You are on page 1of 122

NOMOS AND

THE BEGINNINGS OF
THE ATHENIAN
DEMOCRACY

OXFORD
AT THE CLARENDON PRESS
1969
GLASGOW I'\EW YORK TORONTO MELBOUR~E WELLINGTOX

CAPE TOWN SALISBURY IBADAN NAIROBI LUSAKA ADDIS ABABA

BOMBAY CALCUTTA MADRAS KARACHI LAHORE DACCA

KUALA LUMPUR SI~GAPORE HONG KONG TOKYO

PRINTED IX GREAT BHITAIX

AT THE UNIVERSITY PUESS, OXFORD

BY VIVIAN RIDLEH.

PH.INTER TO THE UNIVERSITY


might almost be described as accidental that this has become

I
T

a book about Cleisthenes and his reforms. However, in looking


back upon its beginnings, it seems to me that the inner logic
of my initial design inevitably led to Cleisthenes. Stimulated by
my teacher, Professor Kurt von Fritz, then of Columbia Univer-
sity and now of the University of Munich, I had long been inter-
ested in the meaning of the expression aypaepos vOfLoS. Not only
the standard monograph on this problem, published by Rudolf
Hirzel as long ago as I goo, but also sporadic (and usually
incidental) remarks about it in current scholarly publications
seemed to me to be misguided in making the tacit assumption
that one single definable concept underlies the expression, and
gradually led me to the conviction that its adjectival part,
aypaepos, though not free from problems, is less problematic
than the noun vOfLos, whose connotations are too numerous and
diffuse to be capable of being reduced to one or two equivalents,
such as 'law' and 'custom', in a modern language. In order to
explain why the adjective aypaepos could be applied to some
kinds of VOfLOL but not to others, even though these were also un-
written, the first and most important step seemed to be to subject
vOfLoS to an exhaustive and systematic analysis of all its connota-
tions, and a leave of absence from my teaching duties in 1961-2
gave me the leisure necessary to complete this part of the study.
In the course of this investigation a new and, I believe, more
profound problem began to demand attention. \Vhat I had re-
garded as the most common connotation of vOfLOS, 'statute',
'law', proved not only to be much less common in the fifth
century than other connotations of the term but also to be first
attested for Athens as late as 464/3 B.C. This necessitated an
expansion of my study to include BWfLos, the word which Draco
and Solon had used to describe their statutes, and I was sur-
prised to discover that BWfLo, and vOfLoS do not overlap chrono-
logically in the sense of 'statute': I could find no example of
a legal-political BWfLoS in Athens enacted after 464/3 B.C. and
no example of a legal-political vOfLO, before that date. Although
none of our ancient sources explicitly informs us of a change in University of Pennsylvania read the finished typescript in its
Athenian terminology from eWfLOS to vOfLoS, the evidence for such entirety; Mr. Russell Meiggs of Balliol College, Oxford, read
a change and the suspicion that it must have taken place at an carlier version of Parts II and III, Dr. Victor Ehrenberg of
a specific point in time and as a result of a deliberate policy London read the entire book in proof, and Mr. G. E. M. de Ste.
were so strong that I decided to track it down, and the outcome Croix of New College, Oxford, not only provided encouragement
of that decision is the present book. and stimulation, but did much else to make our stay in Oxford
Basically, therefore, this book contains the philological study in 1965~6 as rich as it was. I want here to express my profound
of two Greek words which played a crucial part in Athenian gratitude to them all and to assure them that they bear no re-
political thought. Since my main concern here is with eWfLos sponsibility for the imperfections that remain.
and VOfLoS in the sense of 'statute', I chose the end of the fifth I wish to record my gratitude also to a number of institutions
century as the lower limit of my inquiry, because by that time which made the completion of this book possible: Swarthmore
vOfLoS can be shown to be firmly entrenched as the official term Collegc granted me the two leaves of absence from my teaching
for 'statute'. In order to find the possible historical circumstances obligations which enabled me, the one to begin, and the other to
of the change, it seemed necessary first to discover the basic finish the book, and through its Faculty Research Fund provided
ideas underlying eWfLoS and vOfLoS so as to see as clearly as possible secretarial and other kinds of material assistance; a research
the relation of the sense of 'statute' to other connotations and grant from the Fulbright Commission made it possible to spend
thus to find a guide to the general atmosphere in which the 1961-2 in Greece, where I enjoyed the hospitality of the American
change may have taken place. The result of this endeavour, School of Classical Studies; and the award of a fellowship by the
namely that eWfLoS describes a statute as an enactment imposed American Council of Learned Societies gave me the opportunity
from above, whereas VOfLOS regards it as the ratification of what is to complete this book in essence during my second leave, in
generally regarded as valid and binding, pointed to a connection 1965-6, under the best possible conditions in Oxford.
between VOfLOS and the beginnings of the Athenian democracy. Finally, I wish to thank my pupil, Miss M. Rachel Kitzinger,
Since, however, no word for 'statute' is preserved in any text for her effective help in compiling the Bibliography and the
from the more than forty years between the establishment of Index Locorum, and the staff of the Clarendon Press for their
democracy and the earliest occurrence of vOfLoS = 'statute' in constant and cheerful help in editing and publishing this book.
464/3 B.C., my second task was to try to narrow the gap by a MARTIN OSTWALD
more circuitous route. Accordingly, I examined every occur-
rence to the end of the fifth century of all those -vol1'0S compounds Swarthmore College
which appear in Greek writings before 464/3 B.C. Only one of and the University of Pennsylvania
these, laovofLLa, turned out to have strictly political connotations, August 1968
and the fact that the earliest occurrence of its adjective, laovofLos,
can be fairly precisely dated in the period of the overthrow of the
Peisistratid tyranny and the establishment of the Cleisthenean
democracy enabled me to marshal what I believe to be strong
reasons for the adoption of vOfLoS in place of eWfLoS as an integral
part of Cleisthenean policy.
Many kind friends and colleagues on both sides of the Atlantic
have generously helped with advice and suggestions. Professor
A. Andrewes and Mr. A. R. W. Harrison of Oxford and
Professors Henry M. Hoenigswald and Charles H. Kahn of the
PART I

BWf-Loc; and NOf-LoC;

I. BWf-LOC;

2. NOf-LoC;

3. Summary and Conclusion

PART II

NOf-LoC;becomes 'Statute'
1. The Problem Defined 57
2. Evvof-L{a, L1vavof-L{a, and }4vof-L{a 62

3. ' Iaovof-L{a and Athens 96

PART III

Nomos and the Beginnings of the Athenian Democracy


I. ' Iaovof-L{a, Cleisthenes, and NOf-LoC; I37

2. The Originality of Cleisthenes I6I

ENDNOTES I74

BIBLIOGRAPHY I86

INDEX LOCORUM I97

GREEK INDEX 2I2


THIS list does not include abbreviations in general use. When footnote
references are in the form 'op. cit.' or 'loco cit.' full particulars of the work
referred to will be found within the preceding half-dozen pages. The
collections from which fragments are cited are identified in the Index
Locorum.
Andrewes, Eun. A. Andrewes, 'Eunomia', CQ32 (1938) 89-102.
Bowra, GLP C. M. Bowra, Greek Lyric Poetryt (Oxford, 1961).
Brunnsiiker S. Brunnsiiker, The Tyrant Slayers of Kritios and
Nesiotes (Lund, 1955).
G. Busolt and H. Swoboda, Griechische Staatskunde,
2 vols. (Munich, 1920 and 1926).
Buck, GD C. D. Buck, The Greek Dialects (Chicago, 1955).
Busolt, GG G. Busolt, Griechische Geschichte2, 1-2 (Gotha,
1893-5); 31 (Gotha, 1897-1904).
W. Dittenberger, Sylloge inscriptionum Graecarum3
(Leipzig, 1915).
V. Ehrenberg, 'Eunomia', Aspects rif the Ancient
World (Oxford, 1946) 70-93.
-- Die Rechtsidee im friihen Griechentum (Leipzig,
1921).
-GS -- The Greek State (Oxford, 1960).
-- Ison. -- RE, supp!. 7 (1940) 293-301, s.v. 'Isonomia'.
-aD -- 'Origins of Democracy', Historia 1 (1950)
515-48.
-- 'Das Harmodioslied', Wiener Studien 69 (1956)
57-69.
H. Frisk, Griechisches etymologisches Worterbuch
(Heidelberg, 1960- ).
Gigante, NB M. Gigante, Nomos Basileus (Naples, 1956).
Gomme, HCT A. W. Gommc, A Historical CommentaT)' on ThuC)'-
dides, 3 vols. (Oxford, 1945-56).
W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy,
2 vols. (Cambridge, 1962 and 1965).
Heinimann, NP F. Heinimann, Nomos und Physis (Basel, 1945).
Hignett, HAC C. Hignett, A History of the Athenian Constitution to
the End of the Fifth Century B.C. (Oxford, 1952).
R. Hirzel, "'Aypa1Jo<; N6/Lo<;", Abh. d. philol.-hist. Cl.
d. Kgl. Sachs. Ges. d. Wiss. 20. I (Leipzig, 1900).
-- Themis, Dike und Verwandtes (Leipzig, 1907).
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

F. Jacoby, Atthis: The Local Chronicles of Ancient


Athens (Oxford, 1949).
W. Jaeger, 'Solons Eunomie', Sber. d. Preuss. Ak. d.
Wiss. Philos.-hist. Kl. (Berlin, 1926) 69-85.
L. H. Jeffery, The Local Scripts of Archaic Greece
(Oxford, 1961).
G. S. Kirk, Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments (Cam- }4ypaepo/ OE vOfko/ TUS apxus J.t~ xpija()at J.tl)OE 71'EPLEVOs. if;~epwJ.ta OE
bridge, 1954). J.tl)OEv J.t~TE {3ovAijs J.t~TE O~J.tov voJ.tov KVPLWTEPOV E[vaL. This law,
G. S. Kirk andJ. E. Raven, The Presocratic Philoso- cited by Andocides in his speech On the Mysteries, not only set the
phers (Cambridge, 1957).
seal on the revised law code adopted by the restored democracy at
E. Laroche, Histoire de la racine NEM- en grec ancien Athens in 403/2 B.C.,! but marks also the conclusion of a curious
(Paris, 1949).
development in Athenian political terminology. From the end of
J. A. O. Larsen, 'Cleisthenes and the Development
?f th~ !heory of Democracy at Athens', Essays
the fifth century on, the primary connotation of v0J.t0s in legal as
1n Polztzcal Theory Presented to G. H. Sabine (Ithaca, well as in non-legal literature and documents is that of 'statute' ;
N.Y., 1948) 1-16. it signifies a-usually written-enactment which had either
J. H. Lipsius, Das attische Recht und Rechtsverfahren been embodied in the law code at the time of its completion in
3 vols. (1.eipzig, 1905-15). ' 403/2 B.C. or had been incorporated into it additionally through
R. Meiggs and A. Andrewes (edd.), Sources for the cumbersome procedure of V0J.t0()wLa.2 This does not mean of
Greek History between the Persian and Peloponnesian
course that voJ.tos, especially outside the orators, ceased hence-
Wars, collated and arranged by G. F. HilI
(Oxford, 1951). forth to carry the several non-legal meanings which had attached
PMG D. L. Page, Poetae Melici Graeci (Oxford, 1962). to it before;3 but it does mean that the law intended to deprive
Podlecki A. J. Podlecki, 'The Political Significance of the of legal validity any voJ.tos which was not written and, we may
Athenian "Tyrannicide" -Cult', Historia 15 (1966) assume, officially published in an authoritative manner.4
129-41.
H. J. Rose, A Commentary on the Surviving Plays of I Andoc. I. 87, cr. also 85, and Dem. 24. 30. For the date see D. MacDowell,
Aeschylus, 2 vols. (Amsterdam, 1957-8). Andokides: On the Mysteries 197.
2 For this procedure in the fourth century see Dem. 24. 20-3 with R. Scholl,
E. Schwyzer, Dialectorum Graecarum exempla epi-
'Ueber attische Gesetzgebung', Sber. d. philos.-philol. Cl. d. k. bay. Ak. d. Wiss.
graphica potiora (Leipzig, 1923). Miinehen 1886,83-139;]. H. Lipsius, Berliner philologisehe Woehensehrift 37 (1917)
F. Solmsen, Hesiod and Aeschylus (Ithaca, N.Y., 902-12; BS 2. 1010-14; U. Kahrstedt, 'Untersuchungen zu athenischen Behorden',
1949)· Klio 31 (1938) 1-25; and F. Wotke in RE, supp!' 7 (1940), S.v. NOfJoo8ETa"578-81.
H. E. Stier, "N6fkoS BaazAEVs", Philologus83 (1928) Hignett's view, HAC 300, that the Teisamenus decree in Andoc. I. 83-4 is the first
instance of this procedure, has to be modified in the light of the objections raised by
225-58.
A. R. W. Harrison, 'Law-making at Athens at the End of the Fifth Century B.C.',
M. N. Tod, A Selection of Greek Historical Inscriptions, ]HS 75 (1955) 33-5, and by MacDowell, op. cit. 123.
2 vols. (Oxford, 19462 and 1948). 3 In some examples taken at random from Plato VOfJoOS denotes (a) a conven-
Vlastos, Ison. G. Vlastos, AJP 74 (1953) 337-66.
'Isonomia', tionallinguistic usage (Crat. 384 d 7,388 d 12, Tim. 60 e 2); (b) a customary prac-
--IP -- '''Iaovofk{a71'OAtTlK.ry", in J. Mau and E. G. tice (Symp. 182 a 7, Laws 7. 795 a I); (e) a conventional belief (Corg. 482 e 6, Laws
10.889 e 6, 890 d 4,6,904 a 9); (d) a norm of individual behaviour (Rep. 9. 587
Schmidt ;edd.), Isonomia: Studien zur Gleichheits-
c 2, 10.604 a 10, b 6,9,607 a 7, Polito 291 e 2, Laws 2. 674 b 7,8.835 e 5,836 e 4);
vorstellung im griechischen Denken (Berlin, 1964) 1-35. (e) a religious practice (Phaedo 58 b 5, Phaedr. 256 d 7); (f) a condition oflaw-and-
H. T. Wade-Gery, Essays in Greek History (Oxford, order (Rep. 9. 587 a 10, Laws 6. 780 d 5, 10. 904 c 9).
1958). 4 Andoc. I. 86 and 89 show that aypaqJOSis here the opposite not of YEypafJofJoEvOS

U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Aristoteles und but of Q.vayEypafJofJoEvos.


No proof is required to show that vOfJoOS refers primarily to
Athen, 2 vols. (Berlin, 1893). written statutes in the orators. For usage in the inscriptions see Tod, CHI 2,
Nos. 100.6, 116.21, 162. 15, [36], 181. 25, 200. 217,246. But laws governing inter-
state relations, especially those involving religious sanctions, were presumably
814277 B
INTRODUCTION 3

There is evidence that the distinction between vOfloS and legal validity are concerned, it is nevertheless as true for the fifth
ifi~~tafla, which the law of 403/2 B.C. tried to establish, although century as it is for the fourth that vOfloS enjoyed the greater
it had broken down in practice by the middle of the fourth prestige, probably because it was regarded as the more per-
century, remained valid in Greek legal thought. I In the fifth manent regulation of the two. Thus, while the nature of Solon's
century, however, there seems to have been little difference , office and the manner in which his legislation was enacted
theoretically or practically, between these two terms either in explains why later authors referred to his laws as VOflOt but never
form, content, or legal validity.2 In order to have legal authority, as ifi1)~{aflaTa, it is remarkable that the laws of Cleisthenes, which
all that mattered in fifth-century Athenian democracy was that were doubtless validated by the vote of the Athenian Assembly
a measure had been passed by a majority vote of the Council and may well have taken the form of ¢rfJ~{aflaTa, are also in-
or the Assembly or of both and that no successfulaction had been variably called VOflOt, never ifi7)~taflaTa.I
~rought against it in court under the ypa~~ 7Tapavoflwv,3 and The fact that the law cited by Andocides affirms a higher status
SInceall Athenian VOflOt as well as ifi7)~taflaTa, with the exception for VOftas than for ifi~~tafla would in itself not be remarkable,
of Solon's laws, were enacted in this manner, ifi~~wfla seems to be were it not for the circumstance that statutes had not always been
merely a procedural term, derived from the fact that the measure called vOflOt in Athens. Draco and Solon, to whom the earliest
was approved by voting (ifi1)~{~€tv),4 while vOfloS describes the written lerrislation in Athens is attributed (Arist. Ath. Pol. 41. 2,
same measure substantively as a statute.s ,'"
7. I), referred to their enactments not as VOflOt but as BWlwt.
Still, even though we cannot determine any difference between For Draco himself, we have only one text, the re-publication in
vOflOS and ifi~~wfla in the fifth century as far as form, content, and 409/8 B.C. of some of his laws on homicide, which refers to itself
as a BWfloS;z but BWfLOS is so well and so widely attested in later
nei,ther ~ritten nor published; e.g. Tod, GHI2, No. 137. 13-14, where the Aetolian
Tnchomans are accused of having arrested the U1TOVSOepOPOtof the Greater Eleusinian
descriptions of his legislation that there can be no doubt that it
Mysteries 1Tapa Tavs v6J.LoUS T[OVS' KOl.V]ovs TWV rEAA~vwv. was the only technical term he used for his statutes.3 In the case of
'Dem. 20. 92, delivered in 355 B.C., denies any difference between the two, Solon, we know that at least one of the laws on the axones re-
whereas the distinction is maintained by Arist. EN 5. 10, I I 37b28-9, and Pol. 4. 4,
1292a36-7· .On thi~ point see the remarks of Harrison, op. cit. 26-35, esp. 27.
ferred to itself as BWflos, 4 and that in his poems he calls his
2 The eVIdence IS best assembled and discussed by]. Schreiner, De corpore iuris enactments BWfw{ but never VOflOt.s Moreover, it is likely that
Atheni~n;ium 16., Cf. als? ~ilamowitz, AA 2. 1.93, and Kahrstedt, op. cit. 17-18. the oath exacted from the nine archons, which is placed into
B. Ked s ~ssertlOn, Grzechlsche Staatsaltertiimer In Gercke-Norden, Einleitung in die
AltertumswIssenschaft 32• 381, approved by BS 1. 459 with n. 2, that 'das Unter-
the context of Solon's reforms by both Aristotle and Plutarch,
scheidende ist eben nicht der Inhalt, sondern die Form', applies to the fourth I Tbat Cleisthenes' legislation was submitted to the Assembl): and presumably
century rather than to the fifth.
also to the Council is implied in Hdt. 5.66. 2,69.2, as well as Anst. Ath. Pol. 20. I,
3 The introdu~tory. formula for most enactments, ESOtEV 'Tfj f30UAfj Ka1 'Tip S~fL'I', 4,21. 1-2. That it took the form of.p1J<P{UfL(J.'Ta is forcefully argued by Wade-Gery,
suggests that r~tIficatlOn by both Council and Assembly was normally required. Essays 135-54, esp. 139-47. 2 See below, p. 5 n. I.
But the SalamIS decree (IG 12• 1. I), the Hecatompedon inscription (IG 12• 3. 16 3 Arist. Ath. Pol. regularly uses I)wfLo{ of Draco's legislation (see 4. I, 7. I); the
and 4·26), and perhaps also Xen. Mem. 1. 2.42 show that sometimes ratification decree of Teisamcnus of 403 B.C. (Andoc. 1. 83, cr. 81) speaks of the vO/-,Ot of Solon
by the SfjfLos alone, and [Xen.] Ath. Pol. 3. 2 that occasionally approval by the but of Draco's I)w/-,o{; and as late as the third century A.D. Porphyry, De abstinentia 4.
f3ouA~ alone, was sufficient. The date of the introduction of the ypaep-Tj 1TapavofLwv is
not .known; t~e earliest attested case was brought in 415 B.C. by Andocides' father
agaInst SpeuSIppuS (Andoc. I. 17) ; Antiphon's speech against the general Demos-
°
22, could speak of a Draconian I)EU/-,OS.
• Plut. Solon 19. 4: O'TE I)w/-,os .epav1J oS•.
5 Solon, frg. 24. 18-20: I)((J/-'OVS ... Eypa.pa; cr. also the two lines cited by Plut.
thenes ma~ have been a little earlier, but cannot be dated on the basis of [Plut.] Solon 3. 5: I)w/-,ois 'TOiuS. 'TUX~V a.yal)~v Ka1 KDSos o7T<iuuat.- The reading of frg. 24.
Life of Anttphon 20 (= Mar. 833 d). See Hignett, HAC 210-13.
15-16: Kpa'TEL I vO/-,ou f3{1JV'T' Ka1 S{K1JV uuvap/-,ouas, which is based on the London
4 Although the voting procedure in fifth-century Athens no longer involved the papyrus of Arist. Ath. Pol. 12. 4, is less satisfactory than that based on the Berlin
castIng of a pebble (.pfjepos) but took place by a show of hands ; see BS 2. 1000 with papyrus, which reads o/-,oD in place of VOfLOU.The reading o/-'oD is also supported by
n·3·
the quotation of these lines in Plut. Solon 15, and in Aelius Aristeides 28.138 (Keil).
.5 Cf. K~hrstedt, op. cit. 17-18, esp. 18; 'Vor 403 bedeutet Psephisma iiberhaupt
As has been rightly stressed by Ehrenberg, Eun. 82, the choice is not of a lectio
k~me bestlmmte Art von BeschluB, sondern den Modus procedendi bei der difficilior. The decisive arguments against vO/-,ou are its inappropriateness in the
Schaffung von Nomoi.'
context of Solon's seisachtheia and the fact that it does not carry the sense of either
4 INTRODUCTION

included a promise to abide by the 8wp.,ot.l Finally, a fragment of This does not mean, of course, that 8wp.,oswas no longer
Cratinus' Nomoi (frg. 127), which is believed to have been spoken applied to the legislation of Draco and Solon after the end of the
by Solon, confirms that 8wp.,oswas the Solonian expression for sixth century. But it is interesting to note that the older term
'statute', and, according to Aristotle (Ath. Pol. 35. 2), it was from was used for antiquarian and not for substantive reasons. This is
Solon's 8wp.,ot that the Thirty removed ambiguities. proved by the fact that simultaneously with 8wp.,os the new ~erm
After Solon, it is probable that 8wp.,osremained the technical for 'statute', vop.,oc;, is also applied to Draco's and Solon:s le?lsla-
term for 'statute' at least throughout the tyranny, if we may draw tion. A striking example of this appears in the re-publIcatIOn of
this conclusion from Herodotus' assertion (I. 59. 6) that Peisis- Draco's law on homicide, to which reference was made above.
tratus did not change the 8EUp.,W of Athens, and from the pre- For while the Draconian law speaks of itself as a 8wp.,os,the decree
script of a regulation dating from the time of the expulsion of authorizing its re-publication, which precedes it, refers to it as
the Peisistratids, in which the old Draconian legislation against a VOp.,OS.1 Similarly, Andocides and Aristotle use 8wp.,os and vop.,os
tyranny is described as 8EUp.,W Ka~ 7fUTpW.2 Thereafter it is only indifferently when they speak of Draco's laws,2 although most
in the archaic (or at least arehaizing) language of the ephebic fourth-century authors speak of them only as VOp.,OL.3The same is
oath3 and oflocal religious ritual4 and in the elevated language of true of the terminology applied to Solon's laws. Aristotle spe~ks
poetry, where we do not expect to find strict legal terminology, in his own person only of VOp.,OLwhen he dis~usses the S~l?man
that 8wp.,osretains its Solonian meaning after the end of the reforms in Ath. Pol. 7-12; but when he descnbes the reVlSlonof
sixth century.s The evidence points, accordingly, to 511/10 B.C., the laws by the Thirty, he differentiates between the VOp.,OL of
the year in which the Peisistratids were expelled, as the latest Ephialtes and Archestratus and the 8wp.,ol of Solon (Ath. Pol.
current use of 8wp.,os--or, more correctly, its derivative 8EUp.,LOV- 35.2). The decree ofTeisamenus, on the other hand, confines the
in the sense of 'statute'. old term 8wp.,osto Draco but uses VOp.,OLofSolo~'s ~tat~tes (Ando~.
I. 83), and from the mid fifth century on It IS vop.,os that IS
'law' or 'norm' elsewhere in Solon; see Ehrenberg, Eun. 82-4-, and A. Masaracchia,
Solone 34-7-9, where also the most important modern discussions are cited. normally used of the Solonian laws.4
I Plut. Solon 25. 3: W/-,VVEV ... 18lws I)' EKauTos n;,v OW/-,OOET(;JV EV ayopq 7TPOS T0 We shall postpone until later a discussion of when vop.,os first
)"{8<.p KaTarPaT{~wv EL 71- 7Tupaf3a{YJ TWV 8EGp.fiJV, avoplcLvTU xpvaouv laoftETpYJTov ava8~-
UftV EV .d.€Aq;ofs; cf. Arist. Ath. Pol. 7. I: CL 8' fVV€U apxovTES O/-LVVVTES 7Tpas 70 'Al84J
came to occupy the place which had been reserved for 8wp.,os
KaTErpaTL{ov dvae~a£Lv Uvopu.lvru XPVGoiJv, Jav Twa 7Tapa{3wr:JL TWV VOJLwv. 'The use in until at least 511/10 B.C., and content ourselves for the moment
both passages of KaTac/JaTl'w (according to LSJ, not attested elsewhere in Greek with the observation that vop.,oc; was well established as the only
literature) suggests a common source. Plut.'s independence and more faithful
adherence to the original formula is indicated by two details missing in Arist. but
current technical legal term for 'statute' by the time the law cited
corroborated by P!. Phaedr. 235 d: (a) the statue is to be life-size, and (b) it is to be by Andocides was enacted in 403/2 B.C. What our discussion so
set up at Delphi. On the use of Ow/wl in the formula see also F. Jacoby, FCH 3b, far has shown is that at some point between these two dates the
supp!' I (1954-)312, who suggests that Plut.'s 'Ow/-,oOETaL instead of apxovTES is rather
a mannerism than a mistake'.
technical term for 'statute' in Athens changed from 8€up.,os to
2 Arist. Ath. Pol. 16. ro, with my article in TAPA 86 (1955) 106~9, esp. ro8-9. vop.,os and that the two terms exclude one another: before the
3 Tod, CHI 2, No. 204-. 12, with Stob. Flor. 4-. I. 48, and Pollux 8. ro6, as col-
lated by W. Hofmann, De iurandi apud Atheniensesformulis 28-38. I For the law, IC 12• II5 (= Tod, CHI I" No. 87) 19-20: [Kat hot 7TpO]T€[P]?V
4 B. D. Meritt, Hesperia 36 (1967) 72-84- (No. 15), publishes a 'new inscription of ICTE[v]a[vTES EV T]0[,8E TO' Ow/-,o, EVEXEcrOOV .(restoration~ ~uaranteed ,by the, lex m
[TOS apxalos] Ow[/-,o,] ... undertaken after a period of war and desolation when [Dem.] 43. 57). For the introductory enablmg decree, Ibid. ~-5.: [T]O[V] L1paKovToS
much that was sacred had been destroyed by the enemy' (84), which he believes v0J.'OV TO/-, 7TEP<TO c/J[Ov]o. See also Jacoby, Atthis 30~ n. ?4·Similarly I?em. 23·62
contains a deme-decree of Mclite replacing some of the stones destroyed by the quotes an ancient statute (without, however, nammg Its author) whIch refers to
Persians at the Therrikleion, the shrine of the phratry of the Therrikleidai. If he is itself as a Om/-,o,> while Dem. himself calls it a vO/-,OS.
correct, the original regulation may well date back to the sixth century or earlier. 2 Andoc. 1. 8; and I. 83 OEu/-,ol, but I. 82 vO/-,OL. Arist. Ath. Pol. 4· I and 7·1
But the fragmentary state of the inscription invites caution. O€u/-,os, but 41. 2 and Pol. 2. 12, 1274b15-16 vO/-,os.
S e.g. Aesch. Eum. 484-, 571,615, 68l ; Soph. Aj. 1104, Ant. 801, Trach. 682; Eur. 3 e.g. Xen. Gecon. 14.4; Dem. 20. 158,23. 51; Xenarchus, frg. 4·?2. ,
Med. 494-, Tro. 267, frg. 360. 45; Ar. Av. 33 I; and the epigram on the dead of 4 First in Hdt. I. 29. For a summary of ancient references to Soloman vo/-,o, see
Phyle cited hy Aeschines 3. 190. W. Aly, RE, s.v. 'Solon', 958-70.
INTRODUCTION 7

expulsion of the Peisistratids no VOfLOt were enacted in Athens, helped methodologically by the fact that 'statute' is not the ~nly
and there were no new 8wfLo{ after at least the end of the fifth connotation of 8WfL6s and V6fLOS. Both terms have a great vanety
century. The fact that this change in terminology occurred has of uses, and by ascertaining what they are and by classi£y~ng
often been noticed, but its significance has not yet received the
I them we shall be able to discover the basic concept underlymg
attention it deserves, and the problems which it raises have, to each term in its own right and, consequently, determine the
the best of my knowledge, never been recognized. differences between them. This means that our first task is to
The first and most fundamental problem may be formulated: examine every occurrence of 8WfL6s and v6fLoS in Greek lite~ary
why did the change take place at all? In Greek, as in English, and epigraphic documents with a view to establishing the v~nous
the terminology applied to social and political institutions tends categories in which each term is used. In doing so ther? WIll be
in general to be conservative. Expressions once adopted usually no need to take into consideration the whole of Greek lIterature
survive the vicissitudes of changing historical situations and con- and all Greek inscriptions; for since the law cited by Andocides
tinue to be applied even when the original term no longer pro- shows that by 403/2 B.C. v6fLos was firmly entrenched as .the
vides an accurate or modern description of the institution which authoritative legal term for 'statute' in Athens, it will be suf?Cl~nt
it identifies, and often the incumbents of an office are no longer to examine all occurrences of 8WfL6s and v6fLoS from the begmnmg
aware why their office or why an institution accompanying it of Greek writing to the end of the fifth century. ~or it is wi~hin
bears the name that it does. This is in our times true in the that period that the change began and reached I~SconclUSIOn.
United States of the Department of 'State', for example, which This stage of our investigation will be ~ndertaken m. Part .1.
acttttlly handles foreign affairs, and in Great Britain of the The results arrived at in that part WIllbe helpful m trymg to
'Chancellor of the Exchequer', the 'First Sea Lord', and many answer a second problem posed by the fact that v6fLoS came to
other offices and institutions. In Athens, the office of 8WfL08ETYJS supersede 8eufL6s as the official term for 'statute' in Athens. If,
survived long after 8eufL6s had fallen into disuse as a political for reasons still to be ascertained, the Athenians wanted a new
term, and a (3aatAeDS was annually elected long after kingship word to take the place of 8WfL6s in the sense of 'statute', why did
had ceased to exist as a constitutional form. Moreover, the they choose V6fLOS? It cannot be argued that no word other th~n
vaVKpapOt seem to have lost their original association with ships vOfLoS was available to them either in the G~eek ~anguage ~n
already in Solon's time,2 and it is very doubtful whether the general or in the Ionic dialect in particular. lomc ChIOScalled Its
KWAaKpETat of the fifth century B.C. remembered the functions of statutes !)'T]Tpat in the early sixth century B.C.,I and the same te.rn~
the officialswho bore this title originally.3 One would expect this was used not only by such Dorian states as Sparta,2 Messema,
kind of conservatism also to extend to the technical term for Tarentum 4 and Heracleia,5 but also at Olympia6 and on Cyprus.7
'statute'. Accordingly, the fact that in Athens a change from Derived f:om the same root as MTpa is the participial form TCt
8WfLoS to vOfLoS took place is a sufficiently striking phenomenon to EipYJfLEva, which is attested as a term for 'statute' at Mycenae.8
infer that it reflects a deeper change in Athenian thinking about 1 Tod, CHI 12, No. 1. 2 ; Jeffery, LSAC, pI. 65, No. 41. A. 2, dated 575-550 B.C.
the nature of law and the attitude of the Athenians toward their by the same author in BSA 51 (1956) 159-60. .
2 For the pfj"Tpat of Lycurgus see Pluto Lycurgus 6 and 13; Suda (= PhotIUs), S.V.
laws. For since language is the image of thought, a significant
pfj"Tpat. For later Spartan pfj"Tpat see Xen. Anab: 6. 6. 28 (spoken before a Spartan
change in terminology is likely to reflect an important change in judge against a Spartan defendant) ; Pluto AgIs 5, 8, 9, I I ; and IC 5· I, 20. 2-3
thinking. (age of Trajan).
3 IC 5. I, 1498. 12 (early second century B.C.).
In attempting to assess the significance of this change, we are
4 Suda (= Photius), S.v. pfj"Tpat.
1 See especially Hirzel, AN 49 and TD V 358, :3 73-8; Ehrenberg, Rechtsidee I 13- 5 IC 14. 645. 145-6 and 151 (late fourth century B.C.). .
14; and Heinimann, NP 72 with n. 42. 6 Schwyzer, DCE, Nos. 412, 413, 414, and 409, all of the late Sixth or early
2 Arist. Ath. Pol. 8. 3, with H. Hommel, RE, s.v. 'Naukraria', 1938-46. Cf. also fifth century B.C.; see Jeffery, LSAC 218 and 220, Nos. 5,6,8, and 15·
F. Wiist, Historia 6 (1957), 176-8, and Ehrenberg, CS 30-1. 7 Buck, CD, No. 23. 28-9 (second half of fifth century B.C.).
3 BS 1. 589 and Frisk, CEW, S.v. KwAaKpl"Ta,. 8 IC 4. 493: Ko. "To. >€ FP€flolva (early fifth century B.C.).
8 INTRODUCTION

Also available was 'TO ypuepos, which occurs side by side with
p~'Tpa in some of the sixth-century inscriptions from Olympia,
where it refers no doubt to a written law;' 'Tn ypujLjLa'Ta or some
periphrasis involving the verb ypuepw, which is the way in which
the fifth-century code ofGortyn invariably refers to itself;2 a Ci80s,
which appears in Halicarnassus about 460-455 B.C. as a term for
a regulation ratified by an assembly;3 or a alvoc;, which is attested
in a legal sense for Epidaurus and for Delphi.4 It cannot be said,
either, that the Athenians chose v6jLoC; simply because 8wjL6c; was
vanishing as the term for 'statute' in the Greek world. For we
know of TegeaS and of the Locrians6 that their term for 'statute'
was 8€ujL6c; until at least the early fifth century B.C. In other
words, it was not inevitable that v6jLoc; should have been chosen HE recognition that 'statute' is not the only sense in which
to occupy the place left vacant by the abandonment of 8wjL6c;,
for many alternative terms were current elsewhere in the Greek
world to describe a statute.
T 8WfL6c; and v6jLoC; are used in Greek constitutes a ~on:enient
point of departure for our attempt to assess the slgmficance
of the abandonment of 8WfL6c; in favour of v6fLoS. An examina-
Obviously, the question why v6jLoc; came to supersede 8WfL6c; is tion of every occurrence of each of these terms in Greek writings
closely linked with the answer to the question when the change will enable us to determine what particular associations attach
took place. Only after we have some idea of the historical to each and what basic idea, if any, underlies each. And once
circumstances that may have constituted the framework within that has been established, it will be possible to determine how
which the change took place can we venture to surmise what the O€ujL6c; and v6jLoC; are, each in its own way, related to a concept
cause may have been which gave v6jLoS its exalted position in of 'statute'.
Athens. The historical limits we have so far established-after Two methods seem to be available for the attainment of this
511/10 B.C. but before the end of the fifth century-are too goal. The first, which may be called 'etymological', is deductive
wide to be significant, and we shall have to try in Part II to in character and has, therefore, only a limited usefulness for our
narrow the gap between them as much as we can and find, if purposes. For while it may help on occasion to know that OWfL6s
possible, an event or set of events to which it can be attributed, is derived from the same root as 'T{07)fL~ = 'put', 'set', 'place',
and the nature of the event will provide the clue to the signifi- this knowledge may turn out to be a liability rather than an
cance of the terminological change. asset in contexts in which a notion of 'placing' or 'setting' is not
self-evident but depends for its presence entirely upon the in-
1 Schwyzer,DCE, Nos.410. 5,4'3.7,412.'-2,4,8. '9; cf. 'TOypaf'f'a, DCE, No. genuity of the interpreter, especially ifit should appear unrelated
424. 10-1I (mid fourth century B.C.).
•J. Kohler and E. Ziebarth, Das Stadtrecht van Cartyn: at 'Tao€ 'To.ypaf'f'U'T' Eypa'T'Tat to other usages of OWfL6c;. The etymological method is fraught
et sim., VI. '5, IX. 15-16, XI. '9-23, XII. '5-19; a Eypa-rat et sim., III. 29-30, IV. with even greater danger in the case of v6fLoS. There is universal
3', 45-6, 48, VI. 3', VII. 47-8, VIII. 10, 25-6, 29-30,35-6,40, IX. 23-4, X. agreement, as far as I know, that this noun is derived from the
44-5,46, XI. 26-7, 28-9, XII. 15-19; Ka'To. 'To. eypaf'f'Eva, III. 20, IV. 11,50-1,
XII. 22-3. same root as V€fJ-w, whose basic concept involves a 'distribution'
3 Tod, CHI I', No. 25. 19. or 'assigning' of some kind. Still, although the notion of 'dis-
4 Dittenberger, SICJ, Nos. 471. 4 and 672. '5.
tribution' does contribute to an understanding of such relatives of
5 IC 5.2, '59 A. 8; B. 20.
6 Tod, CHI I', No. 24. 46, and Buck, CD, No. 59. A. I and '4. v6fJ-0C; as the geograp h·lca I concepts 0 f VOjL7)" = pasturage,, VOfJ-0S
I

= 'pasture', 'abode', 'district', and also of their derivatives


V0fJ-€VC;= 'herdsman' and the adjective V0fJ-US = 'roaming about
NOTE ON METHOD II

for pasture', attempts to interpret either the musical concept of


I
years earlier, it will be sufficient to limit our examination to
vop,o, = 'melody', 'tune', or the social sense of vop,o" with which every surviving occurrence of the two words down to the end of
we are concerned here, in terms of the verbal connotations have the fifth century B.C. and pass over into the fourth century and
not been very convincing.2 later periods only when a special point requires us to do so.
A more reliable guide to the basic notions underlying 8wp,o,
and vop,o, is provided by what we may call a 'semantic' method.
Its characteristic is that it proceeds inductively from the particu-
lar contexts in which each of the two terms is found, in order to
define the variety of usage of each in different areas of Greek
thought and action. Once this is done, an attempt can be made
to discover whether a common denominator exists which at
once gives a basic meaning of each term and explains how this
meaning is applied in practice in the contexts in which each term
appears. It is at this stage that etymology may shed some light on
our investigation, since the basic idea of a term is likely to reflect
its linguistic connections and ancestry.
Ideally, then, we ought to examine every occurrence of 8wp,o,
and vop,o, in all Greek literature and documents in order to
establish the full range of each term and arrive at its basic mean-
ing. However, to cover in such an inquiry all Greek writings from
Homer3 to, let us say, Galen would not only be tedious but also
unnecessary. Our purpose is to ascertain the relation in which
the sense of 'statute' stands to the other connotations of 8wp,o,
and vop,o" and since we know that vop,o, was firmly entrenched in
Athens as the proper term for 'statute' by 403/2 B.C. and that
8wp,o, had lost this meaning in Athens more than a hundred
I Frisk, GEW, S.v. V€fLW. E. Benveniste, Noms d'agent et noms d'action en indo-
curopeen 79, takes the basic idea of V€fLWto be 'partager ltgalement; faire une attribu-
tion rtguliere, conforme au rang des personnes ou aux convenances de la situation'.
However, Benveniste's definition fails to recognize that the root V€fL- never regards
the distribution from the point of view of an agent who distributes, but assumes
a distribution or assignment already made in an authoritative and generally
accepted fashion.
2 Such attempts are at least as old as PI. Laws 4. 714 a; cf. also [Archytas] in
Stob. Flor. 4. I. 138; Pluto Quaest. conv. 2. 10, 644 c; Et. Mag. S.V. V€fLW. For
modern linguistic interpretations along etymological lines see Benveniste, loco
cit.; M. Pohlenz, 'Nomos', Philologus 97 (1948) 135-42; and the works cited by
Laroche, 206 n. 2. Among historians the relation of the social sense of v6fLoS to the
verb is stressed notably by Hirzel, TDV 379 n. I, and by Ehrenberg, Rechtsidee
114-15. The limitations of the etymological method in the case ofv6fLOS are recog-
nized by Heinimann, NP 59 with nn. I and 2, and by Laroche 163, cf. also 177
and 187.
3 No precursor of either 6£UfL6sor v6fLOS has so far been found in the Linear B
tablets; see A. Morpurgo, Mycenaeae Graecitatis Lexicon 'Index Graecus'.
NOTE ON METHOD II

for pasture', attempts to interpret either the musical concept of


I
years earlier, it will be sufficient to limit our examination to
vop,os= 'melody', 'tune', or the social sense ofvop,os,with which every surviving occurrence of the two words down to the end of
we are concerned here, in terms of the verbal connotations have the fifth century B.C. and pass over into the fourth century and
not been very convincing.2 later periods only when a special point requires us to do so.
A more reliable guide to the basic notions underlying 8wp,os
and vop,osis provided by what we may call a 'semantic' method.
Its characteristic is that it proceeds inductively from the particu-
lar contexts in which each of the two terms is found, in order to
define the variety of usage of each in different areas of Greek
thought and action. Once this is done, an attempt can be made
to discover whether a common denominator exists which at
once gives a basic meaning of each term and explains how this
meaning is applied in practice in the contexts in which each term
appears. It is at this stage that etymology may shed some light on
our investigation, since the basic idea of a term is likely to reflect
its linguistic connections and ancestry.
Ideally, then, we ought to examine every occurrence of 8wp,os
and vop,osin all Greek literature and documents in order to
establish the full range of each term and arrive at its basic mean-
ing. However, to cover in such an inquiry all Greek writings from
Homer3 to, let us say, Galen would not only be tedious but also
unnecessary. Our purpose is to ascertain the relation in which
the sense of 'statute' stands to the other connotations of 8wp,os
and vop,os,and since we know that vop,oswas firmly entrenched in
Athens as the proper term for 'statute' by 403/2 B.C. and that
8wp,os had lost this meaning in Athens more than a hundred
I Frisk, GEW, S.v. V€fLW. E. Benveniste, Noms d'agent et noms d'action en indo-
europeen 79, takes the basic idea of V€fLW to be 'partager ligalement; faire une attribu-
tion rtguliere, conforme au rang des personnes ou aux convenances de la situation'.
However, Benveniste's definition fails to recognize that the root VEfL- never regards
the distribution from the point of view of an agent who distributes, but assumes
a distribution or assignment already made in an authoritative and generally
accepted fashion.
2 Such attempts are at least as old as PI. Laws 4. 714 a; cr. also [ArchytasJ in
Stob. Flor. 4. I. 138; Pluto Quaest. conv. 2. 10, 644 c; Et. Mag. s.v. V€fLW. For
modern linguistic interpretations along etymological lines see Benveniste, loco
cit.; M. Pohlenz, 'Nomos', Philologus 97 (1948) 135-42; and the works cited by
Laroche, 206 n. 2. Among historians the relation of the social sense of v6fLoS to the
verb is stressed notably by Hirzel, TDV 379 n. I, and by Ehrenberg, Rechtsidee
1I4-I5. The limitations of the etymological method in the case of v6fLOS are recog-
nized by Heinimann, NP 59 with nn. I and 2, and by Laroche 163, cf. also 177
and 187.
3 No precursor of either BEUfL6s or v6fLoS has so far been found in the Linear B
tablets; see A. Morpurgo, Mycenaeae Graecitatis Lexicon 'Index Graecus'.
the same concrete sense underlies Demeter's attribute (JWfLo-
epOpO,.1
Although the other connotations of (JWfLo, are less concrete
than this, their relation to the Homeric sense is fairly transparent.
In a well-known passage in Aeschylus' Eumenides,2 (JWfLo, de-
o begin with (JWfLa,. Its earliest occurrence which is at scribes the place or position in the universe granted definitively

