You are on page 1of 9

Rethinking the role of language

in embodied cognition
royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
Guy O. Dove
Department of Philosophy, University of Louisville, 313 Humanities Building, Louisville, KY 40292, USA
GOD, 0000-0003-0470-7006
Opinion piece There has been a lot of recent interest in the way that language might enhance
Cite this article: Dove GO. 2022 Rethinking embodied cognition. This interest is driven in large part by a growing body of
evidence implicating the language system in various aspects of semantic
the role of language in embodied cognition.
memory—including, but not limited to, its apparent contribution to abstract
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375.
concepts. In this essay, I develop and defend a novel account of the cognitive
https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2021.0375 role played by language in our concepts. This account relies on the embodied
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

nature of the language system itself, diverges in significant ways from


Received: 15 December 2021 traditional accounts, and is part of a flexible, multimodal and multilevel
view of our conceptual system.
Accepted: 26 June 2022
This article is part of the theme issue ‘Concepts in interaction: social
engagement and inner experiences’.
One contribution of 23 to a theme issue
‘Concepts in interaction: social engagement
and inner experiences’.
1. Introduction
Subject Areas: A robust and growing body of evidence suggests that conceptual processing is
neuroscience, cognition functionally reliant on action, emotion and perception systems [1–3]. In other
words, we think about the world by means of the same mechanisms that we
use to experience it. Our brains leverage representations indigenous to experi-
Keywords:
ential systems when encoding general knowledge and deploy these
concepts, cognition, embodied, grounded representations by means of a process of neural simulation or re-enactment.
cognition, language, semantic memory Given that a great deal of our experience involves language, it seems reasonable
to wonder whether language itself should be viewed as a significant source of embo-
diment. Despite the initial plausibility of this conjecture, researchers in embodied
Author for correspondence:
cognition have generally excluded language from their conception of embodiment
Guy O. Dove
[4]. This exclusion comes in two primary forms. The first explicitly denies that
e-mail: guy.dove@louisville.edu language contributes to conceptual processing and holds that language merely
engages simulations that are grounded in non-linguistic sensorimotor experience.
This theoretical perspective underlies the orthodox understanding of the term embo-
died language. The second acknowledges that language plays a role in our concepts
but treats it as a fundamentally disembodied symbol system that has no connection
to the mechanisms associated with embodiment. In other words, the appeal to
language is made in the context of embodied/symbolic hybrid approach.
Not everybody subscribes to this exclusion. For instance, some contend that
language serves as an external cognitive scaffold for embodied cognition [5,6].
Two recent theories of concepts, the word as social tool (WAT) theory [7,8] and
the language is an embodied neuroenhancement and scaffold of (LENS) theory
[9], go further and propose that language serves as fully realized source of embo-
diment. The purpose of this essay is to explore what this stronger hypothesis
means and why we should consider it. This critical assessment will be focused
solely on the theoretical potential of the linguistic embodiment hypothesis and
will not be concerned with analysing the similarities and differences between
the WAT and LENS theories (for a comparison of these theories, see [10]).

2. Language as an experiential modality


Embodied cognition is a broad research programme. As such, it encompasses a
variety of theoretical approaches that emphasize the ways in which the body

© 2022 The Author(s) Published by the Royal Society. All rights reserved.
influences thinking [11,12]. If language is a source of mode of experience suggests that conceptual content might 2
embodiment, concepts should rely in part on simulations of be captured in part by means of the simulation of aspects

royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
linguistic experience. of linguistic experience. Roughly put, we might engage in
Admittedly, this idea seems to be a nonstarter for several various forms of simulated talking to support thinking.
prima facie reasons. The experiential components of language The theoretical payoff of this move is that it provides an
seem ill suited to encoding semantic information about cat- integrated framework for understanding the diverse ways in
egories, abstract or concrete. First, the arbitrary connection which language might contribute to the conceptual system.
between words and their referents seems to fit poorly with For example, viewing language as an experiential modality
the apparent connection of embodiment to experiential ground- suggests the possibility that some concepts may be grounded
ing. Aside from iconic sound–meaning correspondences (which in the phonetic and/or motoric aspects of language. It thus
I will discuss below), words often seem to have a disembodied provides an explanation of how the iconicity of linguistic
relationship with the content they encode. Indeed, this arbitrari- symbols might contribute to their ability to encode semantic
ness seems to play an important role in language acquisition content. Going further, understanding the contribution of the
and language change. For instance, the English word hussy is language system to semantic memory as one of re-enactment

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375


descended from a contraction of the Middle English word for also provides a mechanism for understanding how the concep-
housewife [13]. The difference between its historical meaning tual system might leverage the symbolic properties of the
and its current one cannot be explained in terms of its experien- language. Neural reuse of experiential representations associ-
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

tial properties. Given the distal connection between words ated with language action and perception provides access to
and their referents, one might reasonably wonder about the embodied representations that are indirectly connected to
purported role of linguistic embodiment. their semantic content [14,15]. Finally, an embodied approach
Second, the sensorimotor properties of words do not appear also provides an explanation of how inner speech might be
to be fine-grained enough to capture meanings. After all, homo- used to retrieve discourse-related knowledge [10].
phones, homographs and homonyms share perceptual and The fact that much of our experience is mediated by
motor properties. The word bank can refer to a slope, a financial language raises the question of whether language might itself
institution, a flying manoeuver, the act of saving money, and so serve as a source of embodiment. The proposal under consider-
on. Clearly, the way this word sounds, how it is spelled, and the ation holds that the language system facilitates our capacity to
articulatory gestures by which it is produced fail to disambigu- encode semantic content in several important ways: iconic
ate any particular use of it. Standard approaches to language links between linguistic symbols and their content help us
processing handle ambiguity and polysemy by positing inde- acquire and use concepts, labels facilitate our ability to link
pendent semantic representations—usually thought to be together our diverse experiences, word-to-word associations
handled by a semantic code housed in amodal regions of the enable us draw inferences that go beyond our immediate
cortex—that are linked to word forms in a mental lexicon. experience, and knowledge linked to conversations and
Third, an embodied approach seems like an appeal to inner narratives help us to tailor concepts to specific contexts and
speech. A well-known problem with trying to capture meaning tasks. Many of these design features are likely to be particularly
in terms of inner speech is that this move seems to accomplish helpful with abstract concepts.
little more that shift the theoretical challenges up a level. Posit-
ing that actual speech is understood in terms of inner speech
just raises the question of how inner speech is understood. 3. A multimodal, multilevel and flexible
After all, it would be implausible to hold that inner speech is
comprehended by some inner homunculus. approach
These prima facie challenges may in part explain why To assess the possible contribution of language to embodied
researchers have been hesitant to view language itself as a cognition, we need to be clear about what embodiment entails.
source of embodiment. This essay is an attempt to overcome Consistent with the fact that embodied cognition is an active
this hesitancy. In it, I enumerate the empirical and theoretical and dynamic research programme, the notion of embodiment
reasons to include language within an embodied account of cog- has evolved over time. Early on, embodiment was tied to
nition. In other words, I argue that reconceiving the role of what has been called strong embodiment. This term refers to
language in embodied cognition is a promising research topic. accounts that limit simulations to primary sensorimotor areas.
One way to conceptualize the proposal that language is a What is central to a strongly embodied account of concepts is
source of embodiment is to think of the language system as a that conceptual processing involves modality-specific, lower-
kind of experiential modality. While this is not compatible level experiential representations. Many researchers have
with a view of embodiment that limits it to primary sensorimo- moved from a strong conception of embodiment to a weak con-
tor areas, it fits with the current recognition that experiential ception that is both fundamentally multimodal and multilevel.
systems often rely on multimodal regions. Few would argue, This shift has occurred for several reasons. First, it seems likely
for instance, that gustation is not a mode of experience because that embodied simulations include fundamentally multimodal
it is inherently multimodal. phenomena such a gustation and spatial processing. Second, a
At first, this reconceptualization might seem to be little wealth of research suggests that even primary sensory areas
more than a theoretical gimmick. What is to be gained by engage in multimodal processes. Indeed, the very notion
rethinking the language system in this way? I suggest that of primary sensory areas may be tied to a dated and neuroana-
it leads to specific hypotheses and provides a unified theoreti- tomically implausible bottom-up view of cortical functioning.
cal explanation for extant bodies of research that are currently Third, many studies implicate secondary rather than primary
balkanized. A core feature of embodied cognition is that it areas in conceptual processing.
proposes a neural mechanism for our concepts: experiential The notion of embodiment has also shifted on another
re-enactment or simulation. Reconceiving language as a front. Early accounts were generally committed to invariantism
with respect to conceptual content [16]. They proposed that Supporters of embodied cognition have followed Har- 3
concepts involved automatically elicited default general nad’s lead and posited that representations borrowed from

royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
knowledge about category members [17]. More recent accounts experiential systems provide a means of overcoming the
tend to emphasize the degree to which concepts are realized in symbol grounding problem. The idea itself is straightfor-
a task- and context-dependent fashion [18–20]. ward: neural reuse provides the cognitive system access to
Defending these shifts would take up too much space and representations that retain an appropriate connection to the
is beyond the purview of this essay. Instead, I am going to world and its contents. Consider the concept of a dog [28].
assume that they are warranted without argument. By these The hypothesis under consideration is that thinking about
lights, the embodiment of our concepts is multimodal, multile- dogs involves the selective reengagement of various visual,
vel and flexible [21]. The move to a more inclusive notion of auditory, olfactory and tactile experiences with them. This
embodiment—or so-called weak embodiment [22]—has clear reuse of the relevant perceptual or motor areas of the cortex
consequences for including language within an embodied ensures that the selected neural representations retain their
framework. For one, it enables simulations of language to pragmatic connection to their referents. Such neural simu-
involve representations that are tied to language action and lation enables cognitive processes to build on hard-won

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375


perception but are not contained within primary auditory, experiential connections to the world that have been gained
visual or motor areas. This is important because it allows for through sensorimotor experience.
a certain degree of abstractness with respect the question of The symbol grounding problem has become part of the
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

how, for example, words are represented. Words, idioms and origin story of embodied cognition. Unfortunately, there has
phrases can be seen as higher-level multimodal phenomena been a tendency to overinterpret the support that it provides
but still be part of embodied simulations. for embodied cognition [12]. Strictly speaking, it only rules
out purely symbolic accounts. In other words, it leaves
room for hybrid non-symbolic/symbolic accounts of various
types. While it may turn out that fully grounded concepts
4. Symbol grounding provide the most satisfying solution to the problem, inter-
Embodied cognition is often presented as a solution to the mediate solutions remain viable.
symbol grounding problem [1,23,24]. In this section, I am Proposing that language itself can serve as source of embo-
going to argue that the general antipathy to viewing language diment may seem to abandon the lessons of the symbol
as a source of embodiment may rest in part on a misinterpreta- grounding problem. After all, embodiment is typically associ-
tion of this problem. While it provides some justification for ated with the reuse of representations experientially linked to
embodied cognition in general, it does not settle specific issues the semantic content of our thoughts. Language, though, is a
such as whether some conceptual content is encoded by symbolic system whose symbols are connected to each other
means of the flexible neural reuse of linguistic representations. in various ways that are often not directly linked to their refer-
The symbol grounding problem is a theoretical challenge ential content. This worry is misplaced for two reasons. First,
that is incurred by computationalism [25]. Computationalism proposing that some semantic content is encoded by means
requires physical symbol manipulation governed by syntactic of the neural reuse of the language system does not deny that
rules [26,27]. For it to work as an account of thinking, these a great deal of semantic content is encoded in the reuse of
symbols must be semantically interpretable. The central ques- directly grounded representations. Instead, it simply proposes
tion is how they manage to be about objects and events in the that the same cognitive mechanism—i.e. neural reuse—may
world. The symbol grounding problem arises because com- deploy representations involved in linguistic action and per-
putationalism characterizes cognition merely in terms of the ception. For example, the multimodal simulation involved in
relations of symbols to other symbols. Harnad [25] asks us the application of the concept dog within a particular context
to imagine trying to learn Chinese as a second language might include linguistic representations associated with dogs.
solely by means of a Chinese-to-Chinese dictionary. Going Second, there are compelling reasons to think that our concep-
through the dictionary would lead to a kind of symbolic tual system must contain some representations that are not
merry-go-round that bounces from one meaningless symbol directly tied to experience. Because many abstract concepts
to another. Purely symbolic accounts of cognitive systems have referents that we do not directly perceive or manipulate
are in a similar situation because they do not have access to [7,29,30], it is not immediately clear how they can be grounded
anything other than other symbols. in action, emotion and perception systems [31,32]. In other
This is a general problem for computational approaches to words, embodied cognition faces a symbol ungrounding pro-
cognition. What it shows is that a system entirely defined in blem [33,34]. Language may help our conceptual system
terms of the relations between symbols struggles to maintain overcome this problem. The ability to think about democracies,
contact with the world. The obvious solution is to find some genes, or prime numbers may involve in part knowing how to
alternate way to connect some representations to their content. talk about them. Acknowledging this in no way undermines
Almost everyone agrees that experiential systems are the most the importance of more directly grounded neural simulations.
likely candidates to provide this connection. Where the dis- Indeed, it suggests that linguistic and non-linguistic factors will
agreement lies is in the relationship between these systems often work in concert [35,36].
and our concepts. Harnad argues that the common assumption
that theories of cognition developed in a top-down manner will
eventually make contact with theories of peripheral experien-
tial systems developed in a bottom-up manner, is 5. Iconicity
theoretically suspect. He proposes that a more promising Language involves the manipulation and perception of
approach involves intrinsically dedicated symbols that retain physical symbols. Speech production relies on rehearsed
their connection to the world. articulatory gestures and speech perception relies on our
multimodal capacity to anticipate and recognize the products enhance and transform our cognition in specific ways. I out- 4
of these gestures. Viewing language as a source of embodiment line three plausible candidates below.

royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
opens the possibility that the physical properties of linguistic One possibility is that words facilitate generalization.
symbols—i.e. the sights, sounds and motor features that realize They may serve as representational anchors that help stabilize
them—might contribute conceptual processing. In keeping and organize embodied simulations of experience [51,52].
with this suggestion, researchers have begun to examine Words (but not tones, sounds or emotion responses) have
the role that iconicity might play in our concepts. Iconicity is been found to help young children with object individuation
typically defined in terms of resemblances between the sensor- [53]. Verbal cues such as the word dog appear to activate
imotor properties of linguistic symbols and their semantic more general category representations than non-verbal cues
referents [37]. While onomatopoeia is perhaps the most fam- such as the sound of a dog barking [54,55].
iliar form of iconicity, other resemblance-based links between A second possibility is that words help us attend to
linguistic forms and meanings are possible. For example, the specific conceptual features. Support for this hypothesis is
sign for book in British sign language (BSL) involves mimicking provided by neuropsychological case studies indicating that
the leaves of a book [38]. aphasia can lead to impairments on non-linguistic tasks [56].

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375


A growing body of research finds that iconicity leads to Aphasics often struggle with taxonomic tasks that involve
facilitation effects in language production and comprehen- identifying a specific attribute rather than a global compari-
sion. Lexical decision is quicker with iconic English words son [57,58]. One study compared the responses of 12
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

than non-iconic ones [39]. Iconic BSL signs are produced aphasics with that of 12 age and education matched controls
faster than non-iconic ones [40]. A substantial body of on a categorization task [59]. The aphasics were impaired on
research also indicates that iconicity makes important contri- low-dimensional versions of the task (e.g. things that are
butions to word learning [41]. Intriguing crosslinguistic green) but not on the high-dimensional versions (e.g. farm
sound-symbolism patterns have been observed. For instance, animals). A related study using neurologically intact partici-
a robust body of evidence supports the existence of the pants found a similarly selective impairment was induced
bouba-kiki effect: the tendency to associate the nonce word by a verbal interference task [60].
bouba with a round shape and the nonce word kiki with a An embodied perspective not only predicts that the pres-
spiky shape [42]. Words with the /i:/ phoneme (like gleam) ence of a word should alter how we conceptualize a category
have been found to be generically associated with more posi- but also predicts that words themselves should be under-
tive emotionality than words with the /ʌ/ phoneme (like stood in a way that is tied to situations. A third possibility
glum) [43]. Iconicity seems to be especially important in the is that words may engage background frames or schemas
early stages of word acquisition. Children learning English [61]. For instance, the meanings of the English words buy,
or Spanish, for instance, tend to acquire words that receive cost, pay and sell are all understood relative to a commercial
high iconicity ratings before they acquire words that are event frame. A word like vegetarian makes sense in a society
low in iconicity ratings [44]. This developmental evidence where many people eat meat.
fits with the proposal that children can use iconicity to In sum, viewing language as a component of multimodal
bootstrap semantic content [45]. embodied cognition supports three hypotheses concerning
Murgiano et al. [46] offer an embodied interpretation of the role that words might play in cognitive tasks. First, as
iconicity. Drawing a contrast between systemic and situated labels, they may help us generalize away from experiential
views of language, they argue that psycholinguists have over- particulars. Second, their presence might actively modulate
whelmingly adopted the former and this has led to them our categorization processes. Third, their connection to
focus almost entirely on the structural properties of language. frames and schemas may generate expectations and influence
A situated approach maintains that this structure emerges our conceptualization of objects and events. These multimodal
in specific acts of communication that are carried out in phys- connections provide a solution to one of our initial prima facie
ical and social contexts. The situated nature of language problems faced by the hypothesis that words serve as source of
enables interlocutors to leverage embodied resources to embodiment. Words help link together non-linguistically
convey meaning [47]. embodied content. Homonyms, homographs and homonyms
One of the reasons for the recent interest in the cognitive can be distinguished by their different associations.
role of language in embodied cognition is the perception that
language may help explain how we can acquire and use
abstract concepts [15,48]. An intriguing feature of the research
on iconicity is that it appears to show that the sensorimotor 7. A structured symbol system
properties of language can help with the acquisition of con- One of the theoretical challenges faced by the hypothesis that
crete concepts. Iconicity turns out to be a reliable predictor language is a source of embodiment is that, at least from a
of age of acquisition [44]. Moreover, the use of iconic words certain perspective, linguistic symbols appear to be funda-
tends to fade as children acquire larger vocabularies with mentally ungrounded. After all, they do not enjoy the sort
more abstract words in them [49]. Lupyan & Winter [50] go of immediate experiential connection to their referents that
as far as to suggest that iconicity is inimical to abstraction. other embodied representations do. Even iconicity relies on
indirect forms of connection. This distal connection is pre-
cisely what makes language special. Linguistic symbols are
embodied in the sense that they are intimately connected to
6. Word and concept actions carried out in communicative situations. Moreover,
Viewing language as a component of multimodal embodied they are physical symbols that require a suite of associated
cognition suggests that the presence, or indeed the absence, sensorimotor capacities. This form of embodiment, though,
of words should influence our reasoning. Words should allows for arbitrary semantic reference.
Language is an external symbol system that enables us to corpus approach, these models provide a proof of concept 5
leverage culturally derived information. It manages to serve with respect to the idea that the statistical properties of

royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
as a scaffold for semantic memory precisely because it is language provide a rich source of information about the
shared and external. Clark [5,6] points out that language world. Some researchers have adopted an explicitly multi-
alters our cognitive niche by providing a novel set of targets modal approach that views linguistic and non-linguistic
for action and perception. By these lights, language is an experiences as complimentary sources of conceptual infor-
accessible external support for embodied cognition. It is as mation [74,75]. Hybrid models exploiting both experiential
external symbol system that can be manipulated in an embo- and language-based distributional data have been shown to
died way to extend our cognitive reach. be more effective than models that rely on only one of these
Viewing language as an experiential modality builds on resources [76,77].
Clark’s insights, but it also emphasizes the degree to which Concepts are thought to underwrite several cognitive
the sensorimotor skills associated with the manipulation of activities. It may be useful to distinguish between referential
public symbols provides an internal means of capturing and inferential aspects of semantic competence [78]. Referen-
semantic content [9]. Becoming a speaker of a language tial competence concerns the relations of words to objects and

