You are on page 1of 19

AJP Volume 40

The Copenhagen Interpretation*

HENRY PIERCE STAPP This radical concept, called the Copenhagen


Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory interpretation, was bitterly challenged at first
University of California but became during the '30's the orthodox inter-
Berkeley, California 9^720 pretation of quantum theory, nominally accepted
(Received 26 March 1971; revised 29 February 1972) by almost all textbooks and practical workers
in the field.
An attempt is made to give a coherent account of the Recently, perhaps partly in response to the
logical essence of the Copenhagen interpretation of severe technical difficulties now besetting quan-
quantum theory. The central point is that quantum theory tum theory at the fundamental level, there has
is fundamentally pragmatic, but nonetheless complete. been mounting criticism of the Copenhagen in-
The principal difficulty in understanding quantum theory
terpretation. The charges range from the claim
lies in the fact that its completeness is incompatible with
external existence of the space-time continuum of classical that it is a great illogical muddle to the claim
physics. that it is in any case unnecessary, and hence, in
view of its radical nature, to be rejected. Reference
1 contains some stoutly worded attacks on the
Copenhagen interpretation. Reference 2 is a more
moderately worded review article that firmly re-
jects the Copenhagen interpretation. Reference 3
is a list of recent articles in the physical literature
that espouse a variety of views on the question.
The striking thing about these articles is
the diversity they reveal in prevailing concep-
tions of the Copenhagen interpretation itself. For
I. INTRODUCTION example, the picture of the Copenhagen interpre-
tation painted in Ref. 1 is quite different from
Scientists of the late twenties, led by Bohr and the pictures painted in Refs. 2 and 3 by practicing
Heisenberg, proposed a conception of nature physicists. And these latter pictures themselves
radically different from that of their predecessors. are far from uniform.
The new conception, which grew out of efforts to The cause of these divergences is not hard to
comprehend the apparently irrational behavior of find. Textbook accounts of the Copenhagen in-
nature in the realm of quantum effects, was not terpretation generally gloss over the subtle points.
simply a new catalog of the elementary space- For clarification the readers are directed to the
time realities and their modes of operation. It was writings of Bohr 4 and Heisenberg.5 Yet clarifica-
essentially a rejection of the presumption that tion is difficult to find there. The writings of
nature could be understood in terms of elementary Bohr are extraordinarily elusive. They rarely
space-time realities. According to the new view, seem to say what you want to know. They weave
the complete; description of nature at the atomic a web of words around the Copenhagen interpre-
level was given by probability functions that tation but do not say exactly what it is. Heisen-
referred not to underlying microscopic space-time berg's writings are more direct. But his way of
realities but rather to the macroscopic objects of speaking suggests a subjective interpretation that
sense experience. The theoretical structure did appears quite contrary to the apparent intentions
not extend down and anchor itself on fundamental of Bohr. The situation is perhaps well summarized
microscopic space-time realities. Instead it turned by von Weizsacker, who, after expressing the
back and anchored itself in the concrete sense opinion that the Copenhagen interpretation is
realities that form the basis of social life. correct and indispensable, says he must "add that

1098 I August 1972


The Copenhagen Interpretation

the interpretation, in my view, has never been characteristic of the physical system being pre-
fully clarified. It needs an interpretation, and pared. They are called the degrees of freedom of
that will be its only defense."6 the prepared system. The description of the
von Weizsacker is surely correct. The writings specifications A is couched in a language that is
of Bohr and Heisenberg have, as a matter of meaningful to an engineer or laboratory tech-
historical fact, not produced a clear and un- nician. The way in which these operational speci-
ambiguous picture of the basic logical structure fications A are translated into a corresponding
of their position. They have left impressions wave function^(a;) is discussed later.
that vary significantly from reader to reader. For The specifications B on the subsequent measure-
this reason a clarification of the Copenhagen ment and its possible result are similarly couched
interpretation is certainly needed. My aim here in a language that allows a suitably trained tech-
is to provide one. More precisely, my aim is to nician to set up a measurement of the specified
give a clear account of the logical essence of the kind and to determme whether the result that
Copenhagen interpretation. This logical essence occurs is a result of the specified kind. These
should be distinguished from the inhomogeneous specifications B on the measurement and its
body of opinions and views that now constitute result are transcribed into a wave function ^B{y),
the Copenhagen interpretation itself. The logical where y is a set of variables that are called the
essence constitutes, I believe, a completely ra- degrees of freedom of the measured system.
tional and coherent position. Next a transformation function U(x; y) is
The plan of the work is as follows. First, constructed in accordance with certain theoretical
quantum theory is described from the point of rules. This function depends on the type of system
view of actual practice. Then, to provide con- that was prepared and on the type of system that
trast, several non-Copenhagen interpretations was measured, but not on the particular wave
are considered. Next, to provide background, functions ^A{X) and ^B{V). The "transition
some philosophical ideas of William James are amplitude"
introduced. The pragmatic character of the
Copenhagen interpretation is then discussed, and (A | B)=fVA(x)U(x; y)*B*(y)dxdy
the incompatibility of the completeness of quan-
tum theory with the external existence of the
space-time continuum of classical physics is noted. is computed. The predicted probability that a
Finally, the question of the completeness of measurement performed in the manner specified
quantum theory is examined. by B will yield a result specified by B, if the
preparation is performed in the manner specified
II. A PRACTICAL ACCOUNT OF by A, is given by
QUANTUM THEORY
Quantum theory is a procedure by which sci- P(A,B) = \ (A\B)\*.
entists predict probabilities that measurements of
specified kinds will yield results of specified kinds The experimental physicist will, I hope, recog-
in situations of specified kinds. I t is applied in nize in this account a description of how he uses
circumstances that are described by saying that quantum theory. First he transforms his informa-
a certain physical system is first prepared in a tion about the preparation of the system into an
specified manner and is later examined in a initial wave function. Then he applies to it some
specified manner. And this examination, called linear transformation, calculated perhaps from
a measurement, is moreover such that it can the Schrodinger equation, or perhaps from the
yield, or not yield, various possible specified S matrix, which converts the initial wave func-
results. tion into a final wave function. This final wave
The procedure is this: The specifications A on function, which is built on the degrees of freedom
the manner of preparation of the physical system of the measured system, is then folded into the
are first transcribed into a wave function ^A.(X). wave function corresponding to a possible result.
The variables x are a set of variables that are This gives the transition amplitude, which is

A JP Volume 40 / 1099
Henry Pierce Stapp

multiplied by its complex conjugate to give the function, and use quantum theory itself to calcu-
predicted transition probability. late the needed mappings. This program has never
In a more sophisticated calculation one might been carried out in any practical case. One
use density matrices pA(x';x") and PB(y'',y") difficulty is that actual macroscopic devices are
instead of *A(J;) and ¥s(y) to represent the pre- so complicated that qualitative calculations lie
pared system and the possible result. This would beyond present capabilities. The second problem
allow for preparations and measurements that is that such calculations would, in any case, pro-
correspond to statistical mixtures. But this vide only connections between the wave functions
generalization could be obtained also by simply $ of the preparing and measuring devices and
performing classical averages over various ^A(X) the wave functions ^ of the original system.
and ^B(V)- There would remain the problem of finding the
The above account describes how quantum mappings A^>4>A and B—>4>B.
theory is used in practice. The essential points von Neumann's approach is not the one that is
are that attention is focused on some system that adopted in actual practice; no one has yet made
is first prepared in a specified manner and later a qualitatively accurate theoretical description
examined in a specified manner. Quantum theory of a measuring device. Thus what experimen-
is a procedure for calculating the predicted prob- talists do, in practice, is to calibrate their devices.
ability that the specified type of examination Notice, in this connection, that if one takes
will yield some specified result. This predicted NA different choices of A and NB different choices
probability is the predicted limit of the relative of B, then one has only NA+NB unknown func-
frequency of occurrence of the specified result, tions ^A and -&B, but NAXNB experimentally
as the number of systems prepared and examined determinable quantities | {A | B) |2. Using this
in accordance with the specifications goes to leverage, together with plausible assumptions
infinity. about smoothness, it is possible to build up a
The wave functions used in these calculations catalog of correspondences between what experi-
are functions of a set of variables characteristic mental physicists do and see, and the wave func-
of the prepared and measured systems. These tions of the prepared and measured systems.
systems are often microscopic and not directly It is this body of accumulated empirical knowledge
observable. No wave functions of the preparing that bridges the gap between the operational
and measuring devices enter into the calculation. specifications A and B and their mathematical
These devices are described operationally. They images tyA and tyB-
are described in terms of things that can be The above description of how quantum theory
recognized and/or acted upon by technicians. is used in practice will be used in the account
These descriptions refer to the macroscopic of the Copenhagen interpretation. Before de-
properties of the preparing and measuring devices. scribing that interpretation itself I shall, to pro-
The crucial question is how does one determine vide contrast, describe several other approaches.
the transformations A—^A and B-^&B. These
transformations transcribe procedural descrip- III. SEVERAL OTHER APPROACHES
tions of the manner in which technicians prepare
A. The Absolute-^ Approach
macroscopic objects, and recognize macroscopic
responses, into mathematical functions built on von Neumann's lucid analysis of the process
the degrees of freedom of the (microscopic) pre- of measurement is the origin of much of the cur-
pared and measured systems. The problem of rent worry about the interpretation of quantum
constructing this mapping is the famous "prob- theory. The basic worrisome point can be illus-
lem of measurements" in quantum theory. trated by a simple example.
The problem of measurements was studied by Suppose a particle has just passed through one
von Neumann. 7 He begins with the idea that one of two slits. And suppose a 100% efficient counter
should describe the combined system composed is placed behind each slit, so that by seeing which
of the original systems plus the original measuring counter fires a human observer can determine
devices in terms of a quantum mechanical wave through which slit the particle passed.

