You are on page 1of 4

352 COMMENTARIES

understanding forward while also confirming or modifying Canithers, M., Collins, S., & Lukes, S. (Eds.). (1985). The category of
the practical routines associated with our understanding of the person: Anthropology, philosophy, history. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
the world, others, and ourselves (Leary 1990a). Through Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species. London: Murray.
our ongoing attempts to thus link empirical observations Heller, T. C., Sosna, M., & Wellbery, D. E. (Eds.). (1986). Reconstruct-
(experience) and rational conjectures (metaphors) in the ing individualism: Autonomy, individuality, and the self in Western
most effective way, it should be possible for us to advance thought. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Leary, D. E. (1990a). Metaphor, theory, and practice in the history of
psychological theory and practice while avoiding both
psychology. In D. E. Leary (Ed.), Metaphors in the history of psy-
pseudoempiricality and pseudorationality. chology (pp. 357-367). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Leary, D. E. (1990b). Psyche's muse: The role of metaphor in the history
of psychology. In D. E. Leary (Ed.), Metaphors in the history of
Note psychology (pp. 1-78). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Leary, D. E. (1990~).William James on self and personality: Clearing the
David E. Leary, Office of the Dean, University of Rich- ground for subsequent theorists, researchers, and practitioners. In M.
G. Johnson & T. B. Henley (Eds.), Reflections on The principles of
mond, Richmond, VA 23173. psychology: William James after a century (pp. 101- 137). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
References Marsella, A. J., DeVos, G., & Hsu, F. L. K. (Eds.). (1985). Culture and
self: Asian and Western perspectives. London: Tavistock.
Toulmin, S., & Leary, D. E. (1985). The cult of empiricism in psycholo-
Baumeister, R. F. (1986). Identiry: Cultural change and the struggle for gy, and beyond. In S. Koch & D. E. Leary (Eds.), A centuly of psy-
self. New York: Oxford University Press. chology as science (pp. 594-617). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Downloaded by [Mary Roberts] at 22:49 19 September 2014

