You are on page 1of 3

The identification

Reality week 6: 1. Ordinary objects as regions of spacetime


We’ve already encountered the minimalist picture
according to which reality is just a four-dimensional
Objects and spacetime 2. Objections to the identification spatiotemporal manifold.
Challenge: what about people, tables, trees, books,
Cian Dorr 3. Ordinary objects as occupants of spacetime
21 February 2012 planets...?
4. No-overcrowding views
• Eliminativist response: No such things!
• The obvious “reductionist” alternative: these things do
exist, but they are themselves regions of spacetime.

1 2 3

How this looks The mereology of regions An elementary consequence

If instants and intervals of time and material objects


are all spacetime regions, the following are plausible:
• O exists during t: O overlaps t
Standard assumptions about how regions work: • O exists only during t: Every part of O overlaps t
• Any two regions R1 and R2 have a sum (join) • O1 and O2 coincide during t: O1⊓t = O2⊓t
• Any two regions R1 and R2 that share a part have an The doctrine of temporal parts: whenever a material
intersection (meet), R1⊓R2
object O exists during a time t, O has a part that
exists only during t, and coincides with O during t.
• Q: Are all parts of material objects themselves material
objects?

4 5 6

Examples of coincidence among ordinary objects: Which regions are people (etc.)? ‘Part at t’
The inclusion relation on regions is not a good fit to
• Parts of people are not, normally, people. This applies to our ordinary use of ‘part’.
familiar parts like their heads, and unfamiliar parts like
their time-slices. • The steering wheel is not part of the car, since it existed
Smaller lump
clay

Statue earlier.
• Otherwise, we will have to say that there are many
• We ordinarily think of parthood as a time-relative matter:
people giving this lecture right now, some of them very
Statue short-lived.
parts can be gained and lost.
Big lump
Lump of

Standard solution: distinguish ‘x is part of y at t’ from


• Beware of using labels like ‘Fred at noon’ for time-
‘x is part of y simpliciter’.
slices—you will be tempted to forget they are not
people. • Sider’s analysis: x is part of y at t iff x’s temporal part at t
• Schematic analysis of ‘person’: a person is a maximal is part (simpliciter) of y’s temporal part at t.
sum of person-slices which are related to one another in • Problem: Consider a ham sandwich H. Cleopatra+H and
the right way (Lewis, ‘Survival and Identity’). H are parts of one another right now. (Fine, ‘Things and
Their Parts’)
7 8 9
What is it to be F at t? Background to the objections

Sometimes friends of temporal parts say things that


suggest the following completely general schema: 1. Ordinary objects as regions of spacetime
(*) x is F at t iff x’s instantaneous temporal part at t is F.
2. Objections to the identification
Leibniz’s Law: if x=y and Fx, then Fy.
• This might be OK for ‘x is straight at t’ and ‘x is red at t’. 3. Ordinary objects as occupants of spacetime
But it is looks bad for ‘x is a philosopher at t’ or ‘x is a Contrapositive version: if Fx and not Fy, then x≠y.
4. No-overcrowding views
child at t’.
• All philosophers and children are people. No
instantaneous temporal parts are people. So...

10 11 12

1. Leibniz’s Law: nonmodal properties 2. Leibniz’s Law: modal properties 3. Leibniz’s Law: coincident objects

Lumpl could have survived squashing


I last more than 35 years, but could have lasted less
Goliath could not have survived squashing
than 30.
I brush my teeth every day Goliath and Lumpl are material objects that occupy
No spacetime region that lasts for more than 35 years
No spacetime region brushes its teeth every day the same spacetime region
could have lasted less than 30.
Therefore, I am not a spacetime region Therefore, two material objects sometimes occupy
Therefore, I am not a spacetime region.
• How strong is the second premise? • Standard response: appeal to the context-sensitivity of
the same spacetime region
‘could have’. Therefore, it is not true that every material object is
identical to the spacetime region it occupies

13 14 15

4: ‘One object to a place!’ Occupation

Even if we deny that material objects are identical to


A widespread intuition: Two material objects can’t be
regions of spacetime, it is natural to think of each
in the same place at the same time. material object as intimately related to a unique
1. Ordinary objects as regions of spacetime
• There wouldn’t be room, at least if they are ordinary 2. Objections to the identification region of spacetime—the one it ‘occupies’; its ‘exact
objects without special ghostlike powers of
interpenetration. 3. Ordinary objects as occupants of spacetime location’.
• If you accept this intuition, you can’t accept the 4. No-overcrowding views • Some questions we can ask using ‘occupy’:
previously discussed account of the statue-clay cases. (i) Do some regions have more than one occupant?
• The ‘paradoxes of material constitution’. (ii) Are all parts of occupied regions occupied?
(iii)Do distinct material objects ever occupy regions that
coincide at a time?

16 17 18
A common “four-dimensionalist” package: A dreadful argument for temporal parts The argument from temporary intrinsics

Whether or not objects are identical to the spacetime Lewis: ‘If we know what shape is, we know that it is
regions they occupy: a property, not a relation.’
(i) Each region has at most one occupant
The person who went into the barber shop had long So [?], the facts about which things are straight at this
(ii) Every part of an occupied region has an occupant
hair. or that that time must be explained in terms of the
(iii)(Hence:) Distinct objects often do coincide at a time. The person who came out of the barber shop did not facts about which things are straight simpliciter, thus:
Also: have long hair. To be straight at t is to have a temporal part that
(iv)there is a basic relation of timeless parthood among So, the person who went into the barbershop ≠ the exists only at t and is straight simpliciter.
material objects. x is part of y iff the region x occupies is person who came out of the barber shop. • Note that we’d better not say the same thing about being
part of the region y occupies. a child at t, being a philosopher at t, being old at t...
• Note that (ii) and (iv) jointly entail that each material • Is ‘straightness is a property, not a relation’ any more
object has a temporal part at every time it exists. compelling than ‘oldness is a property, not a relation’?

19 20 21

An argument for overcrowding 1. Mereological essentialism (Chisholm).

P1 There is a person-shaped object on the table (a


statue) that came into existence about an hour
1. Ordinary objects as regions of spacetime ago. For each set of atoms S, at most one material object
2. Objections to the identification P2 There is a person-shaped object on the table (a ever has exactly the members of S as parts. It exists
3. Ordinary objects as occupants of spacetime lump of clay) that came into existence many at t iff all of the members of S exist at t.
4. No-overcrowding views years ago. • Consequence: objects never gain or lose parts.
P3 Therefore, there are at least two person-shaped • Q: are these things statues some of the time? People?
objects on the table.
• Which premise will no-overcrowding theorists reject?

22 23 24

2. Dominant sortal view (Burke)

• Statues are formed and destroyed when we


generally think they are.
• Lumps of clay are less long-lasting than we think:
when a new statue is formed, the original lump of
clay goes out of existence.
• When a statue is squashed, a lump of clay that
didn’t exist a moment previously starts to exist.

25

You might also like