1100 I August 1972


The Copenhagen Interpretation

Suppose the particle is represented initially observer does not run both upstairs and down-
by a wave function that assigns equal probabili- stairs. He does one or the other, not both. There-
ties to the parts associated with the two slits. fore the wave function must collapse to a form
And consider a quantum theoretical analysis of that is consistent with what actually does happen.
the process of measurement in which both the But such a collapse is definitely incompatible
particle and the two counters are represented by with the superposition principle.
wave functions. This violation of the superposition principle
It follows directly and immediately from the bothers some thinkers. Wigner8 calls the existence
superposition principle (i.e., linearity) that the of the two modes of change of the wave function—
wave function of the complete system after the i.e., the smooth causal evolution and the fitful
measurement necessarily will consist of a super- statistical jumps associated with measurements—
position of two terms. The first term will repre- a strange dualism, and says that the probabilistic
sent the situation in which (1) the particle has behavior is almost diametrically opposite to what
passed through the first counter, (2) the first one would expect from ordinary experience. He
counter has fired, and (3) the second counter and Ludwig9 speculate that quantum theory may
has not fired. The second term will represent the have to be modified by the addition of a nonlinear
situation in which (1) the particle has passed effect in the macroscopic realm in order to arrive
through the second counter, (2) the second at a consistent theory of measurements. Wigner10
counter has fired, and (3) the first counter has not even speculates that the nonlinearity may be
fired. These two terms evolve from the two terms associated with the action of mind on matter.
in the wave function of the initial particle. The An even more radical proposal was made by
presence of both terms is a direct and unavoidable Everett 11 and supported by Wheeler12 and Bryce
consequence of the superposition principle, which DeWitt. 13 According to this proposal the human
ensures that the sum of any two solutions of the observer actually runs both upstairs and down-
equation of motion is another solution. stairs at the same time. When the human ob-
Notice now that the counters are macroscopic server sees the counter fire he breaks into two
objects and that the wave function necessarily separate editions of himself, one of which runs
contains a sum of two terms one of which corre- upstairs while the other runs down. However, the
sponds to the first counter's having fired but not parts of the wave function corresponding to these
the second, and the other of which corresponds two different possibilities move into different
to the second counter's having fired but not the regions of the multiparticle configuration space
first. Thus the wave function necessarily corre- and consequently do not interfere. Therefore the
sponds to a sum of two logically incompatible two editions will never be aware of each other's
macroscopic possibilities. existence. Thus appearances are saved without
To dramatize this situation, suppose the human violating the superposition principle.
observer now looks at the counters and runs This proposal is, I think, unreasonable. A wave
upstairs or downstairs depending on which counter function times its complex conjugate, has the
he sees firing. Then the wave function of the mathematical properties of a probability func-
entire system of particle plus counters plus human tion. Probability functions for composite systems
observer will consist, eventually, of a sum of two are naturally defined on the product of the spaces
terms. One term will represent the human ob- of the individual component systems; it is this
server running upstairs, and the other term will property that allows different statistical weights
represent this same human observer running to be assigned to the various logically alternative
downstairs. Both terms must necessarily be possibilities. A decomposition of a wave function
present in the wave function, simply by virtue into parts corresponding to different logical al-
of the superposition principle. ternatives is thus completely natural. In the
This fact that the wave function necessarily example described—with the initial specification
develops into a sum of parts that correspond to as described there—there is a finite probability
incompatible macroscopic possibilities must be that the observer will be running upstairs, and a
squared with the empirical facts. The human finite probability that he will be running down-

AJP Volume 40 / 1101


Henry Pierce Stapp

stairs. Thus the wave function necessarily must to the process of measurement itself, coupled
have both parts. If it collapsed to one part or with his parallel treatments of the two very dif-
the other it would no longer correctly describe ferent modes of development of the wave func-
the probabilities corresponding to the original tion—i.e., the smooth dynamical evolution, and
specifications. the abrupt changes associated with measure-
Of course, if the original specifications are re- ment—tend to conjure up the image of some
placed by new ones that include now the specifi- absolute wave function developing in time under
cation that the observer is running upstairs, not the influence of two different dynamical mecha-
downstairs, then the original wave function will nisms. The living, breathing scientist who changes
naturally be replaced by a new one, just as it the wave function he uses as he receives more
would be in classical statistical theory. information is replaced by a new dynamical
In short, the mathematical properties of the mechanism. The resulting picture is strange
wave functions are completely in accord with the indeed.
idea that they describe the evolution of the In the Copenhagen interpretation the notion
probabilities of the actual things, not the actual of an absolute wave function representing the
things themselves. The idea that they describe world itself is unequivocally rejected. Wave func-
also the evolution of the actual things themselves tions, like the corresponding probability functions
leads to metaphysical monstrosities. These might in classical physics, are associated with the
perhaps be accepted if they were the necessary studies by scientists of finite systems. The devices
consequences of irrefutable logic. But this is that prepare and later examine such systems
hardly the case here. The basis of Everett's whole are regarded as parts of the ordinary classical
proposal is the premise that the superposition physical world. Their space-time dispositions are
principle cannot suddenly fail. This premise is interpreted by the scientist as information about
sound. But the natural and reasonable conclusion the prepared and examined systems. Only these
to draw from it is that the wave functions de- latter systems are represented by wave functions.
scribe the evolution of the probabilities of the The probabilities involved are the probabilities
actual things, not the evolution of the actual of specified responses of the measuring devices
things themselves. For the mathematical form under specified conditions.
and properties of the wave function, including New information available to the scientist can
its lawful development in accordance with the be used in two different ways. It can be consid-
superposition principle, are completely in accord ered to be information about the response of a
with the presumption that it is a probability measuring device to the system being examined.
function. The addition of the metaphysical as- In this case the probability of this response is
sumption that the wave function represents the the object of interest. On the other hand, the new
evolution of not only the probabilities of the information can also be regarded as part of the
actual things, but of also the actual things them- specification of a new preparation. The wave
selves, is unreasonable because its only virtue is function that represents this new specification
to save the superposition principle, which, how- will naturally be different from the wave function
ever, is not in jeopardy unless one introduces that represented the original specifications. One
this metaphysical assumption. would not expect the superposition principle to
Everett's proposal, and also those of Wigner be maintained in the change of the wave function
and Ludwig, are the outgrowth of a certain associated with a change of specifications.
tendency to ascribe to the wave function a quality This pragmatic description is to be contrasted
of absoluteness that goes beyond what is normally with descriptions that attempt to peer "behind
and naturally attached to a probability function. the scenes" and tell us what is "really happening."
This tendency can perhaps be traced to what Such superimposed images can be termed meta-
Rosenfeld14 calls "a radical difference in concep- physical appendages insofar as they have no
tion (going back to von N e u m a n n ) . . . , " this testable consequences. The pragmatic interpre-
radical difference being with the ideas of Bohr, tation ignores all such metaphysical appendages.
von Neumann's application of quantum theory The sharp distinction drawn in this section