Naive Baseball Theory

Peter G. Ossorio
University of Colorado

Smedslund poses anew a question that American psychol- A common reaction to such examples is "Well, I didn't
ogy has not dealt with adequately: Is psychology properly really mean that." The qualms that such examples evoke
viewed as being essentially 100% empirical? For most psy- reflect the brute fact that there are many things we commonly
chologists, the answer is "Obviously-yes!" mostly be- take for granted about people, and the "100% empirical"
cause they take it for granted that that is true for science position is not only a violation, but an a priori one at that.
generally and therefore (obviously)must be true for psychol- It is no secret that the classic way of handling those qualms
ogy in particular. The question of what would qualify as a is to dismiss them with the following sort of avowal: "Those
scientific psychology thus enters the picture as a related a priori limits are there, all right, but that's just a remnant
question. from the naive psychological theory we all grew up with
"100% empirical" has two components: (a) the attitude of because it was embedded in the common sense of our culture.
being completely open to observational discovery, wherever But that is what we have to put aside in order to be able to
that might lead, and (b) the thesis or assumption that there are study people scientifically, 100% empirically, as a natural
no a priori limits to where observational discovery might phenomenon."
lead. Proponents of "100% empirical" seem invariably to That raises a new difficulty having to do with subject
take the position that what is being challenged by someone matter. If there were really no limits to what we might dis-
like Smedslund is (a). In fact, there seems to be no disagree- cover in the course of doing "scientific psychology," then
ment at all about (a). The issue is (b). Henceforth, "100% there would also be no limits to how we might properly
empirical" refers to (b) only. describe what we discovered and no limits to the concepts we
If there really are no a priori limits to what we might might use in explaining or understanding what we dis-
discover through an empirical study of people and what they covered. But all this would hold equally if we set out to do
do, several interesting possibilities present themselves. For 100% empirical physics or 100% empirical economics or
example, we might discover that people are really integers or 100% empirical theology or 100% empirical anything. So,
imaginary numbers; we might discover that appearances are then, why in the world call it psychology?
deceiving and there really are no such things as people (what The notion of a 100% empirical anything appears to raise
we took to be people are really organisms, or brains in a vat, serious and seemingly intractable problems.
or . . . ); or we might discover that there really are no such My impression is that a major reason why the issue raised
things as discoveries (there is only information processing, by Smedslund and others has not been adequately faced is
or . . . ); or we might discover that, if a person has a reason that the prospect of a priori limitations appears as perverse or
to do something, he or she will never do it; or we might paradoxical ("But how could it possibly . . . ?!") rather
discover that people obey Newton's laws of motion, or that than as offering a genuine alternative.
scientists are not persons, etc., etc. (There are many et How could it possibly be the case that the domain of
ceteras here. ) human behavior is logically structured to the extraordinary
COMMENTARIES 353
extent represented by 26 axioms, 83 definitions, and more is not generalizing at all. Rather, he is saying, "Here is how it
than 150 corollaries and theorems, as currently found in is with me" (or "This is what I am doing") in a way that
Smedslund's (1988) system of psychologic (PL)? makes what he does understandable.
Although Smedslund uses the axiomatic approach effec- So much for the "self-contradictions" of common sense.
tively, that alone does little to address the question of why Common sense tells us that only someone who was extraor-
one should (or how one could) take an axiomatic approach dinarily naive or who suffered from some sort of trained
seriously in this domain. After all, it is relatively easy to incapacity could possibly mistake such a rationale for an
dismiss the whole thing as an artifact based on a set of purely empirical generalization. (Drawing such a conclusion is nei-
linguistic conventions in how we happen to talk about people ther an empirical generalization nor a case of theorizing.)
in our commonsense, naive psychological theories. Without the distractionsprovided by the notions of false or
I believe one could actually make a case for the a priori contradictory empirical generalizations, it is much easier to
plausibility of an a priori structure in the domain of behavior. see the really fundamental aspects of common sense:
To do this requires the introduction of two basic consider-
ations: (a) the nature of the connection between common 1. Common sense is primarily concerned with practical
sense and "naive psychological theories" and (b) the notion judgment and action, which are universal features of human
of a constitutive conceptual framework. beings and are universally context dependent. It is hardly at
all concerned with universal, context-free empirical gener-
Common Sense alizations or theorizing, which are highly mannered, spe-
cialized, and bureaucratized activities in our cultural milieu.
"Common sense" encompasses several distinct compo- 2. Common sense is learned, and the learning is funda-
Downloaded by [Mary Roberts] at 22:49 19 September 2014