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375


requires the development of a suite of embodied skills. A events in the world, and inferential competence concerns the
child learning a language needs to learn how the phonologi- relations of words to other words. Calzavarini [79] argues
cal units of a language are produced and recognized, how that neuropsychological case studies suggest that these com-
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

morphemes containing these elements are combined to petences are supported by independent neuro-mechanisms.
form words, how words are combined to form phrases and In particular, he identifies a double disassociation between
sentences, and how sentences can be combined to form these competences. He points out that patients with visual
larger forms of discourse. associative agnosia and optic aphasia often exhibit a selective
The linguistic embodiment hypothesis proposes that the deficit with referential skills but retain inferential ones. Cases
brain encodes some conceptual content in the neurologically of a selective impairment of inferential skills are rarer but still
realized language system. Language provides representational attested. One that is particularly suggestive is the case of an
opportunities that would not be available otherwise. As a 86-year-old man with left hemisphere damage from an
stimulus-independent combinatorial system, it enhances our ischemic stroke who performed well on a referential
cognitive capacities in at least four ways [62]. First, its public naming task but poorly on an inferential definition task [80].
nature expands our conceptual range by giving us access to A multimodal embodied approach that includes the
information gathered by other people. Second, its stimulus language system provides an appealing explanation of this
independence enables us to apply the same concept in diverse phenomenon. There are reasons to think that linguistic
situations. Third, its transparent syntactic structure offers competence involves inferential skills that are tied to its com-
opportunities to recognize new semantic connections by allow- binatorial properties. Consider Chomksky’s famous sentence,
ing us to formulate novel thoughts. Fourth, its combinatorial Colorless green ideas sleep furiously [81]. Weiskopf [82] points
properties enable us to recognize the inferential relations out that even though this sentence is difficult to perceptually
among concepts. simulate, we do not have trouble understanding what would
A multimodal perspective predicts that individuals may follow from its truth: namely, that something slept and did so
differ in how they encode individual concepts. A cat-lover furiously, that ideas can be green and colourless, and so on.
may have a lot of fine-grained experiential knowledge about Presumably, our capacity to make these inferences is tied to
the behaviour of domestic cats while a scientist who studies the syntactic structure of the sentence and the symbolic prop-
domestic cats may have more verbally mediated knowledge erties of the words. An inclusive conception of embodiment
about them. In addition, some concepts may generally rely enables us to postulate that both linguistic and non-linguistic
more on verbal information than others. For example, emotion- simulations can be selectively impaired or preserved.
ally neutral abstract concepts may be particularly dependent
on language [41].
The ability of congenitally blind individuals to acquire a
sophisticated understanding of colour concepts [63–65] pro- 8. Inner speech
vides compelling support for a multimodal approach to Treating language as a source of embodiment raises questions
semantic memory that incudes information contained within concerning the cognitive role of inner speech. While embo-
the language system. This hypothesis is bolstered by a recent died theories of conceptual content focus primarily on the
demonstration that a significant amount of information about contribution of unconscious processing, they also acknowl-
colour concepts can be gleaned from the distributional struc- edge a connection between this processing and conscious
ture of colour language [66,67]. Further support is provided mental imagery. In other words, there is a general recognition
by a recent study implicating a region of the left dorsal anterior that conscious multimodal simulations of experience may be
temporal lobe (ATL) in the knowledge of object colours in both useful in certain cognitive and metacognitive circumstances.
early blind participants and sighted controls [68]. If we treat language as an experiential modality, then we
Distributional models of semantic memory propose that should expect a similar cline with respect to linguistically
our knowledge of word meaning is derived from the statistical embodied thought. There should be circumstances under
associations between words. These models propose that the which conscious simulations of language of various stripes
meaning of a word is determined in large part by the company are useful and effective.
that it keeps [69]. They typically extract statistical regularities This idea has historical precedents. Vygotsky [83] pro-
from large corpuses of natural speech [70–72] and have been posed that internalizations of linguistic experience scaffold
shown to perform well on lexical access and similarity tasks learning and memory. A robust body of evidence involving
[73]. Despite the developmental implausibility of the large typically developing children and special populations
supports the claim that inner speech contributes to learning [104]. Within the literature, there has been an active discus- 6
and problem solving [84]. Importantly, the relevant uses of sion concerning possible hemispheric specialization of the

royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
linguistic imagery come in several forms that vary in terms ATLs [105]. Some researchers propose that the left ATL pre-
of their complexity and extent—spanning from fully formed ferentially represents information associated with verbal
self-directed speech to highly condensed brief segments [85]. inputs whereas the right ATL represents information associ-
Borghi et al. [86] have recently developed an approach to ated with non-verbal inputs [106–108]. Others propose that
inner speech that explicitly treats it as a form of embodied the left ATL generally handles word retrieval and that the
cognition and offers an innovative account of its functional- right ATL generally handles visual recognition [109,110].
ity. They propose that inner speech helps individuals Researchers have begun to recognize that abstract concepts
monitor their conceptual content and engage in what they are heterogeneous [111]. Moreover, individual concepts may
refer to as socially oriented metacognition. This approach vary in terms of their relative abstractness in different situ-
builds on the insight that we tend to be less certain about ations and contexts [112]. Fortunately, the hypothesis under
the content of abstract concepts [87,88]. A consequence of consideration does not rest on the abstract/concrete distinc-
this uncertainty is that we tend to rely more on others for tion. While the conjecture that language may serve as a

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375


an understanding of their meaning [89]. Inner speech can source of embodiment is in part driven by a need to explain
help us manage this uncertainty in a couple of ways [90]. our facility with abstract concepts, much of the evidence impli-
First, it can help us monitor our own concepts by enabling cating the functional importance of language outlined in the
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

