You are on page 1of 5

Adaptive Behavior

Special Issue

Adaptive Behavior
2022, Vol. 0(0) 1–5
Blurring Ontological Boundaries: The © The Author(s) 2022

Transactional Nature of Material Article reuse guidelines:


sagepub.com/journals-permissions
Engagement DOI: 10.1177/10597123221098002
journals.sagepub.com/home/adb

Nicolás Alessandroni1  and Lambros Malafouris2 

Abstract
The target article provides valuable reflections regarding the study of cognition-in-the-world and proposes a methodology
that could help researchers unravel the structure and temporal unfolding of lived experience. In this commentary, we
discuss the authors’ commitment to the enactive notion of sense-making as the activity of an autonomous system that
brings forth a meaningful world to maintain its self-constituted identity. From Material Engagement Theory, we hold that
defending such a notion leads to unnecessary ontological asymmetries that obscure the fundamental role of materiality for
cognition. On the one hand, we argue that the relationship of close intertwinement and co-constitution that unites
organism and environment makes it untenable to characterise cognition as being driven by individuals. In our view,
cognition arises from the dynamic encounter between brains, bodies and culture. On the other hand, we suggest that
organism and environment should not be seen as separate ontological categories that come to interact with each other but
as two terms of a transactional process of continuous becoming. Consistently, we propose to consider meaning as
emerging from the in-between space that material engagement creates rather than from the activity of an organism.

Keywords
enactivism, materiality, material engagement theory

In the target article, Poizat et al. propose the foundations of a the authors argue that no unit of analysis other than practice
theoretical and methodological framework for studying as a whole would be sensible for studying cognition. There
cognition-in-the-world. They start from a distributed per- is a strong hypothesis, then, that studying cognition is
spective that conceives cognition as a relational tantamount to studying the characteristics of the confluence
phenomenon – as the emergent product of the encounter of brain, body and world, these being elements that cannot
between brain, body and world, in and through practice. be ontologically distinguished from one another. Transac-
This definition is broadly congruent with contemporary tionally speaking, cognition is the continuous process by
perspectives of cognition (e.g. ecological, embodied, em- which brain, body and world co-constitute each other,
bedded, enactive and extended perspectives) that question giving rise to particular socio-material dynamics. The
orthodox representationalist stances. Insofar as the course- second understanding of cognition in the text is based on a
of-experience framework could contribute to the theoretical less strong hypothesis: cognition is the way in which an
development of current perspectives of cognition and the organism (i.e. an autonomous system) in interaction with its
carrying out of empirical studies, the authors’ effort is to be environment (i.e. structurally coupled to the environment)
commended. brings forth or enacts a meaningful world for itself. In this
Nevertheless, we would like to draw attention to the fact
that two competing hypotheses about cognition coexist in
the text: one transactional and the other enactivist. Ac- 1
Department of Psychology, Concordia University, Montreal, QC, Canada
cording to the first of these, mainly sketched at the be- 2
Hertford College/Institute of Archaeology, University of Oxford, OX, UK
ginning of the article, ‘cognitive phenomena are outcomes
emerging from the orchestration of elements of distributed Corresponding author:
Lambros Malafouris, Hertford College, University of Oxford, Oxford OX1
cultural-cognitive systems, embodied and embedded in
3BW, UK; Institute of Archaeology, University of Oxford, 36 Beaumont
practice (...) Practice is (...) the thinking processes them- St, Oxford OX1 2PG, UK.
selves’ (Poizat et al., introduction). From such a perspective, Email: lambros.malafouris@arch.ox.ac.uk
2 Adaptive Behavior 0(0)