nents, only one of which is of central concern here. Two mentally not the learning of facts or theories. Rather, it is
other components are almost universally targeted by scien- learning how. It is learning how to function as a human being
tistic ideologies as discrediting common sense, and it seems among human beings.
best to dispose of these two red herrings with dispatch. 3. There is a difference between (a) functioning as a per-
First, common sense includes several of what amount to son among persons and (b) anything else. We learn the dif-
empirical generalizations (e.g., "plant corn by the light of ferences between (a) and (b) by participation, not by learning
the full moon"). They can be wrong; they can have only definitions, theories, or rules and then applying them. Corre-
limited applicability; they can be outdated. About all that spondingly, the criterion for what it is to function as a person
needs to be said is that this is a feature of empirical gener- among persons lies in the competence (sensitivities, abili-
alizations, not common sense, and it applies equally to scien- ties, judgment) of those who are human beings among
tific empirical generalizations. Today we have an empirical human beings.
basis for saying that most of our former scientific generaliza- 4. Nevertheless, there is a strong attraction to the idea of
tions are wrong, misleading, or wrongheaded. We do not on being able to say, explicitly and systematically, what it is to
that account denigrate science. (Common sense is not inher- be a person and act as a person. (We draw on that competence
ently less self-correcting than science, either.) in giving an account of what its exercise involves.)
Second, common sense is commonly described as being 5. In addressing this task, two models are particularly
riddled with contradictions (hence incoherent, irrational, useful. The first is ordinary games, such as baseball, tennis,
etc.). How often have we seen examples such as "Out of chess, bridge, and so forth. This is because they have the
sight, out of mind" and "Absence makes the heart grow following features in a noncontroversial way: (a) They are
fonder" used to illustr,atethe self-contradictions of common actual examples of human behavior, (b) an explicit set of
sense? But consider the following example. rules governs each activity, (c) there is no real question as to
A young salesman accompanies an older, experienced what the rules are, (d) the games have to be learned, (e)
traveling salesman on an extended road trip. After about a learning the game does not require learning the explicit rules
week on the road, the older salesman stops at a florist shop and then applying them, and (f) knowing how to play the
and sends a dozen roses to his wife. "Why did you do that?" game is different from knowing that these are the rules of the
asks the younger man. "Absence makes the heart grow game. These features make it easy to say, "Human behavior
fonder" is the reply. The young man nods, "Yes, I can under- in general is essentially like these special forms of behavior,
stand that." Two weelts later, the older man makes a date even though we can't (yet) say exactly what the rules are." It
with a waitress at the restaurant where they have dinner. is a convenience, then, to talk about "the human game."
"Why did you do that?" asks the younger man. "Out of The second model is natural language, such as English.
sight, out of mind" is the reply. The young man nods, "Yes, I This has most of the relevant features of games, with the
can understand that." following relevant differences: (a) Whereas games can be
Indeed, one can understand that. What the example brings learned without reference to explicit rules, natural language
out is that there are a fair number of personally significant in general is learned (by participation and observation) with-
and culturally familiar situations in which competing deci- out reference to an explicit set of rules, and (b) whereas there
sions and courses of action are genuinely available and at- is no real question as to what the rules of baseball (etc.) are,
tractive. Each of these situationshas its own rationale, and, if to codify the rules of English is a difficult, complex, yet-to-
the courses of action are incompatible, so, in general, will be be-accomplished task. Our efforts (and degree of success)
the rationales. And, being culturally familiar, they will be with natural language illustrate the vast complexity of sys-
part of the commonsense repertoire. tematic description that may be required to give even an
Rationales are obvi~ouslynot empirical generalizations. approximate formulation of the cognitive counterpart to a
When the older salesman says, "Out of sight, out of mind," simply and easily acquired competence.
he is not giving us a "wheneverx, then y" generalization. He 6 . The rules of a game are "givens" for that game. They
354 COMMENTARIES

will appear as givens in any explicit formulations. Stylisti- We may do well to reflect on the fact that science is a
cally, they will appear as axioms, postulates, definitions, human enterprise, not a transcendental one. In this form of
stipulations, tautologies, and so on. What they never are are human behavior, as in the others, one primarily learns how to
merely empirical facts about the game. do it, not just because the rules of this game are considerably
less adequately spelled out than are the rules of English but
Given the foregoing, Smedslund's PL can be understood because, ultimately, it is a matter of knowing how. At the
to be parallel to the enterprise of writing the grammar of same time, because much has been written on the subject,
English, although stylistically it does not have the form of a our learning how is often strongly limited by our learning of
grammar. Given the complexity of formulating linguistic some set of rules to which we then restrict ourselves a priori
behavior, which is only one form of human activity (albeit a and call it Science (real scientists don't use caps).
central one), we should not find it a priori implausible to be If we are willing to talk about naive psychological theories
faced with 26 axioms, 83 definitions, and more than 150 of human behavior, we should be eager to talk about naive
corollaries and theorems (and growing) when we talk about psychological theories of human scientific behavior. Perhaps
behavior more generally. This leaves us with the issue of then we could look forward to doing empirical research to
"naive psychological theory." discover scientifically (a) what "empirical research" really
is (who knows what we might discover) and (b) which of our
Constitutive Conceptual Frameworks questions about human behavior could be answered by doing
empirical research.
If I have a theory about baseball, then baseball is defined Given the space limitations on the present commentary, I
as a phenomenon independently of whether my theory about close with a couple caveats and a kind of empirical endorse-
Downloaded by [Mary Roberts] at 22:49 19 September 2014