1102 I August 1972


The Copenhagen Interpretation

between probabilities and the actual things to that completely transcend the realm of causal
which they refer should not be construed as an dynamical connections. The spatially separated
acceptance of the real-particle interpretation parts of any such underlying reality are not
which is described next. independent realities, in the ordinary sense.
Bell's theorem does not absolutely rule out the
B. The Real-Particle Interpretation real-particle interpretation, if one is willing to
The real-particle interpretation affirms that admit these hyperdynamical connections. But
there are real particles, by which is meant tiny they fortify the opinion that a dynamical theory
localized objects, or disturbances, or singularities, based on such a real entity would have no testable
or other things that stay together like particles dynamical consequences. For the strong de-
should, and do not spread out like waves. Accord- pendence of individual effects here on Earth upon
ing to this interpretation, the probability func- the fine details of what is happening all over the
tions of quantum theory describe, typically, the universe apparently rules out any ordinary kind
probability that a real particle is in such-and-such of test of such a theory.
a region. This real-particle interpretation is de-
fended by Popper in Ref. 1, and by Ballentine IV. THE PRAGMATIC CONCEPTION
OF TRUTH
in Ref. 2.
Confidence in the existence of real particles To prepare the mind for the Copenhagen in-
was restored by Bohm's 15 illustration of how terpretation it is useful to recall some ideas of
nonrelativistic Schrodinger theory can be made William James. 17 James argued at length for a
compatible with the existence of point particles. certain conception of what it means for an idea
The price paid for this achievement is this: All to be true. This conception was, in brief, that an
the particles in the (model) universe are instantly idea is true if it works.
and forcefully linked together. What happens James's proposal was at first scorned and
to any particle in the universe instantly and ridiculed by most philosophers, as might be ex-
violently affects every other particle. pected. For most people can plainly see a big
In such a situation it is not clear that we should difference between whether an idea is true and
continue to use the term "particle." For the entire whether it works. Yet James stoutly defended
collection of "particles" in Bohm's universe acts his idea, claiming that he was misunderstood by
as a single complex entity. Our usual idea of a his critics.
particle is an abstraction from experience about It is worthwhile to try to see things from James's
macroscopic objects, and it normally carries, as point of view.
part of the idea of localization, the idea that the James accepts, as a matter of course, that the
localized entity is an independent entity, in the truth of an idea means its agreement with reality.
sense that it depends on other things in the uni- The questions are: What is the "reality" with
verse only through various "dynamical" effects. which a true idea agrees? And what is the rela-
These dynamical effects are characterized by a tionship "agreement with reality" by virtue of
certain respect for space-time separations. In which that idea becomes true?
particular, they are "causal." If the connections All human ideas lie, by definition, in the realm
between particles radically transcend our idea of of experience. Reality, on the other hand, is
causal dynamical relationships, then the ap- usually considered to have parts lying outside
propriateness of the word "particle" can be this realm. The question thus arises: How can
questioned. an idea lying inside the realm of experience agree
Recently, Bell16 has shown that the statistical with something that lies outside? How does one
predictions of quantum theory are definitely in- conceive of a relationship between an idea, on
compatible with the existence of an underlying the one hand, and something of such a funda-
reality whose spatially separated parts are inde- mentally different sort? What is the structural
pendent realities linked only by causal dynamical form of that connection between an idea and a
relationships. The spatially separated parts of transexperiential reality that goes by the name
any underlying reality must be linked in ways of "agreement"? How can such a relationship be

AJP Volume 40 I 1103


Henry Pierce Stapp

comprehended by thoughts forever confined to of whether human ideas can be brought into
the realm of experience? exact correspondence with the essences of the
The contention that underlies James's whole external realities is the success of our ideas in
position is, I believe, that a relationship between bringing order to our physical experience. Yet
an idea and something else can be comprehended the success of ideas in this sphere does not ensure
only if that something else is also an idea. Ideas the exact correspondence of our ideas to external
are eternally confined to the realm of ideas. reality.
They can "know" or "agree" only with other On the other hand, the question of whether
ideas. There is no way for a finite mind to com- ideas "agree" with external essences is of no prac-
prehend or explain an agreement between an tical importance. What is important is precisely
idea and something that lies outside the realm of the success of the ideas—if ideas are successful
experience. in bringing order to our experience then they are
So if we want to know what it means for an useful even if they do not "agree," in some ab-
idea to agree with a reality we must first accept solute sense, with the external essences. Moreover,
that this reality lies in the realm of experience. if they are successful in bringing order into our
This viewpoint is not in accord with the usual experience then they do "agree" at least with the
idea of truth. Certain of our ideas are ideas about aspects of our experience that they successfully
what lies outside the realm of experience. For order. Furthermore, it is only this agreement with
example, I may have the idea that the world is aspects of our experience that can ever really be
made up of tiny objects called particles. Accord- comprehended by man. That which is not an
ing to the usual notion of truth this idea is true idea is intrinsically incomprehensible, and so are
or false according to whether or not the world its relationships to other things. This leads to the
really is made up of such particles. The truth of pragmatic viewpoint that ideas must be judged
the idea depends on whether it agrees with some- by their success and utility in the world of ideas
thing that lies outside the realm of experience. and experience, rather than on the basis of some
Now the notion of "agreement" seems to intrinsically incomprehensible "agreement" with
suggest some sort of similarity or congruence of nonideas.
the things that agree. But things that are similar The significance of this viewpoint for science
or congruent are generally things of the same is its negation of the idea that the aim of science
kind. Two triangles can be similar or congruent is to construct a mental or mathematical image
because they are the same kind of thing: The of the world itself. According to the pragmatic
relationships that inhere in one can be mapped in view, the proper goal of science is to augment
a direct and simple way into the relationships and order our experience. A scientific theory
that inhere in the other. should be judged on how well it serves to extend
But ideas and external realities are presumably the range of our experience and reduce it to order.
very different kinds of things. Our ideas are in- It need not provide a mental or mathematical
timately associated with certain complex, macro- image of the world itself, for the structural form
scopic, biological entities—our brains—and the of the world itself may be such that it cannot be
structural forms that can inhere in our ideas placed in simple correspondence with the types
would naturally be expected to depend on the of structures that our mental processes can form.
structural forms of our brains. External realities, James was accused of subjectivism—of denying
on the other hand, could be structurally very the existence of objective reality. In defending
different from human ideas. Hence there is no himself against this charge, which he termed
a priori reason to expect that the relationships slanderous, he introduced an interesting ontology
that constitute or characterize the essence of consisting of three things: (1) private concepts,
external reality can be mapped in any simple or (2) sense objects, (3) hypersensible realities. The
direct fashion into the world of human ideas. private concepts are subjective experiences. The
Yet if no such mapping exists then the whole sense objects are public sense realities, i.e., sense
idea of "agreement" between ideas and external realities that are independent of the individual.
realities becomes obscure. The hypersensible realities are realities that exist
The only evidence we have on the question independently of all human thinkers. 18

