the need for the other
tized” by practice, reducing an addressable form of storage lo- types. Functional causes are not al-
originally computation-intense re- cated where it is most likely to be ternatives to efficient causes, but
sponse—a child’s attempts to tie a needed. Perhaps more often than completions of them.
shoe—to a mindless habit. The ad- we realize, the medium is memory. Formal analysis requires a lan-
aptation permitted by learning The difference between associa- guage, and models must be a
would come at too great a price if it tionistic and computational models proper subset of that language. The
did not eventually lead to auto- reduces to which automata they signal issue in the formal analysis
matic and thus fast responsivity. are isomorphic with; and this is of conditioning is not association

Copyright © 2001 American Psychological Society


Downloaded from cdp.sagepub.com at University of Texas Libraries on June 4, 2015
140 VOLUME 10, NUMBER 4, AUGUST 2001

versus computation, but rather the Uttal, W. (1998). Toward a new behav-
Aristotle. (1929). The physics (Vol. 1; P.H. Wick-
steed & F.M. Cornford, Trans.). London: Hei-
circumstances of early versus late iorism: The case against perceptual nemann.
information reduction, and the role reductionism. Mahwah, NJ: Erl- Blaisdell, A., Bristol, A., Gunther, L., & Miller, R.
of context—both as a retrieval cue baum. (1998). Overshadowing and latent inhibition
and as memory itself. Automata Wasserman, E.A. (1993). Compara- counteract each other: Support for the compar-
tive cognition: Toward a general ator hypothesis. Journal of Experimental Psychol-
theory provides a language that understanding of cognition in be-
ogy: Animal Behavior Processes, 24, 335–351.
can support appropriate subsets of havior. Psychological Science, 4, Chomsky, N. (1963). On certain formal properties
of grammars. In R.D. Luce, R.R. Bush, & E.
machines to model these processes, 156–161. Galanter (Eds.), Readings in mathematical psy-
from simple association up to the Wasserman, E.A., & Miller, R.R. chology (Vol. 2, pp. 125–155). New York: Wiley.
most complex human repertoires. (1997). What’s elementary about (Original work published 1959)
associative learning? Annual Re- Hall, G. (1991). Perceptual and associative learning.
Comprehension is a four-footed view of Psychology, 48, 573–607. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
beast; it advances only with the Young, M.E. (1995). On the origin of Hocutt, M. (1974). Aristotle’s four becauses. Philos-
progress of each type of explana- personal causal theories. Psy- ophy, 49, 385–399.
tion, and moves most gracefully chonomic Bulletin & Review, 2,
Hopkins, D., & Moss, B. (1976). Automata. New
when those explanations are coor- 83–104. York: North Holland.
dinated. It is a human activity, and Jachmann, F., & van den Assem, J. (1996). A causal
ethological analysis of the courtship behavior
is itself susceptible to Aristotle’s of an insect (the parasitic wasp Nasonia vitrip-
Acknowledgments—This article was writ-
quadripartite analyses. In this arti- ten with the support of National Science ennis, hym., pteromalidae). Behaviour, 133, 1051–
1075.
cle, I have focused on the formal Foundation Grant IBN 9408022 and Na-
analysis of explanation, and formal tional Institute of Mental Health Grant Killeen, P.R. (1989). Behavior as a trajectory
K05 MH01293. through a field of attractors. In J.R. Brink &
explanations of conditioning. Com- C.R. Haden (Eds.), The computer and the brain:
prehension will be achieved as Perspectives on human and artificial intelligence
(pp. 53–82). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
such formal causes become coordi-
Note Krauss, R. (1998). Why do we gesture when we
nated with material (brain states), speak? Current Directions in Psychological Sci-
efficient (effective contexts), and fi- 1. Address correspondence to Peter
ence, 7, 54–60.
nal (evolutionary) explanations of Killeen, Department of Psychology, Miller, R.R., & Matute, H. (1996). Animal ana-
logues of causal judgment. In D.R. Shanks,
behavior. Arizona State University, Tempe, AZ D.L. Medin, & K.J. Holyoak (Eds.), Causal
85287-1104; e-mail: killeen@asu.edu. learning (pp. 133–166). San Diego: Academic
Press.
Recommended Reading
Minsky, M. (1967). Computation: Finite and infinite
machines. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Miller, R.R., Barnet, R.C., & Gra- References
hame, N.J. (1995). Assessment of Santayana, G. (1957). Dialogues in limbo. Ann Ar-
bor: University of Michigan Press.
the Rescorla-Wagner Model. Psy- Allan, L.G. (1993). Human contingency judg-
chological Bulletin, 117, 363–386. ments: Rule based or associative? Psychological Skinner, B.F. (1950). Are theories of learning neces-
Bulletin, 114, 435–448. sary? Psychological Review, 57, 193–216.

Published by Blackwell Publishers Inc.


Downloaded from cdp.sagepub.com at University of Texas Libraries on June 4, 2015

You might also like