T once its ?nly appearance in the Homeric poe~s, comes in


what ~nstophanes of Byzantium and Aristarchus regarded
as the last lme of the Odyssey;2 the marriage-bed which Odysseus
I
to the Erinyes by the gods in accordance with the decree of fate.
The term here does not designate a concrete object but a certain
status conferred by an external agency. From here it is only
and Penelope resume after peace has returned to the household is a small step to the notion of (JWfLo, as the establishment of a
described as a.A€KTpOtO 1TuAuwv BWfLa,. Some scholars, influenced fundamental institution, a sense of which we find a good exam-
by lat~r meamngs of BWfLo" have seen in this expression the re- ple in the same play, when the Areopagus is called a (JwfLo, of
establIshment of an 'order' or of a 'relationship'.3 But, as Ehren- Athene for the trial of murder cases (484,615), or when in the
berg has seen, the context demands a simpler and more concrete Supptices (1034) sexual relations are a (JWfLo, of Aphrodite.3 In the
interpretation; in view of t~e fact that earlier in the same pas- same vein, Pindar describes as a nefLo, the institution of cele-
sage. (23. 177-230) the 10catlOn of the bed forms a subject ofdis- brating an Olympic victor in song (Ot. 7. 88), the establishment
CUSSlOn between Odysseus and Penelope and crowns as it were of the Olympic Games by Heracles (Ot. 6. 69, Nem. 10.33),4 and
Penelope's recognition of her husband, BWfLo, refers 'both to th~ of the Isthmian Games by Poseidon (Ot. 13.40).
couch and the place at which it is situated and describes there- In addition to denoting the institution established, (JEO"[LO,may
fore, a thing placed in a significant location.4 A similar ~sage is also designate the pronouncement or decree which constitutes its
also found in Pindar, who calls the wreaths placed upon the founding act. Thus Athene in Aeschylus' Eumenides (68 I ; cf. 57 I )
brow of ?Ce~ophon of Corinth an EYKWfLWV nBfLov (Ot. 13. 29),s bids the people of Attica listen to the (JWfLo, by which she estab-
and agam m a fragment of Anacreon (frg. 61), where the lishes the Council of the Areopagus as a court of law, and by
word seems to describe something 'stored away', a 'treasure'. a n(JfLa, of the immortals Aegina became a pillar for strangers
(9wfLo, may denote a thing placed in a significant location also from all parts of the world.s The decree which constitutes the
in that difficult passage in Euripides' Helen where Theonoe founding act may later become the basic instrument for the
calls the sulphurous brimstone which she is to use in fumi- institution which has been established by it, and thus we find
gating the air a (JEofLo, aEfLvov UllJEpO" indicating both the brim-
stone and the air it is about to fill,6 and, if Deubner is right,
aUJfpo" fLvxwV in preference to Hermann's ingenious (hiov D.
GEfLVOV()W/LOV al()Epo,
fLVX6v, which most editors favour, including most recently A. M. Dale, Euripides:
Helen ad loc., since I can make no sense of or find any parallel to the kind of in-
I Homeric Hyr;zn 8 ('To Ares'), which has ()wfLoiat in I. 16, is generally admitted ternal accusative which these editors posit for GEfLVOV()wfL6v.
to be ~ost-classleal; see T. W. Allen, W. R. Halliday, and E. E. Sikes (edd.), The I L. Deubner, Attische Feste 44~5, accepted by M. P. Nilsson, Ceschichte deT
Hommc Hymns· 384-5. griechischen Religion 12• 4,64 with n. 4. For a further concrete use of eWfL6, in a re-
• ad. 23·296, with schols. HMQand MV Vind. 133. The view that the Homeric ligious context see R. Herzog, 'Heilige Gesetze von Kos', Abh. d. preuss. Ak. d.
Ot[ysstry ends here has recently been supported by D. Page, The Homeric Odysstry Wiss. Berlin. Phil.-hist. KI. 1928, No.6. 22, line 17, where it seems to mean 'place of
101-36.
burial'.
3 ~o especially Hirzel, TD V 323 with n. I, and E. Weiss, Criechisches Privatrecht I. 2 391-3: fiLoV KAvwv 8EGfLOV I TOV P.oLpoKpavTov €K 8fWV I oo{}€vru T€A€ov.
64 With n. 106.
3 For this interpretation, which makes better sense of the problematic line, see
4 Cf. Ehrenberg, Rechtsidee 105-6. Busolt, CC 22• 173 n. 2, and W. B. Stanford
Rose, CSPA 1. 83.
(ed.), The Ot[ysstry of Homer 2.404, do not go far enough when they interpret ()wfL6, 4 Cf. also Nem. I I. 27, where the Nemean Games are referred to as 7l'EVTaET"IpiIJ'
here merely as 'place', 'location'.
EopTflv flJpaKAEo~ reap.tOv.
5 For the interpretation see Endnote, p. 174 below.
6 Eur. He!' 866. I reluctantly accept Murray's text ()••6v orE, u'fLvOU ()WfLoV
~ Pi~d., 01. 8. ~5-7: TE,()fLO,OE n"
d()ava.Twv Kat T<lvO' ciA"pKEa xwpav ! 7TavToOu-
7TOLULV U1T€GTaG€ gevoLS / KLOva OaLjkOvLav.
{)WfLO, also describing a fundamental regulation. For example, the adjective {){ufLw, occur. -When, for example, Herodotus (I.
the {)WfLol of Aigimios are binding not only for his sons and the 59. 6) tells us that Peisistratus did not change the {){UfLLU of
Doric tribes sprung from them, but also for the descendants of Athens, he probably means the fundamental regulations which
Heracles through his son Hyllus (pind. Pyth. 1. 64). In this con- formed the basis of Athenian society, including not only the laws
text belongs perhaps also the ()€{)< T)fLo" which is found in a law of Draco and Solon but also other institutions and principles, and
from Olympia of about 475 B.C. containing regulations con- when Medea wonders in her argument with Jason (Eur. Med. 494)
cerning the tenure of sacred lands by the theokolos.1 Its precise whether the {){UfLLU binding for mankind are different now from
meaning is hard to determine, but it seems to denote some kind of what they were at the time when she married, the sentiments
title or contract, by virtue of which an owner may claim a piece she voices are probably not unlike those found in a fragment
of land as his own.2 In some cases, {)WfLol of this sort are found in (360. 45) from Euripides' Erechtheus against thos~ W?o overthr0.w
the plural and are political in character, but their content is not 7TuAwa {){ufLLa. Sometimes, however, the adJeCtlval form III
usually specified. The ephebic oath in Athens, for example, con- the implied or expressed singular may specify the content of
tained a promise of obedience to 'the established {)wfLo[ and any a fundamental regulation. Aeschylus, for example, speaks of
others which the rulers in their wisdom may establish in future', 3 reverence for one's parents as written in the third place among
Aristophanes parodies the {)wfLov, apxulov" presumably ofAthens, the {){ufLLa of Dike (Suppl. 708), and toward the end of the
in the Birds (331), and Herodotus (3.31. 3) reports that one of Agamemnon (1564) the chorus warns Clytaemnestra of the specific
the functions of the Royal Judges of Persia was to expound the 8{UfLwV that the doer must suffer.
ancestral {)wfLol. If these passages have a clear political context, The {)wfLO[ and 8{ufLtU discussed in the preceding paragraph
there are other fundamental regulations in which the precise are fundamental regulations sanctioned by powers outside and
force of the {)wfLol and the authority that stands behind them is apart from the human agent who is expected to obey them. But
not entirely clear. The word occurs twice in successive lines in there are also three passages which show that {)WfLo, may denote
Sophocles' Antigone (800-1). In the first of these, the yearning basic rules of propriety and good behaviour whicJ¥re sanc-
which appears in a bride's eyes is described as 'sitting enthroned tioned by forces within the agent himself. This meaning is found,
in power by the side of the great {)wfLo[', presumably signifying for example, in Pindar's excuse (Nem. 4. 33) that T€{)fLo, and the
the fundamental laws safeguarding the institution of marriage, onrushing hours prevent him from telling a story in its entirety,
and in the anapaests which follow, the chorus states that it is where T€{)fLo, evidently refers to the rule that ought to be ob-
carried 'outside the ()wfLo[' by the sight of Antigone proceeding served by the composer of epinician odes, and we encounter it again
to her death. Here the allusion is perhaps to the fundamental when he tells us (Isth. 6. 20) that it is for him a T{{)fLtOV UU¢>{UTU-
laws of allegiance to constituted authority, which the Old Men TOV to praise the Aeacidae whenever he sets foot on the island of
are bound to support and adherence to which has prevented Aegina. Here belong also the {)wfLO[ which Bellerophon claims to
them from opposing Creon's measures.4 A similar vague use can honour in Euripides and which bid him act with decorum. 1
be detected in some passages in which the neuter plural forms of Finally, we come to that group of {)WfLO[ which is of most
immediate concern to us here, since they include the sense of
1 Schwyzer, DGE, No. 411. 3 with SEG II, No. 1178. For the dale see Jeffery,
LSAG, p. 220, No. 10. 'statute'. Each of these {)wfLO[ has a specific content and pro-
2 Cf. D. Comparetti, ]HS 2 (1881) 365-73, csp. 368--9, and T. Rcinach, REG 16 pounds an injunction usually, but not invariably, of a political
(1903) 190-2, for this interpretation.
nature, which mayor may not take a written form. The {)wfLo[ of
3 Tad, CHI 2, No. 204. 11-[4: Kat €i)'TJKo~aw TOW afL KpULVOVTWV Ep..ePpOVW'i Kat
TWV 8€UI_u»v TWV iopvp..€vwv Kat oUS" av TO AOL7TOV i8pvaWVTUt fj.LeppOVW';. For the literary Draco and Solon, for example, were written statutes,2 and it is
versions of this oath see above, p. 4-n. 3.
4 Jebu implies a similar interpretation in his translation 'beyond the bounds of 1 Eur. Stheneboea 15 in D. L. Page, Greek Literary Papyri I. 128.
loyalty' and in his note ad lac.: 'i.e. like Haemon, I also am moved to rebel 2 For Draco see above, p. 3 nn. 2 and 3; for Solon see above, p. 3 nn. 4 and 5,
against Creon's sentence, and to take Antigone's part.' and p. 4, no. I.
16 eEI:MOI: AND NOMOI:

probable that the old Draconian {)'afua concerning the establish- instructions about the use of his blood which the centaur Nessus
ment of a tyranny at Athens, which were revived after the ex- gave to Deianeira were certainly not written, even if Sophocles
pulsion of the Peisistratids, were issued and preserved in writing, I calls them {)wj-to{ (Trach. 682), and neither were the {)dvv 7TUV{)VTU
as were even earlier, according to Aristotle (Ath. Pol. 3. 4),2 the {)'aj-tta which Ajax performed (Aj. 712). Likewise, when the
records kept by the {)wj-to{)l.Tat. But written political {)wj-to{ Erinyes express the fear (Aesch. Eum. 491) that they will be
existed not only in Athens. Among the Locrians TE{)j-tO, seems to overthrown by the new {)'aj-tta of the Areopagus, it is rather
be the most important, if not the only, word used for a written improbable that they are thinking specifically of written statutes;
statute. It first appears about 500 B.C. as the description of a at any rate, the question whether these {)'aj-tta are written or not
written law, probably of the Ozolian Locrians, in which regula- is immaterial to their thought. I The problem of writing is also as
tions concerning the disposition of newly-acquired agricultural irrelevant to Democritus' demand (frg. 266) that a {)wj-tos ought
lands are laid down,3 and in which their law concerning homi- to be established for the protection of public officials as it is to
cide, which may also have been written, is referred to in the Hecuba's question in Euripides' Trojan Women (266-7) which
phrase KIlT TOV dVDPEepOVtKOV TET{)j-tOV.4 There is, further, a written voj-tos or {)'aj-ttOv ofthe Greeks sanctions Polyxena's assignment to
statute of the early fifth century defining the political conditions the tomb of Achilles. In the case of the fifth-century {)E{)j-tOS of
of the settlement by the Eastern Locrians of their colony at Tegea which states that possible disputes arising from a deposit
Naupactus, which refers to itself as TO {)'{)j-ttOV, presumably indi- of money be settled by the people of Tegea, we simply do not
cating that it was intended to be the fundamental constitutional know whether or not reference is made to a written statute.2
instrument of the colony.s Outside politics {)wj-to, survives also Slightly different is Teucer's statement to Menelaus in Sophocles'
as the descriptive term for written cult regulations issued by Ajax (1 I04) to the effect that there is no {)wj-tos by which
demes or phratries. In Athens, for example, there was recently Menelaus was given the right to command Ajax. Taken at its face
found the re-publication after the Persian Wars of an older {)wj-to, value, the very fact that written legislation did not exist in the
probably pertaining to rites at the Therrikleion,6 and from heroic age may be taken to indicate that he is speaking of an un-
Delphi we know the late fifth-century TE{)j-tO, concerning funerals written ordinance. But the language, particularly the use of the
among the phratry of the Labyadai.7 verb €KEtTO, suggests that Teucer's words must be set against
The existence of so many specific {)wj-to{ in writing does not, the background of written legislation prevalent at the time when
however, mean that all political or religious regulations to which the play was first performed. But here again the question of writing
the name {)wj-t6s was applied were ipso facto written.S The is beside the point. The same is true of the final passage relevant
I See above, p. 4 n. 2. to our purposes. The CiDtKOt {)wj-to{, with which, according to the
2 See Endnote, pp. 174-5 below. epigram on the dead of Phyle, the Thirty ruled Athens, no
3 Buck, CD, No. 59. A. I and 14. For the assignment to the Ozolian Locrians the
date, and a bibliography see Jeffery, LSAC 105-6 and 108. ' doubt include, but are not confined to, those of their measures
4 Buck, CD, No. 59. A. 13-14. which were issued in writing.3 In short, writing is an accidental
5 .Buck, CD, No. 57. 46 and Tod, CHI 12, No. 24. 46, with bibliography and dis- but not an essential part of the definition of {)wj-tos in the sense of
CUSSlOn.The inscription is assigned to the first quarter of the fifth century by
Jeffery, LSAC 106. For a fuller discussion see below, pp. 170-3.
a specific political or religious regulation.
6 B. D. Meritt, Hesperia 36 (1967) 72-84 (No. 15). We may, then, summarize our findings as follows. In Greek
7 Buck, CD, No. 52. C. 19.

,8 I do not agree with V. Ehrenberg, Sophocles and Pericles 169, that 'lJw/-,o" or discussed presently argues against it. In fact, Ehrenberg himself (ibid. 34 n. 2)
lJ.u/-,wv ... means by itself written law, law "set up", as, e.g., preserved by the interprets IJwW7,v in Soph. Ant. 797, as 'unwritten laws'.
thesmothetai, and thus distinct from law by usage, or vo/-,o,', and that 'the view which I That statutes are involved here seems beyond doubt, see Rose, CSPA 2. 263
prevailed, for instance, in Solon's thought and dominated the sixth century' was ad loco
'that it was in the nature ofa thesmos to be written'. Surely, the lack of references to 2 IC 5. 2, 159 A. 8 and B. 20, with bibliography in Buck, CD 267.
aypar/>oL IJw/-,o{ is poor evidence on which to base such a conclusion and the 3 Aeschines 3. 190, with the fragments of the inscription found in the Agora
testimony of both non-politicallJw/-,o{ already discussed and politicallJ.~/-,o{ to be excavations and published by A. E. Raubitschek, Hesperia 10 (1941) 284-95.
814277 c t
writings down to the end of the fifth century, {}wJLOi> is used to relation to T£()TJJLL supports what we find in actual usage: it is
describe (a) a physical object placed in a significant location, a thing imposed by a higher power upon those for whom the
(b) an institution or establishment, (c) the ordinance by which authority of the imposing agency makes the BWJLoi> an obligation.
such an institution is called into being, (d) the propriety inherent If we apply this to the sense of 'statute', we may conclude that
in obedience to fundamental regulations, and (e) specific statutes BEUJLOi> is a law given by a lawgiver who is thought of as standing
or regulations of a political or religious character. What all these apart from and above the persons upon whom his law is binding.
connotations have in common is that each involves explicitly or
implicitly not only a {}WJLOi> which is imposed, but also an agency
which places or imposes it and a place or group which is con-
ceived of as the recipient of the imposition and for whom the
{}EUJL0i> constitutes an obligation. A few examples will clarifY the
way in which this general definition applies to the various con-
notations isolated as (a)-(e) above. (a) In the Otfyssey passage, it is
Odysseus who had placed the bed into the stump of an olive-tree
(23. 183-204), and in Pindar's thirteenth Olympian the judges had
placed the wreaths of victory on Xenophon's brow. (b) The gods
are said in Aeschylus' Eumenides to have given the Erinyes their
station in the universe, and Athene has instituted the Areopagus
both as a {}wJL0i> (b) and by means ofa BEUJL0i> (c) as a lawcourt
for the Athenians, while the Olympic and Isthmian Games were
bestowed upon the Greeks respectively by Heracles and Poseidon.
(c) By a TE{}JLOi> ofthe immortals Aegina was given to strangers as
a haven, and Aigimios gave his BWJLoL to his sons. The rulers of
Athens give their {}wJLoL to the Athenian ephebes, and the {}wJLoL
of their ancestors were binding upon the Royal Judges of Persia.
(d) No author is mentioned of the rules of propriety, but such
rules are spoken of as imposed on the poet, the visitor to Aegina,
and on Bellerophon. And (e) in the case of statutes and similar
regulations, men such as Draco, Solon, and Nessus, or bodies such
as the Athenian BWJLO{}ETUt, the Areopagus, the rulers of Locris or
Tegea or of phratries, are spoken of as authors of {}wJLoL, while the
Athenians, Deianeira, Locrians, and phratry members are thought
of as the recipients for whom the {}wJLoL constitute an obligation.
Moreover, the author of most of the {}wJLoL is a person or agency,
divine or human, who is thought of as standing apart from and
above those on whom the BWJLoL are imposed, and the position of
respect accorded to that agency makes the thing imposed some-
thing especially inviolable for the recipients, something that has
an obligating character for them.
We may, then, state that in the case of {}w~i> the etymological
may on various occasions be attributed to the gods, to a lawgiver,
or to an enactment by a society as a whole, the crucial point is
that, regardless of origin, it is recognized and acknowledged as
the valid norm within a given milieu. I
The earliest author to use vOfLo, is also the first to employ the
term in its widest range.2 Hesiod tells us in the 'Works and Days
vOfLoS plays a more central part in Greek life and thought that Zeus ordained for men the vOfLo, that, while beasts, living

5
1N C E

than does 8WfLoS, and since it has, accordingly, been the as they do without 8{wl), devour one another, he gave menjustiee
subject of more extensive scholarly discussion, it is advisable (8{KYJ), 'which turns out to be the best by far'.3 That vOfLo, does
that at the outset of this chapter we re-state our aim and show not here bear the sense of 'law' or 'ordinance' which prescribes
how it differs from the aims of some earlier treatments of the a certain kind of behaviour but designates the behaviour itself
term. We are at this juncture not concerned with elucidating the has long been recognized.4 It is, rather, an order ofliving, a way
meaning of vOfLoS in one particular passage, as are, for example, of life, which Zeus has given to men and which differs from the
those who have tried to define its meaning in Pindar, frg. 169;1 vOfLo, he has given to the beasts. The vOfLo, of men includes and
nor with tracking down the origins of the term as a particular that of the animals excludes 8{KYJ; that it is god-given is only
philosophical concept;2 nor are we interested only in its sense of incidental, for the poin-Jis that it constitutes a norm followed
'statute'; nor do we want to give a historical account of the by any human being who does not want to degenerate into an
semantic development of vOfLoS and its relations to cognate words.3 animal.s
Our purpose is rather to determine what basic concept or root There are two further early examples of vOfLo, as describing the
idea underlies all the various meanings of vOfLoS as they occur in way of life as such of men or animals. The lack of context for
all their contexts before the end of the fifth century B.C., in order Aleman's F0t:8a 8' opv{xwv vOfLw, 7TaVTWV (frg. 40) makes it difficult
to compare this concept with 8wfLoS and discover the differences
between the two. For the sake of convenience we shall for the I Heinimann, NP 65, does not go far enough when he defines vop.os as 'das bei
einer Gruppe von Lebewesen "Geltende"'. The point inherent in vop.os is not
present not consider the various nouns, verbs, adjectives, and merely its validity but that its validity is acknowledged and, usually, accepted by
their compounds which are related to vOfLos, since they will not those whose vop.os it is.
provide us with any insights in this respect that cannot be gained 2 Nop.os does not occur in II. nor, I believe, in ad., despite Zenodotus' reading
vop.ov for voov at ad. I. 3, which has been defended by R. Merkelbach, Unter-
from a study of vOfLoS alone. suchungen zur Odyssee (= Zeternata 2) 158-9 n. 4, and by Gigante, NB 44 with
The thesis which we shall try to substantiate is that vOfLoS in all critical bibliography in n. I. Zenodotus' reading was attacked already in antiquity
its uses describes an order of some kind,4 which differs from other by Aristarchus. and Pohlenz, Philologus 97 (1948) 139, seems to me to be right in
arguing that the plural vop.ovs would be more appropriate if Zenodotus' reading
words for 'order', such as Tcfgt" in the connotation that this order were correct; d. also Laroche 164-6, Stier, NB 232 n. 20, and Heinimann, NP
is or ought to be regarded as valid and binding by those who live 61 n. I I.
under it. In other words, vOfLoS is a norm both in a descriptive 3 276-80: 1'OVOEyap o.vflpomow, vop.ov OtE1'a~E Kpovtwv / lxflvaL p.EV I<at flT]pat Ka,
OlWVOL~ 1TETE7]VOLS I ea8E/-LEV d"A~"OVS', chTf~Jau 8tK'Yl EUTE. P.€T' aVTois· I dvOpcfJ'rroun 8'
and in a prescriptive sense, and although the origin of this norm
EOWKE O/K1JV, ~ 7TOAAOV ap{aTTJ I Y{YV€TUL.
4 See Hirzel, TDV 366 and 368 n. 2; Stier, NB 232.
I e.g. O. Schroeder, "Nop.os'; 1Tavrwv {3aa,AEvs", Philologus 74 (1917) 195-204;
5 A similar sense of vop.os seems to be required in Theog. 66, where the Graees
Stier, NB; Gigante, NB; and my own article 'Pindar, NOMOI:, and Heracles',
and Himeros 7TlIV1'WV1'E vop.ovs Kat {fflw I<EOVa/ o.vflpomwv I<AdovaL. The passage 63-7
HSCP 69 (1965) 109-38. is difficult and has been rejected by many modern editors. But, as has been rightly
2 e.g. Heinimann, NP, or M. Pohlenz, 'Nomos und Physis', Hermes 81 (1953)
observed by Solmsen HA 42 n. 133, the lines fit well into their context. They are
418-38. See also the unconvincing attempt of]. A. S. Evans, 'Despotes Nomos',
retained with improved punctuation by M. L. \\'est, Hesiod: Theogony, with note
Athenaeum N.S. 43 (1965) 142-53, to relate Herodotus' view of vop.os to his idea of
on p. 178, who also accepts van Lennep's emendation of op.ws to vop.ovs in 74·
historical causation.
West's 'ordinances' fits his interpretation less well than our proposed 'ways of
3 As does, for example Laroche.
life'.
4 This point is emphasized by Laroche 177-8, 180, and 196.
NOMa}; 23

to decide whether or not VOfLOS is used in a musical sense; if it demand more blood, and the chorus of Sophocles' Antigone (613-
is not, the poet may well be claiming knowledge of the 'ways' of 14) the rule that there is nothing great in life that does not entail
all birds. Theognis' complaint that the present rulers of Megara destruction (UTY)). In Herodotus we find vOfLoS used in this sense
exercise their leadership EKTparr/),owL VOfLOLS can in its con- in his account of Miltiades. The people of the Chersonese, he
text only mean that the moral norms of human life are being tells us (6. 38. I), offer sacrifice to him and stage horse-races and
perverted by them, so that shamelessness and insolence have athletic competitions in his honour OJs VOfLOS OiKWTfi. From
\'anquished respect and justice. 1 several passages in Thucydides we learn what is the normal order
In the fifth century, this sense of VOfLOS is found in a passage in of things in time of war. The Plataeansjustify their actions against
Sophocles' Antigone (450-2), in which Antigone tells Creon that Thebes before the Spartans by appealing (3. 56. 2) to the vOfLoS
Zeus and Dike have not given to men the kind of VOfLOL which established for all men which permits defence against enemy
would permit him to deny burial to Polyneices. In Aristophanes' attacks, and in their rebuttal (3. 66. 2) the Thebans admit that
Birds (r 344-5), the Parricide asks permission to participate in it is 'in accordance with some sort of VOfLOS' to kill one's opponent
the VOfLOL of the birds;2 in Euripides, Hippolytus doubts that the in battle, but they protest that it was in violation of vOfLoS
ways of the gods apply to men (Hipp. 98); the chorus of the (-rrapavofLws) to slaughter prisoners of war. 1 Most famous in
Supplices (377-8) appeals to Athens not to desecrate vOfLOVS Thucydides is the VOfLoS, cynically invoked by the Athenians (5·
(3POTWV;3 and the Hippocratic treatise On Airs, Waters, and Places 105. 2) against the people of Melos, namely, that both gods and
(16 and 23, 24) speaks of the institution of kingship among the men rule whatever they have in their power.
Asiatics as VOfLOL and states that in general VOfLoS can implant We find vOfLoS in a similar sense in two passages in Euripides.
courage and endurance in the souls of dwellers in valleys where In the Alcestis (56-7) Death accuses Apollo of favouring the
epVULS has not done so. Further, there are a few instances in the rich, if he were to establish the norm (VOfLOS) that old people get
vOfWS-epVULS literature in which vOfLoS is treated as the order of a richer funeral than the young, and Clytaemnestra (fA 694),
human life in genera1.4 thinking that Agamemnon's grief is due to Iphigeneia's impend-
ing marriage, consoles him by saying that time and vOfLoS will
A second use of vOfLoS consists in the application of the term to help him minimize his loss. Here the sense of VOfLOS is evidently
somewhat narrower norms of universal validity which form part the fact that one's children get married, which Clytaemnestra
of the general vOfLoS we have just discussed. 'When, for example, urges Agamemnon to accept. Finally, a fifth-century usage may
the chorus in Aeschylus' Agamemnon (1207) asksCassandra whether be reflected in Callicles' peculiar phrase about the l'OfLOS TijS
she and Apollo produced any children vOfLifJ, the addition of epVUEWS (PI. Gorg. 483 e), to which we shall return again later
vOfLifJ obviously cannot refer to a custom or a statute, but it (pp. 39-40, 51). For the present, it will suffice to point out that the
signifies the Old Men's assumption that in the normal order of phrase itself is clearly intended to show that epVULS and not man-
things the union of male and female will result in children. made vOfLoS is the true norm (VOfLoS) that guides human actions.
Similarly, the chorus of the Choephoroe (4.00) articulates as vOfLoS
the universal norm that drops of blood spilled on the ground Closely related to this is a kind of VOfLoS which describes a pro-
Theognis 289-90, as punctuated by T. ,,y. Allen, RPh II (1937) 280-1, fol-
I cedure, i.e. the normal way in which something is done. For
lowed by J. Carriere's Bude text. For the sense see Laroche 173. example, when Hesiod (Op. 388) advises the farmer that the
2 In the lines immediately following, the comic point consists in a shift of the use
of VOjLOS from the sense of customary practice (KU/\OY VOfL!(,€Tat TOV 1TUTfpa TOrS OpVtULV I Interestingly enough, the Plataean appeal to the Spartans (3. 58. 3), to spare
aYX<LV Kat oaKVHV) to that, of :t~tute (~OI"OS 7T~.\a,,)s, EV_ TaLS T~V 7TE~a~ywv Kvpf3~aLV). them because they surrendered voluntarily, is based on a different kind of vO/-,os,
3 Cf. Thuc. 3. [84]. 3: attDVOl TE TOVS /(OLVOV,' 7TEpL TWV TOtDVTWV OL av!Jpw7ToL VO/-,OVS which is confined to the Greeks, see below, pp. 33-4; cf. the Theban assertion (3·
... 7TPOKUTu),..Vnv. 67.6) that the Plataeans transgressed the vO/-,os of the Greeks in attacking without
e.g. Eur. frg. 920; [Hippocrates],
4 De victu I. II; and Hippias apud PI. Proto provocation. Although verbally these VO/-,OL are confined to the Greeks, the inten-
337 c-338 b. tion of their proponents is no douht to claim a universal validity for them.
VOfLaS of the plains-and of various other kinds of country-is to way of acting under given sets of circumstances or for a particular
strip for sowing, for ploughing, and for harvesting, he merely kind of individual. When Clytaemnestra in Aeschylus' Agamemnon
describes what is the normal and proper way of going about his (594) speaks of the cry she addressed to the gods YVVaLKE{lp vOfLlp in
work. Aeschylus uses vOfLa' in this sense to describe the natural jubilation over the fall of Troy, the dative shows that the oAa-
and proper formulation of a prayer (Cho. 93), Pindar praises AVYfLoS is a cry normally uttered by women under this kind of
Xenocrates of Acragas for practising horse-breeding in the way condition. In Sophocles' Ajax, vOfLa' occurs in this sense in Ajax's
accepted as proper by all Greeks (Isth. 2. 38) and reports that wish that his son be trained in that rough kind of behaviour
Chiron taught]ason the vOfLa' of using drugs (Nem. 3·55), while which is proper to his father (548), and in his words to the chorus
Sophocles calls vOfLa' a hunt which proceeds in a proper way that they alone have stood by him op8ip vOfLlp, that is, as is the
(Ichn. 189). proper conduct expected of one's companions (350). In the
Herodotus describes the vOfLa, by which the lake-dwellers erect Trachiniae Deianeira requests Lichas to observe the vOfLa' proper
their buildings (5. 16.2); and of the one thousand noble lance- to a messenger and not to be a busybody (616), and Heracles
bearers who followed in the train of Xerxes carrying their spears admonishes Hyllus that obedience to one's father is the best
with the point up he says that they held their spears KUTa vOfLov, norm of conduct (II 77) ; in the Antigone the heroine explains the
that is, in the proper way a spear should be carried, in contrast to vOfLa' which made her honour her brother more than any other
others who carried them point down (7. 41. I). To indicate the relative (914), and the chorus of the Oedipus at Colonus asks
improper way of doing things Herodotus twice uses au VOfLa,: Oedipus to step down from the sacred ground and to speak
when Peisistratus did not want to have children by the daughter where it is vOfLo, for all to do so (168).
of Megacles, EfL{aYETo at au KUTa vOfLaV (I. 6I. I), and elsewhere he Herodotus uses vOfLa' in this sense only once (1. 90. 2, 4),
reports that it is au vOfLaS for a bastard son to be king of Persia, if namely when Croesus sends to Delphi to inquire whether it is the
there is a legitimate son (3. 2. 2).1 Also expressions such as EV vOfLa' of Greek gods to deceive their benefactors. In Euripides
XEtpwv VOfLlp (8. 89. I) and E, XEtpwv vOfLoV (9. 48. 2) designate this meaning is found more frequently than in any other Greek
a proper or normal way of acting, viz. the way one acts when author. Medea uses it (Med. 238) to tell the chorus that, when
things are done with one's hands.2 Finally, in a passage of a woman marries, she has to adopt new standards of behaviour,
Aristophanes' Ecclesiazusae (2 16) wool is to be dyed KUTa TOV and later in the play, after she has announced her intention to
apxu'iav vOfLav, in the way it has been done properly from time kill her children, the chorus appeals to vOfLa' (812) to dissuade
immemorial. 3 her from executing her plan. Pheres in the Alcestis (683) does not
accept it as an ancestral or Greek norm of conduct that fathers
There is a fourth area in which vOfLaS describes what is normal, should die for their children, and in the Cyclops (299) Odysseus
and that is the sphere of human conduct or of conduct of the calls it a vOfLaS for mortals to receive the shipwrecked. Elsewhere
gods judged by human standards. Here vOfLa, defines the proper in Euripides vOfLaS describes the love which all living creatures
have for their offspring (frg. 346), the honour owed to those in
1 This is one of the many instances which shows how difficult it is to keep the

vario\ls meanings of VOfLO~ in strictly separated compartments: if Herodotus had power (frg. 337), and the horsemanship and archery which the
expressed himself here positively, saying that a Persian VOfLo~ gave legitimate Phrygians honour as their VOfl-OL (Tro. 1210). The gods are con-
children prececlence in the succession to the throne, it would make better sense to demned for contracting incestuous unions <Lv aUOE~S VOfLaS (HF
regard this VOfLO~ as a constitutional regulation. But the negative character of the
phrase suggests that he is thinking of the impropriety this entails in Persian eyes. 1316), Tyndareus (Or. 503) tells Menelaus that if, instead of
2 Cf. Laroche 196. killing her, Orestes had banished his mother from his house, he
3 In this context belongs perhaps also Menelaus' advice about the bull who would have adhered to the standards of proper behaviour (vofLa')'
refused to go aboard the ship, as reported by the messenger in Eur. Hel. 1561:
he urged his men to carry him on their shoulders 'EAA~VWV vOf''f and throw him in the Theseus the wish is expressed that men should have the vOfLoS
into the ship. of loving only those pious people who are also self-controlled
(frg. 388. 3), and in an unidentified play someone refuses to V()fLOt IJ-rTa Eva<; TOU 8E{OV' /(paTE~
yap TOUaUTOV o/(ouov d8E/..H /(OL
accept it as vO/ws not to love his mother (frg. 1064. 1). Twice EtOPI(f:~ 7Tllen KaL The relation between J'o/LO<; in this
7TEPI)I{!Jf.TU.L I

norms of conduct are treated like statutory enactments: in the fragment with the Heraclitean /..oyo<; has long been seen and need
Hippolytus Artemis explains (1328) that she could not save her not detain us hcre,2 but a few words ought to be said about the
devotee from Aphrodite, because the gods have a vOfLa<; pro- relation of the dv8pW7TELOt VofLOt to the 'one the divine' by which
hibiting them from interfering in each other's sphere, and an they are sustained. The identity of these human vO/lOt with the
old man in the Ion tells Creusa (1047) that there is no vOfLaS to vOfLo~' of the city, mentioned in the preceding sentence, is made
prevent a person from ill-treating his enemies. 1 It is difficult to be abundantly clear not only by the context but especially by the
sure in these two cases whether vOfLaS describes a political enact- yap which introduces the second sentence.3 Their all-inclusive-
ment, a meaning which will be discussed later, or a norm of ness makes it impossible to confine their meaning to any specific
behaviour. The latter seems more likely, because, as far as the customs or political regulations, which thrive in the various city-
Ion passage is concerned, Euripides knew of course that there states, and they must be taken in a wider sense as referring to the
were statutes against offences such as murder and assault and way of life or mores of a city as a whole. That this interpretation
battery, and as regards Artemis' declaration, it is difficult to is correct is confirmed by Heracli tus' analogy (O/{WU7TEp) of the
conceive even of a Euripides as believing the gods to have the vOfLoS of the city with the gvvav 7TaJ'Twv, that is, with 'what is
same kind of administration of justice as men do. There are two common to all things', and that is the LogoS.4But what concerns
Euripidean passages where the opposition to personal lawlessness us most here is the statement that these av8pw7TELOt vOfLat depend
(dvafL{a) suggests that vOfLaS refers to personal behaviour. In the for their sustenance u7Ta Evas TOU 8E{OV. What is meant by Evas TaU
first of these, the chorus of the Iphigeneia at Aulis, complaining of 8E{aV? Are we to take it as a neuter and translate it as 'one the
the absence of ai8w<; and dPET~, laments that lawless conduct is divine' and compare this use to frg. 32, where the 'one the wise
stronger than VofLat (1095), and in the Heracles there is a similar alone is willing and unwilling to be called by the name of Zeus' ?s
condemnation of a man vOfLaV 7TapEfLEvaS, dVafL{q. XaptV 8t80v<; Or are we to regard it as masculine and supply vOfLoV from the
(778). antecedent 7TavTE<; OL av8pw7THOt VofLOt? The decision is hard to
Finally, there belongs in this group a passage in Gorgias' make and is perhaps ultimately immaterial to Heraclitus' thought
Funeral Oration (frg. 6), in which he praises the deceased for having in this fragment. Yet the contrast between 7TavTES and EVos
regarded as the most divine vOfLaS, which most serves the public
'Those who speak with intelligenee must rely with all their strength on what is
interest, to speak and be silent, to act and to refrain from act- I

common to all, as a city relies on its vo,.,.o,


and with even greater strength. For all
ing, as each occasion demands. human vOI'-Ot are sustained by one the divine; it exerts as much power as it wishes,
it is sufficient for all and is still left over.' Translation adapted with modifications
from Kirk and Raven 213. For a different and very suggestive interpretation see
A further use of vOfLoS in a descriptive normative sense differs
A. P. D. Mourelatos, 'Heraclitus, Fr. 114', AJP 36 (1965) 258-66, with translation
from those we have so far discussed in that it connotes not so on p. 265. It is difficult, however, to accept the basic idea of 'are under the ward-
much the norm itself, but the source from which it emanates, the ship of', which M. sces in TpEq,OVTU<. While protection and guardianship are
certainly involved in many epic uses of TpEq,W, the notion of providing sustenance is
authority which issues and guarantees norms. The earliest pas-
far too common in the epic to be njected; see Ii. 5. 70 and 555, 1r. 741; Od. 18.
sage which includes this kind of vOfLaS, in Heraclitus (frg. 114), 130, Ig. 432, 23·325.
provides at once its clearest definition and differentiation from 2 See Stier, NB 237; H. Friinkel, AJP 59 (1938) 320-I; Heinimann, NP 66;
other sensesof vOfLOS. The difficulties of interpreting this fragment Gigante, NB 52; Kirk, HCF 51; Kirk and Raven 214.
3 K. Reinhardt's attempt in Parmenides2 215-16 to differentiate between the
make it necessary to discuss it at some length. The text reads: gvv two was successfully disproved by Heinimann, NP 66, and even more decisively by
vocp MyoVTas iuxvp{'w8at Xp~ T0 gvv0 7TavTwv, O/{WU7TEP vOfLcp Kirk, HCF 51.
1\
17"OlltS, /(at '" 7TOIIV tUXVpOTEpWS.
, I 'A..
TpE'f'OVTat yap" 7TaVTE<; Ott av
, 8PW7TELOt
' 4 See Heraclitus. frg. I, with the discussions cited n. 2 above.
5 ;V TO aoepov tJ-0VVQV ,\EyEv8at OUK JotAH Kat E8E/\n Z"iJVOS ovolLa. For this transla-
1 Cf. frg. IOgl for the same sentiment. tion, see Guthrie, HGP I. 425.
suggests that Heraclitus does indeed posit a divine VO/LOS on which similar language Pindar (Pyth. 2. 43) describes the birth of
all human PO/lOt depend for their sustenance, that is, a vOILO"- which Kentauros from the union of Ixion with a cloud as not being EV
is the source of human vOflm but stands sovereign above them and 8dvv vOflms, and the meaning seems to be that no divine authority
is not exhausted by them. If this assumption is correct, we have
I sanctioned this monstrous marriage. Likewise, when Teiresias
here a sense of vOfLoS which we have not encountered so far. It is (Nem. I. 72) predicts that Heracles will, after his marriage to
not the norm itself but the fountain-head of norms, which it Hebe, UEf-LVOV ulv~uELV vOfLov, this vOfLoS is apparently the power of
issues and which are regarded as binding by those who, in the the gods to dispense norms. I

words of f[g. 114, 'speak with intelligence'. In Sophocles, we find vOfLoS once in a context similar to that in
This usage is supported by three passages in Aeschylus. In the which we noticed it above in Aeschylus' Supplices, when he calls
Supplices (670-3) the chorus says of Zeus that he guides destiny Dike 'her who sits by the ancient VOfLOt of Zeus' (OC 1382). In
aright 7ToAttjJ vOfLCfJ. The precise content of the 'hoary ordinance', the Antigone the authority to dispense general norms is vested in
as we may reluctantly translate it, is hard to ascertain;2 is it an a human ruler. Creon is told by the chorus (213) that it is
ordinance that stands even above Zeus, is the construction in fact possible for him to use vOfLCfJ 7ravT£ both for the dead and for the
a dative of cause, which we ought to translate 'by virtue of living, referring apparently to Creon's power to issue laws which
a hoary ordinance', or are we to take it as a dative of means and will be binding on Thebes, and Creon himself states (177) that
translate 'with hoary ordinance', that is, with an ordinance that the ability of a man is not fully known until one has seen how he
is binding on and accepted by men? The latter seems to be the has handled himself apxufs T€ KUL vOfLOWtV, that is, until his
preferable alternative in view of the fact that there is no evidence authority in issuing regulations has been tested.2 The most cele-
in the Supplices of an order higher than that of the gods, and the brated passage in this connection is the famous ode in the
expression here, whatever its sense, places destiny firmly in the Oedipus in which the VOfLOt VljJ£7TOO€S are praised, the 'norms
hands of Zeus. But in either case we are again dealing with which range on high', whose father is Olympus alone, and which
vOfLoS as the general source of norms or actions. Further, in the are the source of purity in word and deed for mortals.3
complaint of the Erinyes in the Eumenides (778-9 = 808-g) : lw General VOfLOt vested in a human agent appear also in Euripides'
e"€Ot V€WT€pot, 7TaI\UWVS
\" VOfLOVS / KU e t7T7TUUUU
' e'€ KUK X€PWV~ EtI\EU
"\ 8E' description of a tyrant as 'a single individual who possessesvOfLoV
fLOV, the old VOfLOt which the younger gods have ridden down and himself in his own keeping'.4 But he also speaks of the Pythian
wrested from the hands of the Erinyes can only be the authority priestess of Apollo as 'guarding the ancient vOfLoS of the tripod'
which formerly empowered them to wreak vengeance on a homi- (Ion 1322), the authority to dispense oracles which is vested in
cide. The third passage, also from the Eumenides (17 I ), has the the Delphic shrine; and in another passage (Hec. 800), we find
Erinyes accuse Apollo of honouring Orestes, a mortal, 7TUPa. vOfLoV a general VOfLoS controlling even the gods, presumably identical
e€Wv. Although it is possible to interpret the passage as meaning with the source of ordinances dispensed by the gods.s
'beyond what is customary or lawful for gods to do' or 'what is I The scholiast explains the phrase: El)apwT~aftV T0 napa thofs vop.'!' or T~I'
IhavEp.wLV T~V napa Owfs <na'VEaftv. Either interpretation assumes the sense of
proper conduct for a god', there may well be overtones of a
vop.os with which we are concerned here.
general norm which is thought of as standing above the gods.3 In 2 See Jebb's note ad loco
3 863-7 I: d p.o' tvvd') q,EpOVTLp.ofpa Tav / EVaETrTOVayvdav '\oywv / <pywv T€
I Kirk, HCF 51-5. 7TavTwv, cLv VOIL0/, TTpoKHvTaL I I I
vljJITrooe;, ovpavLg. 'v alBEpt T€KVw8eVT€S, Jiv "O)..V/-L7TOS
2 Rose, CSP 4 I. 59, translates: 'Zeus ... who according to hoary custom main- 1TaT~p fLovas, ovoe VLV / 8vuTa rpVULS Q.VEpWV €'TLKTEV •••

tains equity.' This gives a peculiar meaning to a[aa; and what is 'hoary custom' 4 Suppl. 43 I -2 : E[S 'TOV vOfLoV K€KTTJfLEVOS I aUTOS nap' aVTo/.
intended to convey? Aeschylus must have known that it was more than mere 5 Cf. p. 38 with n. 4 below, and Heinimann, NP 121-2. The role which vop.os
custom which entrusted Zeus with the administration of the universe. plays in the Hecuba has been studied by G. M. Kirkwood, TAPA 78 (1947) 61-8;
3 Laroche 190~1 correctly interprets this passage: 'II faut prendre garde for a different interpretation, see D. J. Conacher, AJP 82 (1961) 1-26. See also
qu'Apollon a viole la loi divine, non pas celle que les Olympiens imposent aux J. H. Oliver, Demokratia, the Gods, and the Free World 91-102, with a good biblio-
mortels, mais celie qui les regit, eux les Immortels. Ihwv est un genitif objectif.' graphy of recent discussions on p. 9 I n. I.-To the vop.o' discussed in the preceding
go f9EEMOE AND NOMOE

An interesting problem of interpretation is presented by The- a value above the three types of constitution-the rule of one, of
ognis' complaint (54) about the rulers of Megara, oi 1TpOU{}' oun the many, and of the few-with which Pindar's contemporaries
atKa, 7}LDwav OUT€ VOfLov, and who are now riding high. At a first were familiar. It stands above party and becomes the hallmark
glance, it looks as if Theognis meant by vOfLOV, the sort of thing of a well-ordered society. A similar sense of vOfLo, comes out also
we have just been discussing and criticized them for not having in several Sophoclean passages. In the Antigone Ismene refuses
formerly known anything about the dispensation of justice and to join her sister's plan, because it would be a violation of vOfLo,
the issuing of laws. But the context argues against such an to defy the tyrant's decree (59); at the end of the same play
interpretation. For Theognis goes on to describe the kind of life a repentant Creon believes that it is best to end one's life up-
the present rulers led before they attained power: 'they wore to holding the established order of things;1 when Orestes takes
tatters the goatskins that covered their sides and pastured outside Aegisthus to his death at the end of the Electra (1506), he ex-
the city like deer.'1 In other words, the absence of VOfLOLis here claims that anyone acting in transgression of vOfLo, should be
tantamount to a condition of life outside human civilization, a killed; and in the Oedipus at Colonus (914) Theseus boasts that
life characterized by improper and poor clothing and by a dis- Athens accomplishes nothing without vOfLo,.
organized roaming about outside the confines of the city. The In Herodotus vOfLo, denotes law-and-order in the statement
positive conclusion to be drawn from this is that we find vOfLo, (4. 106) that the Androphagi do not practise justice and use no
herein much the same sense as that in which€vVOfLLais also used. It vOfLo, whatever, and in the celebrated statement of Demaratus
defines the condition of an orderly civilized society and attaches (7. 104. 4) that the Spartans owe their freedom to the mastery over
a moral value to this condition. The same sense of VOfLO, appears them of vOfLo, alone. Thucydides men tions vOfLo, in the senseoflaw-
again in Heraclitus' demand (frg. 44) that a people should fight and-order exclusivelyin speeches, except for his treatment of party
for its vOfLo, as for its wall; there may be a hint of it also in the warfare in Corcyra, where it is said that the formation of parties
av{}pdJ1T€WL VOfLOLwhich are nourished by the divine (frg. 114),2 in such a situation is not contrived for the public good fL€TU TWV
and the demand for law-and-order which this entails may further KELfLEVWVvOfLwv, but for purposes of aggrandizement 1Tapu TOV,
underlie the statement that it is vOfLo, even to obey the will of Ka{}wTWTa, [sc. vOfLOV,] (3. 82. 6).2 For although vOfLo" strictly
one man.3 speaking, may refer here to no more than the positive political
Pindar uses vOfLo, in this sense in Pythians 2. 86-8: €V 7T(lvTa De law by which a state lives, the implication is unmistakable that
, '{}' ~ , , ,/.. ,
VOfLOV €V VYI\WUUO, avYJp 1TP0'f'€P€L,
/ 1Tapa' TvpaVVWL,
",,'.
XW1TOTav ° the observance of such laws is equivalent to law-and-order.
Aa{1po, uTpaTo" / XWTav 1TOAw ot U01JOLTYJPEwvn. 'A man straight- As far as the speeches are concerned, vOfLo, means 'law-and-
forward in speech brings forward law-and-order to everything order' in the argument of the Athenian ambassadors at the
<he does), both under a tyranny, and when the boisterous host, Lacedaemonian Congress that their allies resent any legitimate
and when the wise watch over the city.'4 N0fLO, is here placed as as at Isth. 5. 43, with vo/-,ov as its object. More difficult is the decision whether
7Tana is to be taken (a) as a masculine accusative singular modifying vo/-,ov or
section belong also two fragments from tragedy, cited by stob. Flor. 1. 1. 5 and (b) as a neuter accusative plural. I prefer (b), since EV 7Tana neatly completes the
1. 4·2 (= Nauck2, Adespota, frgg. 471 and 502), in which 0 O€OS and aVaYKT} idea begun in 7TPOq,€PH, if we take EV as the Boeotian equivalent of €ls to express the
are eac:h called the greatest vO/-,os. goal or purpose. If we accept (a), we shall have to take EV adverbially as meaning
, : 55-6: ,aAA' a/-,q,t 7TAwpar", oopas alywv KaT€Tp,{3ov, I 'tw 0' waT' .Aaq,o, Tfjao' 'and besides', 'moreover' (see LsJ s.v. EV C. 2), and translate: 'Moreover, a man
fiI€/-,OVTO 7TOA€OS. straightforward in speech brings forward everything that is law-and-order .. .'
2 Cf. above, pp. 26-8. ] I I 13- I 4: OEOOLKU yap f-L~ TOV~ Kae€aTOrra~ v6f-Lou~ / apLuTov V u<[J'ovTa TOV {3tov
3 Frg. 33: No/-,os Kat {3oVAfi 7T€lOwOa' I.vos. This fragment in particular is too T€A€rV. Since vO/-,os is not likely to refer to Creon's edict here, as it does in 382 and
short and its context too obscure to arrive at any firm conviction about its meaning. 449, and since the expression TOUS KaOHJTWTas vO/-,ovs seems too wide to include
4 My interpretation differs from those usually given. Gildersleeve ad loco and only the religious laws of burial which Antigone had championed, it is best to take
Wilamowitz, Pindaros 292, take 7TPOq,€PH in an intransitive sense and are thus com- the expression to refer to the norms of a well-ordered society.
pelled to give vO/-,os the meaning of 'constitution', for which, to the best of my 2 Cf. the statement in the spurious 84. 2, where human nature is said to have
knowledge, no parallel exists. It seems more natural to regard the verb as transitive, become master of the vo/-,o, and to be accustomed to do wrong 7Tapa TOU, vo/-,ovs.
NOMa}; 33

disadvantage more than if the Athenians, putting aside all con- condition oflaw-and-order, and so also whcn he stressesthe need
sideration of orderly procedure (a7ToOEfLEVO' TOV vOfLOV), had to honour vOfLO, even under adverse circumstances (frg. 433).1
openly aggrandized themselves (I. 77. 3), and soon thereafter,
in the speech in which Archidamus praises the Spartans for not The vOfLo, which have been our concern so far are thought of
being well educated enough to despise law-and-order (I. 84. 3). as universally applicable, valid, and binding. They denote a
The most interesting Thucydidean uses of vOfLo, in this respect general order of life, norms that are recogllized as prevailing in
are to be found in a passage which we shall have to discuss at the universe, proper procedures, norms of proper conduct for the
length in a different context later (pp. 116-19 below). In their individual, and they are applied also to the authority which
defence against the Plataean charge of medism during the Per- issues norms and the condition of civilized law-and-order, which
sian Wars, the Thebans allege that they were at that time ruled is created by adherence to the social norms. We come now to
by a small oligarchical clique, (J7TEpDEEan vOfLo" fLEV KUL Tlp aw- a group of vOfLo, whose validity is confined within a somewhat
rpPOVEaTUT<p EvuvnwTuTov, EyyVTUTW DE TVPUVVOV; in view of this, smaller compass.
they claim, the city as a whole does not deserve to be censured Foremost in this category is the vOfLo, which describes not the
6JV fL~ fLETU vOfLwV Y)fLUPTEV; and the return to an orderly govern- way of life of mankind or of animals as such, but the mores of
ment after the Persian Wars is described as TOVS vOfLoVS EAu{3E a particular group of men. We frequently hear, for example, of
(3. 62. 3-5)·Since vOfLo, are here opposed to tyranny as well as to the vOfLo, which all Greeks share in common (Hdt. 6. 86 (3. 2,
government by a small clique, whose policy is characterized as 7. I02. I; Eur. Or. 495, frg. 853; Thuc. I. 41) and which dif-
the absence of vOfLo" and since vOfLO' are re-established only after ferentiate them from the vOfLo, of non-Greeks (Eur. Andr. 243,
the clique is gone, the term cannot refer to a set of ever-present Bacch. 484), and in many other passages the vOfLo, are clearly
vOfLO' that are accepted by the citizens as part of their general limited to the way oflife enjoyed by a particular people in a par-
way of life. For obviously Thebes had vOfLo, of this sort even ticular state. In this context belongs the vOfLo, for which, as
under the minority rule, just as Sophocles can speak of Thebes in Heraclitus says (frg. 44), a city must fight as for its walls and
the Antigone as having vOfLo, under Creon's rule. The vOfLO' here which we have already mentioned in a different connection
represent a condition which is alleged to have been totally absent (p. 30). Similarly, the avOpw7TEW' vOfLo, of his frg. I 14 (pp. 26-7
from the government of the city during the Persian Wars, a state above) also belong here, since they are the sum total of all the
of law-and-order in which the citizens as a whole (~ gVfL7Tuaa vOfLO' on which the various cities rely, and in Herodotus' account
7TOA',) have some kind of voice in shaping the decisions by which of Darius' experiment (3. 38. 4) the vOfLo, which each people
they will be bound (aiJTOKpaTWp ovaa eavTij,). Just as in Demara- likes best obviously refer to its own mores.
tus' statement about the Spartans, vOfLo, is here treated as the Often vOfLo, designates explicitly or implicitly the mores of
characteristic of a free society.! a specific Greek city, such as Athens,2 Sparta, Thebes, or
Euripides, the last author to whom we turn for this sense of 1 Cf. Or. 523, where Tyndareus asserts that he will defend VOiLeS to the best of
vOfLoS, enumerates among the blessings which Jason claims to his ability. For even though the immediate reference may be to a statute pro-
hibiting talion, the value-judgement implied suggests the larger sense of law-and-
have brought to Medea (Med. 538) that she now knows how to order. A more characteristic Euripidean tone can be detected in a fragment of
live a well-ordered life (vofLO', xpijaOa,) which does not gratify unknown authorship, in which vOiLeS bears this same sense: rrws oilv ni8' ElaopwvTEs
brute force (fL~ 7TPOSlaxvo, Xap,v); and, in attributing to vOfLO' ~ Ihwv y€VOS / E{va, AiYWiLEV ~ VOiLOW' XpwiLElJa; (Nauck2, Adespota, frg. 99).
2 Aesch. Eum. 693; Thuc. 3. 34. 4, 37. 4. Cf. the statement at Thuc. 6. 54. 6
the power to bring great improvements to men (frg. 252) or to that under the tyrants Athens TO'S rrpLV KELiL€VO'S vOiLa'S 'XP"f)TO, although this may
hold together the cities of men (Suppl. 313), he treats them as a equally wel.lrefer to Solo,n's pol,itic~l e?act;ne~ts; the pro;est of Al;ibiades' political
opponents In 8. 53. 2: WS 8ELVOV EL"f) EL TOVS vOiLovS {JtaUaiLEvos KaTEW'; and 8. 76.
1 N0iLos seems to have a similar sense later in the same speech (64. 3), where the 6, where the soldiers on Samos object to the Four Hundred as TOVS rraTpLovs VOiLOVS
Thebans accuse the Plataeans of being pro-Athenian OUTE UKOVTES 'XOVT€S TE TOVS KaTa/.vaavTas. However, in these last three cases Thuc. may also be thinking of
voj.tovs OVU1T€P j.t€XPL TOU oEiJpo. a body of laws or specific legislative enactments.
814"77 D
34 eEEMOE AND NOMOE NOMOE ~