definition, which is evidently based on enactivism, the the individual (i) does not adequately address the lack of
organism is differentiated from its environment and concreteness and (ii) provides an ill-fitting description of
asymmetrical to it. practices.
The transactional and enactivist hypotheses differ in The main reason is that socio-material practices are
the relative importance they assign to the organism. Thus, in distributed systems that bring together a coalition of human
the transactional hypothesis, the organism is only one of the and non-human agents that co-determine and co-constitute
terms that participates in the process of cognitive becoming each other (Malafouris, 2008a, 2013, 2018), establishing
and contributes to the transactional relation in a way that is push-and-pull relationships that bring about new modes of
symmetrical to how other human and non-human agents acting and thinking (Ransom, 2019). More precisely, Ma-
(e.g. other people or things) do. In the enactivist hypothesis, lafouris argues that in real-life situations, perceiving,
anchored in the notion of autopoiesis, the organism is a self- thinking, doing and making are co-defined so that they are
organising system that defines the dynamics of the structural inseparable from each other (Malafouris, 2019a). Thus,
coupling with its environment according to the specific while focusing on individual experience might provide
goals it generates. In other words, for enactivism, sense- researchers with specific data about subjects’ lived expe-
making requires the activity of the organism as an agent riences, it would also detract from the description of the
(e.g. Di Paolo, 2016). transactional nature of the brain–body–world meeting that
We will not dwell here on the similarities and differences the authors are interested in unravelling, as stated in the
between the ways of understanding the organism– introduction of the target article. From the perspective of
environment relationship in enactive perspectives and MET, cognition is situated in the relational space that re-
other theories, such as ecological psychology. First, because unites organism and environment during material engage-
there are currently heated debates on this issue, with people ment (i.e. in the action itself) (Malafouris, 2004; 2021b). In
arguing for the convergence or complementarity of these other words, for MET, the influence of materiality on
perspectives and others opposing this possibility (see, for cognition far exceeds external scaffolding: as materiality
instance, Heft, 2020; Heras-Escribano, 2021; McKinney, envelops our everyday thinking and experience, it mediates
2020; Popova & Ra˛ czaszek-Leonardi, 2020; Ryan & and constitutes our ways of being and developing in the
Gallagher, 2020; Travieso et al., 2020). Second, because world (Malafouris, 2008b).
it would be more productive to analyse why the authors of Accordingly, we believe that a concrete description of
the target article needed to resort to the enactive definition of cognition as called for by the authors in their text could only
cognition as an organism-driven sense-making process and be achieved by analysing the structural and dynamic fea-
what potentially inconvenient consequences follow from tures of the brain–body–environment network as it is ar-
this. The ensuing analysis draws primarily on the premises ticulated in the practices themselves. In a recent case study,
of Material Engagement Theory (henceforth MET; for example, Aston (2020) explored the relationship be-
Malafouris, 2004, 2013; 2019a, 2020; 2021a; 2021b), to tween Cycladic marble sculpting and the development of
which the authors of the target article refer in their text. the social organisation at the sites of Dhaskalio and Kavos
The need to adopt an ‘individual-oriented approach’ on the island of Keros, concluding that the semiotics of
(Poizat et al., introduction) arises, in the target article, in value that organised the intersubjective exchanges emerged
opposition to socio-cultural perspectives that conceive of through the making and using of Cycladic figurines. For
culture as an abstract set of socially organised activities. instance, the author hypothesises that material engagement
According to the authors, these perspectives approach with marble figurines brought forth new ways of directing
practices globally, thus losing sight of the concrete aspects attention, perceiving the body, and identifying and differ-
at play. Following Poizat et al., the solution is to consider entiating self and other (p. 595) (see also Aston, 2021, for an
socially organised activities as well as ‘individual cognitive analysis of how automobiles transform the flows of energy-
constructs’ and the first-person lived experience. We agree matter across different timescales). Similarly, through ob-
that perspectives that understand culture as a set of values, servations in a nursery school, Alessandroni (2021a)
social representations or symbolic meanings tend to de- described the pragmatic benefits that children gain when
scribe practices in an abstract manner and often end up they begin to use objects (e.g. soothers, cups and bibs)
offering top-down explanations (i.e. social values or according to their cultural function. For example, when
meanings determine behavioural performance). We are also children begin to materially engage with objects in ca-
concerned with the need to provide a more concrete ex- nonical ways (e.g. using a cup for drinking water), they
planation of culture, focusing on what people do when they become able to extend functional behaviours to new ex-
engage in socio-material practices (e.g. practice-based and emplars of classes (i.e. they can also drink water from cups
sensorimotor accounts of culture, see Bourdieu, 1977; they have not used in advance), align their action with the
Ingold, 1996/2001; Soliman & Glenberg, 2014; Van Dijk & requirements of school activities more effectively, offer
Rietveld, 2017). However, we believe that the emphasis on objects to other children for them to use canonically and
Alessandroni and Malafouris 3