it is right or wrong or whether it even makes sense to apply it ment of Smedslund's notion of pseudoempirical research.
to baseball. Indeed, it is precisely because baseball is already Fist, although I am pretty well in complete sympathy with
independently defined as a phenomenon that it can make Smedslund's basic position, and I believe his program is
sense to apply my theory to that phenomenon and ask valuable and viable, as the principal author (Ossorio, 1985)
whether it fits. of an alternative approach-descriptive psychology (DP)-
This is not the case with the rules of baseball. Baseball is I'm bound to point out that there are alternatives, including
not defined as a phenomenon independently of the rules that notably those represented by Gergen (1985), Harr6 (1984),
govern that activity. There is not a coherent question to be and Shotter (1985). I believe that one part of DP is closer to
asked along the lines of whether the rules of baseball are PL than are any of the latter.
correct accounts of baseball games or whether they "fit" Although motivated by many of the same concerns as
baseball games. Without those rules, there is no such phe- Smedslund's, DP is almost diametrically opposed to PL in its
nomenon to ask questions about. style and its conceptual/methodological implementation (I
The rules of baseball codify a conceptual framework that am tempted to characterize DP as a kinder, gentler formula-
is constitutive of the phenomenon of baseball. (And the rules tion). Two examples will perhaps suffice:
of any game are constitutive of that game.) If a conceptual
framework is constitutive of a type of phenomenon, then the 1. PL is based on the models of logic, mathematics, and
applicability of that framework is what makes a phenomenon geometry-with the attendant primary emphasis on truth and
that phenomenon. And, for example, a phenomenon that certainty. In contrast, there are no truths in the basic DP
violates the rules of baseball or to which those rules cannot be formulations, and an appeal to truth is never unavoidable.
sensibly applied cannot be baseball. This is (technically) because there are no statements in the
The rules of baseball are constitutive of baseball gamesfor basic DP formulations. These formulations delineate con-
the participants-hence, the rules are inherent to the phe- ceptual structures directly and explicitly rather than indi-
nomenon. As an observer-describer, I can approach a base- rectly through the tautologies that reflect the conceptual con-
ball game with a conceptual framework different from the nections in such a structure. Conceptual structures are used
rules of baseball, and it will still be a baseball game, although (acted on) or not used. They cannot be (a) either believed or
not for me. But, if the participants (somehow) were not not believed, (b) either true or false, or (c) either supported or
acting from the baseball framework, then it wouldn't and not supported by evidence.
couldn't be a baseball game. There is no way to supersede 2. Whereas PL addresses knowledge, truth, and certainty,
those rules on any grounds whatsoever and still have baseball DP is grounded in competence and addresses (and nurtures)
as a subject matter or a phenomenon. competence. Although it makes use of verbalization, the
The rules of baseball are not a theory about baseball any primary vehicle for learning is practice and experience. The
more than they are empirical generalizations about baseball. contrast is underlined by the fact that there are several close
A forteriori, they are not a naive theory about baseball, and conceptual correspondences and even some cases of near-
we could not sensibly envision the day when they would be, identical wording in DP and PL, and yet they work quite
properly, replaced by a rigorous, well confirmed, scientific differently. Compare, for example, these two pairs (one part
theory about baseball (whereupon we could, at last, play it of DP is a set of maxims):
properly?).
In the area of natural language, the criterion of participant a l . PL (Axiom 6.1.7): "A person's awareness of thefu-
competence is recognized and respected. We speak of ture consists of extrapolations from that person's
"native speaker intuition" and recognize that the speakers awareness of trends in the past" (Smedslund, 1988,
are the criterion of what is (correct) English and what is not p. 71).
(although it's not a simple matter). There is no talk of "na- a2. DP (Maxim A9): A person takes the world to be as
ive" prescientific theories here. he's found it to be.
COMMENTARIES 355
b 1. PL (Axiom 4.3.1): " A person P tries to do A in the about?" This would not make sense if it were merely a causal
context C at time t, if and only if, A is the act which, connection that was involved. For example, if I am hypo-
for P in C at t, has the highest expected utility" glycemic, it will not make sense to ask, "What are you
(Smedslund, 1988, p. 57). hypoglycemic about?" although it will make sense to ask,
b2. DP (Maxim C2): A person will not choose less behav- "What caused you to become hypoglycemic?" And similar-
ior potential over more. ly for being exhausted, being drunk, being hungry or thirsty,
and a variety of other states. What is tautological is the
In DP, maxims are primarily warnings and reminders (or connection between an emotional reaction and its grounds,
encouragements) to an observer-describer of human behav- not between an emotional state and its cause.
ior. They are addressed to the issue of how not to go wrong,
how not to do it wrong-where "it" refers to describing I mention this kind of consideration because graduate stu-
people and their behavior. In contrast to axioms that are dents are frequently (and I believe, needlessly) disturbed by
impersonal and emphasize truth and universality, maxims are it ("The whole point is to show what it looks like when you
designed to be used by a person in addressing another person do it right, isn't it?") and, from that, some others will be
who in general already knows but who in that context, for a also, I expect. My guess is that, if the job were done impec-
given purpose (etc.), may benefit from such a warning or cably, the result would not be all that different from what we
reminder (or encouragement). The thrust of this set of max- already see in PL. (Of course, if we were studying sadness,
ims is "Don't violate the a priori requirements that stem from then it would matter.)
the fact that we're talking about people, not about, for exam- Finally, the "empirical support" for the notion of
ple, material objects, egos, organisms, consumer. Not sur- pseudoempiricalresearch: In the early days of DP, one of the
Downloaded by [Mary Roberts] at 22:49 19 September 2014

