You are on page 1of 10

Geography, Marx and the Concept of Nature

Neil Smith and


Phil O’Keefe

Although “nature” is one of the most commonly image of science. Though not exclusive, the positivist
invoked concepts in science (natural or social), it has in tradition dominates orthodox science, and positivism
recent years been the subject of surprisingly little ”presupposes (among other things) that nature exists in
methodological discussion. A n understanding of and for itself, external to human activity. T h u s we can
nature is fundamental to the manner in which science know nature only by perceiving its facts and even-
sees and conducts itself, yet the concept is generally tually discovering its laws. Nature is constituted as an
taken for granted. Even the current enthusiasm to external repository of facts that live according to auto-
write introspective philosophies, sociologies and his- nomous natural laws. Mystery exists in nature only to
tories, science has left the stone of “nature” unturned. the extent that science has not yet discovered these
The neglect is not too difficult to explain; it is wholly facts and laws.
consistent with the contemporary practice and self-

O F NATURE
THECONCEPT IN SOCIAL
SCIENCE

With difficulty has social science adopted this man nature” a genuine rather than accidental concept?
rather stark conception of nature. Intimately con- T h e contradiction within the positivist conception of
nected with human nature, the nature that social scien- nature cannot be ignored by banishing one side of it in
tists study is far harder to view as external. As social theory while it remains in practice.
scientists internalize the positivist paradigm in larger 2 ) T h e second way of dealing with the contradic-
and larger numbers, therefore, they gradually expose tion is the assertion that social science like natural
beneath the concept’s calm exterior a turbulent core; science does study nature but that the nature i t studies
beneath its taken-for-grantedness they reveal a dual is different from that studied by natural science. T h e
conception of nature. O n the one hand, nature is ex- “nature’’ of natural science is deemed autonomous
ternal, non-human reality, pure and god-given; o n the from human activity while that of social science is seen
other, nature is more abstract, incorporating human a s as socially created. Insofar as the contradiction within
well as non-human spheres of reality. In practice, this the concept of nature is perceived, this is a popular
dual conception of nature is contradictory within posi- solution, but it relies o n displacing the contradiction
tivism. A t the same time as i t is strictly non-human, from the concept itself into the nature to which the
nature” is expected to be simultaneously human and concept refers; nature as a unified concept refers to a
non-human. Practicing scientists tend to adopt one or bifurcated reality. T h u s there remains a contradiction
the other concept of nature, sometimes adopting both between this actual nature, which incorporates the se-
consecutively but rarely simultaneously. paration of human and non-human, and the concept,
T h e contradiction within the positivist concep- “nature,’’ which refers to this opposition as a unity.
tion of nature is usually dealt with in one of three ways: 3) T h e third solution dissolves human nature into
I) Natural science studies nature, social science external nature. According to this solution, human be-
does not; it studies society which has nothing to do havior is regulated according to the same body of laws
with nature. T o talk of ”human nature” or the nature as the lowest artropod. T h e difference between them is
of a certain society is therefore only metaphor or lin- simply one of scale and complexity within a single
guistic accident, according to this interpretation. But nature. Social Darwinism and much contemporary be-
this is unsatisfactory because metaphors and linguistic haviorism hold this view of nature. Such a ”solution”
“accidents” have a historical habit of referring to dissolves the contradiction in nature theoretically, b u t
something objectively real. I t is therefore no accident leaves it unsolved practically. In practice, human so-
that we talk of “ h u m a n nature” or the “nature of h u - cieties prove themselves able to appropriate the “laws
man societies.”’ Such usage of ”nature” is not trivial. Is of nature” for their own purposes, and this approp-
not human physiology every bit as “natural” as animal riation along with its purposes are not ruled by
physiology, and are not human psychology and h u - ’ ’ n a tu r a1 law.

man physiology thoroughly intertwined making “ h u - Geography has been particularly resistant to sim-

30
plistic, contradictory concepts of nature. Mainly con- With the eighteenth century there ends in West-
cerned with the relationship between human kind and ern civilization an epoch in the history of man’s
nature (“Man-Nature” or “Man-Environment” rela- relationship to nature. What follows is of an en-
tions, as they used to be called), geographers have gen- tirely different order, influenced by the theory of
erally been more sensitive to the complexity of evolution, specialization in the attainment of
“nature” and less willing to see it in simple dualistic knowledge, acceleration in the transformation of
terms. But even they, in recent years, have succumbed, nature.
as positivism tempted geographers with the promise of
relevance, apparent sophistication, and the resulting
As has been pointed out elsewhere, Marx was also
social prestige. There have been exceptions, of course,
concerned to view nature in historical terms.’ More
among whom Glacken stands out. His Traces on the
than any other historical period, capitalism wrenches
Rhodian Shore is a remarkable intellectual history of
history from its socket in nature, and vice versa. It is
the idea of nature. Unlike Collingwood’s earlier, better
therefore of special importance to make their connec-
known, but less rich The.ldea of Nature, it was never
tion explicit:’
meant to include a programmatic exposition of the
contemporary conception of nature. Indeed, Glacken
ended his account with the eighteenth century. Like In the whole conception of history u p to the pres-
Collingwood, however, but in more sophisticated ent this real basis of history [the material relations
terms, Glacken rightly insisted that a proper under- of human societies with nature] has either been
standing of nature is impossible unless integrated with totally neglected or else considered as a minor
an understanding of history.’ The growth and trans- matter quite irrelevant to the course of his-
formation that nature experiences, however inter- t o r y . . . The real production of life seems to be
preted, can only be understood in conjunction with an primeval history, while the truly historical ap-
understanding of concrete historical development, pears to be separated from ordinary life, some-
and vice versa. Isolated from each other, nature and thing extra-superterrestrial. With this the relation
history become empty ideas. of man to nature is excluded from history
Writing explicitly about the idea of nature, and hence the antithesis of nature and history is
Glacken was also concerned to relate the historical cur- created.
rency of these ideas to the concrete material relation of
societies with nature. He notes that the Greeks were This unity (but not identity) of nature with history un-
able, for the first time in history, to conceive of nature derlies all of Marx’s work, which ought, for that reason
as modified by human activity because their produc- alone, to be of critical interest to social scientists. But
tive forces were.sufficiently developed to demonstrate in addition, Marx offers an alternative, unified and
human power over nature..’ Nonetheless, intellectual non-contradictory conception of nature. Positivism’s
history was Glacken’s primary concern. I t will be o u r contradictory concept of nature was developed (most
purpose here to examine in part what Glacken left recently) out of eighteenth and early nineteenth cen-
aside. First, we shall emphasize not the idea of nature, tury philosophical materialism, and Marx’s critique of
but the concrete relation of human beings with nature. this tradition remains relevant in terms of contempor-
For. i t is this alone which can give Glacken’s history a ary positivism.
material and historical grounding. Second, in contra- Glacken, succumbing to an all too common
distinction to Glacken, we shall look (however histori- mythology, dismissed Marx as teleological.’ Colling-
cally) at the Contemporary period. For good reason, wood, for his part, was so concerned to dismiss Marx
Glacken restricted his account to pre-eighteenth cen- on the first page that he had to resort to a mechanical
tury societies; the coming of capitalism heralded a new misinterpretation of Hegel’s famous “owl of Min-
relation of. human society with nature. In Clacken’.; erva.” This should offer itself as a recommendation
own words:4 not a deterrent.