us to trace a word’s meaning through its connections to earlier sections of this paper involved concrete concepts. By
other words. Rehearsing words in working memory can these lights, the greater reliance of (some) abstract concepts
help us evaluate our understanding in an online fashion. on language provides a means of highlighting the functional
Second, inner speech can engage discourse-related knowl- contribution of language to conceptual processing.
edge by simulating potential conversations concerning the Embodiment is a task-sensitive phenomenon. This raises
concept. In other words, it can be used as part of an inner the possibility that certain tasks should engage the language
dialogue about the contents of our thoughts. system more than others. As discussed earlier, there are
reasons to think that language should be more important
for inferential tasks than for referential ones. Some neuroima-
ging studies have found selective activation of the left ATL by
9. Neural correlates inferential naming tasks [113,114]. A different study failed to
The hypothesis under consideration is that our concepts are find this activation but found instead increases in other tem-
embodied in neural simulations of experience that are flex- poral regions, particularly the left posterior middle temporal
ible, multilevel and multimodal. What distinguishes the gyrus ( pMTG) [115]. Intriguingly, the left pMTG is a com-
linguistic embodiment is the claim that these simulations ponent of the language system and relevant to language
can include elements of linguistic experience. This creates a comprehension [116].
clear neuroanatomical prediction: the language system In the end, the available neuroimaging evidence is sugges-
should play a causal role in conceptual processing. tive but somewhat equivocal. The observed neural correlates fit
Given that many of the tasks used to study concepts are with the current proposal, but alternative explanations are
themselves linguistic, it can be difficult to disentangle the influ- available. For example, an extensive literature suggests that
ence of the language system on conceptual processing from its the ATLs are trans-modal hubs for conceptual knowledge
contribution to decoding the experimental stimuli and generat- [117]. Whether this represents a complete alternative to the lin-
ing the responses. One way to overcome this difficulty is guistic embodiment hypothesis is not fully clear. Trans-modal
to examine concepts that might differ in their reliance on hubs could be an extralinguistic means of organizing stored
language. In keeping with this, a body of literature has found semantic knowledge. However, a hybrid approach that
evidence that the language system is more active with abstract acknowledges existence of such hubs but remains committed
concepts than it is with concrete concepts. Meta-analyses of the to the causal relevance of the language system also seems poss-
available neuroimaging data find that the left inferior frontal ible. Broadly speaking, the neuroanatomical evidence fits well
gyrus (IFG) and middle/superior regions of the left ATL with linguistic embodiment, but many important details have
show greater activation with abstract concepts than with con- yet to filled in. Of particular importance are the functional
crete ones [91,92]. Lexical decision accuracy has been found contributions of specific subregions of the relevant cortical
to be selectively impaired with abstract concepts when repeti- areas. A promising feature of viewing language as a target of
tive trans-cranial magnetic stimulation is applied over the left flexible simulation is that it provides a theoretical framework
IFG and the left superior temporal gyrus [93]. for assessing the relative functional contributions of these
An extensive literature implicates these areas in language areas. This approach enables us to entertain different hypo-
processing. The left IFG, which includes Broca’s area, has theses concerning the contribution of different subregions of
been linked to phonological [94] and syntactic processing the left ATL. For instance, some of these subregions might
[95,96]. Neuroimaging implicates anterior subregions with encode discourse-related information that contributes to the
semantic processing [97–99]. Transcranial magnetic stimulation task- and context-sensitivity of our concepts [30].
studies further implicate these regions in the processing of word
meanings [100,101]. Some researchers propose that they con-
tribute to the retrieval and selection of semantic knowledge
[102,103]. 10. Conclusion
The left superior ATL has been linked to high-level speech Embodied cognition has taken a linguistic turn. Several recent
processing and sentence comprehension [84,85]. It may be theories propose that language plays a functional role in our
involved in sentence-level compositional semantic processing concepts. Some examples are the embodied conceptual
combination theory [118], the language and situated simu- a category, that some conceptual content should be encoded 7
lation theory [119], the language and associations in in the relations of words to other words, and that inner

royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
thinking theory [120] and the symbol interdependency speech should help us resolve uncertainty about our con-
theory [73]. Many of these theories treat language as a disem- cepts. Further support is provided by the fact that abstract
bodied form of symbolic cognition. Two recent theories, the concepts and inferential tasks elicit greater activation in the
WAT theory [7] and the LENS theory [9], buck this trend language system than concrete concepts and referential
and treat language as a source of embodiment. tasks, respectively.
In this essay, I have critically examined the linguistic
embodiment hypothesis on its own. This hypothesis gener-
ates several promising predictions that enjoy a degree of Data accessibility. This article has no additional data.
empirical support: namely, that iconicity should make impor- Authors’ contributions. G.D.: conceptualization.
tant contributions to concept acquisition and use, that the Conflict of interest declaration. I declare I have no competing interests.
presence of a label should influence how we conceptualize Funding. No funding has been received for this article.