Samos;I of a loose political federation such as Thessaly;2 of the However, it is not until the second half of the fifth century that this
Dorians dcscended from Hyllus (Pind. Pyth. 1. 62), or even of a use of vOj.La, really comes into its own, especially in Herodotus .
. clan such as the Pelopidae (Eur. He!. 1429)' More numerous still His insatiable curiosity for the customs of other peoples and his
are examples in which no name of a city is given and the word delight in telling them are too well known to require a detailed
denotes the mores of a city or society in general,3 or where the discussion. He likes the Persian vOj.La, which prevents a father
ways of non-Greek peoples are referred to.4 from seeing his child before the age of five, lest the child's un-
timely death bring grief to him (1. 136. 2- 137. I); I he tells us
The fact that vOj.La, appears in the plural in most of the pas- which Babylonian practices he likes and which he does not;2 he
sages we have assigned to the category of 'mores' suggests that enumerates some of the vOj.La£ of the .Massagetae (I. 2 I 6. I), of the
the Greeks regarded these vOj.La£ as the aggregate of a number of Egyptians (2. 37. I), of the Issedones (4. 26. I), and of many
specific vOj.La£ which dominate different aspects of the life of a other strange peoples.3 He also mentions a few peculiar Greek
people. These vOj.La£, as we shall see presently, are norms which vOj.La£ : there is the vOj.La, introduced by the Argives to keep their
a people regards as valid and binding in its social, religious, and heads shaved until Thyreae be retrieved from the Spartans, while
political life, and we shall direct our attention to them now. the Spartans, conversely, established the vOj.La, of letting their hair
The time is hard to determine when vOj.La, was first used to grow long (1. 82. 7-8) ; and another vOj.La, enjoins the Spartans
describe customs, that is, those social practices which are current to adorn their hair when about to risk their lives (7. 209. 3).4
among a given group and frequently constitute a typical charac- The interests of the Hippocratic tract On Airs, ~Vaters, and
teristic which differentiates it from other groups. The discovery Places are so close to the ethnographic sections in HerodotusS that
in the lyric age that different men have different standardss it is surprising to find how few uses of vOj.La, as 'custom' it con-
would lead us to expect that this usage began among the lyric tains. There is little beyond the programmatic statement (14)
poets, and there are indeed some scattered indications that this that only those people will be mentioned who differ greatly from
may have been SO.6 But the earliest certain occurrence of vOj.Lo, in one another ~ ePVUEL ~ vOWtJ and the ancient vOj.La, of the Makro-
this sense is in a choral song in Aeschylus' Choephoroe (424), in kephaloi of shaping their children's heads, a vO/w, which later
which the maidens beat their breasts and sing an Arian dirge developed into ePVat,.6
after the fashion (EV vOj.La£,) of a Kissian wailing woman. I For other Persian V0JJ-0L see 140. 3 (Magi may kill any creature except dogs
and men); 3. 31. 4 (the Royal Judges find a vOJJ-o<; for Cambyses, permitting the
I Sparta: Hdt. 7.136. I, Thuc. 5.60.2. Thebes: Soph. Ant. 191, Eur. Barch. Persian king to do what he pleases); 5.18.2-3 (Persians tell Amyntas of their vOJJ-o<;
331. Samos: Tod, CHI 12, No. 96.15-16. to have concubines and wives sit with the men after a banquet) ; and 9. III. I (no
2 Pind. Pyth. 10. 70-1, accepting the conventional accentuation. It seems to one asking a boon at a royal banquet must be refused).
make more sense, however, to follow the suggestion ofE. Kapp and read vOJJ-ov, see 2 He likes the manner of auctioning off marriageable women (I. 196. 1-4) and
app. crit. ad loc. in Snell+. their way of curing the sick (I. 197), but not the custom of temple prostitution (I.
3 Soph. Aj. 1073, Ant. 368; Eur. Suppl. 430, El. 234, Or. 487, Bacch. 891 ; Thuc. 199. 1-5). For other Babylonian VOJJ-OL see I. 195.2,200.
2.37. 1,6.18·7; AI'. Nub. 1040 and 1400, Eccl. 609. 3 4. 68. 2 (Scythian custom to swear by the king's hearth), 103. I (Taurians),
+ Eur. Or. 1426 (Phrygians) ; Soph. OC 337-3 (Egyptians) ; and especially Hdt. I I 7 (Sauromatian custom that a woman cannot be married. until she has killed
I. 94. I (Lydians), 172. I (Kaunians), 173.4 (Lycians, Cretans, and Carians); 2. a man), 172. 2 (among Nasamones a bride must sleep with all male wedding
35.2,45. 2, 79·1,92. I (Egyptians); 3·20. 2 (Ethiopians), 82.5,83· 3 (Persians); guests), 190 (Libyans); 5. 6. 1-2 (Thracians).
4.80.5, 105. I, 107 (Scythians with Neuroi and Melanchlainoi), 168. I (Egyptians + Cf. the Spartan vOJJ-o<; of giving the kings a double portion at feasts (7.1°3. I),
and Adyrmachidai), 169. 2 (Giligamai and Libyans), 170, 171 (Cyrenaeans, and the custom introduced by Argives and Aeginetans after some troubles with
Abystai, and Bakales), 187. I (Libyans); 5. 3. 2 (Thracians); 7. 8 a. I and 9·41. 4 Athens, to enlarge women's brooch-pins to one-and-a-half times their original
(Persians). size, to have these dedicated in the shrine of Demia and Auxesia, and to have
5 Cf. B. Snell, The Discovery of the ;Uind, tr. T. G. Rosenmeyer, 47-50. henceforth local rather than Attic vessels used in that sanctuary for drinking
6 Archilochus, frg. 230 (Bude) reads: vOJJ-o<; 8. KP1)TLKO<; 8L8auKfTaL, suggesting purposes (5.88.2). 5 See Heinimann, NP 172-80 and 209.
a Cretan practice. Similarly, Alcaeus (E. Lobel and D. Page, Poetarum Lesbiorum 6 Cf. the beginning of 19, where the practices of the Scythians described in 18
fragmenta, frg. 72. 6: ii"Oa vOJJ-o<; OaJJ-' '''. L] .L] .v1)v) probably refers to a customary are called vOJJ-OL. For the only other passages in which vOJJ-o<; appears in this treatise
practice, cf. frgg. 35. I, 129.25, and 181. I. see above, p. 22.
36 BEl:MOl: A:'\D NOMO};

Thucydides uses vOfL0S' similarly of the Odrysian practice of treated like a statutory enactment, although he, too, elsewhere
accepting rather than giving gifts (2. 97. 4) and of the Spartan (Plut. 789, 795) treats VOftae; with respect; and when the sophist
_custom of having flute-players accompany the troops into the Antiphon (frg. 44A. I. 23-3 I) rejects Tfl. TWV vOfLwv as an
field (5. 70 with 69. 2). Into this context also belongs the old custom arbitrary accretion and favours .pVULS', the final step in the rejec-
(7TuAUU), vOfL0S'), mentioned in connection with the colonization of tion of customary practices has been taken.
Epidamnus, that the founder (olKwT~e;) of a new city be chosen
from the mother-city (I. 24. 2), the generally Greek l'ofLoe; that The VOfLOt we have just dealt with are customary practices
the care of sanctuaries lies in the hands of the power occupying unquestioningly accepted as valid and correct by most people of
the territory in which they are situated (4. 98. 2),1 and also the the society in which they exist, even if later intellectuals could
mLTptoe; vOfLoe; of Athens to bury those fallen in war at public frown upon them. The same development can be detected in
expense (2. 34. 1).2 a closely related sense of vOfLoe;, where the term describes not a
Among the dramatists it is, as expected, Euripides who speaks practice but a belief, an opinion, a point of view, or an intellectual-
of vOfLoe; as a customary practice more frequently than any other. attitude, which starts out by being accepted without question
But it is interesting to note that, while he usually describes as by all members of a given group, but is attacked by intellec-
vOfL0S' practices which are generally observed by those among tuals from the second half of the fifth century on as 'mere' con-
whom they prevail, he also applies vOfL0S' to many practices that ventional belief, foolishly embraced by the ignorant multitude
cannot have had that general validity which the term usually but to be rejected in the light of truer values. Still, even here
implies. In other words, we see in Euripides the beginnings of the judgement about the truth or falsehood of VOfL0S' is always
that denigration of vOfLoe; which reaches its climax in the vOfLoe;- secondary, and the term retains its old signification of something
.pvaLe; controversy. We find respect for vOfLoe; in his statement that regarded as valid by public opinion in general.
different men have different customs (frg. 346. 4), in the vOfLoe; of The earliest example of this meaning is found in Orestes'
the Greeks to honour athletes (frg. 282. 13), of the Aetolians to go exclamation in Aeschylus' ChoepllOroe that Aegisthus has received
to war with only one foot shod (frg. 530. 9), of the Phoenicians to what is commonly held (we; vOfLoe;) to be the proper punishment
bow down before a royal person (Phoen. 294), of the Erechtheids for him who has brought dishonour to another person. 1 But the
to give their children as tokens gold-wrought snakes (Ion 20, 25), best-known and most influential passage in which vOfLoe; bears this
and also in the vOfLoe; initiated by Danaus to call the Pelasgians sense is Pindar's poem which begins: vOfLoe; a mJ.vTwv (3uatAEve;.2
'Danaans' (frg. 228. 8). But when vOfLoe; denotes the custom of As was first pointed out by Wilamowitz, vOfL0S' is here that which
heralds to exaggerate in giving their reports (Heracl. 292-3), the is accepted as right in the opinion and general belief of people, 3
impropriety of women looking at men (Hec. 974),3 or the habit and it was correctly understood in this sense by Herodotus
of throwing the remnants of a meal to the dogs (frg. 469), and I g8g-go: Aly{aBov yap au A€YW /-LOpov' I EX€/" yap aLaxvvTfjpOs;, ws- vaIL0S", 3{wrw.
when Orestes facetiously justifies his murder of Clytaemnestra This passage has been taken by Rose, CSPA 2. 2 I7, as a reference to the Athenian
law which permitted an adulterer to be killed with impunity; and a similar view
with the argument that he had put an end to the vOfLoe; of wives seems to underlie Smyth's translation (Loeb) : 'for he hath suffered the adulterer's
to kill their husbands (Or. 57I), we are no longer dealing with punishment as the law allows.' But apart from the difficulty of equating alaxvvT~p,
customs which are expected to be taken seriously as social norms. of which no other example is cited in LSJ, with /-,OLXOS, the law is unlikely to enter
here, since Attic law permitted this as justifiable homicide only when the adulterer
The same facetious use is found also in Aristophanes' Clouds was caught in the act; see Lipsius, ARR 430-1.
(142 1-6), where the VOfL0S' that fathers beat their sons isjocularly 2 Frg. 169+PO-ry, No. 2450, frg. I. I have discussed this fragment at length in
I As stated by an Athenian herald sent to the Thebans. Immediately before this, 'Pindar, NOMO};, and Heracles', HSCP 69 (1965) 109-38, text on pp. 111-12; for
at 4.97. 2, the Boeotians had accused the Athenians of transgressing Tn VO/-,L/-,anvv its influence in antiquity see ibid., n. 3.
3 Platon: Beitagen und Textkritik, 3rd eeln. by R. Stark, 96: 'Daraus ist zu schlieBen,
'EAA~VWV in occupying the sanctuary at Delium.
2 See Endnote, pp. 175-6 below. daB der vO/-,os, d.h. wie es die Jvlenschen gel ten lassen, bei Gottern und Mensehen
3 For the role of vo/-,os in the Hecuba in general see above, p. 29 n. 5. liber die Qualitiit einer mensch lichen Handlung entscheidet ....
(3·38. 4)·The point of the poem is that, although the theft of 'separation' than of 'birth' and 'death', but accepts the common
Geryon's cattle and of the mares of Diomedes was accomplished by usage when he speaksas an ordinary citizen. 1 Similarly, Democritus
yiokncc, we must not object to it, since they are generally held to (frgg. 9, 125) accepts the way in which people talk (FOfLCfJ) about
be glorious labours ofHcrac1cs; and what is generally bc1ieycdto colour, sweetness, and bitterness, even though he knows that
be right has royal, that is legitimate and not tyrannical, power, I in truth (ETEfi) only atoms and the void exist. In medicine,
and this power is rccognized by both gods and men.2 we find that the author of the treatise On the Sacred Disease uses
Further, the FOfl-OL by which Creon claims in Sophocles' Anti- vOfLa, to discriminate between the ugly and beautiful, the bad and
gone (r 78-91) to be enhancing the greatness of Thebes seem to the good, and the pleasant and the unpleasant (17),2 apparently
consist in conventional beliefs, since he uses the term to sum up regarding this belief as valid and true; but a few chapters later
his convictions about the nature of a good citizen. In Thucydides, (20) he asserts that the popular belief (FofLCfJ) in the diaphragm
A1cibiades uses FOfLa, to describe the high opinion among his as the seat of understanding does not corrcspond to fact, al-
contemporaries which his Olympic victories had brought Athens though he seems amenable to using eppEVE, in ordinary parlance.3
(6. r6. 2), and in Euripides, Hippolytus' attendant calls FOfLa, A final example of a conventional belief which is condoned
the attitude of hatred which most people haye toward a haughty despite the fact that it is, strictly speaking, inaccurate, is Hero-
and unpopular bearing (91, 93).3 dotus' assertion (4. 39. 1) that a certain promontory ends FOfLCfJ
Whereas in these passages the validity of conventional beliefs but not in fact at the Arabian Gulf.4
remains unquestioned and uncha11enged, there emerges in the The next step toward the ultimate rejection of FOfLa, is taken in
second half of the fifth century a cha11enge,which begins with a number of passages, in which conventional beliefs are no longer
doubt and ends in rejection. Heinimann has shown that Hecuba's condoned, because they do not represent truth. In a Euripidean
famous exclamation (Hec. 799-801): d,\,\' at 8w~ a8EFavm Xw fragment (141), illegitimate children are only vOfLCfJ, but not in
KE{VWV KpUTWV / vOfLa" vOfLCfJyap TaU, 8wu, ~YaVfLE8u / KU~' WfLW fact, inferior to legitimate ones, and in the Hecuba (846-9) the
({btKU KU~ b{KUt' WPWfLEFat looks at first glance like an expression of chorus complains of the vOfLat which compel us to look upon
simple accepting faith but contains at the same time the sugges- former enemies as friends, and upon former friends as enemies.
tion that such a faith is not very firmly grounded.4 The reason The same attitude toward vOfLa, is seen again, but in a comic
why we suspect this is that we find a distinction drawn between context, in Aristophanes' Acharnians, when the Megarian assures
vOfLa, and truth as early as Empedocles, who knows as a Dicaeopolis (773) that he is offering for sale what is a pig 'E'\-
philosopher that it is more correct to speak of 'mixture' and ,\avwv vOfLCfJ, that is what every straight-thinking Greek would
I Laroche 174. regard as a pig; but the audience (and probably Dicaeopolis, too)
I have argued this point at greater length in my article cited above (p. 37
2
n. 2), esp. pp. 117~26.
know better. Similarly, when in the parabasis of the Birds the
3 Cf. frg. 52. 8, where time is said to make a noble bearing to be thought of chorus asserts (755-9) that the birds regard as good what men
(= vOiL'!') as haughty. ' here below regard as uZaxpa Tip VOfLCfJKpUTaVfLEFU, what it stresses
4 Heinimann, NP 121-2. Cf. p. 29 n. 5 above.-Something similar mav be
is that general opinion gives only a very relative term. In other
implied in the enigmatic lines from Eur. Bellerophon, frg. 292. 4-6: voaaL O€/JV~TWV
at }LEV fda' avOa/pEToL, / at 3' €K 8EWV 1TapnaLv, ci,\;\a T~ VOJ.L4J / LWfU.B' at.hous. If vOJ-Lw is words, conventional beliefs are contrasted with what is real, and
correctly interpreted in this context as referring to some belief or conviction whi~h however widely FOfLa, is accepted, there arc criteria measured by
whether right or wrong, is commonly accepted, the translation would run: 'but w~
which it is proved wanting. From here it is only a sma11step to
try to cure them [sc. the diseases] in the conviction <that we are able to do so).'
~till, the questioa remains whether a,mL, refers to both self-inflicted and god- the complete rejection of vOfLa, as conventional belief in favour of
InflIcted dIseases or only to the latter. The second seems to me to give a some-
what better scnse: 'although the presence of these diseases is due to the gods, we I <au)
Frg. 9. 5: ~ /JEiL" KaMauat, VOiL'!' (j' ErrLf'liLL Kat aUTO,.
nevertheless act In ;he conviction that we can cure them.' But the reading may 2 A similar point is made in a tragic fragment of unknown authorship, Nauck2,
well be suspect; see r. Gomperz, Sher. d. kais. Ak. d. Wiss. Phi/os.-ms!. Ct. 116 (Wien, Adespota, frg. 26.
1888) 29.
3 Heinimann, NP 86 n. 71. 4 Ibid. 82.
epVat<;, which we find most clearly articulated by Callicles III In Aeschylus the deposition of a suppliant's bough follows
Plato's Gorgias. 1 vOfLo<; (Suppl. 241), it denotes the customary worship of Hermes
(Suppl. 220), the rule that wailings should accompany the paean
The difficulty of analysing a concept such as vOfLo<; into its to the dead (Cho. 150- I), and that a murderer must not speak
constituent elements becomes most manifest as we now turn to until he has been ritually cleansed (Eum. 448-50). I Pindar uses
its uses in religious contexts. For while it is true to say that the vOfLO<; (01. 8. 78) in connection with rites for the dead, and all
term may denote a ritual ordinance, that is, an injunction that religious VOfLOL in Sophocles relate to the proper burial of the
something ought to be done, or a ritual practice, that is, a state- dead (Aj. 1130, 1343; Ant. 24, 519), except that once it refers in
ment that something is actually done as a custom, or a belief: a larger sense to temple worship and ritual as such.2
that is, a conviction that something exists or that it is right that Funeral practices are described as vOfLo<; also by Herodotus
something be done, it is always difficult and often impossible to (2.36. 1,3. 16.3-4,6.58.2), who uses the term for purification
determine in any given context which of these three notions its rites (1. 35. I), for the order of worship and specific temple
author had in mind. The reason for this is not far to seek. As we regulations (1. 132.3, 144.3; 2. 39·4, 42.3), for regulations con-
have seen time and again, the crucial point in vo,uo<; is that it is cerning the granting of asylum (2. 113. 2-3), and for the rule
something which a given society regards as a valid norm for which prevented the Spartans, at the time of :Marathon, from
itself, usually ul1selfconsciouslyand without question, something going to war when the moon was full (6. 106. 3). The term also
which, even when attacked and disparaged, is attacked and dis- has a more general sense when, for example, we are told that the
paraged just because it is a generally accepted norm. It is, there- use of cult images, temples, and altars is not EV vOfLcp for the
fore, immaterial to the Greek way of thinking whether in any Persians (I. 131. I), when he speaks of the treatment of sacred
given context VOfLO<; is a rule, a customary practice, or a belief; animals by the Egyptians (2.65.3), or when he tells us ofa king
its characteristic is that it is something generally regarded and of Scythia who worshipped the gods according to the VOfLOL of the
accepted as correct for a given group. Greeks (4. 78. 4). In this context belong also the VOfLOL of the
The difficulty of which we have just spoken is already ap- Athenians in the formula by which Cleisthenes of Sicyon be-
parent in the earliest passage in which VOfLO<; occurs in a religious trothed his daughter Agariste to Megacles of Athens (6. 130.2).3
sense. The Hecate hymn in Hesiod's Theogony promises honour The Babylonian vOfLo<; prescribing temple prostitution is perhaps
and wealth to him who propitiates the goddess ¥powv LEpa.. KuAa.. equally well taken as a religious or as a social practice (I.
KUTa.. vOfLoV (417).2 It is impossible to tell whether it is a rule or 199·1-5)·
a custom that the worshipper is to follow, and it is equally im- In the public documents that have come down to us from the
possible to make this decision in the case of a fragment which fifth century we meet a religious vOfLo<; in the Athenian decree
states that the apxu'io<; vOfLo<; is best for sacrifices offered by a city.3 concerning Colophon of 447/6 B.C., in which the oath demanded
Similarly, it is hard to know whether vOfLo<;, in the account given I In this context belongs also Apollo's statement, Eum. 576, that Orestes is
by Pherecydes of Syros (frg. 2, co!' 2) about the origin of the VOJL4J [KE-r'rjl£.
2 Ant. 285-7: a!"<p'KLova, I vao", 7Tupwawv ~AOE KavaO~!"aTa I Ka, Y77v
oan,
unveiling ceremony at weddings (avuKu'\v7TT~PLa), refers to a rule €Kdvwv ]ebb puts a comma after EKE{VWV and takes VOj.LOVS as
KUI. VOJ-LOVS OtaUKEOWv;
or to a practice. In short, however interesting for us, the question referring to the laws of Thebes. It is difficult to accept this interpretation, since
of differentiation between rule and practice was unimportant for (a) the whole passage 282-8 speaks only of the gods and not of the city; (b) it is
more logical to take Y77v EKELVWVto refer to the temple precincts rather than to the
the Greek view of VOfL0<;' territory of Thebes as a whole, because it provides thus a more natural continua-
I 482 e-484 c, including the re-interpretation of Pindar, frg. 169, to support his tion to the temples and votive offerings to which Polyneices set fire; (e) its position
VOfLOS TfjS epVGEWS. in the line suggests that EKELVWV is to be taken not only with Y77v but also with
2 That the 'Hymn' is genuine can no longer be doubted after the searching dis- vo!"ou" so that (d) the idea that Polyneices' action disrupted the performance of
cussion ~f M. L. \Vest, Hesiod: Theogony 276-80, cr. also F. So[msen, HA 51 n. 169. ritual practices (vo!"ou, otaaKEowv) makes eminent sense.
3 Hesrod, frg. 22 I : w, KE 7TOAI, pE~naI, VO!"O, 0' apxafo, apWTos. 3 Cf. P. S. Photiades, )lOT/vii 32 (1920) 116 n. I.
NOMOI; 43

of the people of Colophon is to be sworn in accordance with their protests in the Heracleidae (roog- I I) that his death will he contrary
VOfLOS',Iand two phrases in the one-year armistice agreement of to the )}OVOL of the Greeks. Finally, there arc passages which
T

423 B.C. between Athens and Sparta permit the operations of the refer to gellcral religious VOfl.oL, such as the Taurian custom of
Delphic shrine of Apollo to proceed KUTa TOUS' 7TUTp{OVS' vOfwVS" sacrificing strangers to Artemis (IT 465, c[ 35), or the order of
(Thuc. 4. lI8. I, 3).2 worship of Apollo's sanctuary at Delphi (Ion 229, 643).2
The religious VOfLOL were never undermined or disparaged to Aristophanes uses VOfL0S' in a religious sense only rarely and
the same degree to which we noticed this being done to customs always in a joyous context. Thus we hear that it is VOfLoS' for
and conventional beliefs. And yet it is not surprising that we hear women to have fun at the celehration of the orgies in honour of
of deliberate infractions of religious VOfLOL for the first time in the Demeter and Kore (Thesm. 94,]) and to invite Athene to join
last third of the fifth century. In his account of the Plague, their dance (Thesm. 1137), and when sacrifice is offered it is vOfLoS'
Thucydides reports that VOfLOL concerning burial were abandoned that the gods get the entrails (Av. 5 I 8).
in Athens at this time (2. 52.4), and in connection with the story
of civil strife on Corcyra he states that alliances derived their Of the vOf1.oL which constitute the mores of a particular people
strength less from a divine vOfLos--referringprobably to the re- we have now discussed those that express its social and religious
ligious sanctions against breaking an oath--than from a common beliefs and practices. To them we must now add the political and
desire to act in contravention oflaw (3. 82. 6). judicial VOfLOL, that is, those rules and regulations by which the
In Euripides there is only one example of an antagonistic internal life of society as a state is ordered. It is here that we
attitude to religious VOfLOL, and that is in the complaint that the encounter vOfLoS' in its sense of 'statute', although, as we shall see,
gods permit unjust persons to be suppliants at their altars (Ion the term does not by itself imply in the fifth century what it
1312-13). Still, even here the principle that vOfLoS" makes an usually implies in the fourth-century orators, namely, written
altar inviolate seems to be accepted.3 He describes as vOfL0S" the legislation. But it does imply that the regulation which it de-
rule to bury the dead,4 as well as certain specific funeral rites.s scribes is accepted as a valid and binding norm by society, and
As in other authors, it governs the purification ceremonies to that it is usually accepted as such, or expected to be accepted, by
which a murderer has to submit (Or. 429, HF 136I) and other the individual citizen.
kinds of purification (He!. 87 I); it plays a part in wedding The political meaning of vOfLoS' is not found before the fifth
ceremonies (IA 734, Tro. 324), at the Choes feast of the Anthes- century B.C.3 It occurs for the first time in Aeschylus' Supplices
teria (IT 958-60), and at the festival of Artemis at Halai (IT (387-91), where Pelasgus twice mentions an Egyptian vOfLoS",
1458). A religious vOfLoS" is also involved when Eurysthcus which the sons of Aegyptus, as next-of-kin, might invoke to win
power over the daughters of Danaus. In the Prometheus vOfLoS' ap-
I IG 12• 15. 30-1: Ka.,.~ [nU)E KoAoq,ovlo<; o/-,oaaL, Ka()' a KoAoq,]ovlov " "0/-,0<; pears in the plural in two passages (149-50,402-3) to describe
[KEA")" ... J, as emended by W. Kolbe, Hermes 73 (1938) 256-9; cf. also H. Bengt-
son, Die Staatsvertrage des Alterturns 2, No. 145. The reading in ATL 2. D 15 (= SEG
the political principles by which Zeus governs. This may seem
10, No. 17) 41-2 necessitates, without a cogent reason, the assumption of a ditto- surprising in view of the fact that the theme of the Prometheus
graphy. hinges on the point that Zeus' government is tyrannical and has
2 There is also a fifth-century lex sacra from Gytheion, in which VO/IO<; occurs in
an uncertain context; see IG 5. I, I 155; Schwyzer, DGE, No. 51.
not yet won universal acceptance. However, this use becomes less
3 Cf. frg. 1049. 2, and Hel. 800, where Menelaus inquires whether it is a non- surprising as we observe that both passages are given to the
Greek custom for a suppliant to take refuge at a tomb rather than at an altar. chorus of Oceanids, who are resigned to living under the rule of
4 Suppl. 526, 563, and 671. But at 540-1 the possibility of a vO/-,o<; not to bury
them is envisaged. Zeus. Moreover, in both cases the dative plural of the noun is
5 Hel. 1241-3, 1246 (when a person has been drowned, clothes are buried in his 1 That the VO/-,OL here appealed to are concerned with religion is indicated by the
place); 1258 (barbarians sacrifice a horse or a bull at funerals) ; cr. Tro. 266-7, phrase DUX dyvo~ €lJJ-L Tip KTUVOVTt KUT8avwv.
where Hecuba asks Talthybius which Greek vo/"o<; demands that Polyxcna be slain 2 On 643 cf. Heinimann,}lF 167-9, who translates vO/-,o<; as 'Tempelordnung'.
over Achilles' tomb, . 3 For the problem of vO/-,o<; in Solon's po~ms see above, p. 3 n. 5.
connected with the verb KpUTlJVW to indicate that Zeus has won The situation is similar in the second inscription, whose date is
acceptance because of his superior power, and further, the addi- perhaps a few years earlier than that of the Halicarnassian law.
tion of the adjectives VEoXfLoL<; and LOtOt<; introduces a sarcastic It contains the instrument, already mentioned in a different
tone into the use of vOfL0<;: what is regarded as valid and binding context before, by which Naupactus was settled as a colony of the
under the dispensation of Zeus, the Oceanids seem to say, is in Hypoknemidian Locrians.1 Here the written law refers to itself
fact something unprecedented and idiosyncratic, enacted without as a BEBfLtOV, but it contains several clauses stipulating cases,
the consent of the governed. I especially where property is at issue, in which the vOfLW (= VOfLtfLU)
While it is possible and even probable that the passage from of the Naupactians or ofthe various cities of the Hypoknemidian
the Supplices presupposes a background of written law at Athens,z Locrians shall apply (II. 26, 27, 28),2 and mention is made also of
it would be ludicrous even to raise the question of writing in the an 0p90V TOV VOfLtOV (1. 45)' The question whether or not these
case of Zeus' laws. This suggests that in the first half of the fifth rules existed in writing cannot be settled on the basis of the text
century vOfL0<; might or might not refer to written legislation; in as we have it, and we can hope for an answer only if new in-
other words, the question of writing is immaterial to the defini- scriptions containing some of the relevant laws should be found at
tion of a political vOfL0<;' This is confirmed by three inscriptions Naupactus or in Eastern Locris. The point is again that the
from outside Athens, which are approximately contemporary question of whether a VOfLtOV or vOfL0<; is written or not was i.r-
with the Prometheus. relevant for those for whom the BEBfLtOV was drafted; what dId
The first of these, dated between 460 and 455 B.C., comes from matter was that it was a practice or regulation regarded as bind-
Halicarnassus and concerns the settlement of disputes over real ing within a given community.
~state.3 Since the inscription describes itself as a vOfL0S" (II. 32, The third inscription, dated about 450 B.C., consists in a decree
34-5), we are justified in assuming that the term here signifies from Erythrae, which stipulates judicial procedures to be fol-
a written statute agreed to jointly by the Halicarnassians, the lowed, apparently in establishing the qualification of magistrates
Salmacitians, and Lygdamis. But this assumption is not warranted or in punishing malfeasances committed by them.3 The inscrip-
in the stipulation, some lines earlier in the same inscription, tion speaks of itself as a !f;~epWfLu (B 1-2), but it refers three times
,
VOfLWt " ,
OE, '[
KUTU7T E] ~
P VUV, , ~ n- ,\
0PKWlt~U <"
U/t \" '(II • 19-20
TOU<; OtKUUTU<; ). to VOfLOt in such a way that, although the presumption is that they
For not only does the context fail to make clear to whom the oath were written, the text itself offers no unequivocal clues to enable
is to be administered, but it also sheds no light on the question us to determine whether or not they actually were written. In the
whether such oath formulae were prescribed by a written law in first of the three passages, the panel of judges is required to
Halicarnassus (as many oaths in Athens were written) or whether swear the same oath as that taken by the Council, namely, that
vOfLo<; refers here to an unwritten religious regulation or practice. they will pass judgement KUTU vOfL0<; KUL !f;YJeptUfLUTU (II. A 21-2).4
Evidently, the problem whether or not a given regulation existed Since the inscription refers to itself as a !f;~epWfLU, we are justified
in writing was of less importance to those who regarded them- in assuming that the !f;YJeptUfLUm may have been published in
selves bound by vOfL0<; than it is to us. vVriting or its absence did writing; and if we further assume that the distinction between
not apparently make a vOfL0<; any less binding. these two kinds of enactment was the same as in Athens, we sur-
I For the revolutionary connotations of VEOX/-,OS, cf. Aesch. Pers. 693; Soph. Ant. mise that the ~'ofLOt here mentioned may also have been written.
156; Eur. Hipp. 866, Tro. 23 I, IT I 162 ; and especially Hdt. 9. 99. 3 and 104; also The second passage stipulates that judgement be passed 7TAYJUtOV
VEOX/-,OW in Hdt. 4. 201. 2, 5. [9.2, and in Tlmc. I. 12.-The adverb d8ETWS, to
which Bentley rig:'tly emended the d8Ea/-,ws of the manuscripts, points in the same I Tod, CHI 12, No. 24; ef. above, p. 16.
direction: Zeus wields his power with new laws without proper enactment. 2 In I. 30 vo/-,os is used with the same meaning.
2 See G. H. Macurdy, 'Had the Danaid Trilogy a Social Problem?' CP 39 3 The most recent text is that of Meiggs and Andrewes B I 16. The best discus-
(1944) 95-100, esp. 97, and below, pp. 58-9. sion is still that of A. Wilhelm, Jahreshifte d. listen. arch. Inst. Wien 12 (1909) 126-41
3 Tod, CHI 12, No. 25; Buck, CD, :\:0. 2. For a fuller discussion see below, (with revised date, ibid. 14 (191 I) 237)·
pp. 167--70. 4 Note the same phrase in the written heliastic oath in Dem. 24·149·
46 eEEMOE AND NOMOE

n8EvT[u KJUTa T[OJV v6fJ-0v (11. A 25-7). This has been interpreted was written which prevented the Corinthians from giving away
by Wilhelm: 'das Gesetz soIl in del' Niihe aufgestellt werden, ships without payment (6. 89), and the same is also true of some
so daB es den Richtern VOl'Augen steht und jederzeit befragt political Persian I and Egyptian V6fJ-0Lo2
werden kann.'1 If this is correct, it would follow that the v6/-w<; is In Sophocles, v6fJ-0s occurs in a political sense most frequently
an inscribed document. However, this interpretation would make in the Antigone, to describe Creon's proclamation forbidding the
more sense if the KUnt were not there, and we must reckon with burial of Polyneices.3 Creon is of course the main proponent of
the possibility that another kind of v6fJ-0<; may be referred to v6fJ-0S in the Antigone, and the theme of the play revolves around
which mayor may not have been written. The third passage Antigone's refusal to accept his V6fJ-0<;;4 still, the tragedy would
(B 16-24) permits prosecution of a person ons d[aJ70s ~0EL fJ-~ completely lose its point if Creon's v6fJ-0s had not been generally
I<UTa v6fJ-0v TpUrpE<; ~ EgEAw8EPO 7Tufs ~ gEVO, apparently referring accepted by the rest of the population of Thebes. A judicial
to the child of a freedman or a foreigner who poses as a citizen.2 v6fJ-0<; is probably involved in Oedipus' plea before the elders of
vVhatever the precise meaning of the obscure phrase fJ-~KUTa Colonus (OC 548) that he was legally guiltless in slaying Laius,
v6fJ-0v TpUrpE<; may be, it presupposes the existence of regulations the law which permits a person to kill his attacker in self-defence;
defining a citizen, perhaps legislation of the same kind, though and when in the Ajax Agamemnon states (1247) that no v6fJ-0S
not necessarily establishing the same conditions, as Pericles' could ever be established, if like Ajax everyone were to refuse to
citizenship law, which was passed about the same time03 If this submit to the verdict of the judges, we have a very clear example
analogy is correct, it may well be that the Erythraean regulation of the acceptance which the word implies. .
was contained in a written law. In short, although it is probable Euripides' use of v6fJ-0<; in its political or judicial sense strikingly
that the three occurrences of v6fJ-0<; in this inscription all refer to reflects the actual use of the term in the lawcourts and in the
written legislation, this conclusion is based on inferences rather Assembly. He is the first of the tragedians to speak explicitly of
than on direct and unequivocal statements in the inscription written laws and to praise them as a bulwark against tyranny
itself. (Suppl. 433)05 But at the same time the obligating force of v6fJ-o<;
The lack of differentiation between written and unwritten seems to begin to wane. We saw this earlier in his treatment of
political V6fJ-0L is perhaps most familiar from Herodotus. If we the V6fJ-OL which describe customary practices and beliefs in
were to depend on Herodotus alone, we should never know social and religious life, but his negative attitude is even more in
whether Solon's legislation at Athens was written or not; he uses evidence when he mentions political and judicial laws. He may
v6fJ-0<; here (1. 29. 1-2) without any explanation, just as he does also treat written V6fJ-OL, which he praised in the Supplices, as
in mentioning the-probably unwritten-v6fJ-0<; at the time of inhibiting human freedom of action (Hec. 864-7), and the very
Marathon which gave the Athenian polemarch the command of fact of their existence indicates that there are people who do not
the right wing of the army (6. 111. 1). Similarly, it is on the basis automatically accept what v6fJ-o<; demands, and this becomes
of Plutarch (Lycurgus 13. 1) and not of Herodotus that we are led I 3. 31. 2-5 (Cambyses wants the royal judges to find out whethe~ there is
a V0fJ-0> permitting marriage with one's sister, and they find a .v~fJ-OS- whl~h states
to believe that some Spartan political V6fJ-0L mentioned by Hero- that the king of Persia may do as he pleases); 118. I (law glvmg the SIX other
dotus did not appear in writing.4 We cannot tell whether the law conspirators against the Magi free access to Darius) ; 7. 2. I (king has to appoint his
successor before departing on a military expedition).
lOp. cit. 12 (Igog) 134. 2 2. 136.2 (law under Asychis permitting the taking ofloans on the security of
Z I prefer Wilhelm's reading (ibid. 136) d[ a]To> to the a¥Tos- read by Meiggs and one's father's corpse and burial ground); 177. 2 (Amasis' law compelling every
Andrewes. Egyptian to show the source of his livelihood annually to the nomarch).
3 For Pericles' citizenship law of 451/0 B.C. see Arist. Alh. Pol. 26. 4. and Pillt. 3 Ant. 382, 449, 481, 847; cr. Creon's admonition to Haemon at 663, where,
Per. 37. 3. who uses the verb £ypa.pf in connection with it. Cf. Hignett, HAC 343-7. however the word may have the wider sense of 'law-and-order'.
4 5.42.2 and G. 52. 3 (eldest son succeeds to the throne). So perhaps also the law 4 See 'C. P. Segal, 'Sophocles' Praise of Man and the Conflicts of the Antigone',
enacted after Demaratus' defection at Eleusis, 5. 75. 2, which prevented the kings Arion 3. 2 (1964) 46-66.
from going on a military expedition at the same time. 5 See the apt remarks of Stier, NB 244·
48 eEEMOE AND NOMOE NOMOE ~
worst if those who wrote the laws themselves do violence to them the Prytaneion, which is parodied as a vO/-LO, in the Frogs (76 I -4).
(Ion 442).1 Although these are the only Euripidean passages in A background of written legislation is assumed when the Ec-
which vOj1-O£ are explicitly referred to as written, there are many clesiazusae establish the vO/-Lo, commanding intercourse with
more occurrences of the word which show that Euripides wrote an old woman before a young girl can be gratified, 1 when a
against a background which took written legislation for granted. sycophant wants to come to the aid of the established laws (Plut.
We hear of voted decrees through which laws are applied,2 and 914), when in the Birds V0/-LOL are offered for sale or offered to the
of the enactment of the vO/-Lo, that equal votes for and against the choice of the Parricide (1038-9, 1346), and when there is talk of
accused before the Areopagus shall result in acquittal (El. 1268- the laws which the city has enacted (Vesp. 467) or of people who
9), but we are also told that some of the Erinyes refused to ac- want to change decrees and the law (Thesm. 361-2).
cept it (IT 970). Euripides mentions the statutes against murder It is surprising that we find in Thucydides not a single explicit
(Or. 941, HF 1322, Hec. 291) and the law which commands the reference to written legislation, and even when he mentions
Taurians to sacrifice any arriving Greek to Artemis (IT 38, 277, specific political VO/-LOL, it is not always certain whether they are
586, 1189); but we find in the general treatment also the same written or not. The vO/-Lo, prescribing the delivery of funeral
awareness of the inadequacy or restricting force of v0/-L0' that we orations, for example, is evidently attributed by Pericles to a per-
found in his attitude to written laws (Andr. 176, Heracl. 963): son (2. 35. I),z but there is no indication whether he thought of it
people express a dislike for particular laws,3and for the lawgivers as a written or unwritten enactment, or simply as a practice,
who enact them (Cyclops 338); and elsewhere (frg. 597) the introduced by an individual, and then sanctioned by custom.
value of a good character is said to be superior to that oflaw.4 Similarly, we do not know whether the Corcyrean law prohibit-
A similar influence of written legislation is seen in the works ing the cutting of vine poles from the precinct of Zeus and
of Aristophanes. He explicitly refers to the Megarian decree as Alcinous (3. 70. 5-6) was written or not, and we are also ignorant
vO/-L0V, YEypa/-L/-LEvov, (Ach. 532), and the 'old law' which the about the law which laid down the rules of succession to the
birds have EV Tat, TWV TrEAapywv KVp{JWLV (Av. 1353-4) refers of priesthood of Hera of Argos (4. 133. 3), the Olympic v0/-LO, which
course to the tablets on which Solonian laws were inscribed. imposed fines on anyone attacking Elis at the time of the Olympic
Elsewhere he mentions the Solonian laws about inheritance (Av. truce (5. 49. I), or the Syracusan law which barred young men
1650, 1655-6) and about the payment of debts on the first of the from holding office (6. 38. 5). In the case of several Spartan
month (Nub. 1183-7), and we have the written evidence of an VO/-LOL it is again Plutarch's statement (Lycurgus 13. I) that all
inscription (IG 12. 77) for the decree on public maintenance in Spartan laws were unwritten that leads us to believe that the
I The lawgivers in this instance are the gods, but the use of ypa..pavra, suggests laws mentioned by Thucydides did not appear in writing; but
that we are dealing with imagery borrowed from human political praclice.
2 Ion 1250-6, where the Pythian .pfj,po, condemning Creusa is described as Thucydides himself is silent on that point.3
a vO/-,o, (for the contrast here between IJE/-", and vO/-,os, see Laroche 179). See also In addition to these passages there are a number of occurrences
Herae!. 141, where the children of Heracles were by the vO/-,o, of Argos €.pTJ,pw/-,€VO' of vO/-Lo, in a general political context which suggest that written
to die.
3 Frg. 402, where the social vO/-,os of marrying one wife only is attacked and
as well as unwritten regulations and practices are referred to.
treated as if it were an enacted political law. First and foremost here are the VO/-LOL for which Pericles praises
4 Mention should be made here of the difficult frg. 172: our' ElK,)S apXHv our€
J Ece!. 944, 1022, 1041, 1049, 1056, 1077; cf. 759, 762.
Xp~v EtVQc. VOJ-LOV I Tupavvov ([val: fl-wpla Of Kat OtAnI' I O~ TWV OJ-LOLWV {:3ovAETUt KpUTfLV
2 According to the doubtful testimony of Anaximenes of Lampsacus, frg. 24, the
/-,ovos. Not much sense can be made of the first two lines as they stand: €(va, vO/-,ov
person was Solon; but see Gomme ad loc. W. Kierdorf, Erlebnis und Darstellung
rvpawov €(va, is simply not Greek. The corruption is no doubt to be looked for in
der Perserkriege 84-95, dates it after the Persian Wars.
€(va, vO/-,ov and a correction, such as Bothe's or Bedham's, to read av€V vO/-,wv or
3 4.38. 1 (law defining order of succession to the command of the Spartan army) ;
av€V vO/-,ov would grcatly improve the sense. An alternative suggestion would be
5. 63·4 (law designed to prevent king Agis from leading an army without the
that vO/-,ov is a corruption of /-,OVOV and that the second dva' is a corruption of
supervision of ten advisers); 5. 66. 2-3 (Spartan vO/-,os that kings give orders in
avopa, so that the first two lines mean: 'it is not proper and should not be that one
battle to the officers immediately below them in rank, these to the officers below
man alone is tyrant.'
them, etc.).
50 BEEMOE AND NOMOE