prisingly, roughly 90% of these maxims could also be used empirical effects was that all of us who were heavily involved
directly as tautologies, although that is not their raison d7&tre in generating or using the formulations stopped doing em-
and I don't recommend it. pirical research. When the phenomenon was identified, the
The second caveat is that there are formulations in PL for explanation was not long in following: The DP formulations
which it doesn't seern sufficient to disclaim that PL is de- made it intuitively clear that most of the research questions
signed only to get at certain "core" meanings in common actively or prospectively being pursued were not empirical
sense, not to duplicate the vernacular. Take, for example, questions, and therefore it would be not merely useless, but
Smedslund's definition of sadness: "how we feel when actively perverse, to pursue them as research questions. (It
something we want comes to be seen as unattainable or irre- has continued to be the case that researchers who begin to
vocably lost." This does seem to be the right kind of defini- acquire mastery of DP formulations typically go through
tion, but in detail: such a "fallow" period.) Two factors contributed signifi-
cantly to a resumption of research. The first was that the
1. This definition glosses over the difference between conceptual formulations became sufficiently mature so that
being sad and feeling sad. The former does not imply the the lines between empirical and not empirical were generally
latter, although one could connect them with an auxiliary not difficult to draw. The second was that the development of
formulation such as "If one is sad, then one feels sad, un- new research paradigms and research methodology created
less . . ." And, for example, in the classic case of "There's new opportunities to address genuinely empirical questions
good news, and there's bad news," if the good news suffi- in a genuinely empirical way.
ciently outweighs the bad news, I will predictably not feel "Armchair philosophizing" was never in the running.
sad, and there's no reason to assume that I would be sad.
(Note that even if at a later time, upon reflection on the bad References
news, I was sad or felt sad, by then I would have violated the
definition.) Gergen, K. J. (1985). Social constructionistinquiry: Context and implica-
2. The definition glosses over the important differences tions. In K. J. Gergen & K. E. Davis (Eds.), The social construction of
among sadness, despair, regret, disappointment, grief, and, the person (pp. 3-18). New York: Springer-Verlag.
H d , R. (1984). Personal being. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
yes, guilt or anger, all of which are plausible reactions to Press.
"something we want comes to be seen as unattainable or Ossorio, P. G. (1985). An overview of descriptive psychology. In K. J.
irrevocably lost." Some deeper or further analysis seems to Gergen & K. E. Davis (Eds.), The social construction of the person
be called for. (pp. 19-40). New York: Springer-Verlag.
Shotter, J. (1985). Social accountability and self specification. In K. J.
3. Smedslund's commentary on the definition glosses Gergen & K. E. Davis (Eds.), The social construction of the person
over the differences between causes and grounds. If I am sad, ( pp. 167- 189). New York: Springer-Verlag.
it will make sense for s~omeoneto ask me, "What are you sad Smedslund, J. (1988). Psycho-logic. New York: Springer-Verlag.

You might also like