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375


References
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

1. Barsalou LW. 2008 Embodied cognition. Annu. Rev. 15. Dove GO. 2014 Thinking in words: language as an 25. Harnad S. 1990 The symbol grounding problem.
Psychol. 59, 617–645. (doi:10.1146/annurev.psych. embodied medium of thought. Top. Cogn. Sci. 6, Physica D 42, 335–346. (doi:10.1016/0167-
59.103006.093639) 371–389. (doi:10.1111/tops.12102) 2789(90)90087-6)
2. Fischer MH, Zwaan RA. 2008 Embodied language: a 16. Gallese V, Lakoff G. 2005 The brain’s concepts: the 26. Fodor JA. 1975 The language of thought.
review of the motor system in language role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
comprehension. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 6, 825–850. knowledge. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 22, 455–479. 27. Pylyshyn ZW. 1984 Computation and cognition:
(doi:10.1080/17470210701623605) (doi:10.1080/02643290442000310) toward a foundation for cognitive science.
3. Kiefer M, Pulvermüller F. 2012 Conceptual 17. Machery E. 2015 By default. In The conceptual mind: Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
representations in mind and brain: theoretical new directions in the study of concepts (eds S. 28. Prinz JJ. 2002 Furnishing the mind: concepts and
developments, current evidence, and future Laurence, E. Margolis), pp. 567–588. Cambridge, their perceptual basis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
directions. Cortex 48, 805–825. (doi:10.1016/j. MA: MIT Press. 29. Borghi AM, Binkofski F, Castelfranchi C, Cimatti F,
cortex.2011.04.006) 18. Barsalou LW. 2016 Situated conceptualization: Scorolli C, Tummolini L. 2017 The challenge of
4. Borghi AM. 2020 A future of words: language and theory and applications. In Foundations of embodied abstract concepts. Psychol. Bull. 143, 263–292.
the challenge of abstract concepts. J. Cogn. 3, 42. cognition, volume 1: perceptual and emotional (doi:10.1037/bul0000089)
(doi:10.5334/joc.134) embodiment (eds Y Coello, MH Fischer), pp. 11–37. 30. Dove G. 2021 The challenges of abstract concepts. In
5. Clark A. 2006 Language, embodiment, and the Hove, UK: Psychology Press. Handbook of embodied psychology (eds M. D.
cognitive niche. Trends Cogn. Sci. 10, 370–374. 19. Casasanto D, Lupyan G. 2015 All concepts are ad Robinson, L. E. Thomas), pp. 171–195. New York,
(doi:10.1016/j.tics.2006.06.012) hoc concepts. In The conceptual mind: new NY: Springer.
6. Clark A. 2008 Supersizing the mind: embodiment, directions in the study of concepts (eds E. Margolis, 31. Chatterjee A. 2010 Disembodying cognition.
action, and cognitive extension. Oxford, UK: Oxford S. Laurence), pp. 543–566. Cambridge, MA: Lang. Cogn. 2, 79–116. (doi:10.1515/langcog.
University Press. MIT Press. 2010.004)
7. Borghi A, Binkofski F. 2014 Words as social tools: an 20. Connell L, Lynott D. 2014 Principles of 32. Mahon BZ. 2015 What is embodied about
embodied view on abstract concepts. New York, NY: representation: why you can’t represent the same cognition? Lang. Cogn. Neurosci. 30, 420–429.
Springer. concept twice. Top. Cogn. Sci. 6, 390–406. (doi:10. (doi:10.1080/23273798.2014.987791)
8. Borghi AM, Cimatti F. 2009 Words as tools and the 1111/tops.12097) 33. Dove G. 2016 Three symbol ungrounding problems:
problem of abstract words meanings. In Proc. of the 21. Kemmerer D. 2015 Are the motor features of verb abstract concepts and the future of embodied
31st Annual Conf. of the Cognitive Science Society (eds meanings represented in the precentral motor cognition. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 23, 1109–1121.
N. Taatgen, H. van Rijn), pp. 2304–2309. Amsterdam, cortices? Yes, but within the context of a flexible, (doi:10.3758/s13423-015-0825-4)
The Netherlands: Cognitive Science Society. multilevel architecture for conceptual knowledge. 34. Dove G. 2022 Abstract concepts and the embodied
9. Dove GO. 2019 More than a scaffold: language is a Psychon. Bull. Rev. 22, 10 680–11 075. (doi:10. mind: rethinking grounded cognition. Oxford, UK:
neuroenhancement. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 37, 1–24. 3758/s13423-014-0784-1) Oxford University Press.
(doi:10.1080/02643294.2019.1637338) 22. Tirado C, Khatin-Zadeh O, Gatelum M, Jones NL, 35. Günther F, Dudschig C, Kaup B. 2018 Symbol
10. Dove GO, Barca L, Tummolini L, Borghi AM. 2020 Words Marmolejo-Ramos F. 2018 The strength of weak grounding without direct experience; do words
have a weight: language as a source of inner embodiment. Int. J. Psychol. Res. 11, 77–85. inherit sensorimotor activation from purely linguistic
embodiment and flexibility in abstract concepts. (doi:10.21500/20112084.3420) context? Cogn. Sci. 42(Suppl 2), 336–374. (doi:10.
Psychol. Res. 1–17. (doi:10.1007/s00426-020-01438-6) 23. Glenberg AM, Robertson DA. 2000 Symbol 1111/cogs.12549)
11. Anderson ML. 2003 Embodied cognition: a field grounding and meaning: a comparison of high- 36. Günther F, Nguyen T, Chen L, Dudschig C, Kaup B,
guide. Artif. Intell. 149, 91–130. (doi:10.1016/ dimensional and embodied theories of meaning. Glenberg AM. 2020 Immediate sensorimotor
S0004-3702(03)00054-7) J. Memory Lang. 43, 379–401. (doi:10.1006/jmla. grounding of novel concepts learned from language
12. Shapiro L. 2019 Embodied cognition, 2nd edn. 2000.2714) alone. J. Memory Lang. 115, 104172, 1–9. (doi:10.
New York, NY: Routledge. 24. Zwaan RA, Madden CJ. 2005 Embodied sentence 1016/j.jml.2020.104172)
13. Hussy n.d. In Oxford English Dictionary. Retrieved 15 comprehension. In Grounding cognition: the role of 37. Dingemanse M, Blasi DE, Lupyan G, Christiansen
December 2021. perception and action in memory, language, and MH, Monaghan P. 2015 Arbitrariness, iconicity, and
14. Dove GO. 2011 On the need for embodied and dis- thought (eds D. Pecher, R. Zwaan), pp. 224–245. systematicity in language. Trends Cogn. Sci. 19,
embodied cognition. Front. Cogn. 1, 242. 1–13. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. 603–615. (doi:10.1016/j.tics.2015.07.013)
38. Thompson RL, Vinson DP, Woll B, Vigliocco G. 2012 54. Edmiston P, Lupyan G. 2015 What makes words knowledge. Psychol. Rev. 104, 211–240. (doi:10. 8
The road to language learning is iconic: evidence special? Words as unmotivated cues. Cognition 143, 1037/0033-295X.104.2.211)

royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
from British sign language. Psychol. Sci. 23, 93–100. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2015.06.008) 72. Lund K, Burgess C. 1996 Producing high-
1443–1448. (doi:10.1177/0956797612459763) 55. Lupyan G, Bergen B. 2015 How language programs dimensional semantic spaces from lexical co-
39. Sidhu DM, Vigliocco G, Pexman PM. 2020 the mind. Top. Cogn. Sci. 8, 408–424. (doi:10.1111/ occurrence. Behav. Res. Methods, Instrum. Comput.
Effects of iconicity in lexical decision. tops.12155) 28, 203–208. (doi:10.3758/BF03204766)
Lang. Cogn. 12, 164–181. (doi:10.1017/ 56. Noppeney U, Wallesch C-W. 2000 Language and 73. Louwerse M. 2011 Symbol interdependency in
langcog.2019.36) cognition: Kurt Goldstein’s theory of semantics. symbolic and embodied cognition. Top. Cogn. Sci. 3,
40. Meteyard L, Stoppard E, Snudden D, Cappa SF, Brain Lang. 44, 367–386. 273–302. (doi:10.1111/j.1756-8765.2010.01106.x)
Vigliocco G. 2015 When semantics aids phonology: 57. Davidoff J, Roberson D. 2004 Preserved thematic 74. Andrews M, Frank S, Vigliocco G. 2014 Reconciling
a processing advantage for iconic word forms in and impaired taxonomic categorization: a case embodied and distributional accounts of meaning in
aphasia. Neuropsychologia 76, 264–275. (doi:10. study. Lang. Cogn. Process. 19, 137–174. (doi:10. language. Top. Cogn. Sci. 6, 359–370. (doi:10.1111/
1016/j.neuropsychologia.2015.01.042) 1080/01690960344000125) tops.12096)
41. Reggin LD, Muraki EJ, Pexman PM. 2021 58. Semenza C, Bisiacchi PS, Romani L. 1992 Naming 75. Louwerse MM, Jeuniaux P. 2010 The linguistic and

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375


Development of abstract word knowledge. Front. disorders and semantic representations. embodied nature of conceptual processing.
Psychol. 12, 686478, 1–11. (doi:10.3389/fpsyg. J. Psycholinguist. Res. 21, 349–364. (doi:10.1007/ Cognition 114, 96–104. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.
2021.686478) BF01067920) 2009.09.002)
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