O F NATURE
THECONCEPT IN HISTORICAL
MATERIALISM

Marx provided no systematic theory of nature, now generally referred to as historical materialism, and
but in his, as in every other, attempt a t science, a as its name suggests, it attempts a historical explana-
concept of nature is implied. By way of a critique of tion of how capitalism works, focusing on the social
classical political economy, his primary concern was to structures the society creates for sustaining its material
outline a theory of capitalist society. This theory is existence. I t is in this context that Marx discusses

31
nature, but as a n explication of “nature” per 5e these countered, given and transmitted from the p p t . ” ”
discussions remain fragmented and incomplete. At the T h e laws that regulate the development of Marx’s
same time, however, an understanding of “nature” is “second nature” are not a t all the same kind of laws
clearly central to Marx’s project, and a concept is im- that the physicist finds in the ”first nature.” They are
plied in his work though is never more than ipplicit. not invariant and universal laws because the societies
When teased out, elaborated and developed this con- they describe are in flux, constantly changing and de-
cept reveals an insightful theoretical basis o n which to veloping. According to Thomas, ”Marx’s analyses do
build scientific theory. not subordinate society to permanent laws like those
of physics, because society is seen by Marx as being in
transition, as moving toward a new arrangement in
which the ‘laws’ of classical economics will no longer
Nature as a Unity: First and Second Nature
apply. ”I L

Nature separate from society had no meaning for T h e “economic laws of motion” which Marx
Marx; nature is always related to societal activity. He sought were the laws (themselves historically mutable)
meant this materially a s well as ideally; the entire earth which were responsible for this social transition. I t is a
bears on its face the stamp of human activity. Writing law of capitalist society, for example, t h a t to survive,
as long ago a s the 1840s, when Africa was still known individual capitalists v u s t expand and accumulate lar-
as the Dark Continent, Marx and Engels could con- ger and larger quantities of capital. But as a side effect
clude that a “nature [which] preceded human his- of this i n d i ~ ~ i d u anecessity
l to expand, capitalism as a
tory . . . no longer exists anywhere (except perhaps on w h o l e produces the conditions for its own decline and
a few Australian coral-islands of recent origin).”u transformation into something different. By this
Though somewhat iconoclastic 135 years ago, this idea “Marx does not intend to prove that the process was
i q orthodox geographic wisdom today. Historically historically necessary. O n the contrary: only after he
and practically, the relation with nature is at the centre has proved from history that in fact the process has
of human activity since people rely o n nature for the partially already occurred, and partially must occur in
fulfillment of fundamental needs. Theoretically, the future, he in addition characterizes i t as a process
therefore, to conceive of nature as separate from so- which develops in accordance with a definite dialecti-
ciety is a false abstraction: “the idea of o n e basis for life cal law.”I3 Obviously, Marx‘s dialectic is a quite differ-
and another for science is from the outset a lie.”’ In a ent mode of thought from the formal logic of positivist
more ideal sense, to posit nature qs external to society is science, and it i s symptomatic of the narrow-minded-
absurd since this very act of positting implies a prior ness of the latter that its adherents often cannot even
awareness of our k n o w l e d g e relation with nature. W e conceive of different logics. Logic for them is simply
cannot know nature as external; we can know i t only logic, just as nature is nature; when Marx discusses
by entering into a relation with it. This latter, rather ndtLira1 laws in connection with the second nature, the
ideal, assumption hardly tells us a lot, but is utterly positivist consciousness imagines these a s identical
practical in so far as it reminds u s that science cannot with natural laws about the first nature (laws of phy-
in good faith treat nature as external. Yet this is exactly sics, for example) and therefore imagine Marx to be a
what positivism attempts: it ignores the inescapability determinist of one shade or another. B u t when M a r x
of this relation with nature, assumes nature to be an ex- discusses natural law, there is no implication of deter-
ternal thing-in-itself, and then by proceeding to gather minate inevitability, that much is a projection of the
knowledge about this nature, contradicts itself at every positivist consciousness. W h a t Marx alludes to in call-
turn. ing social laws natural is not the society in and for it-
Nature and society are not two totally separate self, b u t the internal relationship between society and
parts of reality as, in common parlance, they are often the people living under i t . T h u s Engels concludes that
assumed to be. Rather, there is a unity of nature that is ”the laws of economics confront men in a l l . . . plan-
differentiated within. T h u s Marx views capitalism as less incoherent production as objective laws over
operating according to “natural laws,” and declares as which they have no power, therefore in the form of
the “ultimate aim” of Capital the attempt to “lay bare laws of nature.”14 Far from being inevitable, these laws
t h e economic law of motion of modern society.” T h e are socially created and can be socially abolished.
laws of its own operation and development are em- While they remain, people are constrained in their sq-
bedded in the structure of capitalist society, and this cidl actions; they can abolish the laws responsible for
society cannot, by purely individual or even legislative this constraint not by isolated individual action but
effort, remove “the obstacles offered by the succes- only by deliberate, collective social action.
sive phases of its normal development.”’u“Men make
their own history, but they do not make it just as they Dialectics of Nature?
please; they do not make it under circumstances chosen
by themselves, but under circumstances directly en- The idea of second nature 15 not new Glacken