Athens in the Funeral Oration: they are the laws written and B.C., which we had occasion to mention earlier, is called a vOfL0S' in
unwritten which the Athenians fear (2. 37. 3), the vOflm to which the preamble which authorizes its publication, although it refers
all citizens have equal recourse in settling their private differences to itself as a 8wfl-oS'/ and the task ofre-publication was entrusted
(2. 37. 1), and from which they derive their courage less than to a commission named uvayparPELS' TWV VOfLWV (ll. 5-6), leaving no
from their native character (2. 39. 4).1 Judicial vOflm in a general doubt that written legislation is involved. It is not quite as clear
sense are also referred to when the Athenians claim at Sparta whether there is a reference to an earlier written act in a coinage
that they use the same laws for themselves and for their allies in law of the spring of 422 B.C., which seems to identify the earlier
commercial suits (1. 77. 1), when Cleon upholds the superiority of law by the name of its proposer.2 In a decree of 418/17 B.C. con-
bad but unchangeable laws over such as are good and invalid (3. cerning funds for the sanctuary ofCodrus, Neleus, and Basile it is
37. 3), or when Nicias gives the contrary advice, namely, that to likely that the V0fl-0S' on the basis of which the funds are allocated
break the laws by a vote is less bad than to let the city take bad to the Treasurers of the Other Gods and the vOfL0S' concerning the
counsel (6. 14). sacred precincts were written.3 Finally, in a decree of 404/3 B.C.,
If so far Thucydides' use of vOfL0S' resembles that of Herodotus, probably an act of enfranchisement, the phrase VOfLOtS' DE TOLS'
he rather resembles Euripides in some instances in which VOfL0S' aUToLS' 7TEPL aUT(vv TUS' uPxuS' xp[7ja8at, 0[S' KaL 7TEPL TWV aAAwv
is envisaged as capable of inhibiting or restraining human action. n81]vaLwv], speaking as it does of vOfL0S' to be applied by the
Neither fear of the gods nor law of men, he tells us (2. 53·4), magistrates, almost certainly refers to written statutes.4
prevented people from indulging in excesses during the Plague, The meaning of v0fl-0S' as the positive law is also found in what
and in his answer to Cleon, Diodotus states that no vOfL0S' can fragments oflate fifth-century philosophy have come down to us.
prevent men from making mistakes (3. 45. 3, 7), and he warns the In his Palamedes Gorgias called written VOfLOt 'the guardians of
Athenians that the best protection against revolts lies not in the the juSt',5 and in his Funeral Oration (frg. 6) he balances correct-
severity oflaws but in the effectivenessof precautionary measures ness in thought and speech (Aoywv Op80T1]Ta) against the fine
(3. 46. 4)·In the Diodotus passages in particular we feel the points of what must be in this context the written law (VOfLOV
atmosphere of a time approaching in which the positive law not UKpt{3ELaS') ; and Pericles and Hippias are represented as having
only influences all thought about vOfL0S', but in which also the defined V0fl-0S' in the sense of written statutes.6 It is less certain
value of vOfL0S' begins to decline in the face of more powerful forces. whether Antiphon had the written laws in mind, when giving
The inscriptions of the last quarter of the fifth century2 show advice (frg. 44A. I. 17-23) to hold the v0fl-0t in high regard when
how vOfL0S' is well on its way to signifying primarily the positive witnesses are present, but to follow rPvatS' when alone, or when
law.3 The re-publication of Draco's law on homicide of 409/8 Callicles states in the Gorgias (483 b) that the VOfLOt are the work of
the weak and tnere majority. Finally, in the account of the origin
I Both here and at 37. 3 specific political or judicial statutes seem to be indicated

rather than a way of life in general: at 37. 3 legislation to help the injured is
of VOfLOt given in the Sisyphus ofCritias (frg. 25·5, 9), the reference
singled out for special mention, while here 7rOVWV WAET!! and fJ-'ryfJ-ETU VOfJ-WV clearly is to positive, perhaps even to written, laws, when he attributes
refers to the Spartans, and particularly to laws such as to return either with their
shield or on it. I IC 12• I 15 (= Tod, CHI 12, ]\;0. 87) 5 and 20, and above, pp. 3 and 5.
2 I exclude from discussion here the section of the coinage decree of 449/8 B.C., 2 B. D. Meritt, Hesperia 14 (1945) 119-22, No. 11. 7: [- - - - Kalia7rEp KeAni" 110]
which comes from the Aphytis fragment. The text as printed in A TL D 14 III, VOfJ-OSh[o] K[apM ..... ]. But Meritt is diffident about the restoration and suggests
lines 14- 15, reads: ~ EVOXO[vs lva' KaTu TOV vOfJ-ov ••. ]. But this reading is so vague that the reading may be vOfJ-wfJ-[a].
that is is practically meaningless, and M. Segre, who first proposed it in Clara 3 IC 12• 94 (ef. SEC 10, No. 103) 17-18,23-5.
Rhodos 9 (1938) 160 with n. I, remarks that it is 'dato soltanto a mo' d'esempio'. 4 IC 22• 10. 6-7. For the date and purpose of this decree see D. Hereward,
3 This is also shown in the four uses of vOfJ-OS in [Xen.] Alh. Pol., which probably BSA 47 (1952) 102-17·
belongs to the early 420S. At I. 9 the term is used of legislation enacted by the 5 Frg. I I a. 30: VOfJ-OVS TE ypa7rTOVS q,vAaK(lS [TE] TOU O'Ka{ov.
cleverest people; I. 10 speaks of an imaginary vOfJ-OS requiring a freeborn person to 6 Pericles: Xen. Mem. I. 2. 40--6, esp. 42: 1Ta.VTES' yap OOTOL VOJ.LOI- ElaLv, OU'; TO
strike a slave; at 1. 18 VOfJ-O~ gives jurisdiction at Athens to the o;jfJ-OS; and at 3. 2 7r;";jlios UVVEAliov Kat OOK'fJ-aUaV EypaifiE ..• ; Hippias: ibid. 4. 4. 13 and PI. Hipp.
one of the functions of the Council is to deliberate 7rEpt vOfJ-wv IiEUEWS. Ma. 284 d-e.
52 fJEl:MOl: AND NOMOI:

the purpose of their institution to the need of putting an end to ritual celebrated at the Choes (959), and Athene bids him at
the primeval, brutish, and disorderly state of society. I the end of the play to commemorate his experience among the
Taurians by establishing the vOfLoS- for the festival of Artemis at
There are two further usages of vOfLoS- which, though they are Halai that a sword be put to a man's throat (1458). Precedents of
closely related to one or another of the uses we have discussed so social customs are involved when in the Trojan vVomen (103I)
far, are still sufficiently distinct to deserve a separate treatment. Hecuba urges Menelaus to kill Helen to set a vOfLoS- for all un-
The fact that the Greeks could think of vOfLoS- as having had faithful wives, in the Orestes (892) Talthybius is reported to have
a beginning in time2 leads easily into its use in connection with an criticized Orestes' murder of Clytaemnestra for not setting up
act by which a precedent might be or actually is established, KaAovs- vOfLOVS- to regulate children's behaviour toward their
although I can find no passage in which vOfLoS- occurs in this sense parents, and Danaus is said (frg. 228. 8) to have established the
before the fifth century. Twice in Sophocles VOfLoS- denotes the vOfLoS- of changing the name of the Pelasgians to 'Danaans'.
precedent by which customary practices may be initiated. In the
Electra Clytaemnestra is warned by her daughter that her killing A second sense of vOfLoS- derived from the fact that it may have
of Agamemnon in retaliation for Iphigeneia's death may have a beginning in time is that of a rule set up or a procedure to be
established a vOfLoS- of revenge, which could easily back-fire followed under certain closely-defined conditions, as, for example,
against her,3 and in the Oedipus at Colonus (907-8) Theseus the rules to be followed in playing a game. This usage is first
I

threatens to apply to Creon the rules for which he has himself found in Aeschylus' Agamemnon, where Clytaemnestra describes
set the precedent, when he tried to seize Oedipus by violence. the course she set up for the beacon signal as VOfLOt AafL7Tao1)-
Herodotus calls vOfLoS- a custom begun by the Carian women who ,popwv (312).2 After that, it occurs in Sophocles to describe the
had been forced to marry Athenians not to eat with their 'rule' Antigone followed in honouring her brother above hus-
husbands and not to call them by their names (1. 146. 3), and a band, child, or parent (Ant. 908), and in Electra's statement to
custom of the Aeginetans and Argives, established after some Chrysothemis that she does not want to live by VOfLOt which
difficulties with Athens, that women should wear brooch-pins demand that a just action be avoided if it brings harm to oneself
one-and-a-half times the normal size and that local rather than (El. 1043). Herodotus describes as VOfLOt the terms agreed upon
Attic ware be used for certain temple rites (5. 88. 2). Similarly, by the twelve kings who ruled Egypt after the priest of Hephaes-
Thucydides reports that the Corinthians, in their speech against tus (2. 147. 3-4) and makes Hermotimus praise the gods for
the Corcyreans before the Athenian Assembly, warned the having applied a just vOfLOS- in delivering into his hands the man
Athenians not to set the precedent (VOfLoS-) of admitting as allies who made him a eunuch (8. 106. 3). In Euripides, Phaedra's
those who revolt from others, since that might back-fire against nurse urges her mistress to follow the rule that love must be
them (I. 40. 4, 6), and in the Melian Dialogue the Athenians dis- accepted (Hipp. 461), Theseus banishes his son on the basis of the
claim any responsibility for having set the precedent that gods vOfLoS- proposed by Hippolytus himself that fathers ought to
and men rule wherever they are the stronger (5. 105. 2). In punish sons who violate their wives (Hipp. 1046),3 and Orestes
Euripides vOfLoS- refers twice in the Iphigeneia among the Taurians to describes his and Electra's relationship to Aegisthus as an enmity
religious practices initiated by Orestes: from his trial dates the 'which knows not the rules of a truce'.4
I The text, as preserved in Sextus Empiricus 9. 54, contains VO/-,Ol, also at line
40: T~V avo/-"av TE Tof, VO/-,OlS KaT€a~1]aEv. But since the point of the passage is that I e.g. Ar. Eccl. 987-8: KaTa TOV EV 7TETTOf, vO/-,ov, and also the difficult fragment
a clever man (7TUKVOS ns Ka, aorpos yvw/-'1]v aV1)p) invented fear of the gods in order of Cratinus (116), cited by Athenaeus 15. 667 f, where the VO/-,Ol of KOTTa~os
to prevent transgression of the VO/-,Ol, the reading VO/-,OlS is hard to maintain, and it seem to be mentioned.
is preferable to accept Schmidt's emendation rpO~Ol, or, less so, Diels's ~poTofs. 2 Fraenkel translates: 'the rules I arranged for my torch-bearers'.
2 This is particularly striking in the earliest extant occurrence of the term in 3 Actually, Hippolytus had suggested (1043-4) that fathers kill such sons, but

Hes. Op. 276, where Zeus has ordered separate ways of life for beasts and men. Theseus is less extreme in his punishment at this point.
3 580-1: opa nOEfaa TOVOETOV vO/-,ov {3POTO"iSI/-'~ 7T~/-,a aauTfj Kat /-,ETayvolUv T'01]" 4 El. 905-6: aa7TovOowl yap I VO/-,OWlV .xOpav TipOE aUI-'~E~A'7Ka/-,EV.
\Vc have now completed our investigation of the various pas-
sages in which vOf1-0S occurs from the beginnings of written Greek
to the end of the fifth century B.C. It remains to sum up what we
have found and to draw some general conclusions. We have
isolated altogether thirteen senses in which vOf1-0S is used in
Greek, and although the nature of a study of this kind makes it
impossible to be dogmatic either about the number of categories are now in a position to compare vOf-ws and BWf1-os with

W
E
established or about the assignment of particular passages to par- one another. The basic idea of BWf1-oS is, as we saw, that
ticular categories, it has been demonstrated that vOf1-0S had a con- of something imposed by an external agency, conceived
siderable range and variety of connotations before the end of the as standing apart and on a higher plane than the ordinary, upon
fifth century. And yet the fact remains that the one word vOf1-0S those for whom it constitutes an obligation. The sense of obliga-
sufficed for the Greeks to express all the connotations which we tion is also inherent in vOf1-os, but it is motivated less by the
have attributed to it, and this, in turn, indicates that there authority of the agent who imposed it than by the fact that it is
exists one underlying basic idea of vOf1-os, of which each meaning regarded and accepted as valid by those who live under it. And
and each occurrence constitutes, as it were, a manifestation. What when we apply these basic concepts to the connotation of
that basic concept was has been suggested at the beginning of 'statute', which both BWf1-os and vOf1-os assumed at different
this section. NOf1-os, in all its senses, signifies an 'order' and im- periods in Athenian history, we see that the two terms approach
plies that this order is, or ought to be, generally regarded as valid the notion of a statute from opposite directions. eWf1-os envisages
and binding by the members of the group in which it prevails. it as being imposed upon a people by a lawgiver legislating for it,
This usually means that the members of a given group accept while vOf1-os looks upon a statute as the expression of what the
vOf1-0S without question, and general if not universal acceptance people as a whole regard as a valid and binding norm.
is especially in evidence in the most general senses of the term, This radical difference between the two terms suggests that
when it refers to a way of life, to the normal order of things, to the change from BWf1-oS to vOf1-0S came about at a time when the
normal procedures, and to normal behaviour, or when it de- Athenians were disenchanted with living under laws imposed
scribes the authority on the basis of which or by which norms are upon them from above, and decided instead to consider as laws
issued, or the condition of law-and-order, in which the vOf1-0t are only norms which they had themselves ratified and acknowledged
obeyed. Acceptance is also implied in the more specific senses, to be valid and binding. The most probable time at which this
when it designates the mores of a people and its various beliefs happened would seem to be the establishment of the democracy
and practices in society, religion, and politics. Even when the by Cleisthenes in the wake of the liberation from the Peisistratid
later fifth century begins to disparage, devaluate, and reject tyranny. Moreover, the fact that we have no evidence in Athens
customary practices, conventional beliefs, religious beliefs and of a gradual transition from BWf1-os to vOf1-0S, of a period, that is,
practices, and the validity of statutes, it does so against the back- in which BWf1-oS and vOf1-os coexisted at Athens as interchangeable
ground of general acceptance by society, which these vOf1-0t enjoy terms for 'statute', points to an abrupt change, which is likely to
and against which the enlightened individual protests. have been the result of a deliberate act.
Unfortunately, none of our sources for the history of Athens
reports such a deliberate act, and there is equal silence about the
reasons for the change from BWf1-os to vOf1-os. Still, there are a
number of indications which will enable us to determine with
some degree of plausibility under what circumstances and at
what point in Athenian history the change took effect. Once
56 eEl:MOl: AND NOMOl:

the date is established, it may be possible for us to discover


whether the change was the result of a deliberate act, and also
whether in effecting it the Athenians followed or were influenced
by similar changes that may have taken place elsewhere in the
Greek world. It is to these problems that we shall address our-
selves in the rest of the book.

Tis safe to infer from the law which we quoted at the begin-

I ning of the Introduction that after 403/2 B.C. any valid statute
was written and, conversely, that any reference to vOfLoS in
a political or judicial sense is a reference to a written law (Andoc.
I. 87). In other words, the definition of the political and judicial

VOfLO> included in the fourth century the notion that it is em-


bodied in a written document. To what extent is this definition
also true of the fifth century? The question has considerable
importance for us in our search for the date when vOfLoS first
came to assume the meaning of 'statute' in Athens. Since the
BWfLoL of Draco and Solon were written, we are obviously inter-
ested in finding out at what time written documents analogous
to theirs were first called VOfLOt. For we can have absolute cer-
tainty that vOfLo> had taken the place of BWfLoS only when written
political enactments bear the new name.
But here we encounter a difficulty. The earliest explicit refer-
ence to written VOfLOt in Athens is no earlier than 425 B.C., when
Aristophanes had Dicaeopolis speak of Pericles' Megarian Decree
as vOfLov> WU7TEP UKoAtu JlEJlpufLfLEVOV> (Aeh. 532), and when, a few
years later, Euripides' Hecuba complains of the restraints im-
posed upon free action by vOfLWV JlpU4)uL (Ree. 866).1 These pas-
sages suggest in the unobtrusive way of their allusion that by 425
B.C. written statutes were no novelty for the Athenians, but that
they had long been part of their daily life. But this date is too late
to be meaningful.
58 NOMOI: BECOMES 'STATUTE'

We can push the evidence for written statutes back almost two OEL TO: aE rPn5ynv KaTd vop.,ov<; TOV<; OlKOBEV,
w<; aUK EXovaL KVpO<; ouoev ap.,rPL aov.!
decades further. When Pericles in his Funeral Oration, delivered
in 43 I B.C., mentions fear manifested in obedience to the VOfLOL , J ,J.,
, Id "
That expressions such as EyyvTuTa yEVOV<;, 'f'EVYHV, an EXovm
as one of the principal factors which keep the Athenians from KfJpo<; are borrowed from the language of the law has been re-
transgressing the laws, the distinction he draws between 'laws marked by many commentators on this passage,2and the tenor of
enacted for the benefit of the injured' and those laws 'which, the passage leaves no doubt that the king. is ~ryin? to make th~
though unwritten, bring generally recognized shame' on the women think of the legal aspects of their SituatIOn. Pelasgus
offender shows that he thought oflaws as normally being written, warning is clearly based on the fact, known from Athe~ian law ~f
else there would be little point in the modifier auoL uypa¢oL the fourth century, that a father had 'absolute authonty.over hiS
ovn<; (2. 37. 3)" The same kind of argument applies also to daughters, whom he could give in marriage or leave by will to the
Antigone's invocation of the uypa7TTa 8(JiJv VOfLLfLU (Soph. Ant. man whom he chose for them'.3 Although the text of no law con-
454-5) some ten years earlier. Her appeal would have made no taining this stipulation has come down to us: texts of similar
impression on the Athenian audience in 442 B.C., if they did not laws have survived (e.g. [Dem.] 46. 18) and It would be very
automatically associate vOfLo<; with written statutes without stop- surprising indeed if such a clause had not been part of Solon's
ping to think that historically Creon's VOfLOL2 were proclaimed in laws on inheritance (Arist. Ath. Pol. 9. 2, 35. 2; Pluto Solon 20. 2).
an age that had no written statutes. We may, therefore, conclude that the reference is to a vOfLoS
Accordingly, we can be absolutely certain that by 442 B.C. the which existed in writing when the Supplices was first performed
Athenians thought of VOfLOL as written. Can we go beyond that? in the archonship of Archedemides in 464/3 B.C.,4 and ~ince no
There is a method by which we can determine whether a given earlier use of vOfLoS in a political or judicial sense has surVived,.we
political vOfLO<; was thought of as written, and although this may take this as the terminus ante quem vOfLo<; assumed the techmcal
method cannot lead to absolute certainty, it can give us results connotation of 'statute'.
which are so probable as to be virtually certain. If we can find We stated earlier that the last attested use of 8wfLo<; is to be
vOfLoS in a context in which provisions are mentioned which we found in the prescript of the old Dracon~an statute ~g.ainst
know from other sources to have been the content of written VOfLOL tyranny re-enacted at the time of the expulsion of the Pelslst~a-
at a later period, it is safe to assume that the term refers to a tids which describes Draco's law as 8EUfLw Kd miTpw (Anst.
written statute, especially if the language of the passage is legal Ath: Pol. 16. 10).5 This means that 511/10 B.C. constitutes the
in character. Now, by a lucky coincidence, the earliest passage terminus post quem for the adoption of vOfLo<; in the sen~eof 'statute'.
in which this is the case is at the same time the earliest passage of Accordingly, vOfLoS must have become the techmcal term for
all in which vOfLo<; is attested in a political sense. In Aeschylus' 'statute' at some point between 511/10 and 464/3 B.C. Our
Supplices (387-9 I), Pelasgus warns the Danaids:
Et TOL KpaTovUL 7TaLo" AlYV7TTOV aEBEV
I 'If the sons of Aegyptus get the power,over you by <appe.aling to) t?e law 0;
the state, saying that they are your nearest km, who would be wlllmg to resIst them.
vop.,cp 7ToAEW<;, rPaaKovTE<; lyyvTaTa yEVOV<; Surely in accordance with the laws of your native land you must plead m your
dVaL, T:<; av TO Lao' aVTLWBijvaL BEAoL; defence that they have no authority over you.' .. . .
2 See T. G. Tucker, The Supplices of Aeschylus 85~6; ]. Vurthelm, Alschyl.os
I I do not share the confidence of]. T. Kakridis, Der thukydideische Bpitaphios Sclzut41ehende 186; Rose, CSP A I. 42. The expression EyyuTaTw yEVOUS occurs m
(= Zetemata 26) 5-6, that the free composition of the Funeral Oration after 404 a legal context at least as early as about 435 B,C" IG 12. 77·6; f?r the fourth cen-
B.C. 'gehort ... zu den sichersten Ergebnissen der neueren Thukydidesanalyse'. See tury see especially the numerous passages m [Dem.] 43 and 44, cIted by S. Preuss,
ibid. 6 n. I, for a good bibliography to 1961 on this thorny problem. There is Index Demosthenicus s.vv. EyyUTUTU and EyyuTaTw.
a lot to be said for F. E. Adcock's view, Thucydides and his History 36-7, that the 3 G. H. Macurdy, CP 39 (1944) 96-7, citing Dem. 27·5, 36. 8, and Isaeus 10. 13·

Funeral Oration 'was written in 431 B.C., while the voice of Pericles still sounded See also]. H. Lipsius, ARR 482-3 with nn. 42 and 43· '
in the historian's ears'. • POxy, No. 2256, frg. 3, with Lesky, op. cit. 58-9'
2 Cf. Ant. 382, 449, 481, 847, 5 Cf. Ostwald, TAPA 86 (1955) 106-9·
THE PROBLEM DEFINED

discussionofthe political andjudicial VOfLOt has shown that Pelasgus' in finding such connotations in passages written before .464/3
indifference to the question whether the law to which he wants B.C., we may take that as an indication that vOfLoS, too, was IIIuse
the Danaids to appeal is written or not reflects a general Greek as the term for 'statute' at that time.
indifference to this same problem. I From at least the fourth The compounds attested before 464/3 B.C: a~e eUvofL{a, ova-
century B.C. on, the Greeks were aware of the importance of VOfL{a, dvofL{a, laovofL{a, and their cognate adjectIval and verbal
written legislation and tried to discover when it began,2 and forms and to their examination we shall now turn.1 But before
Aristotle (Atlz. Pol. 41. 2) notes explicitly that Draco was the we ca~ proceed to that task, we must reiterate what was ~tated at
first to issue written laws in Athens. But in the fifth century they the beginning of Part 1. Analyses ~ased upon etymologIcal con-
do not seem to have been inordinately interested whether or not siderations have no more cogency III the case of the -VOfLOS com-
a given vOfLoS was written. The fact that a political vOfLoS was pounds than they do in the case of vOfLoS. I,know ?f ~o ~tten;pt to
valid and binding was all that mattered to them; they were less derive the -VOfLOS suffixes from the verb VEfLW = dIstnbute that
concerned whether it was embodied in a written document. does not have to strain the meaning of either the root ver~ or
Herodotus' language is no different when he speaks of the written the compound,z while those who regard the suffixesas formatIOns
VOfLOt of Solon from the way in which he speaks of the (presum- from the noun VOfLOS3 rarely, if ever, face the much more releva~t
ably unwritten) VOfLOt of Sparta, or of a (presumably written) question in which of the many connotations of vOfLoS each suffix~s
law of the Corinthians;3 and Thucydides treats the (presumably to be taken.4 In other words, we again have to follow.the semantIc
unwritten) VOfLOt of Sparta the same as a (presumably written) method and base our conclusions on a close analysIs of the con-
VOfLo, in Corcyra.4 texts in which each of them is found.
This circumstance suggests that any political or judicial VOfLOS
of which we hear was potentially written, or, differently ex- I We shall also consider KUKovoflo" which, though not attested b.efore 463 B.C.;.
enters into contexts in which €IJVofliu is also found. No account wIll be taken °d
pressed, that every valid political or judicial vOfLo, had the same dlvOflO, and aVOIW, in a musical sense-e.g. €;;VOflO,: Aleman, frg. 10. 10, a~
authority that a statute has in modern societies. Therefore, any Pind. Pyth. 5. 67 (Andrewes, Eun., esp. 91 n. 6) ; UVOflO" Aesc~. Ag. 151 (L'
trace that we can find of the use of VOfLoS in a political sense before Llo.d-]ones CQ47 (= N.S. 3) (1953) 96, accepted by]. D. DennIston and D..
Pa;e, Aesch;lus: Agamemnon 82) and 1142 (E. Fraenkel, Aeschylus: Agamemnon 3·
464/3 B.C. may be taken as an indication that vOfLo, had assumed
519). But see also p. 86 below. 8 d'
the meaning of 'statute' by that time. Now we saw that VOfLO, 2 Stier NB 23--6 with 235 n. 26, and]. L. Myres, CR 61 (1947) 0-2, ~nve
itself is not attested in the sense of 'statute' before Aeschylus' both €VV;fliu and:>iaovofliu from V€flw. H. J. Erasmus, 'Eunomi.a', Acta Classlca 3
(196o) ..53-64 esp. 54, accepts this derivation for €VVOfliu, and HIrzel, TDV 242-4,
Supplices. But there does exist a number of nouns, adjectives, and ' . r' '.
followed bv BS I. 418, accepts It ,or LGOVOflLU, so as
1 0 Laroche 186-7. The expres-
verbs ending in a -VOfLO, suffix, which are at least as old as the sion taov (~r tau) V€flnv (e.g. Hdt. 6. I I. 3; Soph. aT 579; Pl. Pr~t. 337 a, Rep. 8.
04Jssey. Since these obviously reflect one or the other of the mean- 8 C' Arist. EN 5. 3, 113I '23) contributes little to an understandmg. . , ,
553 a~Ofliu is universally derived from vOfloS, even by those who denve €VVOfl'U
ings of vOfLo, in Part I, an examination of those compounds which TD V 242-3 n. 4 ad fin. ; Ehrenberg, Ison., esp. 293, and
firom tlle ver b , see H,'rzel
. , , 1" f / 7
are attested before 464/3 B.C. will enable uSto seenot only whether Vlastos, Ison., esp. 348-9, who also derives €VVOflLU and ~aovofl;u ~om VOIJ.O" 34.-
" 1] SE esp 82 n I and for LGOVOflLU }< raenkel, op. Clt.
any of them embody the 'statute' connotations of vOfLoS from their 50 For EVVOJ.LLa see a so aeger, , . ., / d ' , .
68~-2. For discussions which regard the evidence for €VVOfl'U an LGOV~flLU as I~-
first occurrence down to the end of the fifth century, but also, if
they do not, whether we can detect in any of them a change in
k
conclusive, see Ehrenberg, Ison. 293; Heinimann, N~1~4 L~r~enk Cie~th. I-I ,
esp.5n.I3;LarocheI63,200-I,and255;andE.\yI, ~rIntIaa I.
4 Only Ehrenberg, Eun. 75, seems to have recognIzed thiS problem.
meaning which suggests that they were influenced by the adop-
tion of vOfLoS as the technical term for 'statute'. And if we succeed
I See pp. 43-52 abOve.
, See Arist. Pol. 2. 12,1274'22-31, and Ephorus, FGH 70. F 139 (= Strabo
6. I. 8).
3 I. 29. 1-2,5.42.2,6.52.3; 5. 75. 2; and 6. 89. Cf. pp. 46-7 above.
4 4. 38. 1,5· 63·4 and 66. 2-3; 3. 70. 5-6. Cf. p. 49 above.
EYNOMIA, AYENOMIA, AND ANOMIA 63

when it describes personal conduct and as a 'condition' when it


refers to the state of a society. I

The only passage in Greek literature before the beginning of


the fifth century in which Evvop.,{a describes a quality is also the
earliest. In the 04Yssry (17. 487) Antinous is warned that the gods
F!VVOj1-£a is the earliest of these concepts to be found in Greek visit cities in the guise of strangers, av()pw7TwV u{3ptV TE Kd EVVOp.,{y)V
l~terature.1 Only the noun form is attested before the end of the EepOpWVTEC;. This warning, given in the context of Odysseus' rude
sIxth century B.C.;2 the adjective dJvop.,oc; is not found before reception by the suitors, the antithetical pairing of EVvop.,{a with
Aesch.ylus.and Pindar,3 and the verb EVvop.,Eop.,at occurs for the u{3ptC;, and the genitive av()pw7TwV all indicate that a contrast
first tIme In Herodotus (1. 97. 3). There seems to be general between proper and improper personal conduct is intended,2 and
~greement t~at before t?e end of the sixth century dwop.,{a has that Evvop.,{a, accordingly, describes a personal quality. The other
lIttle or nothIng to do wIth vap.,oc; = 'statute', 4 but what has not occurrences of Evvop.,{a before 463 B.C. describe a condition.
been clearly recognized is that down to the last third of the fifth With Hesiod it begins to assume a social significance which
century Etwop.,{a and its cognates bear only two senses neither of never quite leaves it for the rest of its history. Hesiod is also the
~hich is immediately related to vap.,oc; = 'statute'. describes it first to make Evvop.,{y) into a personal cosmic force and to give her
eIther a quality of personal behaviour, in which sense it reflects a place in the divine genealogy. She is the daughter of Zeus,
~he.v~p.,oc; whic~ connotes the normal and proper conduct of an begotten with Themis, the primeval goddess of order, after he had
IndIVld.u~I,5or ~tre~ersto the condition of a well-ordered society, consolidated his power over the universe, and her sisters are the
a condItIOn whIch Implies not only the prevalence of good laws H6rai, the forces of order in nature, Dike (Justice) and Eirene
~nd. good governronentwit~in the state, but also the good func- (Peace), the forces of order in human society, and the three
tIOmng.~f th~ socIa.1orgamsm as a whole. It is, in other words, Moirai (Fates), the forces that represent the rhythm of the life of
~ Co~dItIOnIn whIch vap.,oc; means 'law-and-order'.6 The dis- the individual (Theog. 901-6).3 Andrewes aptly calls Eunomie
tInC~I~~between these two senses does not of course preclude the here 'one of the guardians of the social order, keeping the city
possIbIlIty that they may affect one another: there are several from violence and lawlessness';4 but it is not merely in the city
examples, especially of the adjective dJvop.,oc;, where the condition that she maintains order. Her pedigree makes her part of a larger
of law-an?-ord.er is pred.ic~ted as a quality of a city. Still, this order which transcends the city, a universal order established by
does not ImpaIr the valIdIty of the distinction. Only with the Zeus. Hesiod is unique in making Eunomie into a cosmic power.
pseudo-Xenophontic Constitution of Athens does the meaning of I Laroche 200-1 draws a similar distinction between -V0fl-0' compounds that
have a social and those which have a personal signification. But he goes astray
vap.,oc; = 'statute' seem to afTect the compound Etwop.,{a and its
when he confines the former to derivatives from adverbs+vEfl-w and the latter to
cognates. I shall in the following speak of dwop.,{a as a 'quality' derivatives from prepositions+v0fl-0"
2 So Andrewes, Eun. 89-90. W. Nestle, Hermes 77 (1942) 134, V. Ehrenberg,
I The most important full-length discussions of Evv0fl-{a are: ,"Vaser in RE 6 Eun. 76, and G. Vlastos, Ison. 350, speak of the v0fl-0' of hospitality in this connec-
(1909) 1129-31; Andrewes, Eun. 89-102; Ehrenberg, Eun. 70-93' Myres loc tion, but the meaning is surely wider and less specific than that. On the other
CIt.; and Erasmus, loco cit. ' ,.
hand, to accept the view of Myres, op. cit. 81, approved by Erasmus, op. cit. 54,
2 1~hc onl.y exception is Eiiv0fl-0' in Aleman, frg. 10. [0 cited above where the that EVv0fl-lTJ refers here to the state of a society in which each man is given his due,
sense IS rnuSlcal, "
we should have to assume that ii/3p', describes the state of a society in which each
,3 Aesch. frg. 198, from the Prometheus Unbound' Pind. Oi. I. 37 Isth 5 22 man is denied his due; but there is no indication that ii/3p" ever designates the
}'vem. 9. 29. " .. ,
state of a society.
4 ~.g. Jaeger, SE 82, n. I; Andrcwcs, Eun. 8<)-90; Ehrenberg, Eun. 74-5; and 3 But note the inconsistency, typical of Hesiod, with Theog. 217-19, where the
!I!yr(~, loco Clt., ,!he atte~pt ~f Erasmus, op. cit. 57, to show that from Solon on Moirai appear among the children of Night.
Evvofl-L~lmc,a~tS~lglhtdIstributIOn by law' fails to convince, since v0fl-0' did not vet 4 Andrewes, Eun. 89. But there is no support in this passage for his further
mean aw lor "-0 OD. .
comment that Evv0fl-la is here 'the social result of the conduct of the individual
5 See pp. 24-26 above.
citizens who make up the community'.
64 NOMOE BECOMES 'STATUTE' EYNOMIA, ,1YENOMIA, AND ANOMIA 65

When later poets follow Hesiod in personifYing her and in giving negative effects produced by its opposite, LlValJop.,Ly), which 'offers
her a genealogy, the H6rai and the Moirai do not appear as her most evils to the city', whereas 'EVlJOp.,Ly) renders all things well-
sisters, with the result that her sphere of operation is then con- ordered and harmonious'. 1 This positive statement on EVlJOp.,Ly) is
fined to the city-state. Pindar, for example, celebrates Eunomia repeated with only slight variants and with the substitution of
with her sisters Dika and Eirena, 'golden children of well- 'rational' for 'well-ordered' at the very end of the poem ;Z but the
counselling Themis', as denizens of Corinth,1 and in an anony- main bulk of the definition proceeds by showing the ways in
mous lyric poem, perhaps to be attributed to Simonides, the which EVlJOp.,Ly) counteracts LlValJop.,Ly). It often puts fetters on the
Moirai Aisa, Klotho, and Lachesis (here children of Night rather unjust, it makes smooth what is rough (that is, it eliminates fric-
than of Zeus) are implored to send to the city Eunomia together tion), puts an end to greed (K6pos), blinds insolence (v{3pts), and
with her sisters Dika and Eirena.2 A rather different genealogy of makes wither the blossoms of fatuousness (aTY)) as soon as they
Eunomia is found in a fragment of Aleman, in which Promatheia sprout; it straightens crooked judgements (otKat), mitigates the
(Forethought) is her mother, and Tycha (Good Fortune) and works of arrogance, and puts an end to the works of faction and
Peith6 (Persuasion) her sisters.3 There is no context to help us to the wrath of painful strife.3
interpret this relationship, but Ehrenberg is no doubt right when To interpret this passage we must begin by comparing it with
he relates these deities to the Spartan state,4 as implying that law- the statements of Homer and Hesiod on EVlJop.,La and OValJop.,La.
and-order, success, and the acceptance of arguments in a de- Solon follows Homer in presenting EVlJOp.,Ly) as opposed to v{3pts.4
liberative body depend on planned policy. Again, it is in the city But while Homer contrasts v{3pts alone with €UlJOp.,Ly), Solon's
that EVlJop.,La does her work, and that this work is larger than the antithesis involves not only the entire K6pos-v{3pts-aTy) chainS but
establishment of 'good laws' is obvious. Eunomia as a person also a number of other unpleasant consequences, which, though
encompasses the whole social order, which may even be treated, mentioned by Hesiod, are not brought by him into any relation
as it is in Hesiod, as part of a larger cosmic order. to EVlJOp.,Ly) or Llvavop.,tY).6 Thus, the EVlJOp.,Ly) which in Homer ap-
While €UlJop.,La loses her cosmic connotations after Hesiod, her peared as a quality shown in the proper conduct of individuals
association with the city-state is perfected by Solon so as to expresses in Solon the condition of which the blinding of v{3pts is
transform and elaborate the statements of Homer and Hesiod but one factor. For at the same time EVlJOp.,Ly) will also establish
into a programme for political action. The definition of EVlJOp.,Ly) law-and-order in the administration of justice by straightening
as the condition of the society which he hopes to create by his re-
forms is couched in such lively and precise terms at the end of his Ehrenberg, Eun. 81-6; G. Vlastos, 'Solonian Justice', CP 41 (1946) 65-83;
Solmsen, HA 112-17; A. Masaracchia, Salone 246-72; and H. J. Erasmus, op. cit.
poem 'Our City' that some modern scholars have dubbed the
56-7 .
entire poem 'Eunomie', even though there is no ancient warrant •I Frg; 3; ~ 1-2 : ,ws KaKa 1TIIEiuora 1TolI€< i)vovofLlTJ 1TapEX€<, ! EVVOfLlTJ i)' d5KoofLa Kat
for this name.S Solon defines EVlJOp.,Ly) by contrasting it with the ap'TLu 7TaVT '"a1To~~t~€~. ''"' I ", " \ ,

2 38-9: EOn i) V1T avorTJs !1Tavora Kaor avOpw1ToVS apna Ka' 1TLvvora.
Ol. 13. 6-8: EV orEf yap EvvolJia
I val€< KauLyv~ora {3aOpov 1Tolllwv auq,aMs
7£, I 3 33-8: Kat OafLa orois aOLKo,o' afLq"orLOTJO' 1TEoas'
L1lKa Kat OfL6'Tpo¢JosElp~va, TclJ.LL' civ8paut 7TAOlhov, / XPVO'€UL 7TUrOES €Vf30VAoV e€fLLTOSo 7pax€a A€LalvEt, 7TUV€L KOPOV, VfJPLV nfl-aupar,
Cf. Ol. 9. 15-16, where Opus is described as the 'portion of Themis and of her avalvn S' Q.T7]S aV8En q,uofLEva,
saviour daughter, far-famed Eunomia' (tiv eEfL'S OVYUorTJP orE 0< uwor€<pa MlloYXEv I Ev8vVEL oE O{KUS O'KoAuls tJ7TEP~<pava ..,' Epya
ILEyalloi)o~os EVvofLla). 7TpaVVEL, 7TUtlEt 8' Epya O"XoO'Tau{7JS,
2 Page, PMG, frg. I018 (b). 6-7. Cf. Ehrenberg, Eun. 72. On the question of 1Tav€< i)' apyaMTJs ep,oos xOllov.
authorship, see C. M. Bowra, CQ52 (= N.S. 8) (1958) 231-40, reprinted in GLP
404-15. 4 Frg. 3. 34; Od. 17.487.
3 Aleman, frg. 64. S Cf. frgg. 3. 8-9 and 5. 9-IO. For the traditional nature of this sequence and its
4 Ehrenberg, Eun. 77-80. variations see D. H. Abel, TAPA 74 (1943) 92-101, esp. 94-6·
s Frg. 3, esp. 30-9. The most noteworthy discussions of this poem are: Wila- 6 With Solon, frg. 3. 36, EVOVVE' OE olKas oKolI,as, cf. Hes. Op. 219-24,25°,259-64;
mowitz, AA 2. 305-8; I. M. Linforth, Solon the Athenian 194-206 ; Jaeger, SE 6g-85; the epya o,xoooraolTJS and apyaMTJs ep,i)os XOllos of 3·37-8 recall the bad kind of
Stier, NB 233-6; H. Schaefer, Staatsform und Politik 146-51; Nestle, op. cit. 130-5; Strife in Op. 11-16.
814277 F
EYNOMIA, JYl:NOMIA, AND ANOMIA 67

crooked judgements; as a social force, it will put an end to the which are chosen to emphasize the civic and social effects of
works of arrogance, and as a political force, it will quell the ovavopI'I rather than the personal characteristics which dominate
works off action and strife. Its realm is the entire life of the city- in Hesiod's list. That Solon deliberately contrived these changes
state. to establish EtJVOpI'I and ovavoflLY) as concepts of political and civic
Solon is indebted to Hesiod's treatment of both Eunomie and morality is shown by his exclusion from his list of any c.ounterp.art
Dysnomie, and it is in fact only in Hesiod and Solon that Dys- to the Seasons C"Qpat) and the Fates (Mofpat), whIch HesIOd
nomie is found in classical literature. 1 But the differences are names as sisters of Eunomie. Only her civic and political sisters,
more telling than the similarities. Hesiod does not juxtapose these Justice (LlLKY)) and Peace (Eip~vY)), a:e,. however in~irectly, r;cog-
two and establishes no genealogical relation between them,2 nized by him. Moreover, the omISSIOnof Famme (AtflOS), a
whereas Solon's contrast is the result ofjuxtaposition. For Hesiod brother of Dysnomie in Hesiod, indicates that Solon is 'less con-
both are divine persons and part of a cosmic order, which em- cerned that Zeus should favour (the city) with goods-such as
braces not only political but also personal, natural, and theologi- fertility of the fields, food in plenty, rich wool from the sheep,
cal relationships. Their places and functions are determined in legitimate offspring-than that Eunomie should secure the
a genealogical way: it is as daughters and sisters that they are healthy equilibrium of the social structure'. 1 •

related to other cosmic forces which are, in their turn, treated There is one striking similarity between the accounts ofHe~IOd
as divine persons. With Solon it is different. Although he treats and Solon which may well be intentional. Hesiod descnbes
Eunomie and Dysnomie as persons in the sense that he attributes Dysnomie as a descendant of Strife and Night, that is, as p~.:t of
actions to them,3 they seem to work without any divine impulse the old order which is eclipsed by the order of Zeus. EunomIe, on
and so naturally that they may more justly be regarded as per- the other hand, the child of Zeus and Themis, is born only aft:r
sonified abstract forces which Solon saw at work in the world the establishment of the new order and belongs, therefore, to It.
around him.4 They are 'poetic persons' which symbolize, respec- Solon retains the same chronological sequence and makes the
tively, the orderly and the disorderly state of affairs in the city. order of Eunomie follow the order ofDysnomie, but in a startling
Dysnomie is presented by Hesiod (Theog. 226-32) as a daughter of innovation he projects the displacement of one by the other into
Strife ("Epts) and as sister ofToil, Forgetfulness,Famine, Afflictions, the future, or, to be more precise, he thinks of the displacement
Fights, Battles, Murders, Manslaughters, Quarrels, Lies, Disputes, as having not yet taken place. In order to understand the reasons
Fatuousness (.thY)), and Perjurious Oath. Of these only strife and for this projection into the future we must set the final passage of
fatuousness appear under the same name, but not as persons, in the poem, to which alone we have devoted our attentIOn so far,
Solon's list of the forces to be annihilated or mitigated by EVVOflLY). into the context of the poem as a whole.
The rest have their counterpart only in such general expressions Solon opens the poem with an invocation to Zeus and Athe~e,
as 'what is rough' (TpaXEa), 'crooked judgements' (OtKat GKOAwL), who will not let Athens perish even though the corrupt and foolIsh
'works of arrogance' (trTrEp~c/>ava Epya), and 'works of faction' greed of the citizens, coupled with the unjust ~ind of its.rulers,
(Epya OtXOGTaaLy)S),which are more likely to owe their inclusion to tends to drive the city to ruin (frg. 3. 1-10). JustIce, persomfied as
other parts ofHesiod's work than to the Dysnomie passage,Sand Dike bides her time as she silently watches the citizens' actions
past 'and present, and she notes how thei.r de~ravity res:rlts in
I For Solon's debt to Hesiod in general see the excellent discussion by F. Solm- faction war and slavery (14-25), a publIc eVIlfrom whIch no
sen, HA 107-23, to which the following remarks owe much.
2 Dysnomie is described in Theog. 226-32, Eunomie in Theog. 901-6.
individual c~n hide (26--9). The language in which the descrip-
3 Dysnomie 7TapEXE£, Eunomie aJ.t<pLTt87}Ut, AHaLvEL, 7TaVEL, afLavpoi, K.T.'\. tion of the corrupt city is couched is echoed in the fin~l pas~age
4 See Linforth, op. cit. 205 and Solmsen, HA 114-15. There is no evidence for of the poem in a way that leaves no doubt tha.t Solon Iden.tlfied
the assertion ofW. Jaeger, Paideia 1, 3rd EngI. edn. (Oxford, 1946) 141, that Solon
thought of them as divine persons. with LlvavofltY) the conditions which he found m Athens pnor to
5 See above, p. 65 n. 6, with Solmsen, HA 116. I Solmsen, HA 116.
68 NOMOI: BECOMES 'STATUTE' EYNOMIA, .JY£NOMIA, AND ANOMIA 69

his reforms. Since Solon also tells us that Dike, though now
I
a transcendent and absolute ideal of universal validity to which
merely an observer, will certainly come in due course to exact the he hoped to attune his countrymen. The negative tone of his
I

penalty for this state of affairs,2 we can assume that her coming definition is alone sufficient to reject an idealistic interpretation.
will spell the victory of EVVO/LLYj, Dike's sister in Hesiod, over EVVO/LLYj is for Solon simply that condition of law-and-order in
fJVavO/LLYj. Surely, Solon is speaking of his impending reforms, by Athens in which the Ovavo/LLYj of the present will be eliminated or
means of which he hopes to aid Dike to restore to Athens that at least be suppressed, so that the unity and harmony of the city
EVVO/LLYj which will guarantee for the city permanence and the will be re-established, which under the guidance of Zeus and
continued protection of Zeus and Athene. Consequently, Evvo/L{Yj Athene safeguard its survival.z
does not describe any specific legislation which Solon intended to There is one final passage in which €vvo/LLa occurs before 464/3
enact but the state of affairs which he hoped to create by means B.C., and it confirms our contention that before that date the

of his legislation.3 -voILa' suffix in dVO/LLa does not carry the narrow meaning of
Modern scholars have remarked on the religious tone which 'statute'. In his attack on the exaggerated honours heaped upon
informs this poem and the hymnic quality of the praise of the victors of the Olympic Games, Xenophanes (frg. 2) claims
EVVO/LLYj at its end.4 But it is important to realize that Solon him- that his wisdom is worthy of greater honours than the brawn of
self regards his task as religious only in the sense that he is con- men and horses.3 Athletic prowess, he asserts, is not likely to
scious of the approval with which Zeus and Athene will welcome enhance the EVVO/LLYj of the city.4 Since Xenophanes goes on to
his work and of the service to Dike which he will perform in state that an Olympic victory does not 'fatten the store-rooms of
accomplishing it. While Hesiod regarded Eunomie as an already the city',5 it has been argued that his chief interest lay in EVVO/LLYj
existing hall-mark of the new dispensation of Zeus, Solon knows as a source of wealth and prosperity.6 But although it is true that
that it is not Zeus but he himself who will make Evvo/L{Yj a reality dvo/L{a is often associated with wealth in Greek literature,7 for
and that it is in Athens that this realization will take place: mVTa Xenophanes it is a concomitant of dVO/LLYj rather than an essential
OLoa~aL eV/LOS }4eYjVaLOVS /L€ K€,\EJ€L.5 His EVVO/LLYj is to become the attribute. He rather shares, as Bowra suggests, 'the notion of
characteristic of a specific situation in a specific place and at I This is asserted by Jaeger, SE 82, followed by Stier, NB 236, and by Schaefer,
a specific time, and it involves the amelioration of the bad condi- op. cit. 147, who even goes sO far as to include among the aims of Solon's .l,vo/,La
tions prevailing in the present. Solon's EVVO/LLYj is not meant to be 'bewuBte Verneinung der irdischen Guter, iiberhaupt Beseitigung allen Dbels
als der Wurzel der avo/,La'. Apart from the fact that avo/,La or related forms do
I Cf. aq,paQ{1JwIV (5) with tnVV'ra (39); aO'Kos voos (7) and 7T>'ovrovolv 0' aOLKolS not occur in any of the surviving fragments of Solon, an asceticism such as that
~PYlwa< 7THllo/,Evol (I I) with rotS aQ{Kow' a/,q,LTLII1Jol 7T<oa<;(33) ; V{3pIOS EK /'Eya>'1JS described by Schaefer seems alien to the spirit and substance of Solon's reforms.
d>.ym 7TO>'>'a7TallEtv (8) with V{3pLV a/,avpot (34) and apyaM1J<; ~PIOOS xo>'ov (38); A modified idealism, similar to that predicated by Jaeger, is attributed to Solon's
KOPOV (9) with 7TavH KOPOV (34); oraon' ~/,q,v>'ov 7TO>'E/,OV II' Evoovr' E7TEydpH (19) EUVO/'L1J by Ehrenberg, Eun. 84-5, although Ehrenberg recognizes that its estab-
with 7TavH_o' ~pya ,0IxoOr,aOL1JS, 7Ta~E~ 0' apya>'~1J<; <PLOOSxo>'ov (37-8). lishment was for Solon 'a goal of his personal policy, the sort of thing he had
z 16: rWI OE XPOVWI 7Tavrws ~>'II a7TOTHOO/,EV1J. promised to Athens beforehand for the time when he might be given full power'.
3 Andrewes, Eun. 90, interprets the antithesis between OVOVO/'L1J and .liVO/'L1J in Z Cf. Masaracchia, op. cit. 267-8.
this poem too narrowly as a 'contrast between lawlessness and the keeping of the 3 The dates of Xenophanes' life are now generally agreed to be c. 570 to c. 470
laws'. But more seems to be involved than abiding by a set of statutes. For the B.C., see Kirk and Raven 163-4, Guthrie, HGP I. 362-4, and the discussion by L.
same reason, I cannot agree, either, when he continues: 'But it is possible that Woodbury in Phoenix 15 (1961) 134-55. The chronological sequence of his poems
Solon had also in mind the contrast of his own laws with those of Draco.' Similarly, is hard, ifnot impossible, to determine. In the absence of more cogent evidence, the
C. Meier, 'Drei Bemerkungen zur Vor- und Fruhgeschichte des Begriffs Demo- date of 'before 520 B.c.',offered for frg. 2 by C.M. Bowra, Problems in Greek Poetry 16,
kratie' 4-18, esp. 6, is too narrow in his emphasis on legal and constitutional on the basis ofXenophanes' omission of the race in armour, introduced in 520 B.C.,
aspects of d,volda in Solon and later. In trying to establish a relationship between from his otherwise complete list of Olympic contests, seems perfectly reasonable.
Solon's notion of diVO/'L1J and his actual legislation, Wilamowitz went as far as it 4 Frg. 2. 19: TOVVEKEV av o~ p.ii>..>..ov €V €VvofLlTJL 7ToAtS' £1.1].
is possible to go when he said, AA 2. 307: 'natiirlich liegt darin der rat, fur gute 5 22: ou yap tnaLVEl Tavra /,vXOVS 7TO>'IO<;. 6 Ehrenberg, Eun. 86-7·
7 e.g. Horn. Hymns 30. 11-12; Pind. 01. 13.6-8; Timotheus, Persae (Page, PMG,
gesetze zu sorgen.' 4 e.g. Jaeger, SE 77-8 and 84, and Solmsen, HA 117.
5 30: 'My spirit bids me tell these things to the Athenians.' I owe this point to frg. 791) 237-40; and an inscription from Epidaurus of the fourth or third century
Jaeger, SE 76-7. B.C. in Page, PMG, frg. 937. 11-15·
EYNOMIA, .1Yl:NOMIA, AND ANOMIA 7'