42. Cwiek A et al. 2021 The bouba/kiki effect is robust 59. Lupyan G, Mirman D. 2013 Linking language and 76. Andrews M, Vigliocco G, Vinson D. 2009 Integrating
across cultures and writing systems. Phil. Trans. R. categorization: evidence from aphasia. Cortex 49, experiential and distributional data to learn
Soc. B 377, 202003930. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2020. 1187–1194. (doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2012.06.006) semantic representations. Psychol. Rev. 116,
0390) 60. Lupyan G. 2009 Extracommunicative functions of 463–498. (doi:10.1037/a0016261)
43. Yu CS-P, McBeath MK, Glenberg AM. 2021 The language: verbal interference causes selective 77. Bruni E, Tran NK, Baroni M. 2014 Multimodal
gleam-glum effect: /i:/ versus /λ/ phonemes categorization impairments. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 16, distributional semantics. J. Artif. Intell. Res. 49,
generically carry emotional valence. J. Exp. Psychol. 711–718. (doi:10.3758/PBR.16.4.711) 1–47. (doi:10.1613/jair.4135)
Learn. Memory Cogn. 47, 1173–1185. (doi:10.1037/ 61. Fillmore CJ. 1985 Frames and the semantics of 78. Marconi D. 1997 Lexical competence. Cambridge,
xlm0001017) understanding. Quaderni Semantica 6, 222–254. MA: MIT Press.
44. Perry LK, Perlman M, Lupyan G. 2015 Iconicity in 62. Camp E. 2009 Putting thoughts to work: concepts, 79. Calzavarini F. 2017 Inferential and referential lexical
English and Spanish and its relation to lexical systematicity, and stimulus-independence. Phil. semantic competence: a critical review of the
category and age of acquisition. PLoS ONE 10, Phenomenol. Res. 78, 275–311. (doi:10.1111/j. supporting evidence. Neurolinguistics 44, 163–189.
e0137147, 1–17. (doi:10.1371/journal.pone. 1933-1592.2009.00245.x) (doi:10.1016/jneuroling_2017.04.002)
0137147) 63. Bedny M, Koster-Hale J, Elli G, Yazzolino L, Saxe R. 80. Pandey AK, Heilman KM. 2014 Conduction aphasia
45. Imai M, Kita S, Nagumo M, Okada H. 2008 Sound 2019 There’s more to ‘sparkle’ than meets the eye: with intact visual object naming. Cogn. Behav.
symbolism facilitates early verb learning. Cognition knowledge of vision and light verbs among Neurol. 27, 96–101. (doi:10.1097/WNN.
109, 54–65. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2008.07.015) congenitally blind and sighted individuals. Cognition 0000000000000029)
46. Murgiano M, Motamedi Y, Vigliocco G. 2021 189, 105–115. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2019.03. 81. Chomsky N. 1957 Syntactic structures. The Hague,
Situating language in the real-world: the role of 017) The Netherlands: Mouton.
multimodal iconicity and indexicality. J. Cogn. 4, 38, 64. Dimitrova-Radojichikj D. 2015 Concepts of colors in 82. Weiskopf D. 2010 Embodied cognition and linguistic
1–18. (doi:10.5334/joc.113) children with congenital blindness. J. Special Educ. comprehension. Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 41, 294–304.
47. Bohn M, Köymen B. 2018 Common ground and Rehabil. 16, 7–16. (doi:10.1515/jser-2015-0001) (doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.07.005)
development. Child Dev. Perspect. 12, 104–108. 65. Lenci A, Baroni M, Cazzolli G, Marotta G. 2013 83. Vygotsky L. 2012 Thought and language (revised
(doi:10.1111/cdep.12269) BLIND: a set of semantic feature norms from the and expanded.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
48. Dove G. 2018 Language as a disruptive technology: congenitally blind. Behav. Res. Methods 45, 84. Alderson-Day B, Fernyhough C. 2015 Inner speech:
abstract concepts, embodiment, and the flexible 1218–1233. (doi:10.3758/s13428-013-0323-4) development, cognitive functions, phenomenology,
mind. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 373, 20170135. (doi:10. 66. Kim JS, Elli GV, Bedny M. 2019 Knowledge of and neurobiology. Psychol. Bull. 141, 931–965.
1098/rstb.2017.0135) animal appearance among sighted and blind adults. (doi:10.1037/bul0000021)
49. Perry LK, Perlman M, Winter B, Massaro DW, Lupyan Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 116, 11 213–11 222. 85. McCarthy-Jones S, Fernyhough C. 2011 The
G. 2018 Iconicity in the speech of children and adults. (doi:10.1073/pnas.1900952116) varieties of inner speech: links between
Dev. Sci. 21, e12572. (doi:10.1111/desc.12572) 67. Lewis M, Zettersten M, Lupyan G. 2019 quality of inner speech and psychopathological
50. Lupyan G, Winter B. 2018 Language is more Distributional semantics as a source of visual variables in a sample of young adults. Conscious
abstract than you think, or, why aren’t languages knowledge. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 116, 19 Cogn. 20, 1586–1593. (doi:10.1016/j.concog.2011.
more iconic? Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 373, 20170137. 237–19 238. (doi:10.1073/pnas.1910148116) 08.005)
(doi:10.1098/rstb.2017.0137) 68. Wang X, Men W, Gao J, Caramazza A, Bi Y. 2020 86. Borghi AM, Barca L, Binkofski F, Castelfranchi C,
51. Pulvermüller F. 2013 How neurons make meaning: Two forms of knowledge representation in the Pezzulo G, Tummolini L. 2019 Words as social tools:
brain mechanisms for embodied and abstract- human brain. Neuron 107, 383–393.e5. (doi:10. language, sociality and inner embodiment in
symbolic semantics. Trends Cogn. Sci. 17, 458–470. 1016/j.neuron.2020.04.010) abstract concepts. Phys. Life Rev. 29, 120–153.
(doi:10.1016/j.tics.2013.06.004) 69. Firth JR. 1957 Papers in linguistics 1934–1951. (doi:10.1016/j.plrev.2018.12.001)
52. Pulvermüller F. 2017 Neural reuse of action London, UK: Oxford University Press. 87. Shea N. 2018 Metacognition and abstract concepts.
perception circuits for language, concepts, and 70. Blei DM, Ng AY, Jordan MI. 2003 Latent Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 373, 20170133, 1–7. (doi:10.
communication. Prog. Neurobiol. 160, 1–44. Dirichlet allocation. J. Mach. Learn. Res. 3, 1098/rstb.2017.0133)
(doi:10.1016/j.pneurobio.2017.07.001) 993–1022. 88. Villani C, Lugli L, Liuzza MT, Borghi AM. 2019
53. Xu F. 2002 The role of language in acquiring object 71. Landauer TK, Dumais ST. 1997 A solution to Plato’s Varieties of abstract concepts and their multiple
kind concepts in infancy. Cognition 85, 223–250. problem: the Latent Semantic Analysis theory of dimensions. Lang. Cogn. 11, 403–430. (doi:10.
(doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(02)00109-9) acquisition, induction and representation of 1017/langcog.2019.23)
89. Borghi AM, Flumini A, Cimatti F, Marocco D, Scorolli Neuropsychologia 43, 807–814. (doi:10.1016/j. 110. Drane DL et al. 2013 Famous face identification in 9
C. 2011 Manipulating objects and telling words: a neuropsychologia.2004.09.007) temporal lobe epilepsy: support for a multimodal

royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb
study on concrete and abstract words acquisition. 100. Devlin JT, Matthews PM, Rushworth MF. 2003 integration model of semantic memory. Cortex 49,
Front. Psychol. 2, 15. (doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2011. Semantic processing in the left inferior prefrontal 1648–1667. (doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2012.08.009)
00015) cortex: a combined functional magnetic resonance 111. Borghi AM, Barca L, Binkofski F, Tummolini L. 2018
90. Borghi A, Fernyhough C. 2022 Concepts, imaging and transcranial magnetic stimulation Varieties of abstract concepts: development, use and
abstractness, and inner speech. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B study. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 15, 71–84. (doi:10.1162/ representation in the brain. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B
378, 20210371.R1. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2021-0371.R1) 089892903321107837) 373, 20170121. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2017.0121)
91. Binder JR, Desai RH, Graves WW, Conant LL. 2009 101. Zhu Z, Gold BT, Chang CF, Wang S, Juan CH. 2015 Left 112. Barsalou LW, Dutriaux L, Scheepers C. 2018 Moving
Where is the semantic system? A critical review and middle temporal and inferior frontal regions contribute beyond the distinction between concrete and
meta-analysis of 120 functional neuroimaging to speed of lexical decision: a TMS study. Brain Cogn. abstract concepts. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 373,
studies. Cereb. Cortex 19, 2767–2796. (doi:10.1093/ 93, 11–17. (doi:10.1016/j.bandc.2014.11.002) 20170144. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2017.0144)
cercor/bhp055) 102. Badre D, Wagner AD. 2007 Left ventrolateral 113. Emerton BC, Gansler DA, Sandberg EH, Jerram M.
92. Wang J, Conder JA, Blitzer DN, Shinkareva SV. 2010 prefrontal cortex and the cognitive control of 2014 Functional anatomic dissociation of description

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 378: 20210375


Neural representation of abstract and concrete memory. Neuropsychologia 45, 2883–2901. (doi:10. and picture naming in the left temporal lobe. Brain
concepts: a meta-analysis of imaging studies. Hum. 1016/j.neuropsychologia.2007.06.015) Imaging Behav. 8, 570–578. (doi:10.1007/s11682-
Brain Mapp. 31, 1459–1468. (doi:10.1002/hbm. 103. Jefferies E, Lambon Ralph MA. 2006 Semantic 013-9281-9)
Downloaded from https://royalsocietypublishing.org/ on 15 February 2023

20950) impairment in stroke aphasia versus semantic 114. Tomaszewki Farias S, Harrington G, Broomand C,
93. Papagno C, Fogliata A, Catricalà E, Miniussi C. 2009 dementia: a case-series comparison. Brain 129, Seyal M. 2005 Differences in functional MR imaging
The lexical processing of abstract and concrete 2132–2147. (doi:10.1093/brain/awl153) activation patterns associated with confrontation
nouns. Brain Res. 1263, 78–86. (doi:10.1016/j. 104. Hickok G, Poeppel D. 2004 Dorsal and ventral naming and responsive naming. Am. J. Neuroradiol.
brainres.2009.01.037) streams: a framework for understanding aspects of 26, 2492–2499.
94. Chee MW, O’Craven KM, Bergida R, Rosen BR, Savoy the functional anatomy of language. Cognition 92, 115. Marconi D, Manenti R, Catricala E, Della Rosa PA,
RL. 1999 Auditory and visual word processing 67–99. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2003.10.011) Siri S, Cappa SF. 2013 The neural substrates of
studied with fMRI. Hum. Brain Mapp. 7, 15–28. 105. Rice GE, Caswell H, Moore P, Hoffman P, Lambon inferential and referential semantic processing.
(doi:10.1002/(SICI)1097-0193(1999)7:1<15::AID- Ralph MA. 2018 The roles of left versus right Cortex 49, 2055–2066. (doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2012.
HBM2>3.0.CO;2-6) anterior temporal lobes in semantic memory: a 08.001)
95. Caplan D, Alpert N, Waters G. 1998 Effects of neuropsychological comparison of postsurgical 116. Turken AU, Dronkers NF. 2011 The neural
syntactic structure and propositional number on temporal lobe epilepsy patients. Cerebral Cortex 28, architecture of the language comprehension
patterns of regional cerebral blood flow. J. Cogn. 1487–1501. (doi:10.1093/cercor/bhx362) network: converging evidence from lesion and
Neurosci. 10, 541–552. (doi:10.1162/ 106. Gainotti G. 2007 Different patterns of famous connectivity analyses. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 5, 1.
089892998562843) people recognition disorders in patients with right (doi:10.3389/fnsys.2011.00001)
96. Heim S, Eickhoff SB, Amunts K. 2009 Different roles of and left anterior temporal lesions: a systematic 117. Lambon Ralph MA, Jefferies E, Patterson K, Rogers
cytoarchitectonic BA 44 and BA 45 in phonological review. Neuropsychologia 45, 1591–1607. (doi:10. T. 2017 The neural and computational bases of
and semantic verbal fluency as revealed by dynamic 1016/j.neuropsychologia.2006.12.013) semantic cognition. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 18, 42–55.
causal modelling. Neuroimage 48, 616–624. (doi:10. 107. Olson IR, Ezzyat Y, Plotzker A, Chatterjee A. 2015 (doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.150)
1016/j.neuroimage.2009.06.044) The end point of the ventral visual stream: face and 118. Lynott D, Connell L. 2010 Embodied conceptual
97. Dapretto M, Bookheimer SY. 1999 Form and non-face perceptual deficits following unilateral combination. Front. Psychol. 1, 212, 1–14. (doi:10.
content: dissociating syntax and semantics in anterior temporal lobe damage. Neurocase 21, 3389/fpsyg.2010.00212)
sentence comprehension. Neuron 24, 427–432. 554–562. (doi:10.1080/13554794.2014.959025) 119. Barsalou LW, Santos A, Simmons WK, Wilson CD.
(doi:10.1016/S0896-6273(00)80855-7) 108. Snowden JS, Thompson JC, Neary D. 2012 Famous 2008 Language and simulation in conceptual
98. Friederici AD, Opitz B, Von Cramon DY. 2000 people knowledge and the right and left temporal processing. In Symbols and embodiment: debates on
Segregating semantic and syntactic aspects of lobes. Behav. Neurol. 25, 35–44. (doi:10.3233/BEN- meaning and cognition (eds M. De Vega, A. M.
processing in the human brain: an fMRI 2012-0347) Glenberg, A. C. Graesser), pp. 245–284. New York,
investigation of different word types. Cereb. Cortex 109. Damasio H, Tranel D, Grabowski T, Adolphs R, NY: Oxford University Press.
10, 698–705. (doi:10.1093/cercor/10.7.698) Damasio A. 2004 Neural systems behind word and 120. Tillas A. 2015 Langauge as grist to the mill of
99. Haller S, Radue EW, Erb M, Grodd W, Kircher T. 2005 concept retrieval. Cognition 92, 179–229. (doi:10. cognition. Cogn. Process. 16, 219–243. (doi:10.
Overt sentence production in event-related fMRI. 1016/j.cognition.2002.07.001) 1007/s10339-015-0656-2)

You might also like