play with others’ intentions with and through materiality. (Hutchins, 2010). Moreover, this occurs from the very
Interestingly, the development of canonical uses in nursery beginning of life: the first interactions between adults and
school follows a trajectory distinct from that of other types babies do not happen in a vacuum but in and through a
of uses and is effectively promoted by myriad communi- material world that adults actively try to bring to children
cative strategies that adults (i.e. teachers) deploy when through communicative strategies (e.g. showing and giving
interacting (see Alessandroni, 2021b, for an empirical study gestures, demonstrations of object uses and bodily adjust-
in this regard). Finally, in a recent article, Malafouris ments) (Alessandroni et al., 2021a). By virtue of this, the
(2019b) proposed a situated model for understanding the agent could neither pre-exist nor be independent of mate-
causal efficacy of materiality on mental health. Specifically, riality but acquires its character as such in and through the
he argued that the diminishing capacities for memory, in- material engagement it sustains with things (see Malafouris,
teraction and communication that characterise people who 2019a).
have dementia are not only the result of neurological factors From this perspective, MET argues that cognition is not a
but also of radical changes in material ecologies that take property of the individual but an emergent result of the
place under situations such as the transition from home to brain–body–environment system. Cognition is thing-ing,
care home. This is because interacting in a familiar af- namely, thinking and feeling with and through things
fordance space such as the home environment (which may (Malafouris, 2014; 2019a, 2020; 2021b). Thus, if cognitive
be disrupted in cases of dementia) contributes to the con- processes such as intentionality, meaning-making, memory
struction of self-identity and a sense of stability. In line with or conceptual thinking were located somewhere, that place
this observation, Malafouris proposes further studying how would be the transactional space that organism and envi-
people with dementia think with and through things (rather ronment form during material engagement. Accordingly, we
than about things). For example, the author notes that disagree with the suggestion that practices become mean-
objects embody memories thanks to their form and the ingful to an actor (Poizat et al., section ‘Identifying signs,
history of uses that people have performed with them, their components, and their local dynamics’). Practices
making them powerful tools to elicit the re-enactment of become meaningful in and for the extended cognitive
certain forms of material engagement. This has significant system that the organism, others and things come to form
practical consequences. In the author’s words, ‘things during material engagement. In sum, even if enactivism
provide a durable network of material signification, trans- assumes that a fluid and dynamic link between an organism
posable dispositions and bodily habits which can be har- and its environment may be established, it does not concur
nessed to enhance cognitive abilities or compensate with the more substantial anti-localisationist thesis advo-
for memory loss when biological memory is damaged’ cated by MET, which we believe best describes the nature of
(p. 198). All these studies investigate socio-material situated cognition.
practices by emphasising the transactional nature of the All in all, our commentary invites reflection on the
brain–body–world encounter rather than privileging indi- continuing need to consider the individual as the centre of
vidual experience. cognition and the potential utility of blurring the ontological
Another drawback of assuming the enactive hypothesis boundaries between organism and environment for the
involves bearing an ontological differentiation between the study of socio-material practices. As Heft (2020) stated,
organism whose activity guides the sense-making process ‘enaction theory while recognising the tight interdepen-
and the environment, with which the former is structurally dencies within the organismic system seems to underplay
coupled. While enactivism clearly distances itself from the the interdependencies of an organism-environment system’
intellectualist tradition according to which skilled action (p. 11). By contrast, in MET, cognition is not just world-
follows the contemplation of propositions in the mind (for a involving: the world actively participates in shaping how
discussion, see Ryle, 1949), it maintains an ontological cognition (literally) takes place, on a par with the organism
distinction between agent and tool. As Paolucci (2021) and other organisms, with no clear ontological boundaries
pointed out, ‘one of the main theses of enactivism is that between them. Adhering to the more robust transactional
the living organism, in order to survive and build its internal hypothesis, MET argues that the dynamics of the distributed
autonomy, creates a distinction between itself and the en- system that brings together organisms and their environ-
vironment in which it is embedded’ (p. 10). This assumption ment (whether it be material or social) cannot be reduced to
may create the mistaken impression that the existence of an the properties of any of its constituent parts. We believe that
agent is relatively independent of the existence of materi- a discussion of the issues raised here could enrich the
ality. However, this is not the case. In the cognitive ecol- proposal put forward by the authors in the target article and
ogies we live in, mental processes, social processes, collaborate in unravelling the constitutive character of
material processes and bodies are intimately intertwined materiality for cognition.
4 Adaptive Behavior 0(0)

Declaration of conflicting interests (pp. 53–62). McDonald Institute for Archaeological