Hesiod that just government makes a land rich and is rewarded here may be interpreted in a religious sense,' the context suggests
by the prosperity of the people', and if he criticizes the rewards rather that the chorus believes the behaviour of Ajax to have
given to athletes on the ground that they do not enrich the city, changed in a more general way.
it is because 'they have not the true sign of a just government in All the other passages in which EiJVofLta, EiJvofLoc;, and EiJVofLEL-
making the country prosperous, and are in fact a8~Ka'. If this is I a(}a~ occur in the fifth century contain modifications of the themes
correct, Xenophanes' view of EvvofLtYJ is not far removed from first struck by Hesiod and Solon. As in Hesiod, dvofLta is re-
Solon's; that is, for him, too, dvofLtYJ is the condition of a city in garded as a condition associated with 8twT), (}EfL~C;,and Elp~vT), and
which law-and-order prevails. Solon's influence is felt in that dvofLta remains closely linked to
We have now demonstrated that before the end of the sixth the state. But there is also something new: both noun and ad-
century dvofl.ia was used in two senses. As a quality it describes jective frequently characterize a city which possesses law-an~-
the behaviour of a normal and decent human being, and as a con- order. In other words, the condition becomes a characteristIc
dition it characterizes a state which is well governed and in quality. A first hint of this development can be seen in the late
which justice, peace, and order prevail. As we shall show later, sixth century in Xenophanes' expression EV EvvofLtV Elva~ (frg. 2.
avofLta is the opposite of dvofLta as a quality; that 8vavofLta is its 19), which, while describing the condition of the state, takes at
opposite as a condition has been shown in the preceding dis- the same time a first step toward making this condition a charac-
cussion. What is important for our central purpose, however, is teristic quality. This tendency is further developed by Pindar
that, although both EvvofLta and 8vavofLta may be regarded as who while following Hesiod in making Dike and Eirene sisters
describing a political condition, they are not associated with the of Eunomia, daughters of Themis, and antagonists of Hybris
enactment of statutes before the end of the sixth century; in other and Koros, deprives them of the universality which Hesiod had
words, they do not reflect what we called the 'political and attributed to them and names Corinth as their home (ot. 13·
judicial' sense of vOfL0C;= 'statute', but other wider senses of the 6-10),2 and who elsewhere describes Opus as 'the portion of
term. Themis and her saviour daughter, far-famed Eunomia' (Ot. 9·
What was the situation in the fifth century? Apart from its 15-16). No longer is EvvofLta the healthy condition as such. of
frequent occurrence in the Anonymus Iamblichi, which will be law-and-order in city-states, which itself transcends and eXIsts
discussed in connection with avofLta later on, there are only two independently of particular states. It has now become also an
other instances in which dvofLta is predicated of persons, in attribute of particular states such as Corinth and Opus. Whi~e
which it is used, that is, as it was in the 04Jssf!Y, to describe a the language of Pindar in these two poems suggests that he IS
quality of personal conduct. The earlier of these is Pindar's sincere in regarding Eunomia as a divine person, as Hesiod had
description of Tantalus' feast as a dvofLwTaToc; Epavoc; (Ot. I. done, he is also capable of suppressing the personal element
37-8), where the adjective underscores Pindar's view of Tantalus' completely when he speaks of Aegina as a EvvofL0C; 7TOA~C; (lsth.
character, stated in deliberate opposition to the traditional tale 5. 22), when he invokes a EvvofL0C; fLoLpa for the sons of Aetna
which had Tantalus carve up his son to set before his guests.2 (Nem. 9. 29-30),3 or when he calls down the blessing of EvvofLta
The second example comes from Sophocles' Ajax (713), where the I Cf. above, pp. 40-3. For religious overtones in £uvo!'-£asee also the anonymous

chorus rejoices at the dvofLta displayed by its master in the poem from Epidaurus, probably from the third or second century B.C., in Page,
sacrificeswhich he offers to the gods. Although the vOfL0C;involved PMG, frg. 937. 13, and for similar c?nnotations of avo!,-£~ see below,.p. 91.. ,
2 On this passage see the suggestive but very sp~culatlve companson of Pllldar s
I Bowra, op. cit. 30, citing Hes. Op. 236-7. £uvo!'-£awith that of Solon by E. Will, Korinthiaka 620-4·
2 Cf. Andrewes, Eun. 89. There may be a reference in deliberate opposition to 3 The wish, included in this prayer, that Zeus may keep war far away from them,

this passage in an epigram from the first century A.D., ascribed to Nicodemus of may be an echo of Hesiod's association of Eunomia ;Vi;h ~ireni'. Unlike I-~esiod,
Heracleia in Anthologia Graeca 6.316, where the feast of Thyestes is called J..,£.pava however, Pindar does not personify here. The word €Lp7JV7J IS not even mentl?ned,
O.£7TVWV ovavo/-,a. Note that ovavo!'-a is here used in the sense in which uvo/-,a would and if the !,-oLpa prayed for depends on Theog. 904, it must be noted that Pllldar
have been used in the classical period. gives her a civic rather than a cosmic context.
EYNOMIA, JYI:NOMIA, AND ANOMIA 73

upon Thebes. I A similar use of the adjective EiJvofLos is found in Pindar and Aristophanes. When Pindar prays in the First Paean
I

Pindar's older contemporary Aeschylus, who is the earliest extant (10) that Apollo may crown Thebes with the 'flowersof restraining
author to characterize with it the law-and-order existing among law-and-order' (uweppovos av()wtv ElJVop.,{as), he is, to be sure,
a non-Greek people, the Scythians.2 concerned with the condition of Thebes ; but his hope is that this
Bacchylides takes a further step away from personification. He condition should become a characteristic quality of his city.2And
too seems to depend on Hesiod's genealogy when he calls Dika in the only passage in which EVvofLla appears in Aristophanes (Av.
the 'attendant' (aKoAov()OS) of Eunomia and Themis,3 but the 1539-40) it is bracketed together with EV{jovAla and uweppouvvYJ
relation is no longer genealogical in that the three are not mem- as a quality of Zeus dispensed by Basileia.
bers of the same family. At the same time, it becomes even more In all other fifth-century passages EIJVofLia and its cognates are
evident than it did in the case of Solon that they are only 'poetic used in the way Solon used it to describe the condition of a
persons', mere symbols of concepts. For while in Solon we had to society without making the condition a characteristic. While
infer the abstract nature of Eunomie and Dysnomie from the fact Aeschylus (frg. 198) was the earliest author to apply the adjec-
that they are given no genealogy and work without any divine tive to a non-Greek people, Herodotus is the first to apply the
impulse, it becomes difficult to regard Dika as a divine person noun to foreign states in his description of the conditions pre-
when Bacchylides states that the sons of the prosperous choose her vailing in Egypt until the reign of Rhampsinitus (2. 124. I). For
as a 'fellow resident' (UVVOtKOS') and when she is described as if the KaKoTYJS of Rhampsinitus' successor Cheops, with which
'accessible to all men' (EV fLEUlp KELTat KtXELV 7Tllmv av()pw7TOtS). EVvofLla is contrasted here, consisted in closing all temples and in
Her personification has become a literary conceit which does making the Egyptians build his pyramid by their hard labour,
little more than symbolize an abstract quality; and what is true ElJVofLla must be the condition of a state in which the relations
in this poem ofDika will be equally true ofEunomia and Themis. with the gods and within society are well regulated, not neces-
The same trend reappears with a novel twist in Bacchylides' sarily only by the enactment of statutes but by the harmonious
poem in honour of Pytheas of Aegina. EvvofLla is again treated as consensus of ruler and ruled.3 In another Herodotean passage
a 'poetic person'; but her opposition to iJ{jpts, which we encoun- the verb ElJVofLEofLat is used with reference again to a non-Greek
tered in Homer, Hesiod, and Solon, is now expressed positively state, Media. Kingship was established in Media, according to
in that she is described as a 'force of restraint' (uaoeppwv) which Herodotus, when, at an assembly convoked to cope with the
'guards the cities of reverent men in peace'. 4 In other words, the spread of avofLIYJ throughout the land, the friends ofDeioces pro-
poet is less interested in the condition of EVvofLfa in itself than in posed: Ou yap o~ TP07Tl{J T<{J 7TapEOVTt XPEwfLEVOt ovvaTol EffLEV
, I , I ,/.., I t I ,,... Q \ I ,tl
the restraining effect it has. Thus he treats it as a characteristic OtKEEtV TYJV XWPYJV, 'f'EpE UTYJUWfLEV YJfLEWV aVTWV fJaatllEa' Kat OVTW
quality rather than as a condition. The connection between
ISee further, Endnote, pp. 176-7 below.
EVvofLla and uweppouvvYJ, once established, is taken up also by 2See Sandys's translation (Loeb edn., p. 519): 'with the flowers of sober love
I Pind. Paeans I. 10. There is no reason to assume for this passage either a per- of law'.
sonification of £vvop,{a or a dependence on Hesiod, despite the fact that earlier in 3 That no constitutional question is involved is rightly stressed by both Andrewes,

the poem the' Qpal fihp{yovol are treated as persons. Eun. go with n. 3, and H.J. Erasmus, 'Eunomia', Acta Classica 3 (lg60) 58-g. But
2 Frg. Ig8, from the Prometheus Unbound. It seems more natural to interpret the Andrewes's argument that £vvop.{T)here refers to personal conduct because its loss
adjective here as referring to the orderly and good social organization of the was due to the unexpected behaviour of Cheops does not hold water. For if the
Scythians than to take it with Andrewes, Eun. 8g, as referring to their personal KaK6TT)S of Cheops' conduct undermined £vvop.iT), that does not mean that <vvop.{T),
conduct. 3 Bacchylides 15. 53-6. too, refers to conduct. Erasmus wavers between interpreting <vvop.{T) here as
4 Ibid. 13. 186-g : ticI'mJ. .r' £va£{Uwv dvopwv EV £lp~vq. q,v>.aaa[£]I. The impor- (a) 'perfect distribution of rights and duties', (b) 'perfect distribution of Justice',
tance of the association of £vvop.{a and awq,poavvT), first attested here, is indicated by (c) 'good administration of the laws', and (d) 'good order by law'. The idea of
the fact that G. Grossmann, Politische Schlagworter aus der Zeit des Peloponnesischen distribution inherent in (a) and (b) rests on too strained an insistence on the
Krieges, devotes an entire chapter (pp. 10-8g) to 'Eunomia im Sinne der Sophro- etymological derivation of .vvop.ia from VEP.W (see above, p. 61), and although
syne'. But his conclusions go beyond what the available texts justify. Cf. Helen <vvop.{a involves (c) and (d), this does not imply that the 'administration' or
North, Sophrosyne 23-4. 'order' was created by means of statutes or ordinances.
EYNOMIA, .dYENOMIA, AND ANOMIA 75

YJ TE XWPYJ Euvop.YJUETat Kat aUTOt 7TpOS Epya TpE'f'OP.E 8a OUOE


" , " " \ ,,, ' ~\ U7T
~~
./, I
concerned, the constitutional change here is merely an accidental
avop.iYJS avaUTaTOt €uop.E8a. I What is of special interest in this and not an essential clement in dvop.iYJ. The chief purpose
passage is that, although avop.iYJ, which occurs in it three times, articulated by Deioces' fi-iendsis not the establishment of a king
refers, as we shall see below (pp. 89-90), to personal conduct, but the creation of conditions in which people can pursue their
the ElIVop.ia with which the verb contrasts it describes a condition. own work unmolested by the acts of criminals; their avowed end
This is indicated to some small extent by the fact that the idea is is not a constitutional change. As for the second point, we can
expressed by a middle deponent verb,2 and, as the analogy with only reiterate what we said in connection with Solon's Elwop.iYJ :
such middle forms as 0YJp.oKpaTEop.m, oiKEop.at, 7ToAtTEVop.m, etc., while the enactment of good laws is no doubt part of the process
indicates, the middle voice in verbs describing social or political of bringing about the condition oflaw-and-order, 'good statutes'
activities tends to express a general condition rather than a par- do not exhaust the content of dvop.iYJ, and, in addition, they
ticular attribute of society.3That ElIVOP.~UETat describes a condi- could not by themselves stamp out avofJ.iYJ and ensure the free
tion is shown in the present passage by the observation that the pursuit of business to the citizens.
country (xwPYJ) rather than the people inhabiting it is the subject
of the verb: it is not the quality of the land in which the friends of This brings us to a complex of Evvop.ia passages which requires
Deioces claim to be interested but the condition to be created separate treatment. In antiquity as well as in modern times
within it, and, as the context shows, ElJVop.ia is here a state of dvop.ia and its cognates have been related to the constitutional
affairs from which the characteristics of the present state of changes in Sparta, which are attributed to Lycurgus, that is, to
affairs-pillage and lawless conduct-are to be absent and in the enactment ofvop.ot in the political senseof 'statutes' or 'regula-
which each person will be able to pursue his own work free from tions'.I Although Andrewes has shown as long ago as 1938 that
the threat of disruption by the lawless behaviour of others.4 Evvop.ia does not directly refer to the Spartan or any other consti-
One final observation on this passage remains to be made. The tution,2 we shall have to examine the relevant passages once
establishment of Evvop.iYJ here involves a constitutional change, again to determine in what sense or senses ElJVop.ia is predicated
that is, it is to be achieved by instituting a kingship. Does this of Sparta in Greek literature and in what relation, if any, these
mean that the -voP.OS suffix signifies the establishment of good senses stand to the narrow political meaning of vop.OS.3
statutes either in the sense that the new constitution as such will The first passage to be considered occurs in the context of
be good or in that the king will enact 'good laws'? The answer Herodotus' narrative of the situation at Sparta at the time of
to both alternatives must be negative. As far as the first one is I Plut. Lycurgus 5. 4 paraphrases the oracle given to Lycurgus: <vv0fl-ias oE
I 97. 2-3: 'Since we are not able to live in our country with our present way
I. XPrl~oV"n Otoovat Kat. KUTaLV€LV icP'rJ TOV 8€ov ~ 1ToAv Kpa'rfaTTj TWV ciAAwv (UTaL 7TOALTEtWV.
of life, come, let us appoint a king over ourselves. In this way, the country will W. Norvin entitled his studies of the Spartan constitution, Classica et l>.fediaeualia 2
enjoy law-and-order and we shall turn to the pursuit of our own business and not (1939) 247-93 and 3 (1940) 47-118, 'Zur Geschichte der spartanischen Eunomia',
be unsettled by lawless conduct.' and defined the Spartan eunornia, ibid. 3 (1940) 70, as 'eine Gesetzgebung, die das
2 EvvoJ1,E0fl-a, is only attested as a middle deponent, except, according to LSJ, Leben der Burgerschaft regeite und sie zu einem unuberwindlichen Herrn machte'.
once in PI. Laws II. 927 b 6, <vv0fl-0vaa. Cf. the discussion of the crucial passage of Herodotus by W. den Boer, Laconian
3 The special force of this use of the middle is hard to define. The least unsatis- Studies 26-7, esp. 26 n. 2 : ' •.. this justifies our employing the exp"'ession [sc. <vv0fl-io]
factory definition is that of R. Kuhner and B. Gerth, Auifiihrliche Grammatik der as a name for the Spartan constitution or for Lycurgus' laws.'
griechischen Sprache 2. I. I 12: 'die Rolle dessen, weIch en das Stammwort bezeichnet, 2 Andrewes, Eun. 91.

spielen, sich als einen soIchen zeigen, das Streben oder die Gewohnheit haben, als 3 But we need not enter here, except incidentally, on the thorny questions of
ein soIcher zu agieren.' Cf. similarly, but less felicitously, in E. Schwyzer and A. Lycurgus' chronology, his and possible later reforms, and their relation to the
Debrunner, Griechische Grammatik 2. 232, and J. Humbert, Syntaxe grecque3 106. Second Messenian vVar. For a recent discussion of these problems see F. Kiechle,
4 For these reasons I do not agree with Andrewes, Eun. 89, that <VV0fl-EOJkO' refers Lakonien und Sparta (= Vestigia: Beitrage Zlir alten Geschichte 5) esp. IV. 4: 'Die
to conduct. If it did, XWP71 could not be its subject here. Erasmus, loc. cit., goes too inneren Verhiiltnisse Spartas im 7. Jahrhundert', and 5: 'Die Oberlieferung uber
far when he associates <vv0fl-io here with the material prosperity of the state; for die Staseis im archaischen Sparta und die Einfuhrung der Lykurgischen Ordnung.'
the fact that people will be able to work in peace does not in itself mean that the For a sober evaluation of methodology in early Spartan history see C. G. Starr,
state will grow rich. Historia 14 (1965) 257-72.
76 NOMOi: BECOMES 'STATUTE' EYNOMIA, JYl:NOMIA, AND ANOMIA 77

Croesus (I. 65--8). Herodotus begins by relating the news which KaKovofLwTaToL, found only in this passage in Herodotus, suggests,
reached Croesus of Sparta's final victory over Tegea (65. I), on the other hand, that a quality is described which lost its force
won, as we learn two chapters later, in the reign of Anaxandrides with the establishment of new conditions. This is confirmed by the
and Ariston.1 He then proceeds in his rambling way, which has explanation added to the adjective: the Spartans were KaKoL'op.W-
been the despair of those who want to exploit the passage for the TaTOL in their relations among themselves (KaTu TEaePEas mJToJs)
establishment of a chronology of early Spartan history, to narrate and, as a result, they isolated themselves from the rest of the
the developments leading up to the eventual victory over Tegea, world (Kat gE{VOLaL IlTTpoafLELKToL). This seems to mean that one of
and he begins by stating that, although the Spartans in the reign the consequences of their original KaKovofL{a was the absence of
of Leon and Hegesicles succeeded in all their other military any foreign relations, including, therefore, paradoxically enough,
enterprises, their campaign against Tegea failed (65. r). The next the absence of foreign wars.1 What is involved in their internal
step is to account for this mixture of general success and partial KaKovofL{a is more difficult to determine. We can be confident
failure. Herodotus attributes the success to the reforms of Lycur- only that Herodotus did not attribute the KaKovofL{a of the
gus, to which he devotes a short digression (65. 2-66. I). As Spartans to a complete lack of VOfLOL in the way in which Homer's
a result of these reforms, Sparta flourished. But prosperity also Cyclopes completely lacked 8EfLLS (Od. g. 106, I r2-I5). For we
contained the seeds of failure. When the Spartans realized that are told specifically that LyCurg{lS 'changed' (fLETEaTTjaE) all
they were stronger than the neighbouring Arcadians, they grew Spartan vOfLLfLa; Herodotus does not say that he 'instituted'
restive and wanted to attack them, but first sought the advice of (KaTEaTTjaE) them. This presupposes the existence of vOfLLfLa in
Delphi (66. 1-2). Relying on the oracle they received but which, Sparta before Lycurgus; only the vOfLLfLa were 'bad' (KaKu) and
according to Herodotus, was false (xPTjafL0 KLfJO~Acp 7T{avvoL), they a reform was, therefore, needed. Further insights into the nature
concentrated their attack on Tegea and suffered a severe reverse ofpre-Lycurgan KaKovofL{a can be gained by examining Herodo-
(66. 3-4). Here the digression ends, and Herodotus resumes the tus' account of Lycurgus' reforms by which ElJVOfL{Tj was brought
narrative of the Spartan victory over Tegea, won in the time of about.
Croesus (67. 1-68.6). Although Herodotus does not decide in favour of one or the
Of interest to us is the account of the Lycurgan reforms and other of the two traditional sources for Lycurgus' measures, one
the success which they produced (65. 2-66. I), because they are unnamed source attributing them to Delphi and the Spartans
presented as the establishment of EVvofL{a among a people who, at attributing them to Crete, he leaves no doubt of his conviction
some unspecified date prior to their failure at Tegea (ETL 7TPOTEPOV that the entire social and political order (KOafLos) prevailing in the
TOJTWV), had been KaKOVOfLdJTaTOL aXEoov 7TtJ,VTWV 'EAA~vwV.2 The Sparta of his own time is due to the Lycurgan reforms.2 That this
phrase with which Herodotus introduces his account: fLET<EfJaAov is Herodotus' belief is also confirmed by his description of the
OEWOE es ElJVOfL{TjV (65. 2), and the phrase with which he sums it reforms themselves. Lycurgus changed all Spartan vOfLLfLa-and
up : OVTW fLEV fLETafJaAovTES EVVOfL~8Tjaav suggest that he uses both this must include laws, customs, usages, practices, and beliefs-
the noun and the verb in the sense in which he uses them which had previously been regarded as valid and binding by the
elsewhere, namely to describe a condition.3 The adjectival people as a whole; and not only did he change the old, his re-
forms also included sanctions against transgressions of the new.3
I On this passage I am in general agreement with N. G. L. Hammond, JHS 70
(1950) 53-4· I We have here, incidentally, an additional reason for referring En rrpoTfpov
2 The <n seems to me clearly to place the period of KaKovo/"{a not only before the TOVTWV to the time before Lycurgus; for Herodotus knew about the Messenian
failure at Tegea but rather before the reforms of Lycurgus in the reign of Leobotes; Wars and treats them as a foreign entanglement, see 3. 47. 1 and 5. 49. 8.
so Hammond, lac. cit. For a different view, see Andrewes, Eun. 92-3, and Gomme, 2 I. 65. 4: TOV VVV KaTWTfWTa KOU/"OV l:rrapT'~TTlU', although verbally associated
Hey I. 128-9, who believe in a change from KaKovo/"{a to <lJVo/"{a effected c. 600 only with the non-Spartan tradition, is certainly also included in the Spartan
B.C., just before the reigns of Leon and Hegesicles, version by the TaVTa at the end of the sentence.
3 See above, pp. 73-4. 3 I. 65. 5: Kat <,pv>'agE TaVTa /"~ rrapaf3a{VELv.
EYNOMIA, JYl:NOMIA, AND ANOMIA 79

The specific military and constitutional innovations which, ac- been established and which, for that reason, does not yet know
cording to Herodotus, Lycurgus 'instituted' rather than 'changed' law-and-order. I

(EaTY)(JE) after his earlier measures (fkETU DE) are next enumerated,
In the only other fifth-century passage in which El)vo/.da, in the
including the 'sworn brotherhoods', the 'bands of thirty', the verb form, is associated with Sparta it is more closelyrelated to the
'common meals', the ephorate, and the gerousia. In other I Spartan constitution than it was in Herodotus. But even here it is
words, both the changes and the new institutions are, in the eyes the stability and permanence of the Spartan order that is empha-
of Herodotus, part of the reforms of Lycurgus, and, as he pro- sized, and there is no indication that EVvofkla was regarded as
ceeds to state specifically in the next sentence, the reforms as a a name for the Spartan constitution as such. The passage takes
whole created ElJVofkla in Sparta.2 We may conclude, then, that the form of a long parenthesis, inserted in Thucydides' sketchy
El)vofkly) in this passage denotes the condition in which Sparta account of the tyrannies in the Greek world, and its purpose is to
found herself as a result of the Lycurgan reforms. It does not refer explain-it is introduced by yap-why the Lacedaemonians
specifically to the legislation by which the reforms were enacted, played so prominent a part in eliminating them:
although that may well be included; for Herodotus says nothing ~ yap AaKESa{f-Lwv f-LETa T~V KT{ULV TWV VVV ~VOLKOVVTWV aVT~V LlWpLWV
of the manner in which Lycurgus proceeded in enacting his re- €7rt 7TAELUTOV (fjv LUf-LEV Xp6vov uTamauaua of-LWC; ~K 7TallaLTaTov Kat
forms. Accordingly, there is no relation between ElH'ofklY) here and T)vvOf-L~8T) Kat aid aTvpavvEVToc; 7)v' ETT) yap ~UTL f-LaAwTa TETpaK6uLa Kat
VOfk0C; = 'statute'. True enough, the reforms themselves did in- oA{yCiJ 7TAdw ~C; T~V T<iAEVT~V TOVSE TOV 7ToMf-Lov d</>' oD AaKESaLf-L6vLOL

volve military and constitutional innovations, but they were not Tfj aVTfj 7ToALTE{q. xpWVTaL, Kat SL' aVTO oVVaf-LEVOL Kat TO. .EV TaLC; allAaL<;

confined to them:3 EVVOfkly) also includes the condition of the 7T6AEUL Ka8{uTauav.2

Spartan social and political order as a whole (Koafk0C;), brought Thucydides is more specific than Herodotus in characterizing the
about by a change of all vOfkLfka and the perpetuation of the new period preceding the establishment of ElJVofkla as one of civil
order. It is, therefore, not a name for the Spartan constitution but strife.3 But the characteristic of the condition described here as
a description of the whole Spartan way oflife created by it.4 it is in Herodotus by the aorist of the deponent verb EiJVOfkEL-
These conclusions enable us to draw some inferences about the aeaL is not merely its exclusion of aTaaLC;;4 its positive side, as
meaning of KaKovo,uwTaToL. Obviously, it characterizes the Spar- Thucydides goes on to explain-again we find yap-involves the
tans before they had EVvofkly), that is, before the reforms of
I The adjective, again in the superlative form, occurs only once more in extant
Lycurgus. Even at that time they possessed, as we saw, vOfkLfka. Greek literature, Philo, De sacrijiciis Abelis et Caini 5, II p. 268 M. The noun
But these were 'bad' in that they were not conducive to social KaKovo/-,{a is found only once, in [Xen.] Ath. Pol. 1.8 (discussed below, pp. 82-5).
stability, to effective military organization, to good government, 2 1. 18. I: 'For although civil strife prevailed for a longer time in Lacedaemon
after its foundation by the Dorians who now inhabit it than among any other
and, probably because of that, to foreign relations. Moreover, people known, none the less, from the earliest time on, it both enjoyed an orderly
since Lycurgus' order stood for Herodotus at the beginning of the kind of government and has always been free from tyrants. For it is about four
history of civilized Sparta,S the fact that the pre-Lycurgan Spar- hundred years and a little more from the time that the Lacedaemonians have been
living under the same constitution to the end of this war; for this reason they grew
tans are described as KaKOVofkwTaTOL indicates that they exhibited powerful and also settled affairs in other states.'
the qualities of a society in which a civilized order has not yet 3 Kiechle's interpretation of this passage, op. cit. 197-8, is untenable: 'Was
I 1.65. 5: J.Lerd O€ Tn ES 7TOAEIWV ExoVTa, EVwp,oTLas Kat TpL7JKu3as Kat uvaatTw, rrpos Thukydides darlegen will, ist offensichtlich : Sparta wurde zwar auBerst lange von
T€ TOVTOLUL Taus ;r/>opovs Kat y€pov-ras €U'T7]UE AVKofJpyos. Unruhen erschilttert, doch hatten diese keine Schwachung des Staates zur Folge,
66. I : oiJ-rw /-,'V /-,E-ra~aA6v-rE, EVVo/-,~IJ'YJoav.
2 denn die seit alters bestehende Ordnung erfuhr dadurch keinen Bruch; auch
This point is neglected by den Boer, loc. cit.
3 filhrten diese Unruhen in Sparta zu keiner Tyrannis.' If Thucydides had meant to
4 I agree with the conclusion of Kiechle, op. cit. 191, 'daB I 66 mit Evvo,,~IJ'YJoav
say that the period of Evvo/-,{a lasted into the period of o-ro.o", he would more
die Herstellung besserer sozialer Verhaltnisse zum Ausdruck gebracht ist'. But on probably have used the present participle o-rao,o.{ovoa. That Evvo/-,{a put an end to
p. 204 he reads more about the economic situation in Sparta into this passage than o-ro.o" is correctly assumed by Andrewes, Eun. 94; Gomme, HCY I. I go; and
the text warrants. Hammond, loc. cit.
5 See \\!. \\!. How and J. VlTells,A Commentary on Herodotus 12• 88. 4 Erasmus, loco cit., sees only this aspect of EVvo/-,{a.
80 NoMoE BECOMES 'STATUTE' EYNoMIA, JYENoMIA, AND ANOMIA 81

durability of the Spartan constitution over a period of more than An indirect piece of testimony concerning early Sparta points
four hundred years. And just as in Herodotus' account the €V- in the same direction. In his discussion of the causes of revolution
VO!J-LYJ created by Lycurgus' reforms led to a spurt of prosperity, I in aristocracies, Aristotle refers to a poem of Tyrtaeus entitled
so Thucydides, without, however, mentioning Lycurgus' name, EVVO!J-LU to support his contention that a widening gulf between
attributes to it the Spartans' power, never sapped by the ex- rich and poor is one such cause (Pol. 5. 7, Ig06bg6-Ig07"2).
perience of tyranny, to put down tyrannies in other Greek states.2 \Ve do not learn much about the content of the poem beyond the
The aspect of durability, which Herodotus had described as the fact that it was written 'at the time of the Messenian War'l
seal placed by Lycurgus himself on his reform of all Spartan against the background of people oppressed by war demanding
VO!J-L!J-U, is confined by Thucydides to the constitution. He does a redistribution of land.2 The same poem is mentioned under
not, like Herodotus, give details of the constitution and the the same name by Strabo, who assignsit more specifically to the
institutions it affected, except to say that it was never disrupted Second Messenian War, states Tyrtaeus' claim to have been a
by tyranny. Accordingly, YJvv0!J-~BYJuuv describes for him the con- general in it,3 and quotes two couplets of the poem to prove that
dition of stability and durability achieved by the Spartan consti- Tyrtaeus was a Lacedaemonian.4 Modern scholars have attri-
tution. There is neither an indication that he would not use the buted several other fragments of Tyrtaeus to this poem,s but
same verb of any other constitution which had stood the test of since the name EVVO!J-LU, which is our chief interest here, only
time equally well, nor that a constitution deserving to be de- occurs in Aristotle and Strabo, we can use as evidence only what
scribed by the verb t:Vvo!J-€LuBuL would have to have the same they tell us. Although both are late authors in relation to Tyr-
institutions as Sparta. Accordingly, the EVVO!J-LU described by the taeus, there is no reason to doubt their word (a) that Tyrtaeus
verb in this passage is not the name of a specific constitution but wrote an elegiac poem entitled, either by Tyrtaeus himself or by
the condition created by a constitution, and it comes no closer a tradition which is likely to go back to a time well before
than any of the other uses of €VVO!J-LU so far encountered to express- Aristotle, EVVO!J-LU; and (b) that he wrote it in the Second Mes-
ing the narrow political sense of vO!J-os = 'statute'. senian War, in which he himself played a responsible part. At
We may then summarize the results of our inquiry into Hero- the first glance, Aristotle's description of the background of the
dotus' and Thucydides' use of €VVO!J-LU in relation to Sparta by poem might be taken to suggest that its title is to be derived from
saying that they use the noun and the verb to describe the lasting VE!J-W = 'distribute' and refers to a 'good distribution' of the land.6
social and political conditions brought about by the reforms of
I I 306b38: 1mo TOV MW1]vtaKOV 7TaAEf'Ov. For the meaning of v7Ta see Andrewes,
Lycurgus, but that the same terms could also be applied, as Eun. 96 n. I.
Herodotus' discussion of Cheops and Deioces shows, to condi- 2 Igo7aI-2: 8AL{36/LEVOL yap TLVES Ou:t 'TOV 1TOA€jJ.QV ~g{ovv avaOaUTOV 7TOL€LV 7'~V
tions prevalent elsewhere. This sufficesto prove that the Greeks of xwpav.
3 8. 4. 10, C 362 : ~v{Ka q,1]ULVaUTOS' UTpaT1]yfjuat TOV 7TaAEf'OV TOlS' AaKEOatf'OV{OtS'·
the fifth century would associate €VVO!J-LU no more closely with Kat yap Eivai epTJaLv EK€r8EV EV T71 EA€YELq. ..,jv €1TLypatPoUGLV EuvofLLav ... E1TL }-LEV oov
Sparta or with the Spartan constitution after Lycurgus than TOU Tvpra{ov " oEvnpoS' 1mfjpgE 7TaAEf'OS'.
with any other state. 4 Ibid. = frg. 2: aUToS' yap Kpov{wv, KaAAwnq,avov 7TaatS'·Hp1]S', I ZEUS' 'HpaKAE{.
oatS' 7'~VO€ OE3wKE 7TOALV' I o[aLV nfl-a 1TPOAL1TOV'TfS 'EpLVEOV ~V€J.L(;€VTa / €Vp€laV []tA07TO~
[ I. 66. I : avcl T€ €OpafLOV av,dKU Kai Ev(J€v7}81]uav. vijUOV aq"K6p.€lJa.('For the son ofCronus himself, husband of beautifully-wreathed
2 I agree with Hammond, op. cit. 54 n. 59, against Andrewes, Eun. 94, that Hera, Zcus has given this city to the sons of Herac1es. Together with them we for-
'the explanatory sentence ... states not that Sparta's power was due to the sook windy Erineos and arrived in the broad island of Pelops.')
lack of tyranny but that it was due to the continuity of her constitution over four 5 Diehl' conservatively adds only the fragments in Diodorus 7. 12 and in Pluto
hundred years'. Cf. Gomme, HCT I. 130-1, and den Boer, op. cit. 83 n. I. Lycurgu5 6.10 to the Strabo fragment as frgg. 3 a and 3 b. His predecessor, Bergk4,
Thucydides' KaL aiEL aTvpawWToS' O)Vserves a double function. In the first place, it had added three further fragments to it. G. Huxley, Early Sparta 54, apparently
helps explain that the development of Sparta's power was never inhibited by those also assigns Diehl" frg. 6, to the Eunomia. For a full discussion see Andrewes, Eun.
who 7'0 €¢' EUVTWV p.ovov 1TpOOpWjJ.€VOL €S T€ TO Gwp.a Kat, ES oT() 'TOV rs,ov O[KOV avg€LV 95-100.
Ot' auq,aAdaS' OUOV €OVVaVTO f'aAWTa niS' 7TaAEtS'<pKOVV (I. 17): and secondly, it ex- 6 The most influential recent exponent of this derivation of EUVOf'{a, J. L. Myres,
plains what gave the Spartans the will to depose tyrants elsewhere. CR 61 (1947) 80-2, does not use this passage in his argument.
814~77 G
But since Tyrtaeus' known attitude toward a redistribution yap
,
uu
'y , ,
VOfLL.,Et<; OUK EUVOfLEtU aL,
'" 8 ' \ " ,
aUTO<; a7TO TOUTOU tUXUEt
, / t
0
~,...
o7JfLo<; K L
a'
r.... ,..., '''./. ,~c Vl""
of the land 1 makes nonsense of this assumption, and since, I
EIo.EU8EpO<; Eunv.
" ,~"
Et 0
I
EUVOfLLaV "7JTEt<;, 7TpWTU fLEV o'f'Et TOU<; OEsLwTaTo
I
,
" 8' ., \ I ~ \ \ ,
moreover, neither the noun nor the adjective nor the verb bears aUTOr<; TOU<; VOfLOU<; n EVTa<;' E7TEtTa KOl\aUoUUtv OL XP7JUTOt TOU<; 7TOV7JPOU<;
\ I t \ \.... 1\ "" I

this sense in any of the passages we have discussed, we must look Kat f30UIo.EUUOUUtV ot XP17UTOt 7TEpt T17<;7TOI\EW<; Kat OUK EUUOUUL fLUtVOfLEVOU<;
I (:) \ I ,~, \ I ,~\, \ 'y , \ I ,
dv8pW7TOU<; fJOUI\EUEtV OUOE I\EyEtV OUOE EKKI\17UtU.,Etv. a7TO rOUTWV TOLVUV
for a different explanation. The only help we get comes from the
TWV dya8wv TilXLur' av 6 bijfLO<; El<; boulo.e£uv KaTa7TEUOL 1
Strabo fragment. If there is any point at all in the statement that
Zeus himself is responsible for having established the Heracleidae In order to ascertain as precisely as possible what the author of
as kings of Sparta and that the rest of the Spartans have followed this treatise2 means by E1JvofL{a and its verb forms and by KaKO-
them ever since the Dorians came to the Peloponnese, it must vOfL{a, we have to start with the last part of the passage, since it is
surely be an appeal to the 'malcontents to abandon their agita- here that EuvofL{a is most closely defined. That E1JVofL{a denotes
tion and return to their obedience'.2 In other words, the title a condition, in this case the condition of a city in which the
signifies that Tyrtaeus' poem called for discipline and order and 7TOVYJpO{, the common people, are kept in subjection, is .obviou~.
has, therefore, no immediate or exclusive bearing on the institu- Three elements are identified as constituent parts of thIS condI-
tions of Sparta or on her constitution.3 tion. In the first place, legislative power is to be vested in the
It is not until the second half of the fifth century B.C. that the 'most capable' men only. Secondly, the 'good' are to exercise
effect of the new meaning of vOfL0<; as 'statute' is unambiguously judicial power over the 'bad', 3 and third, the 'good' alone are to
reflected in d))J0fL{a in the Constitution if Athens which has come be members of the Council and in their administration will pre-
down to us under the name ofXenophon. Neither the exact date vent 'madmen' from serving as Councillors, making public
nor the authorship of the treatise is known, and although a date speeches, and even from attending the meetings of the Ass~mb.ly,
between the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War and the Thracian including, we may presume, meetings called both for legIslatlve
expedition of Brasidas in the summer of 424 B.C. seems to me and for electoral purposes.
the most plausible, the questions of date and authorship will not What is of special interest in this discussion is that E1JVofL{a is
help us settle the meaning of E1JvofL{a in the tract.4 The relevant first and foremost described in terms of the administration of the
passage is introduced after a discussion of freedom of speech, city in its various branches. This is not to say that what the
especially in the Council, which the democracy grants to every author wants to see established in the city is something other than
citizen, rascally though he may be. This practice, the author con- law-and-order. But when we compare his conception of it with
tinues, may not be conducive to the best kind of state (7TO'\t<;), but it the kind of EuvofL{a associated with Sparta, to say nothing of
isconducive to the preservation ofthe democracy. He then explains:
6 yap bijfLO<; (3oVIo.ETat OUK eVvofLoufLEV7J<; Tij<; 7TOIo.EW<;aUTo<; bOUIo.EVEtv, I [Xen.] Ath. Pol. I. 8-9: 'For the common people wish not to be the,mse!ves
enslaved while the city is governed by good laws but to be free and exercIse con-
dlo.lo.' EIo.EV8EpO<; Elvut Kat apxEtv, Tij<; bE KUKOVOfL£U<; UUT/i) olo.£yov fLEIo.Et·0
trol; that the system of laws is bad is of little importance to them, For from
I Schol. PI. Laws I. 629 a, with Huxley, op. cit. 55, and Kiechle, op. cit. 184-5 what you regard as lack of government by good law~ the common people derive
with 185 n. 5. 2 Andrewes, Eun. 96. their strength and their freedom. But if you are lookmg for government by good
3 Two late associations of Evvoj1-{a with Sparta deserve a brief mention. Diodorus laws, you will first of all see that the most capable en~ct laws for t~em; then th:
7.12.1 adds two lines to the oracle cited by Hdt. I. 65. 3, in which the god promises good men will straighten out the bad, the good men wlll dehber~te m the Councll
to give Lycurgus the EVVOj1-{a he had asked for. Since the 'couplet is wholly un- about the city, and will not let madmen be members of the Counol, make speeches,
suitable to the original oracle' (Andrewes, Eun. 90 n. 6) and seems to assume the or be members of the Assembly. Surely, good measures such as these would very
very late meaning of a 'set of good laws' for EVVOj1-{a, it has rightly been rejected as quickly reduce the common people to slavery.'
spurious. However, Plut. Lycurgus 5. 4 seems to have known the spurious lines and 2 I am not convinced by the arguments ofE. Hohl, CP 45 (1950) 26-35, that we
on their basis initiated the practice of applying the name Evvoj1-{a to the Spartan are dealing with a letter. .
constitution as a whole; see Andrewes, Eun. 9 I. 3 This is probably the meaning of KOAaoovotv in this. context, see. E .. Kalmka,
4 See G. W. Bowersock, 'Pseudo-Xenophon', HSCP 71 (1967) 33-55, esp. 33-8, Die pseudoxenophontische A6!HNAIQN,IIOAI~EIA 12,0;Vl.th.n.. I. ~~t It mlg~t,have
for a critical discussion of the dates proposed. Bowersock's own date, 443 B.C., the wider sense of 'administer correctlve pumshment, dlsoplme, reprove, keep
seems to me to be too early. in check', as in Soph. Aj. 1108, 1160.
Solon's EVvop,[a, which, among other things, 17aVEt Epya ?hxoUTa- This enables us to draw some conclusions concerning the nature
ULYJ<;,we must conclude that the realm of Eiwo/lLa has shrunk to of KaKOI'O/lLa, a noun which is fi-JUndonly here in extant Greek
encompass only the constitutional workings of the state, con- literature. The context makes it clear that the noun describes the
ceived primarily as the enactment and enforcement of statutes. condition antithetical to EVvopLa. It is the consequence of the
Not only is the enactment of statutes the first item that comes to common people's desire for freedom and power; a condition
the author's mind-for no other vO/lOt can be meant in this con- which, to be sure, is not in itself desired by the people, but which
text by TOU<; vO/lov<; TtBEVTa<;-but the judicial process involves is of less importance to them than the prevention of that en-
the application of statutes, and participation in Council and slavement which EiJVo/lLa would entail for them. Like EVVO/l[a, the
Assembly implies the right to formulate them. In short, although noun seems, therefore, to refer to the political institutions and
the word may still retain its old notion of law-and-order, it has legislation which make up the constitution of the state, only that
now become an issue in party politics and embodies, in this in this case the constitution is bad. Like the adjective KaKovo/lW-
instance, the constitutional programme claimed by one political TaTOt in Herodotus' discussion of Sparta (I. 65. 2), the noun as-
orientation as its exclusive prerogative. I sumes the existence of vO/lOt, which are, however, bad and not
This conclusion is confirmed by the use of the verb EVVO/lEfuBat conducive to law-and-order. But while Herodotus understood the
in this passage. In stating that the common people are more -VO/l0<; suffix in a wide sense as including everything regarded as
interested in their own freedom and power to rule than in the valid and binding, it seems here confined to statutes and political
good government of the city (dJVO/lOV/lEVYJ 170"\t<;) the author at- institutions, that is, it is used in a narrow political sense. I
tributes self-interest and partisanship to his political opponents,
while claiming for those of his own political persuasion the main- ~With this we turn now to dVO/lLa, which, as we stated above, is
tenance of what is really good for the state. Moreover, he the opposite of EuvO/lLa as a quality primarily of an individual. It
emphatically states twice that the freedom of the common people is, therefore, best rendered as 'lawlessness', if by that term we
cannot be reconciled with the dJVO/lOV/lEVYJ 17(;"\t<;or with EVVO/lEf- understand not the 'absence of law' but the asocial behaviour of
aBat as such, and goes even as far as naming the absence of EV- an individual who defies law-and-order and who acts in contra-
vopLa (OUK EVl'o/lEfuBat) as the cause of the strength and freedom vention of any or all of the canons regarded as valid and binding
of the people. If this proves the same partisan spirit in the use by the society in which he lives. It describes neither the trans-
of the verb as we found in the use of the noun, the fact that at gression of a particular vO/los--the proper term for that is 17apa-
the beginning of the passage it is the verb and at the end of the l'o/lLa-nor the kind of unconventional behaviour which most
passage the noun which is associated with the 'slavery' of the people frown upon yet tolerate. In all its forms, noun, adjective,
common people suggests that the content of verb and noun are and verb, its signification is more general than that: it denotes
identical in that both regard law-and-order in terms of political a violent and unruly kind of conduct which infringes vO/lo<; both
institutions and legislation. The pseudo-Xenophontic Constitution in its sense of 'law-and-order' and 'proper behaviour'.
oj Athens is thus the earliest surviving document in which law-and- VOP.OLS, ET€paV OE TO KaAws KELa8aL TOUS V0ll-0VS O[S €/-L/1-EVOVaLV (Ean yap 1Tfd8eo(}al. Kat
KaKW, KHfLEVOL<;). Both parts of the definition are framed with reference primarily
order is seen specifically as the condition of a state whose statutes to the statutes: .vvofLla is 'obedience to the enacted laws' and the 'enactment of
are good and which, consequently, enjoys a good constitution.2 good laws'.
I It is strange that there is no juxtaposition of KaKovofLla and 8vavofLla anywhere
I I see no evidence for Hohl's contention, op. cit. 34, that Sparta is here in- in Greek literature, and this lack, when added to the fact that 8vavofLla is found
tended as the model of d,vofLla. only twice in Greek literature (Hesiod and Solon) and KaKovofLla only once as
2 For a similar use of d,vOfLELalJat in the fourth century see Aeschines 3. I.'J'1 and a noun ([Xen.] Alh. Pol.) and twice as an adjective (Herodotus and Philo), makes it
Dem. 24. 139·Aeschines [. 5, where the verb is used of a democratic constitution, difficult to determine the difference between them. On the basis of the little we
proves that not only oligarchs could lay a claim to it. Note especiallv the definition know, we might guess that KaKovofLla is the condition of a society which has bad
of EVIJop.{a in A.rist. Pol. 4. 8, 129433-7: aUK Eun 3£Evv0/l-La T() eD KE'ia8uL TO V'; vop.ovs, VOfLOt, while 8vavofLla is a condition in which forces disruptive of good VOfLO' pre-
p.ry 1T€Uha8aL o£. 8/.0 pia)) fl-€V EvvofLlav tJ1ToATj1TTEOV fdpUL TO 1TE{8eaBaL TOLS KHfLEVOLS vail, forces such as those enumerated by Solon, frg. 3. 34-8. But we cannot be sure.
Contrary to EVvov[a, of which the noun form is the earlier, the iKETEVW, 1Tpoa[D7)T' aV0Il-0v, is best interpreted as a request not to
I

adjective avovos is found before aV0Il-[a makes an appearance. In infer from his having trespassed on sacred ground, of which the
the only pre-fifth-century passage-the only passage, therefore, chorus has just accused him (125-37), that he is a person who
which justifies our inclusion of aV0Il-[a in our discussion here- habitually defies general norms of behaviour, especially in re-
Hesiod describes Typhaon as DHvav B' VfJPWT~V T' aV0Il-0v B', ligious matters.2 J1v0Il-0S may have a religious significance also in
terrible, overbearing, and lawless (Theog. 307). The juxtaposition a Euripidean passage concerning Oedipus. For when Jocasta
of these three attributes shows that aV0Il-0v refers to his conduct in speaks in the Phoenissae of Oedipus' birth as aV0ll-a Il-EV TEKEtV EIl-E
the same general way as the other two expressions do. Just as (380), she is evidently thinking of the violation of Apollo's oracle
DHva, does not describe the impression he makes in a specific which the birth of her son meant: we remember that it was
context, or vfJpLaT~S his attitude in one particular kind of situa- Jocasta herself who reported at the beginning of the play (r8-20)
tion, so aV0Il-0' refers not to his infraction of a specific vall-os but that the Oracle warned Laius that begetting a child would
to his defiance of the social order as such. constitute defiance of the gods and that this would involve his
The next occurrence of the adjective in extant Greek literature own death and ruin for his house. Religious overtones may, but
is after 464/3 B.C., in Aeschylus' Agamemnon, where it is found need not, be present in two passagesin which aV0Il-0' isjuxtaposed
twice (151, r 142) in a musical sense.1 But the richness of Aeschy- with aBw,. Both adjectives are found together in Euripides'
lus' language and his fondness for iridescent epithets extends the Andromache (49 r) to describe the murder plotted by Hermione
meaning in both passages beyond the musical. When Calchas at against Andromache and her son; but it is hard to determine
Aulis invokes Paian to prevent Artemis from bringing on Bva[av whether the planned murder is 'lawless and godless' because
ETEpav aV0ll-av TLV' aDaLTOV, he anticipates the sacrifice of Iphi- Menelaus had lured Andromache away from her suppliant pos-
geneia not merely as a sacrifice 'unaccompanied by music', as ture at the altar or whether it refers to the conduct of Menelaus
sacrifices to the chthonian deities were,2 but also as the turning- and his daughter in more general terms. Similarly, one cannot be
point in Agamemnon's conduct, expressed a few lines further by certain whether or not religious vall-0L are involved in the chorus'
T() 1TavTaToAIl-0v epPOVEtVIl-ETE'YVW (22 r ). The sacrifice is thus de- prayer for the death of Pentheus in the Bacchae : on the one hand,
scribed as one which will defy all norms of proper human con- Pentheus' attitude toward Dionysus justifies his being named as
duct. Similarly, although in the later passage the chorus may TOV aBwv aV0Il-0v aDLKOV 'EX[ovo, 'Yavov [or: TaKov] 'Y7)'YEVfj;3 but on
reproach Cassandra with no more than shouting a 'tuneless the other hand, Pentheus' 'lawless senselessness' (aV0Il-0' deppo-
tune', it would be difficult for the audience not to associate with avv7)), which the chorus had criticized earlier in the play (387),
vall-0v aV0Il-0v also the 'lawless' conduct which has become the and the addition of l.tDLKO, to the other two epithets here extend
'rule' for the house of Atreus (I 142). the force of aV0Il-0S beyond the sphere of religion . .I1v0Il-0S is again
Among the other tragedians aV0Il-0S is attested in two Sopho- found coupled with unjust behaviour in Agamemnon's refusal
clean and seven Euripidean passages.3 Heracles in Sophocles' in the Iphigeneia at Aulis to commit 'lawless acts which are not
Trachiniae applies the adjective to the Centaurs in exactly the just' against his own children merely for the sake ofHelen.4 Else-
same sense in which Hesiod had used it of Typhaon, when he where aV0Il-0' has a passive sense in that it describes the nature
calls them 'an overbearing, lawless host, exceeding in violence'.4 of an act perpetrated rather than the morality of the person who
In the Oedipus at Colonus, Oedipus' entreaty to the chorus, Il-~ Il-', perpetrated it. The Phrygian slave in the Orestes, for example, is
I 142: 'Do not, I beseech you, look at me (as if I were) a lawless person.'
I Cf. above, p. 61 n. I. 2 Cf. possible religious overtones in Evvo/-,{a in Soph. Aj. 713 (above, p. 70). On
2 So H. Lloyd-] ones, CQ 47 (= N .s. 31 (1953) 96. religious connotations of vo/-,o, see above, pp. 40-3.
3 I omit the obviously corrupt o.vo/-,o' of the Laurentianus at Eur. Suppl. 45, and 3 995-6 (= 1015-16): 'the godless, lawless, and unjust earth-born scion of
prefer the correction o.va /-,0' accepted by Parmentier (Eude, 1950). Echion'.
-+ 1°95-6: u-rpa-rov ... uf3pLaT~v, avo/-,ov, lJ1T€POXQV f3tav. 4 399: o.vo/-,a opwvTa KOV 8{Ka,a 1Taroa, ou, <YEtvu/-,'1v,
EYNOMIA, JYl:NOMIA, AND ANOMIA 89

upset by the 'bloody afflictions and lawless ills' that he has seen,! There are three examples of the adverb avofLws, whose logical
and, if Aristophanes' parody of the Andromeda can be trusted, counterpart EVvofLws, curiously enough, is not found. It may have
Andromeda bemoaned the aJ10fLa 7TfLBm inflicted upon her by her religious overtones in Thucydides' report of Pagondas' speech to
father (frg. 122. I I = Ar. Thesm. 1039). the Boeotians before the battle of Dclium, in which he bases
Similar uses of the adjective are found in fifth-century prose. trust in divine aid on the fact that the Athenians have 'lawlessly'
According to Herodotus, Astyages treated Harpagus to a lawless fortified the temple (4. 92. 7). The chorus in Euripides' Medea
feast (avofLO/ Tpa7TE~TI EoawE) when he served him the flesh of his uses aVofL(tJs to characterize the brutal manner in which Jason
son (1. 162. I), and Gyges called Candaules' request to look upon forsook Medea for a new wife (1000), and Gorgias joins it with
the naked queen an 'unsound speech' (!loYOJ1 OUK uyda) and the aOLKws and with the verbs E{3uLaB7) and u{3pLaB7) to describe Helen
act itself 'lawless' (oEwBat aJ1OfLWJ1), clearly because it offended his as more sinned against than sinning in his version of her rape
notions of proper conduct (1. 8. 3-4). (frg. I 1. 7). I