32
traces it back to Cicero, and it reappears in more mod- it.“’” For Marx, as we saw, second nature is to be
ern guise in Hegel. For them, the idea of a second viewed like the first. Schmidt than identifies two his-
nature was connected with the idea of a designed torical dialectics in Marx: ”pre-bourgeois” and bour-
nature.15 It was left for Marx to separate the concept geois. In the earlier historical period ”men are ab-
from this teleology, and in so doing he “stood Hegel’s solutely identical with nature,” and the Object (exter-
dialectic on its feet.” But this dialectical comprehen- nal nature) dominates the Subject (labour); human be-
sion of the second nature, together with Marx’s insis- ings are very much part of and at the mercy of external
tence o n a unified conception of nature, misses the nature. With the advent of the bourgeois period, how-
question first posed by Engels of the role of the dialec- ever, “men succeeded in universally mastering
tic in comprehending the first nature. Engels posed the n a t u r e . . . [and] nature congeals into an abstract in-it-
question as follows:16 self external to men;” the Subject now dominates the
Object. There is not one concept of nature in Schmidt,
Empirical natural science has accumulated such a therefore, but two: nature as external to human activ-
tremendous mass of positive material for know- ity and object to that activity (first nature); and nature
ledge that the necessity of classifying it in each as ”the totality of everything that exists” (the first and
separate field of investigation systematically and the second nature^).'^ Although these are asserted to be
in accordance with its inner interconnection has single reality, in practice - in the rest of the book -
become absolutely imperative. Schmidt tends to treat them as separate, and this allows
him to discuss, among other things, the historical
Establishing these “inner inter-connections” re- necessity of “man’s domination of nature.” That this
quired converting the formal logic of natural science accurately reflects Marx’s conception of nature is
into the dialectic. This Engels did by trying to show doubtful, but it does provide Schmidt with a platform
that the dialectic was inherent in nature, a property of from which to accuse Marx of being utopian.1° For
all material relations, and his “dialectic of nature” be- Marx did not accept the eternal necessity of this
came an integral part of Soviet ideology under Stalin. “domination of nature” that Schmidt introduces.
But ultimately, Engels commits the same metaphysical The “domination of nature” has been a consistent
sin as the scientists whose theory he attempts to inject theme among the Frankfurt School critical theorists, of
with the dialectic. He treats nature as something exter- whom Schmidt is one.L1Yet it is a vague notion, to say
nal, existing in itself, and quite separate from its human the least, and one that tends to promote the crude, bin-
appropriation. If in Lukacs’ philosophical language we ary opposition of society and nature or, as in Schmidt’s
accept the dialectic to be a relation of Subject case, “man and nature.” Behind “man’s domination of
and Object, it is clear that by separating nature from its nature” is a concrete mechanism but one which is de-
human appropriation, Engels has attempted to find the emphasized by the Frankfurt School to a greater or
dialectic within the Object itself? The so-called “dial- lesser extent. Paradoxical as i t sounds, this inner mech-
ectic of nature” is not inherent in nature but rather, as anism is in capitalist society the exploitation of one
we shall see, it is embedded in the human relation with class by another. William Leiss, a student of Herbert
nature. The dialectic, separate from human beings, has Marcuse of the Frankfurt School, points succinctly to
no meaning. this mechanism beneath the mystifying phrase, “the
domination of nature:”LL
Alfred Schmidt’s Concept of Nature
If the idea of the domination of nature has any
Alfred Schmidt’s exposition of T h e Concept of meaning at all, it is that by such means - that is,
Nature in M a n is an ambitious attempt to make expli- through the possession of superior technological
cit in Marx a concept that is only implicit. I t is often capabilities - some men attempt to dominate and
quoted but has not been critically appreciated or as- control other men. The notion of a common
sessed. Stressing the unity of nature and the unity of domination of the human race over external na-
nature with history in Marx, Schmidt begins by distin- ture is non-sensical . . . ‘Man‘ as such is an ab-
guishing Marx’s conception of nature from that of the straction which . . . only conceals the fact that in
contemporary philosophical materialism. He then the actual violent struggles among men technolo-
identifies the first and second natures in Marx but dis- gical instruments have a part to play.
tinguishes him from Hegel, for whom the second
nature is not at all like the first. “Hegel described the Unfortunately, Leiss is also unable to use this insight
first nature, a world of things outside men, as a blind to produce a unified rather than dualistic concept of
conceptless occurrence. The world of men as i t takes nature. For ”domination of nature” he substitutes
shape in the state, law, society, and the economy, is for “mastery over nature,” claiming with some justifica-
him ‘second nature,’ manifested reason, objective Spir- tion that i t has “different connotations,” and ends u p