1104 I August 1972


The Copenhagen Interpretation

Of hypersensible realities James can talk only assertions:


obliquely, since he recognizes both that our
(1) The quantum theoretical formalism is to
knowledge of such things is forever uncertain
be interpreted pragmatically.
and that we can moreover never even think of
(2) Quantum theory provides for a complete
such things without replacing them by mental
scientific account of atomic phenomena.
substitutes that lack the defining characteristics
of that which they replace, namely the property Point (1) asserts that quantum theory is funda-
of existing independently of all human thinkers. mentally the procedure described in the practical
James's sense objects are curious things. They account of quantum theory given in Sec. II. The
are sense realities and hence belong to the realm central problem for the Copenhagen interpreta-
of experience. Yet they are public: They are in- tion is to reconcile this assertion with the claim
dependent of the individual. They are, in short, that it is complete, i.e., to reconcile assertions
objective experiences. The usual idea about ex- (1) and (2). This problem is discussed in Sec. VII.
periences is that they are personal or subjective, The aim of the present section is to document
not public or objective. point (1) by the words of Bohr. This fundamental
This idea of experienced sense objects as public point needs to be definitely settled, for critics
or objective realities runs through James's writ- often confuse the Copenhagen interpretation,
ings. The experience "tiger" can appear in the which is basically pragmatic, with the dia-
mental histories of many different individuals. metrically opposed absolute-* interpretation de-
"That desk" is something that I can grasp and scribed in Sec. III. In what follows, particular
shake, and you also can grasp and shake. About attention will be paid to the possible conflict of
this desk James says "But you and I are com- the pragmatic viewpoint with (i) the element of
mutable here; we can exchange places; and as realism in Bohr's attitude toward the macro-
you go bail for my desk, so I can go bail for yours. scopic world and (ii) any commitment to a funda-
This notion of a reality independent of either of mental stochastic or statistical element in nature
us, taken from ordinary experience, lies at the itself.
base of the pragmatic definition of truth." 19 The quotations from Bohr that follow are
These words should, I think, be linked with taken from his three major works 4 : (I.) Atomic
Bohr's words about classical concepts as the basis Theory and the Description of Nature; (II.) Atomic
of communication between scientists. In both Physics and Human Knowledge; and (III.) Essays
cases the focus is on the concretely experienced 1958-1962 on Atomic Physics and Human
sense realities—such as the shaking of the desk— Knowledge.
as the foundation of social reality. From this The pragmatic orientation of the Copenhagen
point of view the objective world is not built interpretation is fixed in the opening words of
basically out of such airy abstractions as electrons Bohr's first book: "The task of science is both to
and protons and "space." It is founded on the extend the range of our experience and reduce
concrete sense realities of social experience, such it to order . . . " (1.1). "In physics . . . our prob-
as a block of concrete held in the hand, a sword lem consists in the co-ordination of our experience
forged by a blacksmith, a Geiger counter prepared of the external world . . . " (1.1). "In our descrip-
according to specifications by laboratory tech- tion of nature the purpose is not to disclose the
nicians and placed in a specified position by real essence of phenomena but only to track
experimental physicists. down as far as possible relations between the
This brief excursion into philosophy provides multifold aspects of our experience" (1.18).
background for the Copenhagen interpretation, This commitment to a pragmatic view of
which is fundamentally a shift to a philosophic science runs through all of Bohr's works. He later
perspective resembling that of William James. links it to the crucial problem of communication:
"As the goal of science is to augment and order
V. THE PRAGMATIC CHARACTER OF THE
our experience every analysis of the conditions
COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION
of human knowledge must rest on considerations
The logical essence of the Copenhagen inter- of the character and scope of our means of com-
pretation is summed up in the following two munication" (11.88). "In this connection it is

AJP Volume 40 / 1105


Henry Pierce Stapp

imperative to realize that in every account of admits the existence of hypersensible realities.
physical experience one must describe both ex- But there is no commitment by Bohr to the idea
perimental conditions and observations by the that the macroscopic world really is what we
same means of communication as one used in naively imagine it to be. The focus is on the
classical physics" (11.88). "The decisive point is descriptions of our physical experiences and the
to recognize that the description of the experi- demand that they secure unambiguous com-
mental arrangement and the recordings of ob- munication and objectivity. Referring to the
servations must be given in plain language, suit- experimental arrangements and observations he
ably refined by the usual terminology. This is a says: "The description of atomic phenomena has
simple logical demand, since by the word 'ex- in these respects a perfectly objective character,
periment' we can only mean a procedure regarding in the sense that no explicit reference is made to
which we are able to communicate to others what any individual observer and that therefore, with
we have done and what we have learnt" (III.3). proper regard to relativistic exigencies, no am-
" . . . we must recognize above all that, even when biguity is involved in the communication of in-
phenomena transcend the scope of classical formation. As regards all such points, the ob-
physical theories, the account of the experi- servation problem of quantum physics in no way
mental arrangement and the recording of observa- differs from the classical physical approach"
tions must be given in plain language, suitably (III.3). Bohr's closest approach to a commitment
supplemented by technical physical terminology. to the idea that the macroscopic world actually
This is a clear logical demand, since the very word is what it appears to be is, I think, the statement:
'experiment' refers to a situation where we can "The renunciation of pictorial representation in-
tell others what we have done and what we have volves only the state of atomic objects, while
learned" (11.72). the foundation of the description of the experi-
Bohr's commitment to a pragmatic interpreta- mental conditions is fully retained" (11.90). The
tion of the quantum-mechanical formalism is un- commitment here is, I believe, to the appropriate-
ambiguous: " . . . t h e appropriate physical in- ness, in quantum theory, of a classical description
terpretation of the symbolic quantum-mechanical of the experimental conditions, rather than to the
formalism amounts only to predictions, of de- fundamental accuracy of classical ideas at the
terminate or statistical character, pertaining to macroscopic level. This position is in complete
individual phenomena appearing under conditions accord with pragmatism.
defined by classical physical concepts" (11.64). In regard to the irreducible statistical element
" . . . the formalism does not allow pictorial repre- in quantum theory, Bohr was at first ambivalent.
sentation on accustomed lines, but aims directly An initial acceptance of the notion of a funda-
at establishing relations between observations mental element of randomness or indeterminism
obtained under well-defined conditions" (11.71). on the part of nature is suggested by the state-
"The sole aim of (the quantum mechanical for- ment: " . . . w e have been forced...to reckon
malism) is the comprehension of observations with a free choice on the part of nature between
obtained under experimental conditions described various possibilities to which only probability
by simple physical concepts" (11.90). "Strictly interpretations can be applied" (1.4). However,
speaking, the mathematical formalism of quantum he soon qualifies this idea (1.19) and later on says
mechanics and electrodynamics merely offers that at a Solvay conference
rules of calculation for the deduction of expecta-
tions about observations obtained under well- an interesting discussion arose about how to
defined experimental conditions specified by clas- speak of the appearance of phenomena for
sical physical concepts" (III.60). which only statistical predictions can be
Throughout Bohr's writings there is a tacit made. The question was whether, as to the
acceptance of the idea that the external world occurrence of individual effects, we should
exists, and that our physical experiences are adopt the terminology proposed by Dirac,
caused, in part, by the course of external events. that we were concerned with a choice on the
This is quite in accord with pragmatism: James part of "nature," or as suggested by Heisen-

1106 I August 197%


The Copenhagen Interpretation

berg, we should say that we have to do with and the adoption of an essentially pragmatic
a choice on the part of the "observer" con- attitude toward the statistical character of the
structing the measuring instruments and quantum-mechanical predictions.
reading their recording. Any such terminology I t is worth noting that Bohr's notion of com-
would, however, appear dubious since, on plementarity is altogether pragmatic: Ideas should
the one hand, it is hardly reasonable to endow be judged by their utility; physical ideas should be
nature with volition in the ordinary sense, judged by their success in ordering physical
while on the other hand it is certainly not experiences, not by the accuracy with which
possible for the observer to influence the they can be believed to mirror the essence of
events which may appear under the condi- external reality. The use of complementary ideas
tions he has arranged. To my mind there is in complementary situations is a natural con-
no other alternative than to admit in this comitant of pragmatic thinking.
field of experience, we are dealing with in-
dividual phenomena and that our possibili- VI. SPACE-TIME AND THE COMPLETENESS
ties of handling the measuring instruments OF QUANTUM THEORY
allow us only to make a choice between In spite of doubts cast on our intuitive notions
the different complementary types of phe- of space and time by the theory of relativity,
nomena that we want to study (11.51). the idea lingers on that persisting physical ob-
jects occupy space-time regions that can be
Later he says "The circumstance that, in general, divided into ever finer parts. A basic premise of
one and the same experimental arrangement may classical physics is that this classical concept of
yield different recordings is sometimes pic- the space-time continuum is the appropriate
turesquely described as a 'choice of nature' be- underlying concept for fundamental physical
tween such possibilities. Needless to say, such a theory.
phrase implies no allusion to a personification of I t is important to recognize that quantum
nature, but simply points to the impossibility theory has nothing in it that can be regarded as
of ascertaining on accustomed lines directives a description of qualities or properties of nature
for the course of a closed indivisible phenomenon. that are located at the point or infinitesimal re-
Here, logical approach cannot go beyond the gions of the space-time continuum. On one hand,
deduction of the relative probabilities for the the descriptions of the experimental arrangements
appearance of the individual phenomena under and observations are basically operational de-
given conditions" (11.73). "Corresponding to the scriptions of what technicians can see and do.
fact that different individual quantum processes They are not, strictly speaking, descriptions of
may take place in a given experimental arrange- the external things in themselves. Moreover, they
ment these relations (between observations ob- are not descriptions of microscopic qualities or
tained under well-defined conditions) are of an properties. On the other hand, the wave functions
inherently statistical character" (11.71). "The are merely abstract symbolic devices. They do not
very fact that repetition of the same experiment, describe qualities or properties of nature that
defined on the lines described, in general yields are located at points or infinitesimal regions of
different recordings pertaining to the object, the space-time continuum. The abrupt change
immediately implies that a comprehensive ac- of a wave function in one region of space-time
count of experience in this field must be expressed when a measurement is performed far away at
by statistical laws" (III.4). "The fact that in the same time makes any such interpretation un-
one and the same well-defined experimental ar- reasonable. The wave functions of quantum theory
rangement we generally obtain recordings of are to be interpreted as symbolic devices that
different individual processes makes indispensible scientists use to make predictions about what
the recourse to a statistical account of quantum they will observe under specified conditions. As
phenomena" (111.25). These statements indicate Bohr says it: "In the treatment of atomic prob-
a turning away by Bohr from picturesque notions lems, actual calculations are most conveniently
of a inherent random element in nature itself, carried out with the help of a Schrodinger state