The combination of aJ10fLOS with aBEDS and aOtKOS, which we While the adjective and the adverb show no trace whatever of
noticed in the Bacchae, is paralleled in the peroration of Gorgias' having been influenced by the meaning of 'statute' which VOfLoS
Palamedes, in which the speaker tries to turn the table on his came to assume, there are some hints of such influence in the case
accusers by arguing that they would commit a 'terrible, godless, of the noun avofLLa and the verb avofLEw. The earliest preserved
unjust, and lawless act' against themselves if they killed their ally, occurrences of the noun avofLLa are in prose. Herodotus uses it
benefactor, and fellow Greek (frg. Ila. 36), and again in the three times in the Deioces story (1. 96. 2-97. 3), which we had
Anonymus Iamblichi (3. I), where aOtKa and aJ10fLa are combined occasion to mention in connection with our analysis of El)VOfLLa
to describe the kind of acts for which a person ought not to use (above, pp. 73-4). According to Herodotus it was against the
his talents.2 The most illuminating passage on the precise meaning background of much avofLL7) among the Medes that Deioces first
of aJ1OfLOS comes from the speech of the Thebans to the Spartans embarked upon his scheme of gaining power by cultivating a repu-
concerning the treatment of Plataea, as reported by Thucydides. tation for justice. When Deioces refused to sit asjudge any longer,
All the specific charges of transgression are described by the ad- ap7Tay~ and aVOfLL7) became rife again, and when a meeting was
verb 7TapavofLws or the verb 7TapaJ1OfLEw: the Theban attack during convoked to deliberate about the situation, the friends of Deio-
the truce and during the celebration of a religious festival (3. 65. ces advocated the establishment of kingship, so that if TE XWp7)
I, 2) ; the killing of prisoners who surrendered voluntarily and "
EvvofL7)aETat Kat """aVTOt 7TpOSEpya TpE'f'OfLE
./;' B a OVOE
,<;;-,
V7T aVOfLt7)S avaaTa-
t " I "

about whose lives the Plataeans had given assurances (3. 66. 2, TOt EaofLEBa. While it would seem at first glance that the aVOfLL7) on
3); and the attack launched by the Plataeans on the Thebans which Deioces and his friends capitalize describes a condition
without provocation (3. 67. 5).3 But when the Thebans sum up rather than a quality, closer scrutiny shows that it is not a politi-
their grievances in their peroration, they use ~fLtJ1 aJ10fLa 7TaBovatI J cal but a social disorder which he sets out to remedy, a disorder
(3. 67·6) to describe themselves as victims of Plataean 'lawless- which is brought about by the asocial conduct of individuals.
ness' as such, that is, to characterize in general terms the be- This is most clearly seen in the second occurrence of aVOfLL7) in this
haviour of the Plataeans toward them.4 passage, where its combination with pillage (ap7Tay~) shows that
the prevalence of crime rather than anarchy is the problem at
I 1455: q,OVtWV 1Ta8€wv avoflwv TE KQKWV. issue. The final passage, quoted above, provides the corrobora-
2 Below, p. 92 n. 3. Cf. Eur. IA 399 (above, p. 87 n. 4).
3 In the only general statement in this speech containing a form of 1Tapavo/-,Ew,
tion: if the presence of avofLL7) 'unsettles' the Medes and its
01 yap ayovn, 1Tapavo/-,ovat /-,u'\''\'ov TWV E1TO/-,EVWV(65' 2), the reference is clearly to absence enables them to 'turn to the pursuit of business', aJ10fLL7)
the commission of a specific illegal act.
4 Note that for the specific charge repeated here, that the Plataeans transgressed I For the combination of avo/-,w, and aUKw, cf. Gorgias, frg. lla. 36 (above,
the law of the Hellenes to honour assurances given for the lives of prisoners. the p. 88), and Eur. Bacch. 995-6, IA 399 (above, p. 87). For the association of avo/-,{a
verb 1Tapa~a{vw is used. with vf3pt, cf. Hes. Theogony 307 and Soph. Trach. 1096 (above, p. 86).
EYNOMIA, LJYENOMIA, A.l\;D ANOMIA 91

can only be a social malady which consistsin the lawless behaviour with statutes. Ion complains of the injustice of the gods who enact
of hoodlums who cannot be controlled; it does not refer to (ypat/JuvTaS) laws for men, while their own conduct lays them
a political condition of the kind branded as ovavofLtYJ by Solon.1 open to the charge of dvofLtu.1 The fact that the gods do not enact
Thucydides' only use of dvofLtu points in the same direction. the kind of statutes by which a city orders its life is irrelevant
When he introduces his account of the effect of the Plague upon here; the interesting point is that their rules are treated as if they
the conduct of the Athenians with the words: 7TpWTOV TE ~pgE KUL were no more than human political vOflm, subject to change and
€S Ta'\'\U Tn 7TO'\Et €7TL 7TA.EOVdvofLtus TO vOUYJfLU,2 he is obviously annulment, and that, through the use of dvofliu, vOfLOS is brought
thinking less of a political condition than of the demoralizing in in a different sense to deny the gods the moral right to legislate.
effect on individual conduct, which he then proceeds to describe A closer approach to vOfLo, = 'statute' is also evident in the
in detail. verb dvofLEW, which appears only twice in Greek literature before
Euripides is the only tragedian in whose surviving works the the end of the fifth century B.C. Herodotus reports that the
noun dvofLtu is found, and he is also the earliest author to mention members of the Dorian Pentapolis in Asia Minor excluded from
it in a context in which written VOfLOt also occur. Still, the vOfLoS their association, whose centre was the sanctuary of Triopian
negated by the prefix remains throughout the norm of proper Apollo, TOU, 7TEpL TO LPOV dVOfL0UUVTaS (1. 144. I). That the par-
conduct. Twice dvofLta is directed against the gods. The chorus of ticiple describes lawless conduct in a religious matter is not re-
the Heracles brands with the words BEauS dvofLtq, xputvwv (757) the markable, since we have encountered both noun and adjective in
defiant behaviour of Lycus, who had declared (723) his disdain similar contexts before (pp. 86-7, 89, 90 above). But it is curious
of divine retribution for having violated the sanctity of the hearth that, while dvofLtu is usually associated with infractions of the
at which Megara and her children had taken refuge.3 Similarly, general norm of proper conduct, it constitutes here the violation
the simple god-fearing cowherd, who, in the Iphigeneia among the of a specific vOfLoS, which enjoined the dedication in the temple of
Taurians, reports to Iphigeneia the landing of two strangers, tripods won in the games of Triopian Apollo; disregard for this
characterizes as dvofLtq, Bpuuvs (275) one of his colleagues who law by a Halicarnassian led to the exclusion of Halicarnassus
had derided the superstitious fears which the landing had aroused from the organization. In other words, dvofLEW is used here in
in some of his comrades. In three passages dvofLtu is contrasted reference to a specific transgression, which is more commonly
with vOfLo" and as might be expected, vOfLoS describes the proper expressed by the verb 7TupuvofLEW.2 We must, then, regard this
behaviour of an individual in two of these. The chorus of the usage either as exceptional or as emphasizing the asocial charac-
Heracles illustrates the !heme of prosperity leading to madness by ter of an offence which was directed not only at the god, but also
singing of a man who, 'abandoning the norms of conduct and at the association which had entrusted its welfare to his divine
gratifYing his lawlessness, shatters the gloomy chariot of wealth', 4 protection.
and when the chorus in the Iphigeneia at Aulis (1095) laments the There is no reason to assume that the application of dVOfLEW to
rule of dvofLtu over the VOfLOt, it means that lawless conduct has the infraction of a specific law had anything to do with any
eclipsed the order of a society from which respect, goodness, and change in the use of vOfLoS. But the second passage in which the
reverence are gone. The third passage, however, contrasts dvofLtu verb is found, again in a participial form but without reference to

I This refutes the assertion of Jaeger, SE 82 n. I, that OUaV0f'L'l in Solon's poem I Ion 442--3: TrW~ o~v 8£KUWV TOUS VOfLOUS VJLOS ~POTO;S I ypaljJavTus, aUTovs
is merely 'ein metrischer Ersatz fur aV0f'LU'. avo/-dav 0eP/UGKaVHV; 'The contrast of dVOp.,LU with VOJ.LOS = 'statute' is found again in
2 2. 53. I: 'In other respects, too, did the plague initiate in the city a larger Critias' Sisyphus (= frg. 25. 40), if the manuscript reading is correct. But v0f'0"
degree of lawlessness.' ought probably to be emended to 1>0{30", see above, p. 52 n. I.
3 Wilamowitz, Euripides Herakles 22• I71, thinks that aV0f'LU here refers to Lycus' 2 For 7TUPUV0f'€Win Herodotus see the description of Xerxes' maltreatment of
'unglauben'. But the context shows that it is rather the act of proclaiming his dis- the body of Leonidas at 7. 238. 2, where the V0f'0' violated is presumably a sanc-
belief (a1>povu '\0yov OVPUVLWVf'uKapWv KUT€{3U'\') that constitutes aV0f'LU. tion against desecration of the body of a fallen enemy; cf. 9. 78-9 and Thuc. 4.
4 778-80: V0f'0V 7TUP€f'EVO" aV0f'L'! Xap,v Iltoov, I 'OpuuaEv o'\{3ou KE'\U'VOVapf'u. 97-101.
92 NOMOl; BECOMES' STATUTE'

a specific vOfLOS, reveals clear traces of the 'statute' meaning of the blessings of EvvofLtu are matched one by one against the
VOfLOS. The passage is part of the most elaborate treatment of deleterious effects of dvofLta. EvvofLta is a source of trust which
dwofLtu and dvofLtu that has come down to us, and for that reason helps increase the public treasure (7. I), while dvofLta causes lack
we have reserved it for this, the final point of our discussion of of trust and of sociability, so that people will hoard their money
these two concepts. Toward the end of a late fifth-century ex- and thus cause economic shortages (7. 8). EvvofLtu helps us steer
hortation to virtue, incorporated into the Protrepticus of Iam- the best course in good fortune and bad, both financial and per-
blichus and therefore known as the 'Anonymus Iamblichi',1 a sonal, in that it enables the fortunate to enjoy their prosperity in
large section (6-7) is devoted to weighing the blessings of ElJvofL{u security and without fear of plots against them, whereas the un-
against the harm inflicted by dvofLtu on individuals as well as on fortunate are helped by the sociability and trust of the fortunate
states (KUL KOLV?7KUL l8tq,). The theme itself of the treatise makes it (7. 2); but where dvofLta reigns, prosperity is not secure, since
as clear as does every occurrence of the two terms in it that both people conspire against it, while lack of trust and of sociability
describe a quality of personal conduct. Yet there is no doubt that compound misfortune (7.9). EvvofL{u frees people from annoying
this conduct is less viewed as, respectively, adherence to or rejec- tasks (7TpayfLaTa) and gives them time to devote themselves to
tion of general norms of behaviour than as obedience and dis- their proper life's work (Epya TijS 'wijs) and, as a result, releases
obedience to the established laws. The primary connotation of their thoughts from the most unpleasant concerns and turns them
vOfLoS is 'statute' throughout the treatise,z and time and again to the most pleasant (7. 3-4); dvofLtu, on the other hand, deprives
just behaviour is equated with the observance of the statutes.3 men of the leisurely pursuit of their own work and plunges
This attitude also colours the treatment of ElwofL{u and dvofL{u, them into the most unpleasant of annoying tasks (7. 8). And
and this is shown especially by the frequent application of both finally, EvvofLta gives men sleep free from nightmares and pain
terms in financial and economic contexts. After an initial state- and thus prepares them to face the next day with confidence
ment that dvofLtu (disregard for the laws) is incompatible with and good hope (7. 5), whereas dvofLta will bring no pleasant
living in society4and that the EvvofLtu (obedience to the laws) in- thoughts to people, neither in wakefulness nor in sleep, and they
herent in all mankind will make the masses rise up against the wake up fearing the memory of those whom they have wronged
rule of a strong individual who uses his power in an unlawful way,S (7. II).
This rather dull and lengthy list leaves no doubt that both
I There has been a tendency to identify the author as Democritus; see especially dvofLtu and dvofLta are conceived of as qualities of personal con-
Q. Cataudella, Studi italiani difilologia classica N.S. 10 (1932) 5-22, Rend. d. R. Aecad.
Naz. d. Lineei, ser. 6, vol. 13 (1937) 182-210, and REG 63 (1950) 74-106; and A. T.
duct. It is also clear that the vOfLOS to which they are related
Cole, Jr., HSep 65 (1961) 127-63. The arguments, originally advanced by Blass, cannot be limited to the sense of 'statute', for the qualities
that the treatise belongs to the intellectual atmosphere of the late fifth century, enumerated range so wide over aspects that cannot easily be re-
carry conviction and are generally accepted. But I feelIess confident that we can
identify the author with Democritus or with any of the names that have been sug-
lated to legislation (for example trust, sociability, etc.) that it is
gested, e.g. Hippias, Protagoras, Theramenes, since we know too little of their more natural to take the -VOfLOSsuffixin a wider sense as referring
ethical and political doctrines. to behavioural norms. This is especially true of two points made
2 This comcs out with special clarity at 4. 3, where in using the term 'Tlfl-,a, for
losses sustained by fire, death in the family, and loss of livestock, the author feels
about dvofLta which have no counterpart in the section on dvofLtU.
called upon to explain that he does not mean 'penalties', ou Td~ EK TWV V6fl-WV For although the author states at first (7. 6) that 'war leading to
Myw 'Tlfl-'a~. subjugation and enslavement' is more likely to happen to people
3 e.g. at 3. 1 dya8d KaL v6fl-'fl-a are opposed to O:O'Ka KaL O:vofl-a; at 3. 6 goodness in
financial matters is effected by coming to the aid Toi~ v6fl-0'~ KaL T0 O'Ka'<tJ; at 6. 1 "
who flout the law (dvofLoiJm) than to those who obey it (dvOfLOV-
v0fl-0~ KaL TO 8[Kawv are said to be king among men; at 6. 3 a strong man can retain fLEVOLS), it is dvofLtu alone which invites war from abroad and
powcr only by allying himself Toi~ v0fl-o'~ KaL T0 O'Ka'<tJ. makes for friction at home through plots and counterplots (7. IO).
4 6. I: Kav avop.{q. SLaLnia(JUL.
5 6. 4: SOKELV yap uv TO US' U7TaVTUS' civ8pcf.J1T'ovS' Tip TOLOl.1Tc.p ¢>VVTL 7ToAEj..dovs KUTU- Obviously, more than disregard of the statutes is involved here,
GTu8€VTUS oLa T~V euvTwv €tJJJ0iJ-{av. and the same is true when dVOfLta is cited as the one and only
94 NOMOI: BECOMES 'STATUTE' EYNOMIA, jjYI:NOMIA, AND ANOMIA 95

cause of tyranny. It is not tyranny which creates a condition of


I
EVvofLtu and KaKovofLta in [Xenopholl]'S Constitution if Athens,
lawlessness, but it is the lawless conduct of the citizens, not which belongs probably in the early 420S, and in the case of
merely their disregard for the statutes, that creates tyranny; the avofLta not until the Anonymus Iamblichi in the late fifth cen-

avofLta is predicated not of the tyrant but of the people as a whole tury. Accordingly, since vOfL0<; is attested as 'statute' as early as
who 'have turned to wickedness' and have abandoned VOfL0<;and 464/3 B.C., we conclude that it assumed this sense before the four
8tKY).2 Still, even here the sense of 'statute' rings through and even compounds discussed so far showed a trace of it, and that EiJvofLta,
more in those passages which reveal the author's preoccupation 8V(TV0fLta, and avofLta do not enable us to push the date of vOfL0<; =

with economic matters and with plots, where the VOfLOt observed 'statute' back beyond 464/3 B.C.
and flouted are obviously statutes concerning the payment of
debts and those against treason and conspiratorial activities. We
are at the very least well on the way to Aristotle's definition of
EiJvofLta as including both the enactment of good laws and
obedience to the established laws.3
This part of our discussionhas yielded the following conclusions.
Before 464/3 B.C. the suffix of EiJvofLta, 8v(TV0fLta, avofLta, and
their related forms does not reflect the political or judicial
sense of vOfL0<;, of which we found the earliest example in Aeschy-
lus' Supplices. The suffix of dvofLta before that date reflects VOfL0<;
as (a) the norm of proper conduct (pp. 24-6 above), and (b) the
condition oflaw-and-order (pp. 30-3 above), connotations which
have moral rather than political overtones. The opposite of
EiJVofLta in the first sense (a) is avofLta, attested in the early period
only in the adjectival form avofL0<;, which signifies conduct defy-
ing law-and-order, while its opposite in the second sense (b) is
8vavofLta, which describes a condition in the state which is almost
tantamount to anarchy. These findings tally well with the uses of
vOfL0<; attested for the period before 464/3 B.C. 'Ve observed that
it means 'law-and-order' as early as Theognis (p. 30 above),
and while there is no passage before the fifth century in which it
refers to individual conduct, it does appear from Hesiod onwards
in the closely related sense in which it describes the normal way
in which things are done, that is, the norm which avofLta trans-
gresses (pp. 23-4 above).
The earliest indications that vOfL0<; in the sense of 'statute'
affected the meaning of the compounds comes in the case of
I ,. 12: ytV£TUL Sf: Kat ~ 'Tvpavvts, KUKOV ToaOVTOV T€ Kat TOWVTOV, OtJJ< E~ aAAou
'TLVOS ~ dVOfl,{as. OLOVrQt O€ TLV€S' TWV op8wS' aup.f3cf""OVTUt, Tvpavvov
o..v8pOnTWV, QaaL i.L~
ig ci""ov TLVOS Ka8{aTua8uL ... aUK dpewS' Tavru "OYL~OJL€VOL.
2 ,_ 12-16, esp. 13: E7Tftodv yap UrrUVT€S {7TL KUK{av Tpa7TWVrUt .• " and 14: 0rav
oov ravru TO. Svo €K TOV 7T,,~eOUS €KA{1TT/, 0 T€ VOj1.0S Kat. ~ 8lK1].
3 Pol. 4. 8, 1294a3-7 (above, p. 84 n. 2).
IEONOMI A AND ATHENS 97

beyond the observation that in the relevant two lines the la~-
VOf.da which Harmodius and Aristogeiton brought to Athens IS
contrasted with tyranny (TOV Tvpavvov KTaVE-rYJv / laov6p,ovc; T'
)1e~vac; E7ToLYJaaTYJv),and since their main interest for us is chrono-
logical, we shall defer a discussion of them until we ~ave esta?-
lished the meaning of the term through a full analYSISof all ItS
ESU L TSmore conducive to determining the point at which

R
occurrences in the fifth century, to use them then to date the
assumed the meaning of 'statute' in Athens are ob-
v6p,oc; emergence of the concept of laovop,la in Athens.
tained by an examination of laovop,la, the last remaining Most treatments of laovop,la regard it as the name of that
-vop,oc; compound found before 464/3 B.C. Its connotations, as we constitutional form which later came to be called DYJp,oKpaTla.I
shall see, are from its first appearance until at least the end of the But, as we shall see, laovop,la is not a name for a form of govern-
fourth century B.C. purely political, and the context in which it is ment but for the principle of political equality, which, though it
first attested associates it closely with the reforms of Cleisthenes. I
is of course more closely associated with a democratic constitu-
In other words, the appearance of laovop,la seems to be linked tion than with any other, is not necessarily confined to it.
with the beginnings of the Athenian democracy, and this, in turn, Chronological problems, less crucial for us than those besetting
suggests that the adoption of v6p,oc; as the technical term for the Harmodius skolia, also plague the second passage relevant to
'statute' to replace ewp,6c; forms part of the same picture. vVe our inquiry. Alcmaeon of Croton is said by Aristotle to have been
are faced, therefore, with two tasks: in the first place, we have to a contemporary of the old age ofPythagoras,2 Diogenes Laertius
demonstrate what precisely the meaning of laovop,la in its various and Iamblichus called him a pupil ofPythagoras,3 and other late
contexts is, and secondly we have to determine as accurately as authors called him a Pythagorean.4 A number ofmodern scholars,
we can what the date and the circumstances of the first appear- accordingly, date Alcmaeon's fioruit as about 500 B.C., roughly
ance are.2 contemporary with the reforms of Cleisthenes,5 or shortly there-
It is generally agreed that the earliest occurrence of the con-
cept, in the adjectival form la6vop,oc;, is to be found in two stanzas I e.g. vVilamowitz, AA 2. 319, Larsen, Cleisth. 6, and Vlastos, IP I, who, how-
of a song celebrating the tyrannicides Harmodius and Aristo- ever draws a distinction between luovOJ1-ia and DTJJ1-0KpaTia (pp. 7-10); cr. also
C. Meier, 'Drei Bemerkungen .. .' 4-18. That it is not a constitution is recognized
geiton, which Athenaeus includes in his collection of some by Ehrenberg, Ison. 297, and OD 535·
twenty-five Attic skolia or drinking songs.3However, since we can 2 Met. A, 986a29-30 (Ross): KaL yap [EY<VETO TryV ~'\LKiav] }1,\KJ1-aiwv [E7TL Y~POVTL
IIv8ayopq.J The bracketed words arc omitted in Ab .and are ther:fore beheved
glean little information from them about the meaning of laovop,la, by Ross to be a later addition. But, as Ross also recognIzes, the questIOn whether or
not they belong in the text of Met. docs not alfect the truth or falseness of the state-
1 Our discussion will be confined to the political kind of luovoJ1-la and will not ment itself. For the same reason Alexander of Aphrodisias' failure to take cog-
embrace that Epicurean luovoJ1-la which Cic. De nat. deorum I. 50 has Velleius trans- nizance of these words is of no significance; cr.
J. Wachtler, De Alcmaeone Crotoniata
late as 'aequabilem tributionem' and Cotta, ibid. I. 109, as 'aequilibritas'.
5~· .
Some scholars want to attribute the authorship of the Epicurean luovoJ1-la to 3 Diog. Laert. 8. 83; Iamblichus, De vita Pythagorica 104, where Alcmaeon I.Sals.o
Democritus, e.g. C. Mugler, 'L'isonomie des atomistes,' RPh 3e seL 30 (1956) enumerated among the young men who were contemporanes of Pythagoras III h,S
231-50, and S. Luria, 'Zwei Demokrit-Studien', in J. Mau and E. G. Schmidt old age; cf. also 267.
(edd.), Isonomia: Studien zur Gleichheitsvorstellung im griechischen Denken 37-54, esp. 4 Philoponus on Arist. De an. 405'29 (Hayduck, p. 88. II); scho!' P!. Ale. I
45-6. That even the Epicurean luovofLla 'fait, en elfet, partie de toute une suite de 121 e. Simplicius on Arist. De an. 405'29 (Hayd.uck, p. 32. 3-6) reports t~at he
metaphoresjuridiques appliquees it la cosmo logie' is shown by Mugler, op. cit. 232. was traditionally called a Pythagorean, but POllltS out correctly that Anstotle
2 I should like here to pay tribute to the work of three scholars to which, despite
dissociates him from the Pythagoreans.
some disagreements, the following discussion owes whatever value it possesses: V. 5 M. Wellmann, Archeion II (1929) 156 and Archivfiir Geschichte der Medizin 22
Ehrenberg (Ison.; OD, esp. 530-7), G. Vlastos (Ison.; IP), and J. A. O. Larsen (1929) 302-3, calls him a younger contemporary of Dem?cede~, who practised
(Cleisth.) . medicine first at the court of Polycrates of Samos and after hIS fall III 522 B.C. at the
3 Athenaeus 15. 694 c-695 f, esp. 695 a-b. The most recent text is that of Page, court of Darius; W. H. S.Jones, Bulletin of the History of Medicine, supp!. 8 (1946)
PitfG, Nos. 893 and 896, esp. line 4. 3, dates him c. 500 B.C., but admits, n. 5, the possibility of a date as late as 450
814277 H
98 NOMOI: BECOMES 'STATUTE'

after,! and regard him as a member of the Pythagorean schoo!'z Empedocles and Anaxagoras.! This would give us a date about
Now, it would of course be very strange indeed if a physician 450 B.C. for Alcmaeon's activity, and this date tallies well with
and scientist born in Croton at any point in the late sixth or in the statement that his life coincided with the end of Pythagoras'
the fifth century B.C. were to remain unaffected by the teachings life. For if we follow Guthrie in assuming that Pythagoras died
of Pythagoras or his disciples, and the combination of Alcmaeon's about 490 B.C. and that Alcmaeon may have written his book at
provenance with some more or less superficial similarities in doc- any time between the ages of thirty and seventy, we may conclude
trine was probably responsible for his classification as a Pytha- that he was born about 510 and was active between 480 and 440
gorean and as a pupil of the master.3 Still, to admit influence is B.C.2 The lower limit of this range becomes more likely if we ac-
a different matter from asserting membership in the sect. Aris- cept with K. von Fritz3 480 B.C. as the date of Pythagoras' death,
totle recognized this when he noted the similarity of Alcmaeon's for this date would enable us to assume 500 B.C. as the approxi-
penchant for pairs of opposites with the table of the Pythagoreans, mate year of Alcmaeon's birth.4
but, by leaving open the question 'whether he took this doctrine This brings us to the fragment which is preserved by Aetius :
from them or they from him', dissociated Alcmaeon from the
)1I\KfWLWV Tij, [LEV vyLELa, ElvaL UVVEKTLKr;V T~V lUOVo[LLaV TOW ovvapEWV,
Pythagoreans.4 More recently, Vlastos has proved after a close
vypoD, triPoD, .pvXpoD, 8EP[LoD, 7rLKpoD, yAvKEO' Ka1 TlJW 1\0L7TWV, T~V 0'
scrutiny of Alcmaeon's teachings that he was not a Pythagorean.s
EV aVTOr, fLOvapxtav vouov 7TOL1]TLK~V' </>80p07TOLOVyap EKaTEpov fLOvapXLav'
This still leaves us with the question of his dates. The only way in Ka1 VOUOV UV[L1TL7TTELVW, [LEV v</>' OU V7TEp{3ol\f; 8EP[LOT1]TO, ~ If;vXPOT1]TO',
which the statement that he was a contemporary of old Pytha- (V, OE E~ ou OLa 7TM"j80, Tpo</>Yje; ~ EVOELaV, W, 0' EV 0[, ~ (1TEp1 Diels)
goras can be checked is by comparing his doctrines with those of a[fw ~ [LvEAov ~ EyKE</>al\ov. EyyLvw8aL OE 7TOTE
TOl)TOL<; KaK TWV E~W(JEV
other physical thinkers, especially those with whom he shows the alTLwv, vOaTwv 7TOLWV ~ xwpa, ~ K07TWV ~ avaYK1], ~ TWV TOVTOL, 7Tapa-
closest affinity. Such comparisons have shown that Alcmaeon's 7T1\1]ULWV. T~V OE vyELav T~V UV[L[LETpOV TWV 7TOLWV KpiiuLV.5
work preceded the Hippocratic tract On ancient medicine and cer-
tainly the work of Democritus, but that he lived later than vVe have before us a paraphrase in indirect speech and not a
Heraclitus and was, perhaps in his later years, a contemporary of direct quotation, a paraphrase, moreover, which, as Diels already
remarked, shows traces of Peripatetic and Stoic contamination.6
B.C.; Larsen, Cleisth. 8, and Ehrenberg, OD 535, make him belong to the same Caution is, therefore, required in an attempt to extract Alc-
period as the Harmodius skolia. M. Pohlenz, Hippokrates und die Begriindung der maeon's views from Aetius' statement of them. \Ve can, however,
wissenschaftlichen Medizin 82, goes beyond anything the ancient evidence suggests
be confident that the words laovofl,{a and fwvapXLa formed a part
when he asserts that Hippocrates was born in (sic) 460 B.C., a generation after
Alcmaeon's death, thus placing Alcmaeon's death in c. 500 B.C. of Alcmaeon's original statement. For not only is the image
I W. Schmid and O. Stiihlin, Geschichte der griechischen Literatur 1. 1. 766, date created by their contrast so striking that it is not likely to have
him a little before Euryphon (mid-fifth century B.C.); Kirk and Raven 232 put his been introduced by a doxographer, but it is also very much in
floruit in the early fifth century B.C.
2 Schmid-Stiihlin, op. cit. 739; Ehrenberg, Ison. 296, Eun. 89, and OD 535; line with the practice of Presocratic thinkers to explain physical
Jones, op. cit. 3-4; J. L. Myres, CR 61 (1947) 82; Larsen, Cleisth. 9; and L. Edel-
stein, AJP 63 (1942) 371-2, who, however, wants to push his date down to [ The most recent full discussion is that of Guthrie, HGP I. 341-59, esp. 357-9.
'Socrates' time or even later'. Cf. also W. A. Heidel, Hippocratic Medicine 43 and 47. Jones, op. cit. 3 n. 5, believes
3 How little reliance can be placed on the Pythagorean label is shown by the that he preceded Empedocles and Anaxagoras.
inclusion in lamblichus' list (De Vita Pythagorica 104) of Philolaus, Archytas, and 2 Guthrie, HGP I. 357-8.
Leucippus as Pythagorean contemporaries of Pythagoras; see Kirk and Raven 233. 3 'Pythagoras', RE 47. Halbb. (1963) 184.
4 Met. A, 986'27-9: OV7T€P TprJ7TOV EO'K€ Kat 14AKJLalwv " KpOTWV'UT1JS tmOAa{3€LV, 4 I would not wish, however, to lower the date of Alcmaeon's activity as far as
Kat ifTOL OVTOS nap' EK€{VWV ~ EKELVOI, 7Tupa TOVTOU 1TapiAa{30V TOV AOyOV TOVTOV. 430 B.C.
5 Vlastos, Ison. 344-7, accepted now by Ehrenberg, HL 67 n. 23. The same 5 For this text and its translation see Endnote, pp. 177-8 below.
conviction was already expressed by \Vachtler, op. cit. 88, and by W. A. Heidel, 6 H. Diels, Doxographi Graeci 223-4: 'miserrime invrrsum est Alcmaeonis de
AJP 61 (1940) 3-6 and Hippocratic Medicine 43; and it is stated again by Guthrie, sanitate placitum V 30 1 ubi Peripatetic a de quattuor causis c10ctrina Stoicorum
HGP I. 341. 7TOWLS mire copulata est.'
phenomena in political or social images.! It is safe, therefore, to automatically mean that every feature of the image must corre-
assume that Alcmaeon used luovoflia and fLovapx{a not as medical spond to every aspect of the thing which it is called in to explain.
but as political concepts intended merely to help him expound And yet, since the fragment contains no clue which would lend
certain facts about the (human) body by analogy with certain itself to a different method and since, as we shall see, its results
features in the state.Z This means that it is immaterial for an will be internally consistent, we must take either this precarious
understanding of the fragment to speculate whether Alcmaeon route or none at all.
preferred one form of government to another or whether his ex- The mere fact that luovofL{a is here opposed to one-man rule,
periences in Croton mayor may not be reflected in his choice of as it is in the Harmodius skolia, has led some scholars to believe
this contrast.3 In the first place, we know too little about the his- that opposition to tyranny is the primary factor inherent in
tory of Croton at this time and the part Alcmaeon mayor may luovofL{a, and the conviction that luovofL{a began as an aristocratic

not have played in the attempt to make the government of the notion, which was only later appropriated by the Cleisthenean
'Thousand' more democratic4 to use it to elucidate the possible democracy, almost made this beliefnecessary.! But the refutation
meaning of luovofL{a in this fragment, and secondly, the contrast of that view by Vlastos enables us to see the tenor of the Alcmaeon
between luovofL{a and fLovapx{a must have been sufficiently familiar fragment in a different light.z We must begin with fLovapx{a,
to Alcmaeon's contemporaries in a general way to make its which is defined more precisely than is luovofL{a. In attributing
metaphorical use here intelligible to them without previous in- destructiveness to the fLovapx{a EKaTEpov and in citing the excess
quiry into his personal convictions.s Accordingly, the only method of heat or cold as one of the causes of disease, the fragment defines
by which we can hope to gain an insight into Alcmaeon's mean- fLovapx{a as the preponderance or supremacy of one in a pair of
ing is to assume that Aetius' epitome, though couched in the opposite powers over the other, making, as it were, the hot abso-
language of Hellenistic eclecticism, correctly reflects Alcmaeon's lute ruler over the cold, or the dry over the wet, or the sweet
ideas, and to reverse Alcmaeon's analogy by drawing conclusions over the bitter. In other words, fLovapx{a is not envisaged in
from the physical to the political connotations of luovofL{a and terms of the dominance of one quality or power over all the other
fLovapx{a. This procedure is hazardous in that it does violence to five (or more), but simply as the preponderance of one member of
Alcmaeon's emphasis. For him, as we saw, the political image was a pair of opposites over the other.3 Since such a preponderance is,
an aid to the exposition of medical phenomena, and this does not according to the fragment, alone sufficient to cause disease, there
was no need for Alcmaeon to consider the possibility, articulated
I e.g. Anaximander's doctrine of Q{Wf} and TLau, (frg. !), which is taken by Vlas- by later medical men,4 that the same body might simultaneously
tos, Ison. 362, as embodying a doctrine similar to that of laoFop.La here. See also
Heraclitus' doctrines of 1TO)..EP.OS (frgg. 53 and 80) ; of the Erinyes as helpers of Dike exhibit a supremacy of both the hot over the cold and of the dry
keeping the sun in check (frg. 94) ; and the relation between FOILOS and the tWOF over the wet, an eventuality which, if Alcmaeon had wished to
(frg. ! 14). Empedocles' doctrine of Love and Strife is also relevant here, especially apply the political metaphor consistently and exhaustively, he
frg. 30, where NElKOS is said to come €S TLp.as.
2 L. Mac Kinney, 'The Concept of Isonomia in Greek ~1edicine' in Mau and would presumably have characterized as an oligarchy. This point
Schmidt, op. cit. 79-88, fails to recognize that laoFop.La is fundamentally a deserves to be made in order to show that the contrast between
political concept, the application of which to medical matters can only be meta- fLovapx{a and luovofL{a is not necessarily exhaustive, and that it
phorical.
3 This point is well made by Vlastos, Ison. 363-5 with nn. 83-7.
does not necessarily imply that oligarchy was unknown to Alc-
4 Iamblichus, De vita Pythagorica 257. maeon. If he did not need it for his purposes in this fragment,
5 General considerations make it likely, however, that Alcmaeon favoured
laOJ'op.La over p.oFapxLa. Since pre-Aristotelian and particularly pre-Socratic I Ehrenberg, Ison. 296, and OD 535; Larsen, Cleisth. 8.
thinkers tend to regard human and natural phenomena as part of one Koap.os, 2 Ison. 339-44, and IP 10-12.
Alcmaeon would not have wished to define laoFop.La as good for the body but bad 3 This point is missed completely by MacKinncy, op. cit. 79 with n. I, who
for the state. For the persistence of this notion we have to think only of Plato's arbitrarily changes the correct translation of €KUTEPOV, which he found in Kirk and
Timaeus and, especially for our purposes here, of the qualitative identity of in- Raven, to 'any'.
dividual and state in Rep. 2. 369 c-4. 445 c. 4 Cited and discussed in Galen, De temperamentis 1. 2 (510-18 Kuhn I).
that does not mean that under diftlTcnt circumstances la()vojJ~tu a one-to-one qualitative correspondence; quantitative considera-
might not be opposed to oligarchy as well as to monarchy.l tions, which play a more crucial part in modern science, are
'!aovop.,[u is defined only as 'that which holds health together' almost totally lacking or only at an inchoate stage of develop-
(Tij<; vyudu<; aVVEKTLK~V). But the definition of health which ap- menU While the notion of a well-proportioned mixture occurs
pears at the end of [Plutarch],s part of the fragment enables us frequently in the Hippocratic corpus, I have found no example of
to go beyond this and to infer from the description of j1.ovuPXtu a verbal combination of aVj1.j1.ETptU or its cognates with Kpiim<;,
what precisely this 'bond of health' is. According to his para- or their cognates.2 They rather tend to conjoin Kpiim<; with
j1.ErgL<;,
phrase health is ~ aUj1.j1.ETpO<; TWV 7TOLWV Kpom<;, 'the well- j1.ETpW<; or its adverb to express a balanced mixture of two