33
with an even cruder distinction than Schmidt’s h e is constantly helped by natural forces.” By “his in-
between “internal” a n d ”external” nature. T h o u g h h e dustry,’’ the producer “changes the forms of the mat-
talks of “ t h e subtle interplay of internal a n d erials furnished by nature, in such a way as to make
external nature,” this is a subtlty in words rather than them useful to him. T h e form of wood, for instance, is
practice; it is a subtlty foisted o n t o the rather unsubtle altered, by making a table o u t of it. Yet, for all that, the
separation of internal from external.L3 table continues to be that common, everyday thing,
Despite his intentions, Schmidt was unable to wood.” *
avoid a dual conception of nature. T h r o u g h o u t h e ab- In so far as labor produces useful commodities
stracted the labor process from the specific historical that fulfill h u m a n needs, ” i t is a n eternal nature-im-
mode of production under which it occurred, preferr- posed necessity, without which there can be n o mat-
ing to talk of labor per se. T h e “labour-process,” for erial exchanges between men a n d nature, and therefore
Schmidt, “does not undergo any [historical] change no life.”” But labor effects more than just a simple
radically dividing the stages of production from each change in the form of matter; it produces a simul-
other.” T h u s h e proposes to investigate the relation. taneous change in the labourer, and it is from this ab-
with nature as mediated through the labor process, stract definition of the relation with nature that a uni-
without at first characterizing “ t h e relations of pro- fied marxist theory of nature can be constructed.
duction within which that process takes To
this extent h e denies his o w n assumption that nature Labour is, in the first place, a process in which
cannot be considered separately from history. T h e both m a n a n d nature participate, and in which
nature of the labor process, which mediates the relation m a n of his o w n accord starts, regulates, and con-
of history with nature, is no exception. As we shall see, trols the material re-actions between himself a n d
it is precisely this exploitation of labor power which, nature. He opposes himself to nature as one of
under capitalism, ties nature together as a unity, both her o w n forces, setting in motion arms and legs,
practically and conceptually. head and hands, the natural forces of his body, in
I t is not difficult to read Marx (as Schmidt has im- order to appropriate nature’s productions in a
plicitly done) as though h e too were offering a dual form adapted to his o w n wants. By thus acting o n
conception of nature. After all, Marx never provided a the external world a n d changing it, h e at the same
svstematic theory of nature and m a n y of the references time changes his o w n nature.‘8
and discussions he provides are ambiguous o n this
point. A n d as Schmidt discovered, it is necessary to Like Adam Smith, but unlike contemporary neo-classi-
complement Marx’s statements about nature with a cal economists for whom utility and value are synony-
broader overall understanding of his project. But it is mous, Marx distinguished two ways of viewing a com-
precisely here that Schmidt fails, for if anything h e is modity: as a n embodiment of useful attributes and
too pedantic. H e understands the close-grained details qualities which supply the commodity with a use-
o t Marx’s word, phrases, and sentences, but has trouble zialue; and as an embodiment of a certain quantity of
focu.;ing o n these as a whole. Otherwise, he could labor time, which supplies it with an exchange-value.
never have substituted an historical version of the Use-values are the material substratum of exchange-
labor-process, even in the context of his search for a values, and in so far as nature can be equated with the
Marxist concept of nature. A more rigorous and con- realm of use-values as Schmidt claims, we can view it in
sistent reading of Marx will allow u s to comprehend similar terms. Nature then becomes the material which
nature as historically unified through the labor pro- has its form altered by productive labor, becoming also
ce.., for “industry,” according to Marx ”is the histori- the material embodiment of exchange value; the wood
cal relationship of nature with man. is made into a commodity, the table. Things are pro-
will have to alter o u r perspective. I t will be necessary t o duced, we assume, because they are needed, and the
look not for a “concept of nature” p e r se, but for an “relation with nature” is thereby a use-value relation.
understanding of the relation of h u m a n societies with Natiiral material is qualitatively altered by being
nature. brought into h u m a n productive activity, and human
activity is simultaneously worked into natural material
outside itself.
Production in General Since Marx was initially concerned to explain the
inner workings of the capitalist economy, h e tended to
In his initial, abstract introduction to the topic in abstract trom the sphere of use-values, focusing o n ex-
Cupital, Marx depicts production as a process by change-values. T h u s his notion of nature did not expli-
which the form of nature is altered. T h e producer “can citly proceed beyond this rather abstract equation of
work only as nature does, that is by changing the form nature with use-value. Given this abstract formulation
of matter. N a y more, in this work of changing the form it is possible to see h o w a dual conception of nature