AJP Volume 40 / 1107


Henry Pierce Stapp

function, from which the statistical laws govern- In a pragmatic framework the claim of com-
ing observations attainable under specified condi- pleteness has a different natural meaning. The
tions can be deduced by definite mathematical natural meaning of the claim that quantum
operations. It must be recognized, however, that theory provides for a complete scientific account
we are here dealing with a purely symbolic of atomic phenomena is that no theoretical con-
procedure the unambiguous physical interpreta- struction can yield experimentally verifiable pre-
tion of which in the last resort requires a reference dictions about atomic phenomena that cannot be
to the complete experimental arrangement" extracted from a quantum theoretical description.
(III.5). "In fact, wave mechanics, just as the This is the practical or pragmatic meaning of
matrix theory, represents on this view a symbolic scientific completeness in this context.
transcription of the problem of motion of classical
mechanics adapted to the requirements of quan- VII. WHOLENESS AND COMPLETENESS
tum theory and only to be interpreted by an The second essential ingredient of the Copen-
explicit use of the quantum postulate" (1.75). hagen interpretation is the claim that quantum
The fact that quantum theory contains nothing theory provides for the complete scientific ac-
that is interpreted as a description of qualities count of atomic phenomena. During the more than
located at points of an externally existing space- thirty years spanned by his three books4 Bohr
time continuum can be construed as evidence polished and refined his views on this point. His
of its incompleteness. However, all we really know final, and I think best, summary is as follows:
about the space-time continuum is that it is a
The element of wholeness, symbolized by the
concept that has been useful for organizing sense
quantum of action and completely foreign
experience. Man's effort to comprehend the world
to classical physical principles, has . . . the
in terms of the idea of an external reality inhering
consequence that in the study of quantum
in a space-time continuum reached its culmina-
processes any experimental inquiry implies
tion in classical field theory. That theory, though
an interaction between atomic object and the
satisfactory in the domain of macroscopic phe-
measuring tools which, although essential
nomena, failed to provide a satisfactory account
for the characterization of the phenomena,
of the microscopic sources of the field. The bulk
evades a separate account if the experiment
of Einstein's scientific life was spent in a frus-
is to serve its purpose of yielding unambigu-
trated effort to make these ideas work at the
ous answers to our questions. It is indeed
microscopic level.20 The rejection of classical
the recognition of this situation which makes
theory in favor of quantum theory represents,
recourse to a statistical mode of description
in essence, the rejection of the idea that external
imperative as regards to the expectations
reality resides in, or inheres in, a space-time
of the occurrence of individual quantum
continuum. It signalizes the recognition that
effects in one and the same experimental
"space," like color, lies in the mind of the beholder.
arrangement. (III.60).
If the classical concept of the space-time con-
tinuum were accepted, then quantum theory This statement is augmented and clarified by an
could not be considered complete, i.e., if it were earlier statement:
accepted that the persisting objects of nature The essentially new feature in the analysis
literally reside in a space-time continuum, with of quantum phenomena is . . . the intro-
their various parts definitely located in specific duction of a fundamental distinction be-
regions, then a complete scientific account of tween the measuring apparatus and the ob-
atomic phenomena would, by virtue of the jects under investigation. This is a direct
natural and normal meanings of these words, in consequence of the necessity of accounting
this framework, be required to describe whatever for the functions of the measuring instru-
it was that is located at the points or infinitesimal ments in purely classical terms, excluding in
regions of that continuum. Quantum theory does principle any regard to the quantum of ac-
not do this, and hence a claim of completeness tion. On their side, the quantal features of
would be an abuse of language. the phenomena are revealed in the informa-

1108 I August 1972


The Copenhagen Interpretation

tion about the atomic objects derived from ciated with the atomic object: The atomic object
the observations. While within the scope of represented by the wave function has no meaning
classical physics the interaction between the in quantum theory except via its link to experience
object and apparatus can be neglected or, if formulated in terms of specifications that refer
necessary, compensated for, in quantum to the measuring instruments.
physics this interaction thus forms an in- Bohr evidently believed that there is in atomic
separable part of the phenomena. Accord- processes an element of wholeness—associated
ingly, the unambiguous account of proper with the quantum of action, and completely
quantum phenomena must, in principle, in- foreign to classical physical principles—that cur-
clude a description of all relevant features of tails the utility of the classical idealizations of the
the experimental arrangement (III.3). measuring instruments and atomic objects as
separate, interacting entities, and that the re-
The basic point here is that well-denned objec- sulting inseparability of the atomic object from
tive specifications on the entire phenomenon are the whole phenomenon renders statistical de-
not restrictive enough to determine uniquely the scription unavoidable.
course of the individual processes, yet no further This way of reconciling the pragmatic character
breakdown is possible because of the inherent of quantum theory with the claim of complete-
wholeness of the process symbolized by the quan- ness seems rational and coherent. I t is, of course,
tum of action. based on quantum thinking itself and is therefore
This way of tracing the need for a statistical essentially a self-consistency consideration. The
account of atomic phenomena back to the element validity of quantum-mechanical thinking as a
of wholeness symbolized by the quantum of action whole must, of course, be judged on the basis
appears to take one outside the pragmatic of its success, which includes its coherence and
framework since it refers to the measuring device, self-consistency.
the atomic object, and their interaction. Also, it The question of the completeness of quantum
is not immediately clear how one is to reconcile theory was debated by Bohr22 and Einstein.23
the separate identification of these three things Einstein's counter arguments come down on the
with the "impossibility of any sharp separation following points: (1) It is not proven that the
between the behaviour of the atomic objects and usual concept of reality is unworkable; (2) quan-
the interaction with the measuring instruments tum theory does not make "intelligible" what is
which serve to define the conditions under which sensorily given; and (3) if there is a more com-
the phenomena appear" (11.39). plete thinkable description of nature, then the
In this connection it is important to recognize formulation of the universal laws should involve
that the "atomic object" and "measuring instru- their use.
ments" are, within the framework of quantum Bell's theorem16 deals a shattering blow to Ein-
thinking, idealizations used by scientists to bring stein's position. For it proves that the ordinary
order into man's experience in the realm of atomic concept of reality is incompatible with the sta-
phenomena. This point is developed by the author tistical predictions of quantum theory. These pre-
in Ref. 21. Bohr's words emphasize that these dictions Einstein was apparently willing to accept.
separate idealizations are inseparably linked by Einstein's whole position rests squarely on the
quantum thinking in a way that is completely presumption that sense experience can be under-
foreign to classical thinking. The idealization stood in terms of an idea of some external reality
"the measuring instrument" is a conceptual whose spatially separated parts are independent
entity used in the description of the experimental realities, in the sense that they depend on each
specifications; the idealization "the atomic object" other only via connections that respect space-
is a conceptual entity that is represented by the time separation in the usual way: Instantaneous
wave function. These are inseparably linked in connections are excluded. But the existence of
quantum theory by the fact that the specifica- such a reality lying behind the world of observed
tions described in terms of the measuring in- phenomena is precisely what Bell's theorem proves
strument are mapped onto wave functions asso- to be impossible.