proportioned mixture of the qualities'. The Stoic terminology elements,3 although similar conjunctions also describe a balance
used here makes it unlikely that these words are an exact quota- involving more than two factors.4 But with Aristotle and his
tion from Alcmaeon, but the idea of health as a mixture is so successors, among whom are to be numbered the doxographers
common in Hippocratic and later Greek medicine,2 and of the to whom we owe the preservation of Alcmaeon's fragment, the
cosmos as a mixture so current in Presocratic philosophy,3 that it combination of aVj1.j1.ETptU and Kpom<; begins to appear consis-
would be surprising if Alcmaeon, with his penchant for opposites,4 tently as an expression for a mixture involving the balance of two
had not defined it in a similar way.5 We may assume, therefore, elements only. Aristotle's definition of health, for example, is in
that [Plutarch]'s words correctly reflect the essence of Alcmaeon's the Physics couched in terms very similar to the Alcmaeon frag-
original statement. ment: vytELUV KUL E!JEgtUV EVKpaaEL KUL aVj1.j1.ETptq. 8Epj1.WV KUL
What is of greater interest for our purposes, however, is that if;vxpwv Tt8Ej1.EV;5 and in the De partibus animalium he speaks of
the mixture which is health is described as aUj1.j1.ETpO<;. The con-
cept of a aUj1.j1.ETpO<; Kpom<; is not uncommon in the Greek medical remarks on aV!"!"€TpOS are confined to its meaning in the expression aV!"!"€TpOS
Kpaa's. There are passages, especially in Galen, which suggest that aV!"!"€Tp{a may
writers as well as in the doxographers, and it describes the com- in other contexts refer to the commensurability of more than two entities; see, for
mensurability of two and only two qualities, powers, humours, example, Galen's account of the Ganon of Polyclitus in DK6 I. 391. 24 and 29-36.
I Cf. Vlastos, op. cit. 157. Festugiere, op. cit. 41-3 gives reasons for believing
conditions, or other factors.6 This commensurability is seen as
that Hippocratic medicine was groping toward exact quantitative measurement.
I The formation oA,yapx- is, as far as can be judged, no older than the formation 2 The question whether or not the Hippocratic writers differentiate between
S'7!"oKpaT-, which is first attested in the treaty with Colophon of 447/6 B.C., see IG KpaaLS and !,,€,t,s (and their respective cognates) still awaits treatment. I am reluc-
12• 15.37 = ATL 2. D 15.48. Herodotus is the earliest literary source for both tant to assume with Jaeger, op. cit. 240 n. 13, that there is no sharp distinction
oA,yapx- and S'7!"OKpaT-; see A. Debrunner, "LJ'7!"oKpaTia", Festschrift fiir Edouard between them in the fifth century B.C. Aristotle differentiates between the two in
Tieche I 1-24, esp. 15-16. Even if the noun oA,yapxia was not available to Alcmaeon, Top. 4. 2, 122b26-31 and 123"4, as does Alexander of Aphrodisias, De mixtione 3
he might have used a periphrasis to describe it. My point here is merely that the (Bruns 216. 28-217. 2), paraphrasing Chrysippus.
fragment cannot be used to prove that Alcmaeon knew only two forms of govern- 3 e.g. On Ancient Medicine 5 (ad fin.) : patients should be given drink commen-
ment. surate with their bodily condition: Tiiai T€ Kp~a€(J' Kat TiP 1TA..jOELStar/JVM.aaovTES ,os
2 See the passages cited by A.-J. Festugiere, Hippocrate: L'Ancienne Mldecine !"€Tp{WS EXO'; or On regimen 3. 69: disease results if exertion and food do not
(= Etudes et Gommentaires 4) 37-8. Cf. G. Vlastos, 'Equality and Justice in Early J.L€Tp{W~ EXEL 71'POS aAA1]Au ... a7To of: TOU larl~€Lv -rrpos crAATJAa vy€LTJ 7TpOUEGTLV. Further
Greek Cosmologies', GP 42 (1947) 156-78, esp. 156-8, and G. E. R. Lloyd, passages with discussion in Festugiere, loco cit. The notion of mixture in Hippo-
Polarity and Analogy 20-1. cratic medicine is ably discussed by C. W. Muller, Gleiches zu Gleichem: Ein Prinzip
3 e.g. Parmenides, frgg. 9, l2, and 16, cr. 8. 55-61; Empedoc1es, frgg. 8,17.4-8 friihgriechischen Denkens (= Klassisch-philologische Studien 31) 142-5.-Cf. Thuc. 8.
and 16-20,21, esp.line 14,22, and 26; Anaxagoras, frgg. 4, 6,10,12, and 17. 97.2 (on the government of the Five Thousand) : !,,€Tpia yap ~ T€ ES TOUS o'\{YOVS Kat
4 Cf. Arist. Met. A, 986a31-4; Diog. Laert. 8. 83. TOUS 1TOA'\OUS tVyKpaa,s, terminology which may well have been borrowed from
5 W. Jaeger, The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers 1 57 and 226 n. 48, is Greek medicine.
probably right in asserting that the concept of mixture played a central part in 4 e.g. the four humours in On the Nature of Man 4.-0n the idea of symmetry
Greek medicine before Parmenides introduced it into philosophy. On Parmenides' and proportion in the Hippocratic writers in general see W. Jaeger, Paideia 3
role in making mixture a central concept in Greek natural science see O. Gigon, (Engl. trans.) 27.
Del' Ursprung del' griechischen Philosophie 273-4. 5 7.3, 246b4-6: '\Ve ascribe health and well-being to a mixture and proportion
6 Only the absence of complete concordances to the Greek medical writers of hot and cold elements.' Cf. Top. 6. 2, 139b21 and 6.6, 145b8, where health is
prevents me from saying that this is invariably the case. I must emphasize that my defined as a aV!"I-'€Tp{a of hot and cold elements. Alexander of Aphrodisias,
fluxes beginning in the head when 'the elements about the brain aVfLfLETpOS" KpaaLS TWV 7TOtWV is thus the precise opposite of the
are colder than the well-proportioned mixture'. I In the doxo- fLovapx{a EKaTEpov, and since, moreover, the bond of health is de-
graphy the expression appears in Empedocles' attribution of the fined as the laovofL{a TWV OvvafLEwv, we may conclude that in this
origin of trees to the aVfLfLETp{a TijS" KpaaEwS" in them, which en- fragment both aVfLfLETpOS KpaatS" and laovofL{a describe a balance
compasses the formula ("-0Y0S") for male and female,2 in Theo- between the two opposites in a given pair in which neither one
phrastus' criticism of Anaxagoras' theory of sensation, where he dominates the other.I It is not stated explicitly, nor need it be,
asserts that the relation of perceived object and perception stands any more than it needed to be stated in the case of fLovapx{a, that
EV aVfLfLETp{q. TLV~Ka~ KpaaEt,3 in his account of Diogenes' theory of health requires balance within all pairs of opposite powers, that is,
smell as coming about when the air about the brain is TV KpaaEt that it requires as many laovofL{at as there are pairs of opposites.
aVfLfLETpOS with the odour perceived,4 and in his description of For, since the imbalance of anyone pair is sufficient to destroy
Democritus' view that thinking presupposes a well-proportioned the fabric of health as a whole, there is no reason to discussin this
mixture of the elements of the soul, but that the mind wanders context what would happen if more than one pair were to be out
when it gets too hot or too cold.S Among the medical writers it is of balance. Nor does the fragment explicitly state that health
Galen's De temperamentis (Greek: 7TEP~KpaaEwv) which shows best requires also some kind of balance between powers that are not
that a aVfLfLETpOS"Kpoms involves only two terms, and the terms in formally opposites of one another, for example between the hot
this treatise are always the paired opposites of the powers dry- and the wet or between the cold and the dry, any more than it en-
wet and hot-cold.6 visaged in the case of fLovapx{a that one power might dominate
These medical and doxographic parallels leave no doubt what- all the rest. A balance of this kind would probably have had to
ever that in Aetius' opinion Alcmaeon, too, conceived of health be expressed by the term laOfLotp{a rather than by laovofLLa. For
as a mixture of the two powers or qualities that belong to the the doxographers as well as the medical writers use laofLotp{a
same pair of opposites.7 Since the condition characterized as the whenever they want to describe the balance of all elements in a
Quaestiones I. 9 (Bruns 19. 30-2) is probably dependent on Aristotle: EV floEV yap TV mixture,2 and in the language of law and politics laofLOtp{a is the
T<VV OvvafloEwv TOVTWV [sc. 8EPflo0T'l' .pVXpOT'l' VypOT'l' ~'lPOT'l'] 1TpO, uAA'lAa avflo- regular word for describing the balanced sharing of-usually--
floETpiC[ ~ vyEia. Cf. the Stoic definition in Chrysippus, frg. 471 (v. Arnim 3. 121):
A€YETat DE ElvaL (JwJLaTO~ voaoS' ~ aaVJLfL€Tpla TWV Ell U1.JT0, OEpp..OU KUf. ljivxPov, ~YJPofj
more than two parties in the same thing.3 It should, however, be
Kat vypofJ •..• ~ 8' EV 7ip aWfLun vy{na EUKpaa[a TLS' Kat aUJLp,erp{a TWV OtTlPYJILe-I-'WV noted that the difference between these two ideas resides less in
<0' Elp'lflo<vWV), the number of parties involved than in the fact that laofLotp{a is
I 2. 7, 652b36: (laOl<; av n TO. 1TEp' TOV EyK<q,aAov .pVXPOTEpa aVfloflo<TpOV KpaaEW"
always treated as a general concept, applicable wherever there is
2 Aetius 5. 26.4 (=Doxographi Graeci 438. 21-439. 4=DK6 31. A 70). Cf.
Theophrastus' criticism of Empedocles' doctrine of sensation, De sensibus 12-15 something to be 'equally shared', whereas laovofL{a remains basi-
(= Dox. 502. 25-503. 29 = DK6 3 I. A 86), beginning: (lAw, yap 1TOld TryV flo'~tV cally a social and political concept.4
TV aVflofloETpiC[ TWV 1TOpWV. 3 De sensibus 32 (= Dox. 508.18-21).
4 Ibid. 39 and 41 (= Dox. 510.15-18 and 51 I. 2-4 = DK6 64. A 19). See also I So also Festugiere, op. cit. XXIII.
Theophrastus' criticism of this doctrine, ibid. 46 (= Dox. 512.11-14). 2 For the doxographers, see, for example, Empedocles in Aetius 5. 19. 5 (= Dox.
5 Ibid. 58 (= Dox. 5 I 5. 22-5 = DK6 68. A 135) : 1TEp' oE TOV q,pOVE'V E1Tt ToaovTOV 430-1 = DK6 31. A 72); the Pythagoreans in Theophrastus, Metaphysica 33
ELp1]KEV, o'n Y{VETUt aUfLJLETpWS EXOVU1]S TfjS ¢JvxiJs Kuru T~V Kpaaw· Jav Sf 7TEpl8EP/-L()S' (= DK6 58. B 14) ; and Pythagoras in Diog. Laert. 8. 26. For the medical writers
7<, ~ 1TEpi.pvXpo, y<V'lTal, floETaAAaTTHI' q,'laL. For some excellent remarks on the see, for example, the Hippocratic On Airs, Waters, and Places 12. 18-19 (Jones) and
meaning of aVflofloETpia in Theophrastus see H. Frankel, H'ege und Formenfruhgriechi- Galen, De temperamentis I. 4 (K. I 526-7 and 533-4), 9 (K. I 564), and 2. I (K. I
schen Denkens2 175-6. 573). Cf. [Arist.] De mundo 5, 396b35. In this context belongs also Soph. El. 87: yill"
6 De temperamentis (Helmreich) I. 6 (K. I 542, 544, 547-8, and 550), 8 (K. I la0flo0Lp' d~p, although only two commensurables are involved. The fact that lao-
557); 2. 2 (K. I 595), 4 (K. I 606-7 and 610) ; and 3. 4 (K. I 678). flo0lpia usually refers to more than two elements does not, of course, mean that it
7 Cf. Eryximachus in PI. Symp. 186 d, who regards it as the function of the can never be used to describe a balance involving only two.
physician to engender 'love' in each of the same pairs of opposites as those 3 See Endnote, p. 178 below.
enumerated in Alcmaeon's fragment: oEf yap Ory 7(' Ex8taTa ana EV T0 aWfloa7( q,iAa 4 \Vhenever it occurs in other contexts, it is as a metaphor or symbol borrowed
OlDV ..,' ElvaL 1TOtEiv Kat, Epiiv dAA~"WV. EGn oJ EX8LUTU Ta EvavnWTUTU, tf;vxpov 8EpfL<P, from the life of society, as here in Alcmaeon's fragment. It is, therefore, not
1TLKpOV 'YAUKEr, t'YJPov uypcp, 7TQVTU Tel TO"UtJTU 1 a 'medical formula' (Vlastos, op. cit. 156), since, despite its usefulness in describing
For Alcmaeon, then, laovoflia is a balance in the body politic, The nature of laOVOf{{a is further elucidated by three passages in
seen as the equilibrium of two 'powers'. What Alcmaeon thought Herodotus. 1 All three resemble the Harmodius skolia and the
these two powers were is harder to ascertain. While it is tempting Alcmaeon fragment in that iaovofl{a is opposed to tyranny, yet
to identify them with the terms in which Thucydides praised the there are clear indications that opposition to tyranny is not the
government of the Five Thousand (8. 97. 2) as a flETp{a gVyKpam, essential meaning of the term.2 This emerges most decisively from
of the few and the many, there is no suggestion whatever in the the most famous of these passages (3. 80. 2-82), the Debate of the
fragment that Alcmaeon may have had the same elements in three Persian nobles, which followed the overthrow of the false
mind, and it is extremely unlikely that quantities such as 'the Smerdis,3 where laovofl{a is opposed not only to one-man-rule-
many' and 'the few' would have found a place in his doctrines. 1 called, without any difference in meaning, Tvpavv{, or flovvapX{YJ
We depend, therefore, entirely on inferences drawn from Aetius' -but also to oligarchy. That Otanes, the champion of laovofl{YJ in
paraphrase, and this does not provide us with a very solid founda- the Debate, proposes in effect the establishment of a democratic
tion. Yet it is perhaps not entirely unwarranted to see a clue form of government in Persia is explicitly stated by Herodotus
again in the treatment of flovapx{a. For if flovapx{a denotes the later in his work.4 \Vhile this is sufficient to prove the close con-
supremacy of one power over only one other power, it is hard nection between laovofl{YJ and DYJfloKpaT{YJ in Herodotus, it still
to see what these powers might be, except ruler and ruled. If leaves open the problem to which we must now address our-
Alcmaeon's meaning, then, is that monarchy consists in an excess selves: is laovofl{YJ here merely a synonym of DYJfloKpaT{YJ, as
of power on one side and a deficiency of it on the other, we may some scholars have maintained,s or, if not, what is the distinction
infer that under laovofl{a the power of those who govern is between the two?
balanced by the power of those who are governed. Further than To answer this question intelligently, we first have to examine
this we cannot go, nor can we determine in what terms Alcmaeon the other two passages in which Herodotus uses the noun. The
may have thought of these two powers in balance with each earlier of these (3. 142-3), dated in the same year as the Debate
other. The concept of rotation in office, for example, through (522 B.C.), appears in the story of Maeandrius' attempt to re-
which the Athenian democracy achieved its balance, was as nounce the tyranny over Samos, which he had inherited from
familiar to the physicians of the fifth century as it was to its Polycrates. The motive for the renunciation which Herodotus
political practitioners,2 but there is no indication that we have puts into his mouth is his adherence to an equalitarian principle,
here in Alcmaeon an anticipation of the later definition of his dislike that anyone man, including Polycrates, should lord
democracy as the form of government whose citizens rule and are it over men like unto himself.6 How seriously Maeandrius takes
ruled in turn.3 That the term laovofl{a as used by Alcmaeon has his equalitarianism is shown by the words in which he casts his
closer affinities with democracy than with any other form of decision: EYW DE E, flEaov T0v aPx0v TLBEt, laovofl{YJV UflrV npo-
government cannot be doubted. But it is noteworthy that he uses ayopEVw. Two points in this phraseology are revealing. The con-
as the opposite of flovapx{a not DYJfloKpaT{a, which nakedly denotes stitutional innovation which Maeandrius offers the Samians is
the 'rule of the people', but a term which in some way expresses expressed in words almost identical with those in which Herodotus
the principle of equality-the equality of vOflO, for ruler as well had summed up the essence of Otanes' position in the Debate :7
as for ruled-which a democracy embodies. I Herodotus uses only the noun, and not iaovoiJ-os or iaovoiJ-€w.
2 See the criticisms of Ehrenberg and Larsen made by Vlastos, IP 5 n. 2. The
a medical phenomenon, its true sphere of application remains political. See also E. opposition of the two is also over-emphasized by Leveque and Vidal-Naquet,
Will, Korinthiaka 618-19; P. Leveque and P. Vidal-Naquet, Clisthhze l'athinien 31; op. cit. 28-9.
and above, p. 96 n. 1 ad fin. 3 See Endnote, pp. 178~9 below.
I On the absence of quantitative considerations see Vlastos, op. cit. 157, and 4 G. 43. 3: WS xP€OV ,,') o1JiJ-oKpaT€wIJa, n':paus.
Festugiere, op. cit. 41-3. 2 See Vlastos, op. cit. 158. 5 e.g. Larsen, Clcisth. 6-7, and Ehrenberg, OD 526.
3 The earliest extant definition along these lines is in Eur. Suppl. 406-8. Cf. 6 142. 3: O€O'1TO'WlJ dvSpwv OfLOLWV €WVT4J.
Arist. Pol. 6.2, 1317a4o-b3, 1317bI8-20. 7 3. 80. 2: ES iJ-€aov IUpa'[)a' KUTUIJ"VU' 7<, 7TP>7YiJ-UTU.
by 'placing the rule in the middle' he offers any citizen the right Demaratus attribute the freedom of the Spartans not to their
to hold high office. That any and every citizen is meant is shown institutions but to the principle of the rule of vOfJ0<; which pre-
by the fact that the speech is made before an assembly of all vails among them (7. I04. 4-5),' and he attributes to the principle
Samians, convoked by Maeandrius himself. I There can, ac- of luYJYop{YJ, won by the Athenians after their liberation from
cordingly, be no doubt but that the new constitution offered by tyranny, the victories of the young democracy over the Boeotians
l\1aeandrius in place of tyranny is a democratic form of govern- and Chalcidians in 506 B.C. (5. 78).2 Although these parallels do
ment. More revealing still is the second point, the choice of the not constitute proof that luovofJ{YJ in Maeandrius' speech refers to
phrase luovop-L-'lv vp-tv 7TpoayopEvw. The verb usually employed by a political principle rather than to a form of government in which
Herodotus as well as by other Greek prose authors for the estab- EAEV8Ep{YJ is embodied, they tend at least to support this view.
lishment of a new form of government is Ka(){uTYJIUz or, when the The second passage which will help us understand the meaning
change from one constitution to another is stressed, fJE8{UTYJlu.3 of luovofJ{YJ in the Debate of the Persian nobles is the description
Nowhere in classical Greek texts, as far as I know, is a verb of the measures taken by Aristagoras to prepare for the Ionian
meaning 'to declare' or 'to proclaim' found to express either of Revolt: KU~ 7TpWTU fJEv AOYlti fJETE~<; T~V Tvpaw{oa luovofJ{YJv E7TO{EE
these ideas. Accordingly, the luovofJ{YJ proclaimed by Maean- Tfj MtA~Tlti, w<; av EKOVTE<; UI}T{:jJ OL MtA~UW£ uvvu7T£ura{aTo, fJETU OE
drius, however closely related to democracy, is not identical with KU~ EV Tfj aAAn ' !wv{17 (5·37. 2). Aristagoras'
TWVTO ToflTO E7TO{EE
it. The only alternative is that it is the principle of political grant of luovofJ{YJ is part and parcel of the same democratic senti-
equality, and that this is the case here is indicated by a number of ments current in Asia Minor about this time of which Herodotus
circumstantial features in the story, especially by Maeandrius' speaks in connection with his narrative of the events of 5 I 2 and
equalitarian motives and his offer to make high office accessible again of 492 B.C. This sentiment is used in 512 B.C. by Histiaeus,
to all. The expression T~V EAEV8Ep{YJV VfJLV 7TEptT{8YJfJt, with which fearful of the tyrants' fate without Darius' support, as an argu-
he sums up his offer at the end of his speech, as well as his founda- ment against the revolt of Ionia from Persian rule,3 and Mar-
tion ofa cult of Zeus Eleutherios (3. 142.2,4), points in the same donius took cognizance of it in 492 B.C., when he deposed the
direction.4 For although later Greek political thought saw a close tyrants and established democracies in the Ionian cities in
relation between EAw8Ep{a and democracy,S Herodotus, in the order to protect the rear of his projected expedition to the north
only other two passages in which he links EAw8Ep{a to a form of coast of the Aegean.4 So also here Aristagoras tries to capitalize
government, neither confines the connection to democracy nor on democratic sentiments, when he grants the Milesians luovofJ{YJ
speaks of it as inherent in a form of government as such. He makes to enlist their support for his planned rebellion. What precisely
does this luovofJ{YJ entail? According to Herodotus' narrative,
I 142.2: EKKX1u'T}V uuvaydpas mlvTwv TWV aUTwv. On the importance of this see
Vlastos, IP 6 with n. 3. I On the relation between <Awe,pia and vO/-,os in Herodotus see the stimulating
2 Hdt. 5. 92T}. 5,6.43.3, 131. I; Tlmc. 1. 115. 3,4. 74·3, 8.72; Andoc. 1. 97, 2. essay by K. von Fritz, 'Die griechische <AWefp,a bei Herodot', H!iener Studien 78
27; Lysias 2.18,12.42,13.12; Arist. Ath. Pol. 29. I and 3, Pol. 2.12, 1273b38, etc. (1965) 5-3 I, csp. 5-25.
3 Thuc. 4. 76. 2, 8. 75. 2; Arist. Pol. 2. 12, 1274'7, etc. When it is emphasized 2 That lUT}yopiT} refers to a democratic principle here is generally recognized.
that the change comes from within, /-'ETafJaXXw is used, e.g. PI. Rep. 8. 555 b, 562 a. \Vhat is more difficult to understand is its use here (as also at Dem. 15. 18) as the
Arist. Ath. Pol. 41. 2 uses the nouns /LETafJoX~ and /-,fTauTau<s to describe the cardinal principle to describe democracy as such, since there seems to be no
constitutional changes in Athens. logical connection between free speech and the defeat of the Boeotians and Chal-
4 The fact that Maeandrius wants to retain the priesthood of the new cult for cidians. Still, that lUT}yopia is characteristic only of a democratic form of govern-
himself and his descendants does not affect the argument.-On the relation of ment is well shown by G. T. Griffith, 'lsegoria in the Assembly at Athens',
luovo/-,'T} and EXEVefp'T} in this passage ef. Herodotus' caustic remark, after the dis- Ancient Society and Institutions:. Studies Presented to Victor Ehrenberg on his 75th Birthday
belief of the Samians in Maeandrius' sincerity had prevented them from getting the 115-38, and A. G. \Voodhead, "'IuT}yopia and the Council of 500", Historia 16
laovOflIfJ offered to theIn, au yap 3~, W~ oi'KUat, Ef30VAOVTO E:[VUL tA.€VB€POL (3. 143.2). (1967) 129-40.
5 See, for example, Arist. Pol. 4. 4., 1291b34-5 (where EAEVefpia and luoTT}s are 3 4. 137. 2: OT}/WKpaTfWea< /-,8:A'\OV ~ TUpaVVnJWea<.
the main characteristics of democracy), 5. 9, 1310'28-32, and especially 6. 2, 4 6. 43. 3: 'TOUr; yap TUprivvou~ TWV ' ]wvwv KUTu1Tuvaus 7TuvTas 0 Map3oVLG~
13 Q'4o-bl 7· 0TJ/LOKPUTLUS KUTLUTU ES Tas 7TO.\LUS.
110 NOMOI: BECOMES 'STATUTE'

Aristagoras did nothing about setting up a democracy in Miletus they must have included not only the right of all citizens to par-
and little, if anything, about establishing democracies in the ticipate in the election of the officialswho were to rule in Arista-
other Ionian cities whose tyrants he deposed. The connotations of goras' absence, but also, if we are justified in drawing inferences
,\oYo/ leave no doubt but that, in Herodotus' view, Aristagoras' from Maeandrius' use of the word in his offer to the Samians, the
abdication was a sham, and that it was is corroborated in the right of all citizens to be candidates for election to high office.
sequel in that the effective control of the state remained firmly in Moreover, these rights must have been sufficient to maintain
his hands. In the case of the other cities, we only learn that he orderly government in Miletus during Aristagoras' journey to
ordered the citizens to appoint generals;1 there is no talk about mainland Greece, and the response of the Milesians shows that
laovofl-{YJ here, nothing is said about the method of appointing the Aristagoras had gone some way in satisfying their desire for
generals, and nothing about their functions. There is, in other democracy.
words, no indication at all whether the deposition of the tyrants We can now return to our point of departure and examine
led to the establishment of a new form of government or whether what light these two passages throw on the most elaborate dis-
the generals merely assumed the powers previously exercised by cussion of laovofJ-{YJ in Herodotus, the Debate of the three Persian
the tyrants.2 At any rate, Herodotus states clearly that the final nobles. We noted before that Otanes' proposal, summed up by
end of tyranny in Ionia and its replacement by democracies had Herodotus as II EpaVat laovofJ-{YJv a7TEUowv 7TOtfjaat (3. 83. I), is later
to wait until Mardonius needed Ionian support in 492 B.C. What, paraphrased as elis XPEOV ELYJ 0YJfJ-oKpaTEW8at IIEpaas (6. 43·3),
then, is the meaning of laovofl-{YJv E7TO{EE Tfj Mt'\~To/, if it does not thus establishing a close link between laovofJ-{YJ and democracy.
signify the establishment of a democratic form of government? On the other hand, the Maeandrius and Aristagoras passages
That the grant of laovofl,{YJ was, unlike the abdication, not a sham have taught us that laovofJ-{YJ is not a form of government but
is shown verbally by the position of '\0Yo/, which refers only to a political principle. Does the use of laovofJ-{YJ in the Debate sup-
fJ-ETEiS T~V Tvpavv{oa, not to laovofl-{YJv E7TO{EE, and historically by port our findings and, if so, can we learn more from it about the
the fact that it achieved the result intended in that the Milesians nature of laovofJ-{YJ ?
remained loyal to Aristagoras during his absence in Sparta and It is peculiar that despite Otanes' espousal of the democratic
Athens, and continued their struggle against Darius even after cause the word 0YJfJ-0KpaT{a or its cognates do not occur in any
the Athenians withdrew their support (5. 38. 2, 103. I). In view part of the Debate.l Megabyzus and Darius refer to the form of
of this, Herodotus can only mean that Aristagoras succeeded in government proposed by him variously as ES TlJ 7T,\fj80s • • •
granting the Milesians rights similar to those which Maeandrius epEPELVTO KpaTos (3. 81. I), O~fJ-o/ .•• xpaa8wv (3·81. 3), and
had not succeeded in granting the Samians. Knowing that with- o~fJ-ov •.. apxovTo, (3.82.4), and Otanes himself speaks of 7T'\fj-
out his leadership and organization the revolt would make no 80, apxov (3. 80. 6). These expressions are the closest approxima-
headway, he could not possibly have gone all the way in giving tions to the concept of 'popular rule' and therefore the closest
the Milesians the 0YJfJ-0KpaT{YJwhich they desired and in entrusting
the management of affairs to the people as a whole. But he could [ The explanation given by Larsen, Cleisth. 6, and accepted by Vlastos, IP 3
n. 5, that the word 0TJll.OKPU·rLU was not yet available when this passage was written,
give them a greater degree of political equality than they had is unsatisfactory. For it assumes either that a considerable time elapsed between
enjoyed before, even while reserving for himself an 'unequal' the composition of 3. 80. 2-82 and that of 6.43. 3 and 13I. I, where 0TJJ1-0KpUT{U is
status, which would be meaningless, anyway, during his absence used, or that Herodotus took the Debate from an earlier source which did not yet
know the term 0TJJ1-0KpUT{U. The first assumption is highly dubious, because a gap
abroad. 'Ve are not told what concrete form these rights took, but wide enough for this development in political terminology cannot be posited for
the composition of Herodotus' work, even if we do not accept R. Lattimore's view
I 5. 38. 2: a'TpaTYjYov~ fV €KauTT/ TWV 71'oA.{wv K€A€vaas- €KaUTOV$" KaTaaT~aat. ('The Composition of the "History" of Herodotus', CP 53 [1958] 9-21, esp. 9)
2 If Aristagoras' own procedure in Milctus can be taken as a guide, the two that it is 'a continuous piece of writing which Herodotus set down from beginning
generals to whom the leadership of the revolt was entrusted were not democrati- to end in the order in which we now have it'. For the improbability of the second
cally elected but appointed by Aristagoras himself, see 5. 99. 2. assumption, see Endnote to p. 107 below, pp. 178-9.
equivalent to 8YI/.LOKpaTLa in this passage. It is, in fact, 7rAfj80s institutions which manifest it in the Debate are perhaps found
apxov which Otanes sets out to define in the passage which most most consistently in democratic forms of government but they
concerns us here: 7rAfj80s oE apxov 7rpWTa fJ-Evovv0fJ-a mlvTwv KaA- are not confined to democracies. This shows again that tUOv0fJ-La
AWTOV EXEt, tUOV0fJ-LYJV,8EVTEpa 8E T01)TWV TWV a
fJ-0vvapxos 7rodEt is the principle of political equality; it is not a constitutional
,~,
OVOEV' '\
7ral\i.p ' , apxas
fJ-EVyap , '" apxEt, V7rEV
"8 ~"'"apxYJv EXEt, ~OVI\EV-
vvov OE P \ ' form, and it ensures for all citizens an equal chance to be elected
fJ-aTa 8E 7ravTa ES TO KOLVOVaVa,pEpEt (3. 80. 6). I for office, an equality in holding magistrates accountable for
It is important to bear in mind that the statement is made their official acts, and an equal opportunity to participate in the
about the 7rAfj80s apxov, not about tUOV0fJ-LYJ,which is merely the shaping of policies.1
first and positive part of the two things said about the 7rAfj8os The four passages in which tUOv0fJ-La, its adjective, or its verb
apxov. ' Iuov0fJ-LYJ, 'the fairest name of all', graces the 7rAfj8os occur in Thucydides confirm essentiallythe results of our investiga-
apxov, while, negatively, it does none of the things a monarch tion into Herodotus' use of the term. As in Herodotus, it is closely
does. The arbitrariness and violence of a monarch had been related to democracy but not identical with it; it is a political
characterized by Otanes earlier in his speech (3.80.3-5), and the principle rather than a form of government, and it implies not
institutions with which he now proceeds to characterize the only an equality of political rights but also the potential exercise
7rAfj8os apxov are precisely those which at once differentiate it of political power. But there are some slight shifts in emphasis
from a monarchy and embody its salient principle, which gives it which add a new dimension to the concept. The first of these
'the fairest name', tUOV0fJ-LYJ.The sortition of magistrates prevents shifts reflects the difference between the times in which Thucy-
the envy, the willingness to listen to slander, and the suscepti- dides lived from those of Herodotus and his predecessors. For the
bility to flattery which had been predicated of the monarch (3. latter, the problem of tyranny versus popular government was
80. 4-5) ; the accountability of the magistrates (Ev8vva) stands in a burning issue, whereas the constitutional question which divided
contrast to the monarch's unaccountability (avEv8vvi.p, 3·80. 3), the various states during the Peloponnesian War was whether
and public deliberation of all matters of public policy is denied by a democratic or an oligarchical form of government was more
the very fact of one-man rule. desirable, Sparta generally tending to support oligarchies and
Now, while these three institutions express the principle of Athens democracies. Accordingly, oligarchy tends to take over in
political equality, they are embodied in but not identical with Thucydides the place which tyranny had occupied as the oppo-
democracy. It is a fact, and Herodotus was no doubt aware of it, site of tUOV0fJ-La in the Harmodius skolia, in Alcmaeon, and in
that these three institutions could, in a different measure, also be Herodotus, especially that narrow form ofoligarchy which Thucy-
found in non-democratic forms of government. We hear of sorti- dides calls 8vvauTELa. Thus, for example, the Thebans try to
tion being used in some 0ligarchies,2and in Sparta, which was not justify their pro-Persian policy in 480/79 B.C. by blaming it on
regarded as a democratic state in antiquity, some form of Ev8vva a '8vvauTELa of a few men', which they contrast with both a
is known to have existed3 and, as two recent studies have shown, democracy and an oALyapXLa taOv0fJ-0S (3. 62. 3) ;2Brasidas would
many matters of public policy were decided not only in the not have been able to march through Thessaly in 424 B.C., 'if
Gerousia but also in the Assembly.4 In short, tUOV0fJ-La and the local Thessalian tradition had not sanctioned a 8vvauTELa rather
1 I prefer the Bude text, which retains the yap after fJ-EV(d P), to Hude's Oxford than taOV0fJ-La' (4. 78. 3); in party warfare the democrats use
text, which drops the yap (a Stob.).
2 Arist. Pol. 4. 15, I 300b I~3 (cf. Ath. Pol. 4. 3 and 30. 2) and Anaximenes in 1 It is noteworthy that laovofJ-la comes closer than any other Greek word to
L. Spengel, Rhetores Graeci I. 2 (ed. by C. Hammer) 22. expressing the modern notion of 'rights' in the sense in which we speak of the
3 Arist. Pol. 2. 9, 1271a6, Rhet. 3. 18, 1419a31. For sortition and euthyna in other 'rights of man', 'rights of a citizen', 'Bill of Rights', etc.
oligarchies, see BS 313, 315, 361-4, and 366-7. 2 It is true that this ovvaaT£la ot.lywv dvopwv is called <yyvTaTw Tvpavvov; but
4 A. Andrewes, 'The Government of Classical Sparta', in Ancient Society and since this is the closest Thucydides ever comes to opposing tyranny to laovofJ-la,
Institutions 1-20; and W. G. Forrest, 'Legislation in Sparta', Phoenix 21 (1967) there is no justification for emphasizing this contrast. For a full discussion of
11-19· this passage, see below, pp. 116-19.
814277
laovoflZa rrOAtTtK1] as a slogan to counter oligarchical claims of the most beautiful name of rrMi(}o, apxov. Thucydides extends this
'rule of the best' (3. 82. 8) ; and Athenagoras intimates that the relation in that he associates laovofLZa with rrMi(}o, or related con-
young oligarchical hot-heads in Syracuse do not want 'to be on cepts in everyone of the four passages in which it occurs. More-
a footing of political equality with many others'. The association I over, there is a very slight but perceptible difference in what
of laovofLZa with democracy in three of the four passages shows each author means by rrMi(}o, in its political sense. While Hero-
again its close affinity with this form of government; but its dotus tends to use it almost exclusively as a descriptive term for
association with a moderate form of oligarchy in the fourth pas- the 'people as a whole', encompassing all social strata, Thucy- I

sage shows that democracy and laovofLZa are not identical. dides, in all the laovofL{a passages, confines its meaning to a seg-
That the nature of this difference is for Thucydides the same as ment of the population, namely, to the 'common people', the
it had been for Herodotus is illustrated by two points. Herodotus 'broad masses', as distinguished from an upper oligarchical or
had already recognized the emotive appeal of laovofLZYJ when he aristocratic class, usually with the connotation that they consti-
had Otanes refer to it as ovvofLa mLvTwv KaAAtaTOv (3. 80. 6). But tute a majority which, if given the opportunity, can make the
while he had shown its operation in specific democratic institu- weight of its numerical superiority felt.2 Thus, 'political equality
tions, Thucydides uses the term almost exclusivelyin propaganda for the masses' is the democratic war-cry (3. 82. 8) ; if the majority
contexts, or, to borrow Vlastos' felicitous phrase, as 'more of a ofThessalians had had laovofL{a with those in power, they would
banner than a label'.2 It is, for example, conspicuously absent have expressed their sympathy for Athens by preventing Brasidas'
from Pericles' comparatively sober appraisal of the Athenian passage through their country (4. 78.2-3) ; the rroAAo{ with whom
democracy in the Funeral Oration,3 while in Athenagoras' parti- the Syracusan oligarchs refuse to share political equality are the
san praise of democracy over against oligarchy it seems to be common people (6. 38. 5); and it was the majority of Thebans
equated with the propagandistic ideas of 'equal rights for equal who were muted by an oligarchical clique during the Persian
men' and with the participation of every social group in the Wars but enjoy political rights under an oAtyapx{a laovofLo, (3.
management of state affairs in a democracy.4 In times of party 62. 3-4).3 For Thucydides, therefore, laovofL{a constitutes the
warfare the democrats use 'political equality for the masses' as political equality of the majority-presumably equality with the
a slogan against the oligarchs (3. 82. 8), and the Thebans speak members of the upper classes-which, where it exists, makes the
of their own OAtyapxZa laovofLo, when they want to impress the will of the majority determine the policy to be pursued by the
Spartans (3. 62. 3).5 As in Herodotus' account of the Debate, state. Moreover, as the case of the Thessalian rrMj(}o, (4·78.2-3)
Thucydides uses laovofLZa as a propaganda tool without, however, indicates most unequivocally, laovofL{a includes political power
confining the applicability of this principle to democracy. as well as political rights: without the possibility of exercising
The second point is seen in the association of laovofLZa with political power, the Thessalians could not possibly have been
rrA7j(}o,. Herodotus had Otanes in the Debate speak of laovof-dYJ as
I e.g. 3. 80. 6 (TO 7TAij9o<;dEtfLV), 81. 1,82. 1 and 2, 83·2; 4.200. I; 5. 76; 8. 34.
Only at I. 158. 2 and 5. 92. 1 do there seem to be overtones suggesting that
I 6. 38. 5: p.~ p.era 7roAAwv laovop.fra9at. a 'majority' is meant.
2 IP 8.-The only exception is laovop.La in the account of Brasidas' passage 2 The idea of majority rule seems to inhere in all political uses of 7TAij9o<; in
through Thessaly (4. 78. 3)· Thucydides. In addition to 'common people', he uses 7TAij9o<; (a) for the masses as
3 Gomme, HeT 2 and 3. 109-10,347, and 542, comments on 2.37. I (p.E.,..aT' a political force (3.47. 2; 4.66. I; 6. 8g. 4; 8. 9. 3; 8. 92. 9 [codd.]); (b) as an
8£Kurd. fL€V TOUS Vop,ovs 7TPOS 'TU rOta ouJ.¢opa 7TaUL TO Laov) that it expresses 'demo- equivalent of EKKA'Ja{a as the sovereign decision-making body in a democracy (2.
cratic laovop.La', cr. also J. T. Kakridis, Der thukydideische Epitaphios (= Zetemata 26) 65.8, 72. 2, 73. I; 3·37·5, 70.6; 4. 22. 2 and 3, 84·2 [bis] ; 5·41. 3, 60. 1 and 5;
25-6. This is plainly wrong, since the taov here applies to private differences, 6. 38. 2,60. 4), in which the vote of the majority determines all issues (3.42. 6,
whereas laovop.{a is invariably concerned with public, i.e. political and constitu- 43.2; 4·105. I, 106.2; 5. 27. 2,45.1; 8. 81. I); (c) to describe a political assembly
tional, rights and powers; so also Vlastos, IP IS. in a non-democratic state in which all or a majority of citizens may participate (I.
4 6. 38. 5: Kat 1TWS 8tKaLOV TOllS aVTOVS p.~ TWV aVTWV dtwva8aL,' and 39. I: Ofj/-,DV 72. 2; 5. 84. 3 and 85. I); or (d) in inter-state relations, to indicate the majority
tvp.7rav wvop.aa9a" oA,yapx{av OE P.EpO<;K.T.A. of member-states in a political league (I. 125. I ; 5. 30. I).
5 Cf. Ehrenberg, OD 536. 3 For 7TAij9o<; = 'common people' see also I. 9. 2; 2. 3. 2; 4. 21. 3; and 8.48.3.
116 NOMOE BECOMES 'STATUTE'
political rights, that is, with their oligarchical rulers their
thought of as able to bar Brasidas' path. However, these dif- I

majority would have ensured that no pro-Persian policy' would


ferences in emphasis are rather minor in character, and in all
have b:cn pursued at the time. They would have had these rights
essential points the two authors are in agreement with each other.
and thISpower, the Thebans claim, if a democracy or an oALyap-
For both laovof-L{a is a political principle and not a form of
x{a laov~fLos had been the constitutional form of Thebes during
government, and for both it involves not only the political
the PerSIan ·Wars.That a democracy would have vouchsafed the
equality of all citizens but also the potential power they possess;
Theban commons this equality is self-evident. But that they
but while Herodotus views it as the political equality of the
would have enjoyed the same equality under an oligarchy re-
people as a whole, Thucydides thinks of it as the equality of the
quired some explanation, and that is the reason why the adjec-
power of the majority with that of the upper classes.
tive laovof-Los had to be added to oALyapx{a.
These points are summed up most clearly in the one Thucy-
The specific reference of Karu oYjfLoKpar{av is presumably to the
didean passage which has caused most trouble to scholars, namely,
constitution of Plataea, which enabled the Plataeans in the past
in the response of the Thebans to charges of medism during the
to opt for an anti-Persian policy. It is more difficult to be sure
Persian Wars which had been levelled against them by the
what state preciscly is mcant by oALyapx{a laovof-Los. Are the
Plataeans before a Spartan commission ofjudges in 427 B.C. The
Thebans speaking of the constitution under which they lived at
text reads:
the time of their speech, in 427 B.C., or of the constitution which
Ka{ToL md.jJaaeE EV Orl{-' EL8EL EKO.TEpoL ~fLWV TO£JTO E1Tpagav. ~fLZV fLEV enabled the Spartans, whom they are here addressing, to take up
yap ~ 1T()ALS'T<JTE ETlJYXavEv OUTE KaT' oALyapx{av laovop,ov 1TOALTEDovau arms against the Persians in 480/79 B.C. ? Either interpretation has
OUTE KaTa 8TJfLOKpaT{av. 01TEp 8E Ean VOfLOLS'fLEV KaL T<{1 aW<ppOVEaTCiTl{-' found supporters,! and both can be defended, although it seems
EvavnWTaTOV, eYYVTCLTW 8E rvpavvov, 8vvaaTE{a oMywv dv8pwv ElXE TO. more probable that the Thebans are thinking of their own present
1TpayfLaTa. Kat OUTOL l8{aS' 8VVafLELS' eA1T{aavTES' En fLiiAAOV ax~aELv El TO.
constitution, since their speech is devised to establish their re-
rou M~80v KpaT~aELE, KaTEXOVTES' laXVL TO 1TMjeoS' e1TT/yaYOVTO aUTOIJ.
spectability in the eyes of the Spartans.2
KUL ~ gDfL1Taaa 1TOALS'OUK aUTOKpaTWp ouaa EavTfjS' TOUT' E1TpagEV, ouo'
!n order to show that oALyapx{a laovofLos is not an inappro-
CigLOV aUTfj oVEL8{aaL J)v fL~ fLETa vOfLWV iffLapTEV.2
pnate name for the Spartan constitution, it is sufficient to recall
The implication here is that, if the common people of Thebes that Aristotle cites Sparta as the prime example of a mixture of
had had any say in the matter at all, if they had enjoyed equal democracy and oligarchy, enumerating as democratic features
the equalitarian education of children and youths, the equality of
[ In view of this, Gomme's interpretation of Luol'ofJ-la as 'constitutional, law- men promoted by the syssitia and the likeness of dress, and the
abiding government, in which all citizens have equal civil rights, though not equal
political power' (HCT 2 and 3. 347), is untenable, since Luol'ofJ-la is not a form of
participation of all citizens in the election of the Gerousia and in
government but does involve equal political power. This interpretation is all the eligibility for the ephorate, while he calls oligarchical the absence
more surprising since Gomme recognizes, ibid. 379, that Luol'ofJ-la and apwToKpaTla
'describe certain conditions which ideally should accompany the two forms of I Theban constitution: P. Cloche, Thebes de BIotie 73 with n. 2; Vlastos, Ison.
government'. For a full criticism of Gomme's views on Luol'ofJ-la see Vlastos IP 360 and IP 14; L. Moretti, Ricerche sulie leghe greche 136; I. A. F. Bruce, An Histori-
who takes them as his point of departure. ' ,
cal Commentary on the Helienica Oxyrhynchia 160 with n. 2. Spartan Constitution: C. F.
2 3.62.3-4: 'And yet consider under what conditions each of us acted as we did.
Smith, L?eb Thucydi?es, vol. 2 (1953) lIOn. I; K. von Fritz, Wiener Studien 78
Th: consti~ution of our city at that time happened to be neither an oligarchy in (1965) 26. BS 1413 WIth n. I occupy an intermediate position, assuming that the
whIch all CItizens enjoy equal political rights nor a democracy. An institution most moderate oligarchy was instituted in Thebes under Spartan influence after the
opposed to lawful and orderly administration and to the soundest procedures, and
battle of Plataea.
clo~est to ~ tyrant, a clique of a few men, controlled our affairs. These, in the hope 2 This assumption would be strengthened if we could take KaTel OTJp.oKpaTlav as
of mcreasmg their own power, if the cause of the !'.fede were to prevail, forcibly
a reference to the democratic regime in Thebes which, according to Arist. Pol. 5·3,
suppressed the common people and brought him in. The city as a whole had no
.1302b29, was overthrown after the battle ofOenophyta. Since, however, this regime
power over herself when this policy was adopted, and she does not deserve to be
ISsaid to have fallen because of its bad administration (cf. [Xen.], Ath. Pol. 3. I I),
reproa:hed .for, ~istakes she committed when there was no lawful and orderly the Thebans may not have wished to remember it here.
admIllistratIOn. For the meaning of vop.os in this passage see above, pp. 32-3.
of the lot from the election to any office and the concentration of even though they may possibly have had the right to participate
the judicial power to inflict death and exile in the hands of a few in the election of their councillors. From this point of view, then,
I

men (Pol. 4. 9, 1294bI4-34).1 Similarly, under the Theban con- the Theban constitution was an oligarchy and was called such by
stitution, which lasted without substantial change from 447 to Thucydides (S. 3 I. 6; cf. 4·76. 2). In short, if this was the con-
386 B.C.,2 the full citizens enjoyed rights and powers which would stitution of Thebes in 427 B.C., the Thebans were right not only
well justify the appellation laovoj.Lo<;. According to the Hellenica in contrasting it with government by an oligarchical clique, but
Oxyrhynchia each member-state of the Boeotian League had four also in calling it an oligarchy because of its restriction of active
councils, of which each acted in turn as the executive branch of citizenship, but an OAtyuPX{u laoJloj.Lo<;, because all full citizens
government and prepared all matters to be discussed by the enjoyed equal political rights and equal political power.2
other three councils; only measures approved by all four councils There is no need to pursue our analysis of laoJloj.L{u into the
could authoritatively be acted upon. Any full citizen was eligible fourth century. While it is true that there is some evidence that
for membership in one of the councils.3 These two features, the the concept came to be coloured by the 'statute' meaning of
eligibility to the councils of all full citizens and the rotating ad- VOj.Lo<;, that merely meant that political equality was predicated
ministration by each of the four councils, gave Thebes that upon the enactment of equitable laws and adds nothing essentially
equality of political rights and of political power which is ap- new to what we have ascertained about laoJloj.L{u in the fifth
propriately reflected in the epithet laovoj.Lo<;. But this did not century.3 Before proceeding now to a discussion of the problem of
mean that Thebes was a democracy. For full citizenship was chronology, that is, of the question when and under what circum-
limited to those who owned a minimum amount of capital, stances laovoj.L{u first appeared in Athens, it will be useful to ask in
probably fixed at the requirement for the hoplite census.4 Since the light of the results we have obtained which sense or senses of
only a minority of Thebans can have ranked as hoplites and VOj.Lo<;laoJloj.L{u is likely to reflect. That it must be a political vOj.Lo<;
higher,Sthis means that the majority was barred from membership is evinced by the very fact that, unlike UJloj.L{u, laovoj.L{u is never
in the councils and thus from the active exercise of power, used of individuals but always of the state.4 Moreover, whereas
ElJVo,u{u, OvaJloj.L{u, UJloj.L{u, and KUKOVOj.L{U carry moral overtones,
I Cf. also the Spartan 0fLoW', Pol. 5. 7, 1306b30, with Xen. Lac. Resp. 10. 7,
laovoj.L{u always retains a purely political character. Alcmaeon
Anab. 4. 6. 14.
2 See BS 1414-15; Cloche, op. cit. 71 ;]. A. O. Larsen, Representative Government sees in it the balance of a political community in which ruler and
in Greek and Roman History 31; Moretti, op. cit. 133; and Bruce, op. cit. 157. ruled do not exceed one another in power; for Herodotus laovoj.L{YJ
3 Hellenica Oxyrhynchia (Bartoletti) 16. 2, with the discussions in BS 1417 with
n. I, Larsen, op. cit. 31-2, and Bruce, op. cit. 157-64. We know less about the
embodies the principle that every citizen shall have an equal
functioning of these local councils than is generally recognized. We do not know
(a) of how many members each of the four councils was composed; (b) whether this proportion reflects a general pattern, it may well have applied to Thebes
every full citizen was actually a member of one of the councils or whether he was between 447 and 386 B.C. At any rate, I know of no other statement that might
merely eligible (.tiiv fLETEXELV suggests the latter alternative); (c) in what manner form the basis for]. A. O. Larsen's assertion, TAPA 86 (1955) 41, that the active
the councillors were appointed and (d) assigned to serve on one council rather than citizens of the Boeotian Confederacy constituted 'less than one-half of the adult
on another; and (e) whether those citizens who, because of their low census, were males of the citizen body'.
not themselves eligible to council membership were entitled to vote in the elections I See above, p. 118 n. 3.
to the councils. 4 See Endnote, p. 180 below. 2 E. Will, Korinthiaka 619, aptly paraphrases o'\,yapxia laovofLos as 'democratie
; The proportion of full citizens to those below the hoplite census is hard to limitee it la base'. For the moderate character of Theban oligarchy, see also BS
ascertain even approximately. Of the Boeotians mentioned as participants in the 1416; Larsen, Representative Government 32; Moretti, op. cit. 135-6; and Bruce, op.
battle of Delium by Thuc. 4. 93. 3, 8,500 seem to have belonged to the hoplite ci t. 157-64.
census (this includes 500 peltasts) and 10,000 light-armed troops were certainly 3 The most important fourth-century passages, i.e. those in Isocrates and Plato,
below that census. Although these figures apply to the Boeotians as a whole and not are discussed in detail by Vlastos, IP 18-35. For a criticism of his views see End-
even to their full complement, it is probable that the ratio of hoplites to the lower note, pp. 180~2 below.
classes was the same for Thebes, cf. Moretti, op. cit. 134 and 150-1. [Herodes], 4 The exception, o.vryp laovofL'KoS in PI. Rep. 8. 561 e, is only apparent and not
Peri politeias 30- [, suggests that in the oligarchies set up by Sparta after the real, since the adjective obviously does not describe a man who 'has equal rights
Peloponnesian "Var only one third of the citizens enjoyed full citizenship, and if and powers', but one who 'adheres to equalitarian principles'.
opportunity to occupy a position of authority, to check authority, Our next task is to fit the results obtained from our discussion
and to participate in framing those regulations which will affect of laovofLla into a historical context. For since laovofL{a has been
the welfare of the state; and the element stressed by Thucydides shown to be a purely political concept, related to the political
is that under laovofL{a the common people, as constituting the senses of vOfLos, we may be able to infer from the circumstances
majority of the citizen body, have equal rights and equal powers surrounding the earliest evidence for laovofLla at what point vOfLOS
with those who rule the state. This suggests that laovofL{a has its first assumed its sense of 'statute'. There is, as far as I know,
closest affinity with two of the senses of vOfLoS isolated in Part I general agreement that the Harmodius skolia constitute our
above. Since it distributes power in the state on a basis of earliest surviving evidence for laovofLla in the form of the adjec-
equality, it seems to reflect the vOfLoS which describes the tive laovofLos. But since some controversy surrounds the date at
authority to issue norms and of which we found the first indica- which they were composed, and much controversy the historical
tion in Heraclitus and the first clear expression in Aeschylus' circumstances of their composition, we shall have to address
Supplices (above, pp. 26-9). In this sense, then, laovofL{a confers ourselves to these problems now.
equal authority to govern upon both ruler and ruled. But from The Harmodius skolia consist of four stanzas, celebrating the
a different point of view the term reflects the political norms and achievements of the tyrannicides Harmodius and Aristogeiton,
regulations by which both ruler and ruled are equally bound, the which are included in Athenaeus' collection of some twenty-five
statutes which are valid and binding equally on both, which we Attic drinking songs (15. 695 a-b). Only two of these stanzas,
encounter first also in Aeschylus' Supplices (above, pp. 43-52). It Nos. 10 and 13, contain the wordlaovo{wvS, but since all four are
is no accident that, contrary to the vOfLoS embodied in the other relevant to the problem of determining the date and the historical
compounds we have discussed, neither of these senses is attested background of these two, I shall quote them in full:1
before the fifth century B.C.
There is one point to add. By its very nature the principle 10 EV fLVPTOV KAaDL T6 g{</Jos </Jop~uw

expressed by laovovla has its closest affinity with democracy, al- WU7TEP :4pfLODLOs KaL i1pWToyE{TWV
~, " I
aTE TOV Tvpavvov KTaVETTJV
though, as we have tried to show, it is not identical with oYjfLO-
lUOVOfLOVS T' i18~vas E7TotTJuaTTJV.
Kpa,r(a, since it does not designate a form of government. But
since the terminology for all constitutional forms, except the II </J{Am8' :4pfLODt', ou n TTW TE8vTJKas,
monarchical, I developed much more slowly than the constitu- V~UOtS D' EV fLaKapwv UE </Jautv ECVat,
tional forms themselves,zthe authors who wrote before oY)fLoKparla [va 7TEp 7ToDwKTJS i1XtAEDs
and oY]rLOKparEfa8at were coined used the principle most charac- TVDEtDTJV TE t</Jam T6V Eu8A6vt L1tofL~DEa.
teristic of a democracy to describe the democratic form of govern-
ment, and there can, consequently, be no doubt that Alcmaeon 12 EV fLVpTOV KAaDL T6 g{</JOS </Jop~uw
WU7TEP :4pfLoDLOS KaL i1pwToydTwV
and Herodotus are thinking only of democracy when they speak
OT' i18TJva{TJs EV 8vu{ats
of laovof-Lla.
aVDpa Tvpavvov "I7T7Tapxov EKatVETTJV.
I While the Linear B tablets speak of wanax and ltiwtigettis (see M. Ventris and
J. Chadwick, Documents in Mvcenaean Greek 119--25, and L. R. Palmer, The Inter- 13 aiEL u</Jwtv KAEOS EUUETat KaT' acav,
pretation of Mycenaean Greek Texts 83-95), they do not yet know abstracts to describe </J{Am8' :4pfLODtE KaL i1pWTOyEt TOV,
the institution of monarchy. The earliest uses I can find of an abstract term for ~ \'
on TOV Tvpavvov KTaVETTJV
,
a form of government are TVpUVV{, in Archilochus, frg. 22. 3, and /l-ovuPX{u in
Alcaeus, frg. 6. 27, in E. Lobel and D. <L.) Page, Poetarum Lesbiorumjragmenta. lUOVOfLOVS T' )1e~vas E7TotTJuaTTJV.
, Both o:l,yuPX{u and 0'1/l-0KpUT{U are first found in Herodotus, see A. Debrunner
"LJ'1/l-0KpUT{U" 11-24, esp. 13-18, although 0'1/l-0KpUT{U may be older, if it is correctly I The text is Page's, PMG, Nos. 893-6. The most valuable recent discussions of
restored in the Athenian treaty with Colophon of 447/6 B.C., IG'. 15. 37 = A TL 2. the date of these stanzas are: Brunnsaker; Ehrenberg, HL; and Bowra, GLP
D 15·48. 373-97, esp. 391-6; see also Podlecki.
( 10) In a myrtle bough I will wear the sword like Harmodius and than it solves. Ehrenberg himself regards it as 'something of a
Aristogeitonwhen they killed the tyrant and made Athens isonomous. puzzle' how this slogan of the nobility could so quickly have
(1 1) Dearest Harmodius, you are no longer dead, but people say that become 'the watchword of the democracy'.1 Moreover, in none of
you are in the Islands of the Blest,where is swift-footedAchillesand, the other laovofJ-la passages which we have examined is the term
they say, the son of Tydeus, noble Diomedes. (12) In a myrtle bough restricted to only one class of society, but it always refers to the
I wiII wear the sword like Harmodius and Aristogeiton,when at the people as a whole, and further, Vlastos, after canvassing all the
sacrificeto Athena they slewa tyrant-man, Hipparchus. (13) For ever
possible historical references of laov6fJ-ovS' in the Harmodius skolia
will you both have fame on earth, dearest Harmodius and Aristo-
has shown that it can have been used neither as 'a neutral term
geiton-because they slew the tyrant and made Athens isonomous.
which simply means liberation from tyrannic rule, without any
The internal evidence for the date presents a few problems, positive specification of the sort of government that followed', nor
but more problematic are the circumstances of composition. The as 'a term which does describe the ensuing regime, but thinks of it
mention of the murder of Hip parch us in three of the four stanzas only as the reinstatement of the pre-Peisistratid constitution'.2 In
and of the death of Harmodius in the fourth gives us 514 B.C. as view of this, Ehrenberg, with his characteristic forthrightness, has
a firm terminus post quem for the Harmodius skolia as a whole. conceded that his belief in an aristocratic laovofJ-la was erroneous.3
More problematic is the reference in the last two lines of stanzas This means that the laov6fJ-ovS' .f18~vaS' of stanzas 10 and 13 can
ro and 13 to the creation of an laov6fJ-ovS' .f18~vaS'. Our analysis of refer only to the constitution established by Cleisthenes, and the
all the fifth-century passages in which laovofJ-la occurs has shown aorists E11'OLY)aaTY)v, with which each of these stanzas ends, show
that it embodies the concept of political equality and is usually that the constitution was an accomplished fact by the time
associated with a democratic form of government. This suggests these stanzas were composed, so that 507 B.C. can be taken as
that these lines refer to the democratic constitution ushered in by a firm terminus post quem for their origin. But it also means that we
the reforms of Cleisthenes, so that we could adopt 507 B.C. as the shall have to account for two distortions of historical facts in the
terminus post quem for the two stanzas (ro and 13) in which they Harmodius skolia. Before we can discuss those, however, some
appear. But can we be sure? The result of adopting this view further problems of dating remain to be clarified.
would be that the skolia contain not merely one historical mis- If we could assume that the four stanzas quoted by Athenaeus
take but two. For if the Athenians sang this song soon after the constitute one song, we should be able to leave matters at that
events celebrated in them they would have-or ought to have- and try now to establish a terminus ante for the song as a whole.
known even better than we that Harmodius and Aristogeiton But there are indications that this was not the case. The earliest
neither slew the tyrant nor established a democratic form of extant reference to 'the Harmodius' is found in Aristophanes'
government. Acharnians (g80), and the scholion on that passage cites as the
There is no way of getting round the first of these mistakes, beginning of that song what appears as the second stanza (I I) in
and the only way of avoiding the second is to posit for laov6fJ-ovS' Athenaeus' collection.4 To the two different beginnings given by
a reference to something other than the reforms of Cleisthenes.
assume two historical mistakes than to posit an otherwise unattested and a priori
This path was actually taken by Ehrenberg, who advocated the unlikely aristocratic laovofLia..
view that, before being embraced by Cleisthenes and his ad- [ OD 531.
herents, laovofJ-la denoted an equality of the members of the 2 Ison. 339-44.
3 HL 67 with n. 23, where he expresses reserve, however, about Vlastos' treat-
Athenian nobility in the face of the 'inequality' of tyranny, and ment of the skolion as a whole.
that it became the slogan of the nobles who were exiled after the 4- EV 'Tar~ TWV 7T(hwv UVV600LS' noov p..tAOS' 'TL, :4pf-LOOLOV Kai\oVfl-€vOV, 00 ~ apx~·

murder of Hipparchus.1 But this view creates more problems ¢{ATUT€ :4.PfLoou oun 7TOU TfOv'Y/Kas (= Suda, s.v. OVO€1TOT' eyw TOUTOV v1Tooi;OfLat
K.T.A. Cf. also ibid. S.V. 7TC5.POtVO~). That the scholiast's identification of this stanza
I Ehrenberg, Ison. 294--6; Eun. 89; and OD 530-4. His views were accepted by as 'the Harmodius' may be right is suggested by Ach. 1093, where dancing-girls
Larsen, Cleisth, 8. However, Vlastos, Ison. 339-44, has shown that it is easier to are called Ta #ATa.O' :4PfLooiov, no doubt as a parody on this same stanza. Hesychius,
124 NOMOI.: BECOMES 'STATUTE' II.: 0 NOMI A AND ATHENS 125