34
could be read into Marx, since like Schmidt, h e has only power, which they must sell to survive.30Compared to
at this point asserted the unity of nature without deriv- its predecessors, the capitalist mode of production is
ing it practically, i.e., logically and historically. In real- inherently progressive and revolutionary. As it devel-
ity, Schmidt has failed to go beyond Marx in any sub- oped internationally, capitalism swept before it all
stantive way; what he has articulated is a rationaliza- other modes of production. These were forcibly subor-
tion for the dual conception he implicitly reads into dinated to the dictates of capitalism which, since it
Marx. Yet this dual conception contradicts Marx‘s had achieved a higher level of productiveness than all
larger project. preceeding modes of production, had the political and
military, as well as the economic, wherewithal1 to en-
force its expansion. Hence the growth of colonial em-
Production for Exchange pires among the more advanced capitalist nations of
Few contemporary societies do not produce goods Europe and the fierce competition between these na-
for an exchange economy, and given such an arrange- tions leading to sporadic imperial wars.
ment, o u r understanding of the “relation with nature” Under capitalism, the relation with nature is a
use-value relation only in the most subordinate sense.
can be further refined. In short, it can no longer be seen
Before anything else it is an exchange-value relation.
as a purely use-value relation since if things are pro-
duced for exchange, direct need is no longer the sole de- “Expansion,” ”growth,” “progress” and “develop-
terminant of what is produced. Exchange-value is what ment” refer primarily to economic change (the neces-
the immediate producer seeks when he or she produces sary accumulation of greater and greater quantities of
for exchange. This exchange-value generally appears capital) upon which all other kinds of change are made
in material form as money which mediates the exchange dependent. At a day to day level, these changes are par-
ticularly apparent in the spheres of reproduction and
of commodities.
With an exchange system we begin to see not a consumption. Witness, for example, the constant bar-
homogeneous relation with nature, but rather the pro- rage of nostalgia for uncommercialized art and cul-
duction of a second natureout of the first, the develop- ture, or the perpetual Christmas time complaints about
ment of a set of social institutions to carry out and the commercialization of religion. This commercial-
regulate this exchange. Although the second nature is ization is in reality a capitalization, an extension of the
composed of (and circulates) products produced o u t of capitalist commodity structure into realms of life and
the first nature, it is for the most part only indirectly re- experience that had previously been ”sacred,” that is,
lated to i t through the production process. This separa- had survived independently in the realm of use values.
tion of first and second natures Schmidt conveys well Now, however, art, religion and culture are in the pro-
because his intellectual mentors (Kant and Hegel pro- cess of becoming commodities much as scientific
dominantly) lived and wrote in a time when precapital- knowledge already is, and their exchange-value label
ist exchange economies had developed fully and were (price) comes to dominate their use-value.
in the process of giving birth to capitalism. The un- But i t is not just this ”second nature” that is in-
reconciled dualisms in Schmidt’s concept of nature, creasingly produced as part of the capitalist mode of
particularly the idea of a second versus a first nature, production. The “first nature” is also produced. In-
are more truly and practically representative of this deed the “second nature” is no longer produced o u t of
historical period - a period of developing exchange the first nature, but rather the first is produced by and
economies - than any other. Schmidt set off to ”deter- within the confines of the second. Whether we are
mine more exactly the position of Marx between Kant talking about the laborious conversion of iron ore into
and Hegel,” and this is precisely what he has done. He steel and eventually into automobiles or the profes-
h a s abstracted from the historically different mode of sional packaging of Yosemite National Park, nature is
production that has developed since Kant and Hegel, produced. In a quite concrete sense, this process of
and which preoccupies Marx. He has treated Marx as production transcends the ideal distinction between a
an amalgamation of, rather than a movement beyond, first and a second nature. T h e form of all nature has
Kant and Hegel.2g been altered by human activity, and today this pro-
duction is accomplished not for the fulfillment of
needs in general but for the fulfillment of one parti-
Capitalist Production cular ”need:” profit.
Over forty years ago, this exchange-value relation
Based on private property, capitalism differs from with nature was intuitively recognized and unwitting-
other exchange economies in this: it produces on the ly encapsulated by t h a t great imperial geographer,
one side a class which possess the means of production Isaiah Bowman, who declared that human beings
for the whole society yet who do no labour, and on the “cannot move mountains” - not, that is, without first
other side a class that possess only their own labor ”floating a bond issue.”$’

35
To say that nature is produced does not imply that tion of the inherent beauty, sanctity and mystery of
every atom of some tree, mountain or desert is h u - nature. T h e meaning of nature to them is not only
manly created, any more than that every atom of the sacred; it transcends such vulgar considerations as
Empire State Building is humanly created; matter is production. Yet those are the same people who drive
neither created nor destroyed. It does mean the human their campers to Yellowstone to see Yogi Bear, who
activity is responsible to a greater or lesser extent for gladly use the beauty salon in the wilderness of Yose-
the form of matter; the size and shape of the buildings, mite, and who capture the wildest nature o n film so
the hybrid or location of the tree, the physignomy of they can reproduce in their living room. No less than
the mountain, the spatial extent of the desert. T h e ab- nature itself, the cultural meaning of nature is socially
stract difference between Schmidt’s first and second produced. This is not to diminish the genuine insights
natures is transformed into a difference of degree, and that an imaginative phenomenology (as opposed to
the unity of nature becomes practically realized in pro- humanism) can offer; rather it is to understand the lim-
duction. Behind the vague and mechanical “domina- its as well a s the possibilities of this form of dis-
tion of nature” we find in reality the production of course.JLT h e “realm of freedom actually begins only
nature. where labour which is determined by necessity. . .
There will be those who see this theory of nature ceases.” T h e “true realm of freedom. . . can blossom
centered on the nature of production as a crude viola- forth only with this realm of necessity as its basis.”jJ