AJP Volume 40 / 1109


Henry Pierce Stapp

Einstein's second point, about whether quan- tions." Specifications are what architects and
tum theory makes intelligible what is sensorily builders, and mechanics and machinists, use to
given, is taken up in the next section. communicate to one another conditions on the
Einstein's third point raises two crucial ques- concrete social realities or actualities that bind
tions. The first is whether a complete descrip- their lives together. It is hard to think of a
tion of nature is thinkable. Can human ideas, theoretical concept that could have a more ob-
which are probably limited by the structural jective meaning. Specifications are described in
form of human brains, and which are presumably technical jargon that is an extension of everyday
geared to the problem of human survival, fully language. This language may incorporate con-
know or comprehend the ultimate essences? And cepts from classical physics. But this fact in no
even if they can, what is the role in nature of way implies that these concepts are valid beyond
universal laws? Is all nature ruled by some closed the realm in which they are used by the
set of mathematical formulas? This might be one technicians.
possibility. Another, quite compatible with present In order to objectify as far as possible our de-
knowledge, is that certain aspects of nature ad- scriptions of the specifications on preparations
here to closed mathematical forms but that the and measurements we can express them in terms
fullness of nature transcends any such form. of the "objective" quantities of classical physics.
The meaning of these "objective" quantities for
VIII. QUANTUM THEORY AND us is tied to the fact that we conceive of them as
OBJECTIVE REALITY
the qualities of an external world that exists
The Copenhagen interpretation is often criti- independently of our perceptions of it. The
cized on the grounds that it is subjective, i.e., formulation of the specifications in terms of these
that it deals with the observer's knowledge of classical quantities allows the human observer
things, rather than those things themselves. This to be eliminated, superficially at least, from the
charge arises mainly from Heisenberg's frequent quantum theoretical description of nature: The
use of the words "knowledge" and "observer." observer need not be explicitly introduced into
Since quantum theory is fundamentally a pro- the description of quantum theory because the
cedure by which scientists make predictions, it connection between his knowledge and these
is completely appropriate that it refer to the classical quantities is then shifted to other do-
knowledge of the observer. For human observers mains of science, such as classical physics, bi-
play a vital role in setting up experiments and ology, psychology, etc.
in noting their results. But this elimination of the observer is simply
Heisenberg's wording, interpreted in a super- a semantic sleight of hand. Since the conceptual
ficial way, can be, and has been, the source of structure of classical physics is recognized as
considerable confusion. It is therefore perhaps fundamentally an invention of the mind that
better to speak directly in terms of the concrete is useful for organizing and codifying experience,
social realities, such as dispositions of instru- the knowledge of the observer emerges, in the
ments, etc., in terms of which the preparations, end, as the fundamental reality upon which the
measurements, and results are described. This whole structure rests. The terms "knowledge of
type of terminology was favored by Bohr, who the observer," or "classical description," or
used the phrase "classical concepts" to signify "specifications" are just different, ways of sum-
descriptions in terms of concrete social actualities. ming up in a single term this entire arrangement
On the other hand, Bohr's terminology, though of ideas, which follows from the recognition of
blatantly objective, raises the question of how the limited domain of validity of classical concepts.
quantum theory can be consistently constructed Bohr cites certain ideas from biology and psy-
on a foundation that includes concepts that are chology as other examples of concepts that work
fundamentally incompatible with the quantum well in certain limited domains. And he notes
concepts. that there have been repeated attempts to unify
Perhaps the most satisfactory term is "specifica- all human knowledge of the basis of one or another

1110 I August 1972


The Copenhagen Interpretation

of these conceptual frameworks.24 Such attempts critical question, however, is not whether there
are the natural outgrowth of the absolutist view- is in fact a world "out there," but rather what the
point, which holds that the ideas of man can connection is between the world "out there"
grasp or know the absolute essences. The pragma- and our ideas about it.
tist, regarding human concepts as simply tools Russell argues, essentially, that we can make
for the comprehension of experience, and averring plausible inferences, based on the structure of
that human ideas, being prisoners in the realm of our experiences, and build up a reasonable idea
human experience, can "know" nothing but other of the outside world. James would insist that
human ideas, would not be optimistic about the this whole structure is nothing but a structure of
prospects of complete success in such ventures. abstract ideas built upon our common experi-
For him progress in human understanding would ences, and that the transexperiential world that
more likely consist of the growth of a web of may somehow "cause" our common experiences
interwoven complementary understandings of never enters into this structure at all.
various aspects of the fullness of nature. James evidently believes that his idea of a
Such a view, though withholding the promise for table is similar to yours and mine. In general,
eventual complete illumination regarding the different people's ideas about sense objects are
ultimate essence of nature, does offer the prospect not identical, but they are similar enough to
that human inquiry can continue indefinitely to form the basis of effective social communication.
yield important new truths. And these can be There exists, in this sense, a realm of public or
final in the sense that they grasp or illuminate shared experiences that form the basis of inter-
some aspect of nature as it is revealed to human personal communication. This realm constitutes
experience. And the hope can persist that man the primary data of science. The aim of science
will perceive ever more clearly, through his grow- is to construct a framework of ideas that will
ing patchwork of complementary views, the link these common, or public, or shared, ex-
general form of a pervading presence. But this periences together in ways that reflect various
pervading presence cannot be expected or re- aspects of the empirical connections that exist
quired to be a resident of the three-dimensional between them. Thus the whole structure of
space of naive intuition, or to be described funda- science is, quite obviously, a structure that is
mentally in terms of quantities associated with wholly confined to the world of ideas.
points of a four-dimensional space-time con- Russell would presumably grant this. But he
tinuum. would argue that we can, nonetheless, make
plausible inferences about the world based on the
APPENDIX A: PHILOSOPHICAL ADDENDA
structure of experience. Yet his commitment to
Several questions of a philosophic nature have rationality requires him, I think, to admit that
been raised by a critic. This appendix contains our ideas might not be able to fully comprehend
my replies. the realities that are the causes of our experience.
Question 1: How does one reconcile the com- And if the evidence of science indicates that this
mitment of James and Bohr to the public charac- possibility is the one realized by nature, then I
ter of sense objects with the radical empiricist think his rational approach, based on plausible
doctrine that ideas can agree only with other inferences drawn from available evidence, would
ideas? Russell's Analysis of Matter indicates the require him to admit that this possibility has a
difficulty in performing this reconciliation. good "probability" of being correct.
Reply: Russell's arguments do not confute the Although the arguments of Russell do not
ideas of James and Bohr as I have described confute the position of James, as I have described
them. Both of the latter authors would, I think, it, there is definitely a basic difference in orienta-
readily admit that human experiences are prob- tion. Russell embarks on a quest for certainty
ably not the whole of reality but are probably about the external world, but settles for an ac-
merely a part of the whole that is related to the count to which he assigns high "probability."
rest via some sort of causal-type connection. The James views the quest for certainty about the