Research.
The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with re-
Malafouris, L. (2008a). At the potter’s wheel: An argument for
spect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.
material agency. In C. Knappett & L. Malafouris (Eds.),
Material agency: Towards a non-anthropocentric approach
Funding (pp. 19–37). Springer Science+Business Media.
The author(s) received no financial support for the research, au- Malafouris, L. (2008b). Between brains, bodies and things: Tec-
thorship, and/or publication of this article. tonoetic awareness and the extended self. Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences,
ORCID iDs 363(1499), 1993–2002. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2008.
0014
Nicolás Alessandroni  https://orcid.org/0000-0002-6595-0969 Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind. A theory of
Lambros Malafouris  https://orcid.org/0000-0003-2140-4998 material engagement. The MIT Press.
Malafouris, L. (2014). Creative thinging: The feeling of and for
References clay. Pragmatics & Cognition, 22(1), 140–158. https://doi.
Alessandroni, N. (2021a). Object concepts and their functional org/10.1075/pc.22.1.08mal
core: Material engagement and canonical uses of objects in Malafouris, L. (2018). Bringing things to mind: 4Es and material
early childhood education. Human Arenas, 4, 172–195. engagement. In A. Newen, L. De Bruin, & S. Gallagher
https://doi.org/10.1007/s42087-020-00119-5 (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition (pp. 754–772).
Alessandroni, N. (2021b). The road to conventional tool use: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/
Developmental changes in children’s material engagement 9780198735410.013.40
with artefacts in nursery school. Manuscript submitted for Malafouris, L. (2019a). Mind and material engagement. Phe-
publication. nomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 18(1), 1–17. https://
Aston, A. (2020). How the Cycladic islanders found their marbles: doi.org/10.1007/s11097-018-9606-7
Material engagement, social cognition and the emergence of Malafouris, L. (2019b). Understanding the effects of materiality on
Keros. Cambridge Archaeological Journal, 30(4), 587–610. mental health. BJPsych Bulletin, 43(5), 195–200. https://doi.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S095977432000013X org/10.1192/bjb.2019.7
Aston, A. (2021). You can’t perform the same ritual twice: Minds, Malafouris, L. (2020). Thinking as “thinging”: Psychology with
materials, automobiles, and the emergence of form. World things. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 29(1),
Archaeology, 53(1), 158–172. https://doi.org/10.1080/ 3–8. https://doi.org/10.1177/0963721419873349
00438243.2021.1972831 Malafouris, L. (2021a). How does thinking relate to tool making?
Bourdieu, P. (1977). Outline of a theory of practice. Cambridge Adaptive Behavior, 29(2), 107–121. https://doi.org/10.1177/
University Press. 1059712320950539
Di Paolo, E. (2016). Across the uncanny valley: The ecological, the Malafouris, L. (2021b). Making hands and tools: Steps to a process
enactive, and the strangely familiar. Constructivist Founda- archaeology of mind. World Archaeology, 53(1), 38–55.
tions, 11(2), 327–329. https://doi.org/10.1080/00438243.2021.1993992
Heft, H. (2020). Ecological psychology and enaction theory: McKinney, J. (2020). Ecological∼enactivism through the lens of
Divergent groundings. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 991. Japanese philosophy. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 1347.
https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.00991 https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01347
Heras-Escribano, M. (2021). Pragmatism, enactivism, and eco- Paolucci, C. (2021). Cognitive semiotics. Springer. https://doi.org/
logical psychology: Towards a unified approach to post- 10.1007/978-3-030-42986-7_1
cognitivism. Synthese, 198(Suppl 1), S337–S363. https://doi. Popova, Y. B., & Ra˛ czaszek-Leonardi, J. (2020). Enactivism and
org/10.1007/s11229-019-02111-1 ecological psychology: The role of bodily experience in
Hutchins, E. (2010). Cognitive ecology. Topics in Cognitive agency. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 539841. https://doi.org/
Science, 2(4), 705–715. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1756-8765. 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.539841
2010.01089.x Ransom, T. G. (2019). Process, habit, and flow: A phenomeno-
Ingold, T. (1996). Culture, perception and cognition. In J. Haworth logical approach to material agency. Phenomenology and the
(Ed.), Psychological research. Innovative methods and Cognitive Sciences, 18(1), 19–37. https://doi.org/10.1007/
strategies (pp. 99–119). Routledge. s11097-017-9541-z
Malafouris, L. (2004). The cognitive bases of material engage- Ryan, K. J., & Gallagher, S. (2020). Between ecological psychology
ment: Where brain, body and culture conflate. In E. and enactivism: Is there resonance? Frontiers in Psychology,
DeMarrais, C. Gosden, & C. Renfrew (Eds.), Rethinking 11, 1147. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01147
materiality: The engagement of mind with the material world Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Hutchinson House.
Alessandroni and Malafouris 5

Soliman, T., & Glenberg, A. M. (2014). The embodiment of culture. in Psychology, 11, 1257. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.
In L. Shapiro (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of embodied 01257
cognition (pp. 207–219). Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group. Van Dijk, L., & Rietveld, E. (2017). Foregrounding sociomaterial
Travieso, D., Lobo, L., de Paz, C., Langelaar, T. E., Ibáñez-Gijón, practice in our understanding of affordances: The skilled
J., & Jacobs, D. M. (2020). Dynamic touch as common intentionality framework. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 1969.
ground for enactivism and ecological psychology. Frontiers https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01969

You might also like