IMPLICATIONS

Science of nature with the dialectic. That dialectic already


exists in the relation to nature exemplified by natural
“ W e know only a single science,” wrote Marx and science. T h e issue is not to inject the dialectic but to re-
Engels, “the science of history. O n e can look a t history trieve it.
from two sides and divide i t into the history of nature By holding nature as external to society, the Ob-
and the history o f men. Both sides are dependent on ject as wholly outside the Subject, natural science con-
each other so long a s men exist.”j4 This unity of science stitutes itself as rigorously non-dialectical. I t makes it-
was not an abstract principle for Marx but the eventual self deliberately blind to the other side of its relation
product of a concrete social development: “Natural with nature. Yet as it maintains this externality of
Science will in time subsume the science of man just as nature, it a t the same time appropriates nature, brings it
the science of man will subsume natural science: there within itself, in order to produce knowledge of it. This
will be o n e science.”” Or as Wilbur Zelinsky rather very project is clearly contradictory; nature is assumed
unwittingly explains: ” I entertain the wicked suspi- external but made internal. This and other contradic-
cion that when o u r vision of science h a s graduated to a tions arise from the way natural scientists relate to na-
higher level, we shall discover, to o u r surprise, that the ture, but they are ignored or rather displaced and exter-
precociously adolescent natural sciences must be con- nalized. They do not long remain external, however;
sumed within a larger, essentially social science of they resurface in quite tangible form and are becoming
which they form a peculiar special subset.” This after more and more difficult to conceive as externalities:
describing Marxism as a luxuriating religion.jb the production of deficient soils and the general de-
O n the basis of this historical understanding of gradation of much agricultural land; the production of
the ~rnification of science, it is possible to recast culturally deficient landscapes; pollution, and the er-
Engels’ unfortunate attempt to inject the dialectic into ratic availability of resources; the politics of nuclear
nature. Contemporary “natural science” is an histori- energy; internal scientific revolutions.’-
cal relic. I t originated in the sixteenth and seventeenth Burgess notes appropriately that “geographical
centuries with the need to appropriate nature through theory, at the heart of which must stand a concept of
industry, and reflects this need concretely by continu- nature, oscillates between a generality t h a t would ap-
ing to posit nature as wholly external to human activ- pall even a diplomat and an ecelecticism that would
ity. By so doing, science could provide capitalism with frighten a scientologist.”j8 T h e foregoing sketch of a
t h e technology through which nature could be social- theory of nature offers a more coherent focus for
ized. At the precise moment when nature was being scientific research. I t suggests two things: first, the re-
theorised a s external, however, the last vestiges of this lation of human societies and individuals with nature
externality were being practically destroyed; nature is the inescapable context or problematic for science;
became increasingly produced. T h e unity of science second, the unity of this relation is contradicted by the
therefore demands nothing so simple as the injection arbitrariness of disciplinary boundaries. Geography is

36
not unique in its concern to produce a “science of to a triage policy - the ’‘logical’’selection of which vic-
man’s relation to nature;” all science is concerned to a tims should be assisted after the event.41
greater or lesser extent with this relation. In capitalist society, it is the material production
It is possible to illustrate this argument more con- of nature that unifies the previously separate social
cretely with reference to natural hazard research. and natural realms, but it does so without, at the same
Typically, this research displays the three major ways time, making them identical - without dissolving one
of dealing with the contradiction within the positivist into the other. This offers a superior framework within
conception of nature (see page 1 above). T h u s the which to view disasters. It emphasizes not nature or
physical science paradigm deems nature as totally se- society as such, but primarily the relation w i t h nature
parate from human activity, and it is this interpreta- (first and second nature); it is this relation that is re-
tion that dominates natural hazards research.3g T h e sponsible for shaping both nature and society in the
hazard event (landslide, flood, earthquake, etc.) is seen production process. I t is a social relation which in
as the result of the natural and inevitable operation of capitalist society means a class relation. Thus vulner-
internal physical processes ranging from the geologi- ability to disaster is, as the Malthusian approach re-
cal to the climatological. This interpretation accepts cognizes, a class relation, but the reasons for this are
hazards as natural, meaning in effect that they are not to be found in the individual incapabihties of the
“acts of God” - beyond the realm of societal influ- working class, peasantry or whatever: “nature does
ence. I t is not surprising, then, that most government not produce on the one side owners of money or com-
research money is channeled into the search for ”nat- modities, and on the other men possessing nothing but
ural” causes, rather than an examination of human their own labour power. This relation has no natural
vulnerability in hazards, for the assumption of the basis, neither is its social basis one that is common to all
autonomy of nature provides plausiable depoliticized historical periods.”42 The division of labor, which
explanations for the distribution of the disaster’s ef- achieves a qualitatively different significance with the
fect throughout the population. And these “act of coming of capitalist society, ensures differential ac-
God” explanations are then used by insurance com- cess to nature, and this is equaIly the case with so-called
panies to avoid liability - an astute use of feudal scien- natural disasters. Exposure to the environment pro-
tific categoreis by finance capital. duced under capitalism is universal, but the conse-
A second approach to natural hazards has been quence of this exposure are far from uniform.
pioneered by geographers, who have likewise asserted
the separation of natural and social events, but who
place this separation under a larger umbrella concept Space
of nature; natural and social science study different
natures. At best this interpretation understands disas- Just as geographers cannot seriously claim “the re-
ter occurrence a s an inter-face between a vulnerable lation with nature” as theirs alone, nor can they claim
population and an extreme event. This dualism does space as their exclusive turf; since space is the product
not surpass the subject-object distinction of nature and of concrete material relations, all science is concerned
society and so reduces scientific inquiry to an exami- with space. The geographer can claim space as his o r
nation of two forms whose essential natures are given. her own only by abstracting space from its material
More frequently, disaster vulnerability is analysed as and social context, thereby granting it a metaphysical
if nature is neutral so that the environment is hazar- existence or ontological autonomy i t does not deserve.
dous only when it “intersects with people.”“” But In recent years, Marxists have criticized geo-
behind this positted neutrality of nature with respect to graphers for their “fetishism of space.” This fetishism
society is a clear technocratic agenda that seeks to con- makes “relations between people, social groups or
trol “natural” hazards by extending the human domi- classes appear as relations between areas or places.”43
nation of a supposedly external nature. So far as it goes, this critique is appropriate, but the
The third approach to hazards which reflects the Marxist literature has not yet developed an alternative
third method for dealing with the contradiction in the means for discussing space.44The theory of nature out-
positivist concept of nature, amounts to the dissolution lined schematically above offers insights into the com-
of human nature into external nature. Virtually Mal- position of this alternative understanding of space.
thusian in outlook , this approach notes that the poor If space is seen not as a fixed thing but as an aspect
are worst affected in most disasters, and attributes this of the relations between concrete pieces of matter (i.e.,
not only to the lack of resources commanded by the if we view space as relational), the theory of nature
poor, but especially to a tendency for the poor to breed holds within it an integral theory of space. We need no
too fast. This approach is a classic example of blaming longer view space as an “abstract universal,” whatever
the victim, and the policy recommendations accom- this means, but can now see i t as historically altered
panving it make this clear. The Malthusian logic leads along with the human alteration of nature. The pro-