AJP Volume 40 / 1111


Henry Pierce Stapp

external world as totally misdirected. Certainty science that is thoroughly objective, yet securely
in such matters is clearly unattainable. The truly rooted in the realm of ideas and experience.
rational course of action is to admit at the outset Question 2: In the author's article21 on the
that our aim is to construct a framework of ideas S-matrix interpretation of quantum theory it
that is useful for the organization of our experi- was admitted that the pragmatic interpretation
ence—and for the conduct of our lives—and to of quantum theory leaves unanswered deep meta-
put aside the whole vague question about the physical questions about the nature of the world
connection of ideas to nonideas, and the equally itself. And it was noted that the apparent absence
vague question about the "probability" that a of unanalyzable entities in quantum theory sug-
certain scheme of ideas gives us a true or valid gests a "web" structure of nature that somewhat
picture of the world itself. resembles the structure proposed by Whitehead.
In any case, the claim that we can make valid Does the absence of similar remarks in the present
inferences about the world itself acquires cred- work signify a retraction of the earlier views?
ibility only to the extent that a truly adequate Reply: The aim of the present work is to de-
picture of the world itself can be constructed. No scribe the Copenhagen interpretation. More pre-
such picture exists at present. And the difficulties cisely, the aim is to describe this author's under-
in constructing a scientific view of the world standing of the essential common ground of Bohr
itself are precisely those admitted by Russell and Heisenberg on the question of the inter-
himself, namely the incorporation of quantum pretation of quantum theory. The author's own
phenomena and infinitesimal space-time intervals. views are an elaboration upon his understanding
I t is precisely these difficulties that force us to of the Copenhagen interpretation, and are given
fall back to the position of James. in the $-matrix article.
In short, the position of Bohr and James, as
I have described it, is not a denial of the causal APPENDIX B: CORRESPONDENCE WITH
theory of perception. It is simply a recommenda- HEISENBERG AND ROSENFELD
tion that we view science not as a quest for a The views that have been put forth as repre-
metaphysical understanding of that which lies sentations of the Copenhagen interpretation differ
outside the world of ideas, but rather as an in- widely. Thus the question arises whether my de-
vention of the human mind that man constructs scription succeeds in capturing the essence of
for the purpose of incorporating into the world the Copenhagen interpretation as understood by
of human ideas abstract structural forms that cap- Bohr and Heisenberg. To shed light on this
ture certain aspects of the empirical structure of question I inquired of Heisenberg whether the
man's experience. In this undertaking an impor- description given in a first version of this paper
tant class of data are those experiences that are seemed to him basically in accord with the views
common to different human observers, such as of himself and Bohr, or whether it seemed dif-
our common or shared experience of the table ferent in any important way.
about which we all sit. The level of experience at
Heisenberg replied:
which these common experiences are most similar
is the level at which a round table is experienced Many thanks for your letter and for your
as a round table, not as an oval two-dimensional paper on the Copenhagen interpretation. I
visual pattern that depends upon where one sits, think that your text is a basically adequate
or a set of tactile sensations that depend on where description of the Copenhagen interpreta-
one's hand rests. In science we need "objective" tion, and you probably know that Niels Bohr
descriptions of the experienced world. We need was very interested in the ideas of William
descriptions that do not depend on who it is that James. I would, however, like to mention
has the experience. Operational specifications fill one point where you seem to describe the
this need. They are descriptions of possible human Copenhagen interpretation too rigorously.
experiences that do not refer specifically to any On p. 35 you ask the question "Can any
particular individual. They allow us to create a theoretical construction give us testable pre-

1112 I August 1972


The Copenhagen Interpretation

dictions about physical phenomena that can- I am enclosing the English translation of
not be extracted from a quantum theoretical a passage in one of my lectures in which I
description?" and you say that according to have tried to describe the philosophy of
the Copenhagen interpretation no such con- Plato with regard to this point. The English
struction is possible. I doubt whether this is translation was done by an American philos-
correct with respect to, for example, biolog- opher who, as I think, uses the philosophical
ical questions. Logically it may be that the nomenclature correctly. Perhaps we could
difference between the two statements: "The connect this Platonic idea with pragmatism
cell is alive" or "The cell is dead" cannot be by saying: It is "convenient" to consider the
replaced by a quantum theoretical statement ideas as existing even outside of the human
about the state (certainly a mixture of many mind because otherwise it would be difficult
states) of the system. The Copenhagen in- to speak about the world before human minds
terpretation is independent of the decision of have existed. But you see at these points we
this point. It only states that an addition always get easily at the limitation of lan-
of parameters in the sense of classical physics guage, of concepts like "existing," "being,"
would be useless. "idea," etc. I feel that you have still too
Besides that it may be a point in the much confidence in the language, but that
Copenhagen interpretation that its language you will probably find out yourself.
has a certain degree of vagueness, and I doubt
I replied:
whether it can become clearer by trying to
avoid this vagueness. Regarding the question of nonhuman ideas
it seems to me unlikely that human ideas
The paper was revised so as to make it ab-
could emerge from a universe devoid of
solutely clear that the claim of completeness of
idealike qualities. Thus I am inclined to the
quantum theory refers specifically to atomic
view that consciousness in some form must
phenomena. Some superfluous material was elim-
be a fundamental quality of the universe . . . .
inated, and the present Sees. V and VII, with
[However] It is difficult to extract from
their extensive quotations from Bohr, were added.
Bohr's writings any commitment on Platonic
Heisenberg's comments on the revised version
ideals. Indeed, Bohr seems to take pains
were as follows:
to avoid all ontological commitment: He
Many thanks for sending me the new version focuses rather on the question of how we as
of your paper on the Copenhagen interpreta- scientists are to cope with the limited
tion. It is certainly an improvement that you validity of our classical intuitions.
quote Bohr extensively, and your whole In view of Bohr's reluctance to speculate
paper has become more compact and more (in print at least) on the nature of the
understandable after these changes. There is ultimate essences it has seemed to me that
one problem which I would like to mention, the consideration of these matters should not
not in order to criticize the wording of your be considered a proper part of the Copen-
paper, but for inducing you to more investi- hagen interpretation. If the Copenhagen
gation of this special point, which is how- interpretation is considered to be an over-all
ever a very deep and old philosophical prob- world view that coincides with the complete
lem. When you speak about the ideas world views of both you and Bohr, then
(especially in Chap. IV), you always speak there is danger that the Copenhagen in-
about the human ideas, and the question terpretation may not exist; for it is not clear
arises, do these ideas "exist" outside of the (from your respective writings at least)
human mind or only in the human mind? In whether you and Bohr are in complete agree-
other words: Have these ideas existed at ment on all ontological and metaphysical
the time when no human mind existed in questions. Moreover, in your work Physics
the world? and Philosophy you discuss many of these

AJP Volume 40 / 1113


Henry Pierce Stapp

deeper philosophical questions, yet have a completely with your view that the Copen-
separate chapter entitled "The Copenhagen hagen interpretation is not itself a complete
Interpretation." This suggests that "The over-all world view. It was never intended
Copenhagen Interpretation" should be in- to be such a view. I also agree with you that
terpreted in a restricted way. I have inter- Bohr and I have probably not looked upon
preted it to be not the complete over-all the Platonic ideals in exactly the same way,
joint world view of Bohr and yourself, but and therefore there is no reason why you
rather the essential common ground of you should go more into the problems of the
and Bohr on the specific question of how Platonic ideals in your paper. Still there is one
quantum theory should be interpreted. reservation which I have to make in connec-
My practical or pragmatic account of tion with your paper and which I mentioned
quantum theory was based on the account in my last letter. I think that you have too
given in your chapter "The Copenhagen much confidence in the possibilities of lan-
Interpretation." This concrete account jibes guage. I think that the attitude which is
completely with the abstract pronounce- behind the Copenhagen interpretation is not
ments of Bohr, as the quotations of Bohr in compatible with the philosophy of Wittgen-
my Sec. V bear witness. Thus I think it stein in the Tractatus. It may be com-
correct and proper to regard the pragmatic patible with the philosophy contained in the
interpretation of the formalism as an integral later papers of Wittgenstein. As you probably
part of the Copenhagen interpretation. Sim- know, Bertrand Russell liked the Tractatus of
ilarly, I drew from our conversations at Wittgenstein, but disapproved of the later
Munich an understanding of your commit- papers and therefore I could never come to an
ment to the position that quantum theory agreement with Russell on these philosophical
provides for a complete description of atomic questions.
phenomena, and this position seems com-
pletely in accord with that of Bohr. Thus I I replied:
think it correct and proper to regard also Thank you for your very informative letter.
this position as an essential part of the I had not previously fully appreciated the
Copenhagen interpretation. But in view of point you were making, which as I now under-
Bohr's silence on Platonic ideals I would stand it, is this: You regard recognition of
hesitate to include considerations on that imperfectability of language to be an im-
question in my account of the "logical essence portant element of the attitude that lies
of the Copenhagen interpretation." This is behind the Copenhagen interpretation. This
not meant to suggest that the Copenhagen point was not brought into my account of
interpretation bans further search for a com- the Copenhagen interpretation, and is indeed
prehensive world view. It indicates only that somewhat at odds with its avowed aim of
the Copenhagen interpretation is, in my clarity. . . . [ B u t ] scientists must strive for
view, not itself a complete over-all world clarity and shared understandings, since
view: It is merely part of an over-all world without striving even the attainable will not
view; the part that establishes the proper be achieved. . . .
perspective on quantum theory. I empha- Your words on the matters raised in our
sized in the closing passages of my paper correspondence would certainly be extremely
that man's search for a comprehensive world valuable to readers of my article. And any
view is not terminated by the Copenhagen paraphrasing I might make would diminish
interpretation. Rather it is significantly this value. Thus, with your approval, I would
advanced. like to include the full content of your letters
(apart from personal openings and closings)
Heisenberg replied:
in an appendix to my paper, along with
Many thanks for your letter. May I just certain connecting excerpts from my own
briefly answer the relevant questions. I agree letters. I have enclosed a copy of the proposed