37
duction of space, by which is meant the alteration of serves on the other side to annihilate this space with
spatial relations brought about by the simultaneous al- time, i.e., to reduce to a minimum the time spent in mo-
teration of the form of concrete pieces of matter, is an tion from one place to another.
integral part of the production of nature. Thus, with An abstract theory of the production of space
respect to "natural" disasters, the spatial pattern of would be as limited as an abstract theory of nature
famine changed fundamentally with the rise of capital- (above, pp. 3-4), and would risk the same philosophi-
ism. Once random, famine became systemic and spa- cal contradictions that eventually plagued Schmidt.
tially systematic, striking the underdeveloped world As with nature, a sophisticated understanding of how
most severely. Without stating the theory explicitly space is produced depends o n an equally sophisticated
Marx hints at a similar notion of the production of understanding of the capitalist mode of production.
space:45while capital must on one side strive to tear Space and place are produced as part of this mode of
down every spatial barrier to intercourse, i.e., to ex- ~ ~ understanding of uneven develop-
p r o d u ~ t i o n .An
change, and conquer the whole earth for its market, it ment is therefore central.

CONCLUSION

The capitalist mode of production can continue to of . . . Science to bring . . . science to the point where i t
produce nature - and. as a by-product, space - only so can be presented diale~tically."~' By thus retrieving the
long as it can continue to produce its own "natural" dialectic, science will also retrieve the politics of class
baqis: Labor on the one side, Capital on the other. To struggle which rightfully permeate its subject-matter,
grasp scientifically this relation with nature, it will be but which, under orthodox bourgeois conceptions of
necessary to do as Marx did: "through the critique science, are ideologically displaced.

NOTES

I . k")r ;I sketch! iiccount o f the wa? in which "nature" came his- f m ~ n o t e2. Glacken never discusses Hegel'\
toricall) to he applied to the w c i a l realm. see Louis Althusser's discus- . W . k . Hegel. T h e Philosoph,, of Right. ( L o n -
\ion t i t Monte\quieu i n Poliric.c and Hivtori.. (London: New Left don. O x f o r d Llniversit! P r e w 1952 edn.). p. 20.
Book\. 1972). Paradoxicall!. the concept o f nature I\ con\picuously 16. F. Engel\. T h e Dialecricc of 'Yature (Moscow: Progress Puh-
ahrent Iron1 the re\[ oI',Althu\scr'\ u o r k . lishers. 1972 edn.). p. 42.
1. Clarence Glacken. Traces on rhe Rhodian Shore. (Berkeley: 17. Georg l.ukac\. Hi,vrori. and Cla.s.\ C'otrvciDu.TIie.\.v. (Cambridge.
Oiii\cr\it! 01'California Pres\. 1967): R.G. Collingwood. The ldea of M a \ \ : MIT Pres\. 1971).
$ a / u r e , ( L o n d o n : O x f o r d University Press. 1965). See also C. 18. Schmidt. op. cir.. footnote 12, p. 43.
(;lacken. "Changing ldcas o f the Hahitahle World." in W . L . Thomas. 19. Schmidt. op. cit.. footnote 12. pp. 82. 27.
cd . Man'c. Role i n Changing rhe Face of the Earrh. (Chicago: Chicago 20. Schmidt. op. cir.. footnote 12. Ch. 4.
L ' n i \ c r \ i t ) Pres\. 1956). 21. F o r the Frankfurt School o n "the domination o f nature." \ee
3 . Cilacken. o p . cir.. footnote 2. p. 117. Herbert Marcuse. One Dinwrr.c.ional M a n . (London: Abacus, 1972):
4. Glacken. op. cir , footnote 2, p. 705. M a x Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno. The Eclipw of Reason. ( N e w
5. Neil Smith. "Geography. Science and Post-Positivist Mode\ o f Y o r k : Columhia University Press. 1947): Jurgen Hahermas. T o w a r d a
t \planation 4 Critical Revieu." P r o g r c r i n H u m a n Geographi,. 3. 3 Rarional Socier~.. (Bo\ton: Beacon Press. 1970).
(Scptemher. 1979). pp. 356-383. 22. M'illiam Leiss. The Donririatiorr of .liarure. (&)\ton: Beacon
h K a r l M a r x and Friedrich Engel\. The German ldeologi,. ( N e u Prcs\. 1974). p p 123, 122.
k ( i r k : International Publisher\. 1970 edn.). p. 59 2 3 Lei\\. o p c i r , , footnotc 22. pp. 110. 19X.
7 Glacken. ( ~ pcir., . footnote 2. pp. 550. 649. 21. Schmidt. o p . cir. lootnote 12. pp. 91. 93.
8 . M u r x and Engel\. o p c i r , , footnote 6, p. 63. 25. Marx. o p cir., f o ~ ) t n o r e 9p.. 355.
9 . K a r l Marx. Earli. W r i / i n ~ . y(Hamondsworth:
, Penguin, 1975). p. 26. Marx. o p c i r . , footnote 10. pp. 43. 71. I n this edition o f C'apiral
155.
... "Nature" i\ \<)metime\ capitali/ed in trandation. hut w e have decided
10. K a r l Marx. Capital. ( N e u York: International Publisher\. 1967 t o retain the l o n e r c:t\c. \ince i t i\ ; h a ) \ capitaliied in the German
edn.). Vol. I . p. 10. original h! dint of i t \ being a n o u n and l o r n o other apparent reason.
I I K a r l Marx. i'he l X r h Brurnaire o/ Louis Bonaparre. ( N e w T h i \ i\ in keeping with other translations.
Yorh: International Puhli\hcr\. I963 edn ). p. 15. 27 Marx. o p < , i r . , footni)tc 10. p. 33.
13. Paul Thomas. "Mars a n d Science." Polirical Sludies. Vol. 21. 2X. Marx. ~ p<,ir.. . I i o t n o t c 10. p. 177.
( 1976). pp. 1-23, 20. Alfred Schmidt. T h e Concept of Narure i n M u m 29. Schmidt. op. cir.. footnote I?.p. 12.
( l . o i i d o n . N e w I cft Book\). C h . 4. 30. Marx. o p cir., lootnote 10. p. 570.
13. F-riederich Engels. .Anti-Duhring, (London: Laurence and U i\- 3 I . I w i a h Bowman. Geographi. i n Relariotr / o / h e S ( ~ c i aScience.,.
l
hcirt. 1975 cdn ). p I h l . ( N e u Y o r k . Charles Scrihner. 1971).
1-1. t-ngcI\. quotcd i n Schmidl. o p . cir.. footnote 12. p. 13. 32. F o r ail a\\c\sment o f phenomenology in geograph! arid the di+

38
tinction between humanism and phenomenology see Smith, op. cit., Geography, Vol. 50, (1974). pp. 256-77.
footnote 5. 42. Marx, op. cit., footnote 10, Vol. I , p. 169 (emphasis added). Af-
33. Marx, op. cit.. footnote 10, Vol. 3, p. 820. For a more elaborate ter the I976 earthquake in Guatemala City there occurred an interest-
version of this argument, see Smith, N. ‘The Production of Nature’ ing illustration of the class relation with nature. Residents stopped
John Hopkins. Mimeo. talking of an earthquake and called it a “classquake.” See also P. Sus-
34. Marx & Engels. Feuerbach, (London: Lawrence and Wishart. man, P. O’Keefe, and B. Wisner, “Global Disasters: A Radical Ap-
1973). p. 15. proach,” in K. Hewitt, ed., Approoches to Notionol Hazard, (Water-
35. Marx, op. cit.. footnote 9, p. 355. loo, Ontario: W.ilfred Laurier University Press), forthcoming.
36. Wilbur Zelinsky, “The Demigod’s Dilemma,” Annals of the 43. Jim Anderson, The Political Economy of Urbanism, (London:
Association of American Geographers, Vol. 65, (1975). pp. 140, 125. Department of Planning, Architectural Association, 1975).
c.f. also: “the natural sciences are in a pre-social state,” David Har- 44. By 1978, Edward Soja could write: “Thus what could prove to
vey. Social Justice ond the City, (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univer- be the most significant implications of Marxian spatial analysis for
sity Press, 1973. 1973)- p. 127. both theory and practice are, I contend. being obfuscated throuph the
37. On the degradation of cultural landscapes see E. Relph. Place well-intended but short-sighted efforts of radical scholars to avoid the
and Placelessness, Pion. London. 1976. On science’s reaction to its fetishism o f space.” Edward W. Soja, “The Socio-Spatial Dialectic:
own occasional sterility, consider the reaction to Thomas Kuhn’s The Annals AAG, Vol. 70, 2 (1980). p. 208.
Structure of Scientific Revolutions, U. of Chicago Press, 1962. That 45. Marx, Grundrisse, (Hammondsworth: Penguin, 1973). p. 539.
this book was so ecstatically received is due to the relatively sophis- See a150 David Harvey, “The Geography of Capitalist Accumulation:
ticated way in which Kuhn explained scientific revolutions as the pro- A Reconstruction o f the Marxian Theory,” Antipode, Vol. 7.2.
duct of a dialectical process of development within science. But he (1975), pp. 9-21: reprinted in Richard Peet, ed.. Radical Geography,
managed to do so purely as an exercise in intellectual history, without (Chicago: Maroufa Press, 1977). pp. 263-92.
threatening the cherished autonomy of science from other human 46. Henri Lefebvre has pioneered the attempt to devise a theory o f
activity. Neither did he impose external social reality on the transub- the production of space, but it should be clear that his theory relies on
stantial psyches of practicing scientists, nor did he for a moment enter- a negation of nature and its replacement with “space“, rather than on
tain the dangerous idea that the dialectic had a place in natural scien- a theory of the production of nature. Despite the fact that he focures
tific inquiry itself, as opposed to the history of it. o n the producrion of space, Lefehvre ends u p with a somewhat similar
38. Rod Burgess, “The concept of Nature in Geography and dual conception to the o n e we found in Schmidt; except Lefebvre’s is a
Marxism.” Antipode. Vol. 10.2, (1978), p. 4. dual conception of space. On the one hand, space is a primordial
39. For a statement of this approach see E.A. Keller, Environmen- realm like time o r matter: on the other it is concrete and produced.
tal Geology (Columbus: Merrill. 1976). Lefehvre is unable to reconcile this dual conception because he intro-
40. The paradigmatic work in this approach is I. Burton, R.W. duces space within the problematic of reproduction not production.
Katcs. and G . F . White, The Environment as Hazard. (New York: Ox- The production of space is subordinated to the reproduction of social
ford University Press, 1978). relations. Henri Lefebvre, The Survival of Capitalism, Alison and
41. Among adherents to this approach see Garrett Hardin, “The Busby, London. 1976. S K Kalso Soja, op. cir,, footnote44.
Tragedy of Commons,“ Science. Vol. 162, (1968), pp. 1243-8. For a 47. Marx in a letter to Engels, February, 1858, quoted in Schmidt,
critique of Malthusian population doctrine see David Harvey, “Popu- op. cit., footnote 14. p. 52.
lation. ReSoUrcKS. and the Ideology of Science.’’ Economic

SUBSCRIPTION BLANK

Rates:

$20 Libraries/ In stituti on s


$15 Regular Subscription
$10 Student Subscription

Foreign Postage Charges:


Surface mail: a d d $5.00. Enclosed is a check or money order in the amount of

Name

Address

City State Zip


Send to: A N T I P O D E , Box 225, West Side Station, Worcester, Massachusetts 01602

39

You might also like