1114 I August 1972


The Copenhagen Interpretation

appendix, apart from your reply to the your March 31 title ["Quantum Theory,
present letter. Pragmatism, and the Nature of Space-time"],
the reason being that it does not contain the
Heisenberg replied: "Many thanks for your
phrase "Copenhagen interpretation," which
letter. I agree with your intention to publish my
we in Copenhagen do not like at all. Indeed,
letters in the appendix to your paper." this expression was invented, and is used by
I required also of Rosenfeld, as the close com- people wishing to suggest that there may be
panion and co-worker of Bohr, and prime de- other interpretations of the Schrodinger equa-
fender of his views, for an opinion of the extent tion, namely their own muddled ones. More-
to which my description succeeded in capturing over, as you yourself point out, the same
the essence of the Copenhagen interpretation as people apply this designation to the wildest
it was understood by Bohr. misrepresentations of the situation. Perhaps
Rosenfeld expressed full agreement with my a way out of this semantic difficulty would
account, and gave hearty approval. He went on be for you to say, after having pointed out
to comment on the relationship of Bohr to James. what the difficulty is, that you make use of
I include his remarks because of their historical the phrase "Copenhagen interpretation" in
interest: the uniquely defined sense in which it is
It may interest you to know that I several understood by all physicists who make a
times endeavoured to persuade Bohr to make correct use of quantum mechanics. Surely,
explicit mention of the affinity between his this is a pragmatic definition.
attitude and that of James, but he firmly
refused to do so; not because he disagreed,
* This work was supported by the U. S. Atomic Energy
but because he intensely disliked the idea of
Commission.
having a label stuck onto him. Indeed you I
K. 11. Popper and M. Bunge, in Quantum Theory and
may have noticed that some philosophers Reality, edited by M. Bunge (Springer, New York, 1967).
2
are already busy tracing imaginary influences L . E. Ballentine, Rev. Mod. Phys. 42, 358 (1970).
3
of various philosophers upon Bohr. With re- Quantum Theory and Beyond, edited by E. Bastin (Cam-
gard to William James, I am quite sure that bridge IT. P., Cambridge, Eng., 1970); L. Rosenfeld,
Suppl. Progr. Theoret. Phys. (Extra number) 222 (1965);
Bohr only heard of him from his friend, the J. M. Jauch, E. P. Wigner, and M. M. Yanase, Nuovo
psychologist Rubin, and from myself in the Cimento 48B, 144 (1967); L. Rosenfeld, Nucl. Phys.
'30's. He then expressed enthusiastic ap- A108, 241 (1968); A. Loinger, Nucl. Phys. A108, 245
proval of James' attitude, which he certainly (1968); Arthur Fine, Phys. Rev. D2, 2783 (1970).
4
felt akin to his own; but it is a fact—a very Niels Bohr, Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature
(Cambridge U. P., Cambridge, Eng., 1934); Atomic
significant one, I think,—that James and
Physics and Human Knowledge (Wiley, New York, 1958);
Bohr developed a pragmatic epistemology Essays 1958/1962 on Atomic Physics and Human Knowl-
independently of each other. edge (Wiley, New York, 1963).
5
It might be advisable to add somewhere W. Heisenberg, The Physical Principles of the Quantum
Theory (Dover, New York, 1930); in Niels Bohr and the
in your paper a remark to that effect in order
Development of Physics, edited by W. Pauli (McGraw-Hill,
to avoid further misunderstanding. As a New York, 1955), p. 12; Physics and Philosophy (Harper
matter of fact, I have never myself in the and Row, New York, 1958); Daedalus 87, 95 (1958).
6
papers I wrote on complementarity brought C. F. von Weiszaeker in Ref. 3.
7
the pragmatic aspect of Bohr's thinking in J. von Neumann, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum
Mechanics (Princeton, U. P., Princeton, N. J., 1955).
explicit relation with James, precisely in order 8
E. Wigner, Amer. J. Phys. 3 1 , 6 (1963).
to avoid such misunderstanding. 9
G. Ludwig in Werner Heisenberg und der Physik
unserer Zeit (Friedrich Vieweg, Braunschweig, 1961).
He went on to say: 10
E. Wigner in The Scientist Speculates, edited by I. J.
I notice from your further letters with new Good (Basic Books, New York, 1962), p. 284.
II
Hugh Everett in, Rev. Mod. Phys. 29, 454 (1957).
title pages that you hesitate about the best 12
J. A. Wheeler, Rev. Mod. Phys. 29, 463 (1957).
title for your essay. I have no very strong " B r y c e DeWitt, in Phys. Today 23, 30 (Sept. 1970).
view about this, but I would incline to prefer 14
L. Rosenfeld, Nucl. Phys. A108, 241 (1968).

A JP Volume 40 I 1115
AJP Volume Ifi

20
" D. Bohm, Phys. Rev. 85, 166, 180 (1952). A. Einstein, in Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Physicist,
16
J. S. Bell, Physics (N. Y.) 1, 195 (1964) and Varenna edited by P. A. Schlipp (Tudor, New York, 1951), p. 675.
21
Lectures, Preprint Ref. TH.1220-CERN, Aug. 1970. See H. P. Stapp, Phys. Rev. D3, 1303 (1971).
22
also Ref. 21. N. Bohr, Phys. Rev. 48, 696 (1935) and in Ref. 20,
17
William James, The Meaning of Truth (Univ. Michi- p. 201.
23
gan, Ann Arbor, Mich., 1970). This reference to James does A. Einstein, in Ref. 20, p. 665.
24
not mean that the ideas reviewed in this section are For an interesting and very readable account of the
exactly those of James or wholly those of James. Countless four principal conceptual structures that have been
philosophers have said similar things. advanced as the basis of overall world views see S. C.
18
Reference 17, p. 239. Pepper, World Hypothesis (U. of California Press, Berke-
"Reference 17, p. 217. ley, Calif., 1966).

On the Doppler Effect

B. RAM A derivation of the nonrelativistic Doppler


Physics Department effect as given by Miller 1 proceeds as follows:
New Mexico State University It is asserted that the phase kx — wt of a plane
Las Cruces, New Mexico 88001 wave exp [i (kx—at) J is invariant for two observers
(Received 25 October 1971; revised 18 February 1972) moving uniformly relative to each other.2 This
assertion is justified by associating the phase with
Expressions for the Doppler effect are derived without the number of waves passing a point with co-
employing any assumption about the phase of a plane ordinates (x, t) in the reference frame of the first
wave. It is shown that the invariance of this phase under observer in a time t, with the first wave crest to
both the Galilean and the Lorentz transformations is a reach there being one which passes the origin at
trivial consequence of the mathematics and is independent t=0, and then stating that this number will, of
of its association with any physical process.
course, be equal to the number of waves passing
over the corresponding point with coordinates
(x', t') in the reference frame of the second ob-
server in the time t' =t, the point (xr, t') being such
that it coincides with (x, t) at t = t'. The invariance
of the phase is then used to derive the expression
for the nonrelativistic Doppler effect. The same
derivation is repeated for the relativistic case3
with the exception that the Lorentz transforma-
tion is used in place of the Galilean transformation
to connect the two frames.
Three objections can be raised to this deriva-
tion. First, the validity of the statement that the
number of waves passing the point (x, t) in
the unprimed system in a time t is equal to
the number of waves passing over the corre-
sponding point (a/, t') in the primed system, up
to the time t' = t, is not at all obvious. Second,
while the association of phase with the physical
process of counting may be useful, the invariance
of the phase is completely independent of this
physical association. Third, M0ller's treatment

1116 I August 1972

You might also like