Athenaeus and the scholiast on the Acharnians respectively, Aristo- the song. Moreover, the fact that one of the three beginnings is
phanes' Wasps (1222-6) adds a third in a passage which, in otherwise unknown to us points to the possible existence in
giving us the earliest information we have on the traditions of antiquity of additional stanzas, which may now be lost to us, and
singing skolia, provides us with an explanation for these dif- the practice of capping, as shown in the scene in the ~l1asps,
ferent beginnings. The setting is Bdelycleon's attempt to teach makes it probable that new stanzas were constantly added as
his father Philocleon how to behave at a banquet. Among other long as the practice of singing skolia at banquets remained a
things, he wants him to learn 'how to cap drinking songs properly' living tradition. 1 This in turn makes it likely that the four
(Tel aKo/t!' 07TWS oEgE! KU/tWS), and to this end he starts 'the stanzas which Athenaeus has transmitted to us were composed at
Harmodius' with a line which he asks his father to cap (4ow oE different times.2
7TpWTOS :4pfLootov' oEgat oE au), and this line is not only different In view of this, the terminus post quem of 507 B.C. is valid only for
from those cited as the beginning by Athenaeus and the scholiast the first and fourth stanzas of Athenaeus' collection (10 and 13)'
on the Acharnians, but it is nowhere else attested for the Harmodius For the second and third stanzas (I I and 12) our only guide is the
song at all : OVOELS7TW7TOT' dv~p EyEvT' )1B~vu!s- 'no man was ever negative fact that neither of them as much as mentions the libera-
born in Athens .. .'.1 The fact that we have thus three beginnings tion from the tyranny and the positive fact that the praise of
attested for the song proves that the stanzas did not follow one Harmodius in the second stanza (I I) and the statement that they
upon the other in any set sequence-or in any sequence at all, killed Hipparchus in the third (12) give 5 I 4 B.C. as the terminus
for that matter, since we do not know whether or not a single post quem. How soon or how late after that date they were com-
stanza could stand by itself, and whether or not other stanzas posed we cannot tell. But, as Ehrenberg has pointed out, the
customarily followed upon the first one sung on a given occasion. third stanza (12) differs from the first (10) and the fourth (13) in
For if the 'capping' procedure in the Wasps is any guide, the that it is free from distortion of historical fact: Hipparchus is men-
first singer needed apparently to sing no more than one or two tioned by name and he is called a tyrant, not the tyrant, and the
lines,2 to which the second would add another one or two lines. Panathenaic festival is correctly identified as the occasion of the
If this was the procedure, it would explain why the first two lines murder.3 This and the militant tone of the stanza, more ap-
of stanzas 10 and 12 of Athenaeus' collection are identical and the propriate to a time of struggle than to the years after the expul-
last two lines of stanzas 10 and 13 almost identical each with the sion of the tyrants, suggest that it may have originated among the
other. They may, therefore, be 'movable' lines belonging tradi- opponents of the tyranny soon after Hippias exiled and killed
tionally to the Harmodius song as beginning and capping lines, many of them as a sequel to Hipparchus' murder.4 Once we
respectively, capable of being combined with one another accord- recognize these as valid grounds for dating the third stanza (12)
ing to the pleasure of those whose turn it was to start or to cap soon after 514 B.C. but before 51 I/ro B.C., we may also aClmit the
s.v. l1p/"OO{OV /"<)\0<:;, attributes TO €71t IIp/"o8{tp 710('l70.v aKdAwv to one Callistratus.
But since (a) it is uncertain whether he refers to this stanza, a different stanza on I For our knowledge of the tradition, we depend mainly on Dicaearchus and
Harmodius now lost, or to the whole group ofskolia on the tyrannicides, and since Aristoxenus, as reported by the scholiast on PI. G9rg. 451 e, cf. also on Ar. Nub.
(b) we do not know who this Callistratus was or when he lived, Hesychius' entry is 1364, and Pluto Quaest. conDo1. 1,615 b-c. The basic modern treatment is that of
not of much use to us. R. Reitzenstein, Epigramm und Skolion 3-13; the most important recent discussion
I I see no need to assume with Ehrenberg, HL 60-1, that it is merely a variant is that of A. E. Harvey, 'The classification of Greek lyric poetry', CQN.S. 5 (1955)
beginning of what is the first stanza (10) in Athenaeus. It seems much more likely
157-75, esp. 162-3 and 174"-5·
that we have here the beginning of a different stanza now lost to us, in which only 2 The significance of this was first recognized by Reitzenstein, op. cit., esp. 22-3·
one of the tyrannic ides was celebrated, presumably Harmodius, because (a) his His results were improved upon by F. Koepp, Neue Jahrbiicher fiir das klassische
name and not Aristogeiton's is mentioned at line 1225; (b) the song is usually re- Altertum 9 (1902) 614-34, esp. 615, accepted by Aly, RE S.V. 'Skolion' 562, and
ferred to by his name alone, see, for example, Adz. 980, 1093; Ar. frg. 430; Anti- by Ehrenberg, HL 58 n. 5. Cf. also Bowra, GLP 393·
ph ant's, frg. 85; Aelius Aristides 11.80; etc.; and (c) his youth made him the more
3 HL 66.
popular of the tyrannicides. 4 Hdl. 5. 62. 2; Arist. Ath. Pol. 19. I, with Ehrenberg, HL 66, and Brunnsaker
2 Two, if Philocleon's 'capping' at 1227 is a premature interruption.
23-4·
second stanza (II) as earlier than the first (IO) and the fourth period. 1 Since Athenaeus called his collection }tTTLKa ad'\ta (IS'
(13), since it simply praises Harmodius without specifying his 693 f.), and since the same term is used, apparently for the same
achievements. If we interpret it as saying, 'Harmodius, you have collection, by Dio Chrysostom (2. 63), it is safe to conclude that
not died in vain', as well we might, its tone would suit the op- all twenty-five songs originated in Attica. Of the twenty-one
ponents of Hippias as well as does the tone of the third stanza songs which remain if we leave the four Harmodius stanzas out
(12). Consequently, Brunnsaker is probably right in assigning it, of consideration for the present, seven are impossible to date with
too, to the period between 514 and SIO B.C.I any verisimilitude, since they contain moralizing maxims and
If the rather tenuous evidence makes a date soon after the witticisms which could have been composed at any time and for
event celebrated plausible in the case of the second (I I) and any kind of society.2 Of the remaining fourteen, only four are
third (12) stanza, can we assume that the first (10) and fourth datable with any degree of certainty, two by their author and two
(13) stanzas were also composed soon after the event which they by the events which they celebrate. The ascription of No. 7 with
celebrate, that is, soon after a democratic form of government was some (though not complete) confidence to Simonides (about
instituted in Athens in 507 B.C.? To attain certainty in this matter 556-468 B.C.) 3 and of No.8, on the basis of papyrus finds, to
is impossible and we must be satisfied if we can marshal suffi- Alcaeus (born about 620 B.C.)4 suggests that other songs in this
ciently impressive circumstantial evidence to give us any plausi- collection may also belong to the sixth century or the early
ble answer at all to this question. The safest way to approach decades of the fifth. A more precise date is given by Nos. 23 and
the problem is by trying to find a terminus ante quem for the two 24, also preserved in Aristotle's Constitution of Athens (19, 3, 20. 5),
stanzas which celebrate the establishment of laovoj-tLa. which commemorate two thwarted attempts undertaken after
The direct evidence is not of much help, for the earliest refer- 514 B.C. to overthrow the tyranny of Hippias, the attempt of
e~ce to the beginning of the first stanza (10), which is identical Kedon, and the defeat at Leipsydrium. Now, since Kedon left no
WIth the beginning of the third (12), is not found until 4II B.C., other mark on Athenian history, and since the Leipsydrium song
when the chorus of old men in Aristophanes' Lysistrata sing of says nothing of the success which eventually came to the op-
the sword the~ will wear in a myrtle bough to fight against the ponents of the tyranny, it is generally and, I think, correctly
Spartan conspIracy to set up a tyranny in Athens, which they assumed that both were composed shortly after the events, that is
suspect behind the revolt of Lysistrata's women (631-3). This within the period SI4-SIO B.C.S
leaves us wit~ a gap of ninety-six years between the two termini,
I Reitzenstein, who did the pioneer work on dating the collection, reached the
a gap too wIde to be useful, and we must, therefore, try to conclusion that it was completed by the middle of the fifth century, on the ground
narrow it by a more indirect route. that Pindar influenced and Praxilla was influenced by songs contained in it (op.
We are helped in this endeavour by the conclusion arrived at cit. 13-24, esp. 14-15). More recent work on the collection has shown that
Reitzenstein's reasons are not compelling, and the date has been pushed back
independently by Reitzenstein and Wilamowitz in' I893, that much closer to the time of Marathon and Salamis by Bowra, GLP 375-97, to
the collection of twenty-five skolia, of which the four stanzas of whose arguments much of the following discussion is indebted.
the Harmodius form a part, constitutes a unified whole, which 2 No.6 praises true friendship, NO.9 honesty, No. 19 companionship in love and
drink, No. 25 loyalty, while Nos. 20, 21, and 22 contain proverbial wisdom in vary-
Athenaeus took from a single source.2 Therefore, if we can date ing degrees of coarseness. Bowra, GLP 381-3 and 390-1, seems to me to be going too
the songs in this collection other than the Harmodius skolia and far in trying to link these songs with an aristocratic society, and especially with the
find that all belong to a more or less well defined period, we may world of the Peisistratids. 3 For the testimonia see Page, PMG frg. 651.
4 Alcaeus, frg. 249 with D. L. Page, Sappho and Alcaeus 196-7, and Bowra, GLP
presume that the Harmodius skolia, too, belong to the same
374-5·
5 See Bowra, GLP 383-4. The date of Leipsydrium is confirmed by Hdt. 5. 62. 2.
I Brunnsaker 23-4. Ehrenberg, HL 60-1, is uncertain on this point. He dates II Bowra dates Kedon's attempt before 514 B.C., presumably because Aristotle dates
ear her .than 13.but suggests only a date 'not very early' for the latter. it before Leipsydrium. But it seems much more probable that both Kedon's at-
2 Reltzenstem, op. cit. 13-14; Wilamowitz, AA 2. 316-22. Accepted by Bowra, tempt and the defeat at Leipsydrium are measures taken by Hippias' opponents
GLP 375-6. after their exile from Athens as a consequence of Hipparchus' murder.
A considerable amount of circumstantial evidence has enabled precinct of her shrine (Philochorus, frg. 67) and which was
C. M. Bowra to assign five of the remaining ten songs to the burned down by the Persians at the time of Salamis and had
times of Marathon and Salamis, and the other five to the period miraculously sprouted forth a new shoot by the next day (Hdt.
of Peisistratus and his sons. Among the first four songs, all of 8. 55; Paus. 1. 27. 2).
which are addressed to deities closely associated with Athens, the The first five songs may then plausibly be regarded as a group
fourth stands out as the only one devoted to a non-Olympian that celebrates events connected with the Persian Wars, and the
god, Pan. Moreover, Pan is-strangely for an Attic song-ad- very specific nature of the incidents to which they seem to be
dressed as 'lord of famed Arcadia'-J4pKaoLas JLEOEWV KAEEVVrlS. related suggests that, like the Kedon and Leipsydrium songs,
This can most reasonably be explained as a reference to the they were composed very soon after the events to which they are
establishment of the Pan cult in Athens after the battle of devoted. The same may be said of a second block of five songs
Marathon as a result of Philippides' vision in the Parthenion (Nos. 14-18) which may reflect events associated with Peisistra-
mountains in Arcadia on his way to Sparta. I Once this is ac- tus and his sons. Bowra has adduced cogent reasons for relating
cepted, a number of other songs fall into place. Bowra has No. 14, the Admetus song, to the help rendered Hippias by the
shown that the appellation of Artemis as dypoTEpa in NO.3 may Thessalian cavalry under Cine as at the time when the Spartans
well be related to the sacrifice of five hundred goats to her, under Anchimolius landed in Attica in an attempt to expel
vowed by Miltiades and offered by the polemarch on the sixth Hippias.1 If this is correct, 'the Admetus' was composed in
day of Boedromion, the anniversary of the battle of Marathon.2 Peisistratid circles, that is, it comes from the opposite side of the
That at the beginning of the whole collection should stand songs political fence to that which produced the Kedon and Leipsyd-
to Athene and the Eleusinian goddesses is natural enough at any rium songs. Furthermore, it creates the probability that the next
time; but the title TpLTOyEVEta applied to Athena in No. I asso- two songs in the collection, Nos. 15 and 16 on Ajax and Telamon,
ciates this song with a time of special emergency, such as that are derived from Peisistratus' interest in Salamis and in the
in which Athens found herself at the time of Marathon and again Troad. For it was in the campaigns for the possession of Salamis
of Salamis,3 and the invocation of Demeter and Persephone in that Peisistratus won his first renown, and it was to Sigeum in the
NO.2 may well be related to the vision of Dicaeus, son of Theo- Troad, conquered by his father, that Hippias fled after his expul-
cydes, and Demaratus on the Thriasian Plain just before the sion.2 More doubtful, but still within the realm of the possible,
battle of Salamis, when they saw the dust of an army of 30,000 is Bowra's association of the two couplets which follow, Nos.
men 'arise from Eleusis to bring aid to the Athenians and their 17 and 18, with one or both of the Dionysiac and Panathenaic
allies' and heard their mystic shout.4 If, then, the four introduc- festivals, which were reorganized by Peisistratus.3 If Bowra's as-
tory songs can be associated with Marathon or Salamis, the vic- signment of these songs is correct, we may again assume that all
tory in NO.5 may well refer to one of these battles. The mutilated or most of them were composed soon after the events which they
state of the last line leaves uncertain the role played by Pandrosus celebrate. For while their survival may be explained by the ab-
in the victory. Bowra has interpreted her presence as an indica- sence of any reference to the tyrants and by the general tenor of
tion that the song was composed in honour of Marathon, when their references to gods and heroes, they are not likely to have
her shrine was still intact.5 But her name may equally well be been composed in honour of Peisistratus' exploits and those of
taken as an allusion to the sacred olive tree which stood in the his allies after the expulsion of tyrants.
1 Hdt. 6. 105, with Bowra, GLP 385-6. Bowra's conclusions are speculative and the basis which they
2 GLP 387-9, citing Aelian, VH 2. 25; Pollux 8. gl ; Pluto De malignitate Herodoti provide for our inquiry into the terminus ante quem of the first (10)
26, 862 b-c. Bowra accepts Aelian's 300 goats and 6th ThargeIion; but see L.
Deubner, Attische Feste 20g with n. 6. 3 GLP 388-g.
1 Hdt. 5.63.2-4 and Arist. Ath. Pol. Ig. 5, with Bowra, GLP 376-9.
4 Hdt. 8. 65. Bowra, GLP 389-go, sees only social but no political implications
in this song. 5 GLP 386-7.
2 cr.
Arist. Ath. Pol. 17. 2; 14. 1 ; Hdt. 5. 94. I, with Bowra, GLP 379-80.
3 GLP 380-1.
and fourth (13) stanzas of the Harmodius skolia cannot be said to and Aristogeiton belonged.! This hypothesis might conceivably
be firm. Yet their cumulative effect is sufficiently impressive to provide a reasonable explanation, if the two stanzas merely
draw some plausible inferences. Three periods of Athenian his- credited Harmodius and Aristogeiton with slaying the tyrant,
tory seem to be represented in Athenaeus' collection of Attic that is, with liberating Athens. But since they are also praised for
skolia : the time of Peisistratus and his sons, the opposition to the having made Athens luovofLoVS, it is difficult to see, as Ehrenberg
tyranny, and the time of the Persian Wars, particularly the vic- has pointed out, who the anti-Alcmaeonids would have been who
tories of Marathon and Salamis. Since, moreover, none of the would have paid this tribute to the tyrannicides.2 If they had
twenty-five skolia seems to have been composed later, we may re- been supporters of Isagoras, as Jacoby seems to believe,3 they
gard the time shortly after Salamis as the terminus ante for the would hardly have wished to celebrate the establishment of
origin of the poems contained in the collection, though perhaps luovofL{a at all. If, on the other hand, they were anti-Alcmaeonids
not for the collection in its present form. Within these three who supported the democratic reforms but opposed Cleisthenes,
groups the four Harmodius skolia may well join the Kedon and the complete silence of all our sources about them makes them
Leipsydrium songs as members of the group representing the too hypothetical an entity to be taken seriously. Moreover, the
opposition to the tyranny, and since, as we have seen, the datable implied contention that the Gephyraei were 'one of the great
songs in the collection were presumably composed soon after the clans ... with whom Kleisthenes fell out immediately after the
events which they celebrate, it is a reasonable assumption that expulsion of Hippias, perhaps as early as 511/10 B.C.' is not sup-
the first (10) and fourth (13) stanzas of the Harmodius were ported by any evidence at all.4
written not long after the establishment of the Athenian de- This weakness in Jacoby's argument was recognized also by
mocracy in 507 B.C., the only event to which, in the light of our one of the most ardent admirers of his theories of the anti-
analysis of luovofL{a, the lines luovofLoVS T' }48~vas E7TOL7]UUT7]V can Alcmaeonid origin of the tyrannicide cult, A. J. Podlecki.5 The
refer. solution he proposed in its place is very radical indeed. He re-
This brings us to a consideration of the historical circumstances gards it as axiomatic that the Alcmaeonids 'would have opposed
in which stanzas 10 and 13 were composed. How are we to ac- vehemently anyone who put forward the claims of Harmodius
count for the two falsifications of historical fact which these and Aristogeiton' and that 'the supporters of the claims of
stanzas contain? For while these stanzas credit Harmodius and Harmodius and Aristogeiton must have been the political op-
Aristogeiton with having slain the tyrant (and thus having ponents of the Alcmaeonids, at least in the early stages of the
liberated Athens) as well as with having made Athens luovofLoVS, fiction before it became established as the "official version" '.6
every adult living in Athens in the last decade of the sixth century Not being able to find these anti-Alcmaeonids in the period
must have known (a) that Harmodius and Aristogeiton did not immediately following the reforms of Cleisthenes, he proceeds
kill Hippias and that the liberation was effected by the Spartans not only to attribute the institution of the tyrannicide cult to
under Cleomenes acting under the prodding of Delphi and the Themistocles in 477 B.C., but also to speculate that 'it was
Alcmaeonids, and (b) that it was Cleisthenes who established Themistocles who gave the term luovofL{a the particular demo-
a democratic form of government. Among the solutions pro-
I cratic slant which it was later to bear', and to assign the present
posed for this problem, two deserve particular attention. F.
Jacoby tried to resolve it by assuming that the falsification was the I Jacoby, cr.
Atthis 16o; 339 n. 53; also 340 n. 54.-For Harmodius and Aristo-
geiton as Gephyraei, Hdt. 5. 55 and 57. 1.
deliberate work of forces hostile to Cleisthenes who wanted to 2 See Ehrenberg, OD 531-2, for a full demonstration of the historical improba-
deprive the Alcmaeonids of the credit for having liberated Athens bilities to which Jacoby's position would lead.
by attributing it to the Gephyraei, the genos to which Harmodius 3 Jacoby, Atthis 340 n. 53 ad fin.
4 Vlastos, Ison. 342 with n. 17. The quotation is from Jacoby, Atthis 339,
I (0) Hdt. 5. 62-5; Arist. Ath. Pol. 19.2-6. (b) Hdt. 5. 66.2,69.2,6.131. !; n·53·
Arist. Ath. Pol. 21. 5 Podlecki 131. 6 Podlecki 130.
Il:ONOMIA AND ATHENS 133

version of the Harmodius song to the period in which the statues the Roman liberation from tyranny, does not inspire confidence. I

of the tyrannicides by Critius and Nesiotes were set up, that is But there is an indication that Pliny's date is at least approxi-
477/6 B.C. Now, since our ancient sources give us considerably
I mately correct. The clue is provided by Pausanias' ascription of
more information about Themistocles than they do about Cleis- the group to Antenor (I. 8. 5), no doubt the same Antenor
thenes, it is harder to explain in the case of Themistocles than in whose signature appears on the base of Kore No. 681 in the
the case of Cleisthenes why we get from them no hint whatever Acropolis Museum,z·and who is believed to have contributed to
that Themistocles either coined or ever appealed to the principle the pedimental sculpture of the reconstructed Temple of Apollo
of political equality. If he had done so, we should rather have at Delphi.3 Since the inscription on the Kore base can be dated on
expected it about the time of his election to the archonship in epigraphical grounds shortly before or after 525 B.C.,4 and since
493/2 B.C., when he may have faced a stiff opposition especially his work at Delphi is dated soon after 5IO B.C.,s Antenor's
from those whom Aristotle calls 'friends of the tyrants' (Ath. Pol. activity belongs in the last quarter of the sixth ccntury.6 This
22. 4), than in 477 B.C. Moreover, in view of the fact that we makes Pliny's date approximately acceptable, and we may, there-
know of no constitutional innovation attributed to Themistocles, fore, assume that Antenor's statues were in fact erected in honour
his authorship of laovolJ-{a is rather unlikely. And with this the of Harmodius and Aristogeiton soon after the expulsion of Hip-
necessity of associating the Harmodius song with the dedication pias.7 A more precise date is impossible to attain, and we do not
of the new tyrannicide group of Critius and Nesiotes vanishes. know whether the statues were set up before or after conflict
In attributing to Themistocles the institution of the tyrannicide broke out between Isagoras and Cleisthenes. The years of con-
cult, Podleckiz has to brush aside the importance of a tyrannicide solidation in internal politics which followed the Cleisthenean
group of statues by Antenor which, we are told by Pausanias, reforms would favour a date soon after 507 B.C. rather than the
existed in Athens before 480 B.C. and was removed to Persia by turbulent period offriction between 510 and 507 B.C.S
Xerxes to be later returned to Athens either by Alexander the If, then, Harmodius and Aristogeiton could be honoured in
Great or one of his successors,3 and which, according to the bronze so soon after the liberation from tyranny, there is no
Parian Marble, was replaced in 477/6 B.C. by the new group by reason why the liberation may not at the same time have been
Critius and Nesiotes.4 According to Pliny (NH 34. 17) these attributed to them in song. In other words, the presence of
statues were set up in Athens 'eodem anno quo et Romae reges Antenor's statues soon after 510 B.C. supports a date soon after
pulsi', that is, in 509 B.C. It is true, as Brunnsaker has demon- 507 B.C. rather than Podlecki's date of 477 B.C. for the composi-
strated, that this date, with its synchronism of the Athenian with tion of the first (10) and fourth (13) Harmodius skolion, and, like
I Podlecki 138, 139-40. He avoids committing himself on the problem of what I Brunnsaker 40-1 and 43.
parts of the Harmodius skolia were composed at what time (139): 'Some version 2 IG 12• 485. The question whether or not base and statue belong together does
or part of the song may have been sung earlier, but what better time for a revival not affect our argument.
of an "old favorite" and even an expansion of it, than the occasion of the new 3 See G. Lippold in Handbuch der Archiiologie, ed. W. Otto and R. Herbig, 3. I.
"tyrannicide" dedication?' We do not learn here when the earlier version origin- 81 with n. 3.
ated and what it contained. On Podlecki's assumptions, any part of it must have 4 Jeffery, LSAG 75. 5 Lippold loco cit. with n. 2.
originated among anti-Alcmaeonids, and since he admits that it must have 6 On Antenor's date see P. Orlandini in Enciclopedia del!'arte antica I. 408-9, s.v.
originated after 510, it is as hard to see in his case as it is in Jacoby's who its anti- 'Antenor' (with bibliography); on the date of Antenor's group of tyrannicides see
Alcmaeonid authors may have been. Brunnsaker 41, 43, and 97-8; and G. Becatti, Archeologia classica 9 (1957) 97-107.
2 Podlecki 135 and 137 contents himself with the assertion that Antenor's group 7 Cf. Jacoby, Atthis 339 n. 52. But I do not agree that Cleisthenes' exile is
cannot 'have made much of an impact'. But the very fact that it was erected, pre- a terminus post quem for the statues.-The suggestion, first made by P. Corssen,
sumably at public expense, is sufficient proof that the action of Harmodius and Berliner philologische Wochenschrift 23 (1903) 350-1 and Archiiologischer Anzeiger
Aristogeiton had made an impact earlier than 477 B.C. (1903) 41, and elaborated by A. E. Raubitschek, AJA 44 (1940) 58 n. 2, JHS 60
3 Paus. I. 8. 5, who attributes their return to Antiochus; Val. Max. 2. 10, ext. (1940) 54, and Dedicationsfrom the Athenian Acropolis 116,482, and 514, that the
I, attributes it to Seleucus; and Pliny, NH 34. 70, and Arrian, Anab. 3. 16. 7-8 and Antenor group does not antedate 488 B.C., has effectively been laid to rest by the
7. 19·2, to Alexander. arguments of Brunnsaker 90-5.
4 Marmor Parium, ep. 54 (Jacoby), with Paus. I. 8. 5. 8 Cf. Becatti, op. cit. 100.
II:ONOMIA AND ATHENS 135

the two stanzas of the Harmodius skolia, shows that the tyran- Cleisthenes. The same reason may also explain the second dis-
nicides were in fact honoured as such very soon after the libera- tortion of historical fact, the attribution of the establishment of
tion.1 \Vhat made the Athenians accept this misrepresentation of the democracy to Harmodius and Aristogeiton. \Ve have tried to
fact so soon after the liberation must remain a matter for show above that the opponents of Cleisthenes, to whom Jacoby
speculation; still, a probable explanation is not hard to find. If wants to assign the skolia, cannot be identified. But is it really
the Kedon and Leipsyclrium songs were composed, as it is sug- necessary to assume that only opponents of Cleisthenes could
gested they were (above, p. 127), by the exiled opponents of attribute the establishment of Zuovop.,{a to the tyrannicides? Can-
Hippias soon after the events which they celebrate, and if the not the Harmodius have been sung without malice? If Herodo-
same people sang the second (I I) and third (12) stanzas of the tus (5. 78) could credit the defeat by the young democracy of
Harmodius soon after the murder of Hipparchus, as Ehrenberg Spartans, Boeotians, and Chalcidians in rapid succession to its
has suggested,2 these exiles might after the expulsion of Hippias ZU7]yopl7], it is not hard to believe that the Athenians would them-

have credited with the actual achievement those heroes whose selves celebrate the establishment of ZuovofLla in a song. In fact, if
martyrdom had sustained them in exile, and who had inspired we were to look for a specific date for the first (10) and fourth
them to persist in their efforts until Hippias was finally ousted. (13) skolion, the enthusiasm reflected in Herodotus' statement
Moreover, since the role of Delphi and of the Alcmaeonids in the about the source of the victories would make 506 B.C. a vcry
expulsion had been confined to prompting the Spartans, whereas likely occasion. To have included Cleisthenes' name in the praise
the actual success was due to Spartan arms (Hdt. 5. 62-5; Arist. of ZuovofLla would have been in bad taste; but to attribute it to
Atlz. Pol. I g. 2-6), the Athenians may have wished to suppress the the same hero-martyrs to whom the liberation had been attributed
fact by making the liberation an Athenian affair.3 could hardly have given offence to Cleisthenes. On the contrary,
This, it seems to me, is the most plausible reconstruction, on it would not be surprising if a man of Cleisthenes' political
the basis of the few facts we do know, of the atmosphere and the acumen had found considerable propaganda value in attributing
spirit in which the first (IO) and fourth (13) stanzas of the to Harmodius and Aristogeiton the sum total of his political
Harmodius were created. There is, accordingly, no need to read achievement, not only his part in the liberation from tyranny but
a slight to Cleisthenes, motivated by party spirit, into the fact also the establishment of ZaovofLla in Athens. In this manner, far
that this simple patriotic song ignores the Alcmaeonid contribu- from minimizing his own merit, as some have asserted, 1 he would
tion to Hippias' ouster. For when patriotic songs name heroes, have counteracted any odium that may have attached to him for
they name thc dead and not the living, and the courageous attempt having accepted the archonship of 525/4 B.C. from Hippias,2 and
of Harmodius and Aristogeiton, their failure notwithstanding, at the same time would have enlisted popular support for his
was more likely to capture the popular imagination than either programme by presenting it as the continuation and completion
the army of Cleomenes or the machinations of'Delphi and of what Harmodius and Aristogeiton had set out to accomplish.
These considerations do not, of course, constitute proof that the
~ Ehrenber?, HL 68:-9, accepts a date after 507 B.C. for the first stanza (10). The first (IO) and/or fourth (13) stanza of the Harmodius song
objectIOns raIsed agamst this by P. Leveque and P. Vidal-Kaquet, Clisthine originated in Cleisthenes' circle, but they do show that the
l'~tM~ie~ 30 n. 2, namely, 'on a peine it croire que Ie meurtre prive d'Hipparque
solt Slvlte devenu un acte politique', loses its force in that it fails to take anv note of
Antenor's tyrannicide group. ' I K. Schefold, Museum Helveticum 3 (1946) 67-70. For an effective criticism ofllis
Z See above, p. 125 with n. 3. view see Ehrenberg, OD 533-4·
3 Th~s has be~n suggested by Ehrenberg, OD 530 and 532-3, accepted by z See the fragment of an archon list of c. 425 B.C., published by B. D. Meritt,
B.runnsaker 25 with n: 94 .. Cf. Bowra, GLP 394.-A good modern parallel is pro- Hesperia 8 (1939) 59-65 (= SEG 10, No. 352). That the inscription is an archon-
VIded by the ceremomes stIlI held every 20 July in Germany to commemorate the list and that Cleisthenes' name appeared on it as the archon for 525/4 B.C. can be
generals who on that day in 1944 were no more successful than Harmodius and regarded as settled, W. E. Thompson, C] 55 (1959-60) 217-20, C. W. J. Eliot and
Aristogeiton had been in putting an end to a tyranny which was put down a year M. F. McGregor, Phoenix 14 (1960) 27-35. Additional fragments of the list are
later only through the outside intervention of the allied forces. published by D. W. Bradeen, Hesperia 32 (1963) 187-208.
glorification of the tyrannicides is not incompatible with the role
the Alcmaeonids played in making Athens laov6;wvc;, and they
support the date shortly after 507 B.C. for which we have been
arguing.!

NOMOS AND THE BEGINNINGS OF


THE ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

HE fact that the laovop.,{a of Athens was celebrated in song

T and attributed to the national heroes shortly after 507 B.C.


permits the inference that the term was not invented by the
author or authors of stanzas IO and 13 of the skolia, but was
borrowed from the actualities which he or they set out to cele-
brate. In other words, these stanzas indicate that the concept of
laovop.,{a played a part in the events leading up to and culminat-
ing in the establishment of the Athenian democracy by Cleis-
thenes. Weare not told by any of our sources what this part was,
and for that reason certainty about it is impossible to attain.
Still, we do know enough about the reforms themselves and the
political activities preceding and following them to enable us to
reconstruct a sequence of events in which the principle of lao-
vop.,{a can be assigned a place.
Thanks to the work of H. T. Wade-Gery! it is now possible to
form a reasonably accurate chronology of the events leading up
to the reforms and of Cleisthenes' role in them. After an initial
period of accommodation between Hippias and the heads of
some of the noble 'political' families of Athens, in which Cleis-
thenes accepted the archonship for 525/4 B.C. and Miltiades that
for the following year,2 relations between the tyrant and the
noble gene again became strained. Few details are known about
this development for the period between the end of Miltiades'
I Essays ! 35-54.
Z See above, p. !35 with n. 3.
138 NOMOI; AND BEGIKNINGS OF .\ TIIE:\L\N DEMOCRACY IEONOMIA, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOE 139

archonship and the murder of Hipparchus at the Panathenaic unlikely to have been the only factor in alienating the affections
festival of 514 B.C. At some time before 511/10 B.C. and probably
I of the Spartans from the Peisistratids,I it was doubtless a suf-
within the period 524/3 to 514 B.C., the Alcmaeonidae, the genos ficiently weighty factor for later tradition to ascribe the eventual
whose head was Cleisthenes, went into exile; Miltiades of the liberation of Athens from tyranny to the Alcmaeonids as well as
Cimonid family2 was sent off by the Peisistratids to the Thracian to the Spartans (Hdt. 6. 123. 2; Thuc. 6. 59. 4). A Spartan at-
Chersonese, probably about 5 I 6 B.C., which indicates perhaps tempt under Anchimolius to invade the city from the sea was
that the archonship had failed to reconcile him to the Peisistra- frustrated soon after the landing by Cine as and his 1,000 Thes-
tids, who were suspected of having had his father Cimon mur- salian cavalry, who came to Hippias' aid. To discourage similar
dered;3 and, if any trust can be placed in Andocides (2. 26), his attempts in the future and to protect himself in the face of a
great-grandfather Leogoras went into voluntary exile. Relations deteriorating situation in Athens, Hippias immediately began to
deteriorated further after the murder of Hip parch us : the tyranny fortify Munichia in the Piraeus, but before this enterprise was
grew harsher and many members of noble families were exiled completed, a second and larger Spartan force, led by king
or killed.4 As a result, the opposition to the tyranny stiffened. Cleomenes, invaded Attica and routed the Thessalian cavalry
Several attempts by the exiles to force their way into Athens and sent against them. Athens was now open to Cleomenes and,
oust Hippias were thwarted, among them the attempt by Kedon, together with 'those Athenians who wanted to be free', consisting
a nobleman,s and the more ambitious effort, spearheaded by the presumably mainly of the exiles, he besieged the acropolis, where
Alcmaeonidae, to fortify Leipsydrium, which we have already the Peisistratids had taken refuge behind the Pelargic Wall.
mentioned (above, p. 127). After Leipsydrium, the Alcmaeonids According to Herodotus, the siege would not have resulted in
used a different method to secure their aim. Through their capitulation, had not the children of the Peisistratids been cap-
friendly connections with Delphi, established early in the sixth tured as they were being smuggled out of the country. To obtain
century when Alcmaeon commanded the Athenian troops in the their safe return, the Peisistratids surrendered and agreed to
First Sacred \Var,6 they obtained the contract to rebuild the leave Attica within five days, which promise they fulfilled by
Temple of Apollo, which had been destroyed by fire in 548/7 settling at Peisistratus' old stronghold in Sigeum on the Scaman-
B.C. (Hdt. 2. 180; Paus. 10. 5. 13), and with the contract came der in the Troad.
the administration of large sums of money and influence at Of these events only the fortification of Munichia, interrupted
Delphi.? By a judicious deployment of both they persuaded the by Cleomenes' incursion, and the surrender of the acropolis are
Pythia to instigate the Spartans to liberate Athens, and the given a precise date by Aristotle. The former is placed 'in the
Spartans complied despite the friendly relations which bound fourth year after the death of Hipparchus' and the latter 'in the
them to the Peisistratids. Although the prompting of t~e Oracle is archonship of Harpactides' (Ath. Pol. 19. 2, 6),2 and both dates
converge on our 511/10 B.C. The sequence of events in the next
I Except where otherwise stated, the account in this paragraph is based on three years can be established only in barest outline, and we
Hdt. 5. 62-5 and Arist. Ath. Pol. 19. lack much essential information even on the events themselves,
2 The reasons for calling the descendants of Cimon Coal emus 'Cimonids'
rather than 'Philaids' are stated by vVade-Gery, Essays 164 n. 3. I Arist. Ath. Pol. 19. 4 (cf. 17. 3-4) suggests that the friendship between the
3 For Miltiades' dispatch see Hell. 6. 39. I, with \Vade-Gery, Essays 161-3; for Peisistratids and Argos was a source of annoyance to the Spartans. In addition, the
Cimon's death, Hdl. 6. 103.3, with Wade-Gery, Essays 155-8, and A. Andrewes, Spartans will certainly not have liked Bippias' overtures to Persia after 514 B.C.
The Greek Tyrants 110. through the marriage of his daughter to the son of the tyrant of Lampsacus
4 Cf. also Hdl. 5. 55, Thuc. 6. 59. 2. (Thue. 6. 59. 2-3). And, in general, the tradition on Sparta's enmity to tyranny
5 That he was a nobleman is suggested by the aya8oi, al'8paatl' in the second and on her overthrow of the tyrannies in Greek cities is so strong that, although we
line of the couplet cited by Aristotle, Ath. Pol. 20. 5. know few details, it may have motivated her to liberate Athens; see Thuc. I. 18.
6 Plut. Solon II, with <W.) G. Forrest, BCH 80 (1956) 41-'2 and 49-51. I, Arist. Pol. 5. 10, I312b7-8.
7 For an excellent summary of the nature and sources of this influence see 2 The expulsion of the tyrant is dated in the fourth year after the murder of
Leveque and Vidal-Kaquet, op. cit. 40 n. 3. Hipparchus also by Hdl. 5. 55 and Thuc. 6. 59·4·
140 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY II:ONOMI A, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOI: 141

although they are among the most crucial for the development of archonship of Scamandrius, and there are good reasons for as-
Athens over the next hundred years. Harpactides had no doubt suming this to have been in 510/09 B.C.I
held his archonship with the approval of the tyrant or, at least, There is one further measure which may belong in the archon-
not without it (Thuc. 6. 54. 6). Since nothing else is known about ship of Scamandrius and which was later to be affected by the
him, we may assume that he was not an important 'friend of the reforms of Cleisthenes. We learn from Aristotle that after the
tyrants' and was permitted to serve out what remained of his overthrow of the tyrants a revision of the roll of citizens (owifiTJrpt-
term of office. The machinery of government probably did not GfLDS) was undertaken, 'since it was alleged that many were
cease to function, because, as Thucydides tells us (6. 54. 6), the enjoying citizenship, although they had no right to it' (Ath. Pol.
tyrants had left the old Solonian constitution intact, merely filling 13.5).2 We have no information on the procedure followed in the
the important offices with their own men, and the fact that the OWifiTJrptGfLDS and little about the identity of its victims. But since
archons were chosen directly and not by lot made this very easy proof of citizenship can only have been membership in a phratry
(Arist. Ath. Pol. 22. 5). Immediately after the fall of the tyranny, before Cleisthenes' reforms, we may surmise that the owifiTJrpt-
Athens returned to 'aristocratic politics as usual'. A struggle for GfLDS obliged the phratries (a) to determine who was and who was
political power erupted among the noble families who had played not a proper member, and (b) to exclude from exercising the
a part in the overthrow, very like the rivalries that had sur- rights of citizenship anyone who could not prove his membership
rounded the rise of Peisistratus earlier in the century (Hdt. I. in a phratry. This raises the question as to whom the owifiYJrptGfLDS
59-6 I ). Cleisthenes, the Alcmaeonid, opposed Isagoras, son of deprived of citizenship. Aristotle suggests that 'people of impure
Teisander, a member of an old noble family who sacrificed to descent' (ot T0 yEVEt fL~ KaBapo{) were affected by it, who-or
Zeus Karios.1 It is probable that their rivalry did not burst into rather, whose parents-feeling insecure in their possession of
the open at once. For the measures, which can plausibly be dated citizenship, had joined Peisistratus' diakrioi through fear (Ath. Pol.
to a time very soon after the expulsion of Hippias, aim at the 13.4-5). Greek tyrants often rewarded their supporters by grant-
punishment of the Peisistratids and the amelioration of condi- ing them the rights of citizenship,3 and Peisistratus or his sons
tions created by them, and they are unlikely to have divided may have so rewarded the Thracian and Argive mercenaries who
those whom opposition to the tyranny had just united. The first had helped win the battle of Pallene, his bodyguard,4 and per-
of these was the revival as BEGfLta Kat 7TCLTPWof an old Draconian haps other immigrants whom Peisistratus' development of indus-
law, under which anyone attempting or abetting the establish- try had attracted to Attica.5 Regardless of whether or not such
ment of a tyranny at Athens was declared an outlaw, and the I T. J. Cadoux, ]HS 68 (1948) 113, accepted by MacDowell, Andokides: On the
publication of the names of the Peisistratids-and presumably Mysteries 92-3.
also of the ban pronounced against them--on a stele erected 2 That there was a 'iita.pTJ</>wp.6safter the fall of the tyranny is disbelieved by
some scholars on the ground that it is thought to be in conflict with Aristotle's
on the acropolis.2 The second was the enactment of a decree statement, Pol. 3. 2, 1275b34-7, that Cleisthenes 7TO.\,\O,}s... E</>vAETEvaft'vovs Kat
prohibiting the torture of Athenian citizens (Andoc. 1. 43),3 80VAoVS p.ero{KovS; see F. Jacoby in FGH 3b, supp!. I. 158-60. However, since
evidently in order to prevent recurrences of the kind of treat- Aristotle attributes only the enfranchisement to Cleisthenes, the difficulty can be
resolved by assuming that the 8ta.pTJ</>wp.6stook place before the reforms of Cleis-
ment meted out to Aristogeiton after the murder of Hippar- thenes, very probably soon after the expulsion of Hippias; cf. Hignett, HAC 132-3.
chus.4 Andocides, our source for this measure, assigns it to the On the enfranchisement see below, pp. 151-2. 3 See Hignett, HAC 112.
4 Hdt. 61. 4, 64. I; Thuc. 6. 55. 3, 57. 1,58.2; Arist. Ath. Pol. 15. 2, 18. 4. It
I Hdt. 5. 66. I, Arist. Ath. Pol. 20. I, with D. M. Lewis, 'Cleisthenes and Attica', is noteworthy that the 80pv</>6po. seem to be of foreign origin, whereas the fifty
Historia 12 (1963) 25-6. KopuvTJ</>6po.,whom the people gave to Peisistratus at the beginning of his tyranny,
2 Arist. Ath. Pol. 16. 10, Thuc. 6. 55. 1-2, with M. Ostwald, TAPA 86 (1955) are explicitly described as citizens by Hdt. I. 59. 5 and differentiated from the
108-9' 80pv</>6po.; cf. Pluto Solon 30. 3.
3 It is not clear from the context whether this prohibition was confined to judicial 5 Immigration of skilled craftsmen into Attica and grant of citizenship to them
proceedings or whether it was more general in character. is attested only for Solon (Plut. Solon 24)' But it is very likely that Peisistratus con-
4 Thuc. 6. 57. 4, Arist. Ath. Pol. 18. 4, Diodorus 10. 17. 2, Polyaenus I. 22. tinued Solon's policy in this respect.
142 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY II:ONOMI A, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOI: 143

persons had ever been formally admitted into the phratries, they Hetaireiai as early as 506',1 at least not in the sense in which they
may well have exercised in practice such citizen prerogatives as existed toward the end of the fifth century, Aristotle's choice of
attending meetings of the Assembly and of the Heliaia with the words may indicate that the part of the conflict which Isagoras
explicit or tacit approval of the tyrant, whom they had helped won was a dynastic struggle for power in which each protagonist
and to whom they looked for protection. The descendants of such had the support of his aristocratic following (ETafpOt), 2 and the
people were no doubt regarded by many Athenians as Tip yEVEL point of Herodotus' 7TpoaETatpt~ETat may be that after his defeat
fL~ KaBapot and, even though by 510/09 B.C. they knew no home Cleisthenes made the people that which his aristocratic ETafpot
other than Athens, they were deprived by the tnafYJeptafLoS of had been before, namely, the main source of his political support.
rights which they may have exercised defacto without possessing In any event, the victory ofIsagoras over Cleisthenes of which our
them de iure, because they owed their position to the support they sources speak must have consisted in Isagoras' election to the
had given the tyrants. I
archonship, and it was probably after the election had taken
About the events of the year following the archonship of Sca- place that Cleisthenes began to seek the political support of the
mandrius (509/8 B.C.) we have only the information of the Mar- masses.
mor Parium that Lysagoras-otherwise unknown-was archon The chief difficulty in the chronology of the events in 508/7
eponymus, and that contests of men's choruses were introduced and 507/6 B.C. is that Aristotle dates the reforms of Cleisthenes in
for the first time,2 presumably at the Panathenaic festival. If, in the archonship of Isagoras (Ath. Pol. 21. 1), whereas Pollux tells
addition, we can trust Pliny's date (above, pp. 132-3), it was in us that it was under Alcmaeon that the Athenian tribes 'became
this year or the year preceding it that Antenor's statues of the ten' (8. 110). But the difficulty can be resolved with the help of
tyrannicides were erected. Of far greater importance, however, Herodotus' narrative of events (5. 66-73. 1), which Aristotle
is the rivalry between Isagoras and Cleisthenes, which must have (Ath. Pol. 20. 1-3, 2 I) followsvery closely, except that he separates
come to a head in this year. What precisely happened we do not his account of the content of the reforms from his account of the
know. All we are told is that Cleisthenes lost the struggle (Hdt. events leading up to the reforms, while Herodotus incorporates
5. 66. 2; Arist. Ath. Pol. 20. 1) and that Isagoras was elected as his more succinct account of the reforms into the general narra-
archon for the following year, that is for 508/7 B.C. (Dion. Hal. 1. tive.3 Following, then, the sequence of Herodotus, we may as-
74.6, 5. 1. 1). But we may draw one conclusion from Aristotle's sume that Cleisthenes proposed and gained acceptance of his
assertion that Cleisthenes' defeat took place Tafs ETatpEtatS. Since reforms after he had 'taken the people into partnership' after the
ETatpEfat are known in Athenian history primarily as political election of Isagoras to the archons hip (5. 66. 2). We shall come
clubs of young aristocrats of oligarchical sympathies, who played back to the significance of this later. For the moment it will
a prominent part in the events of 415, 411, and 404 B.C.,3 Aris- sufficeto say that the result of his cultivating popular support and
totle's statement has been interpreted as 'a mere inference' from of the reforms was, according to Aristotle, to 'turn the state over
the narrative of Herodotus, who uses the verb 7TpoaETatpt~ETat to to the common people'.4 The success of Cleisthenes' policy is
describe Cleisthenes' step of 'taking the people into partnership' indicated by the fact that he not only managed to get his reforms
after his defeat by Isagoras. \Vhile I agree that the passage can- accepted as a private citizen in the teeth of the archon in power,s
not be regarded as 'independent testimony of the existence of but also to get Alcmaeon, to judge by the name his kinsman and
I Wade-Gery, Essays 138, referring to Hdt. 5.66.2.
I e.g. the oopvrpopo' are alleged to have killed Harmodius (Thuc. 6. 57·4, Arist.
2 Note the adjective 7rpoowa€Ta'pov used to describe Leipsydrium in the skolion
Ath. Pol. 18. 4). Cf. Ar. Eq. 447-3, where the Sausage-seller accuses the Paphla-
quoted by Arist. Ath. Pol. 19·3.
gonian of being descended from the oopvrpopo' of 'Byrsine', wife of Hippias.
3 See Wade-Gery, Essays 136-9, also Cadoux, op. cit. 114-16 n. 249.
2 Marmor Parium, ep. 46 (Jacoby), with Cadoux, loco cit.
4 Ath. Pol. 20. 1 : a7rOO,OOV, .,.0 7rAT/IiH "'~v 7roA,nLav.
3 For a full discussion see F. Sartori, Le eterie nella vita politica ateniese del VI e V
S Wade-Gery, Essays 136, 142-3. For a more detailed argument which, in my
seeolo a. C. 99-143. For their activities in 415 B.C. see also MacDowell, op. cit.
opinion, effectively disposes of all earlier views see Cadoux, loco cit.
190-3.
144 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY IEONOMI A, CLEISTHENES. AND NOMOI: 145

supporter, elected as archon for the following year, S07/6 B.C. 1 It is Attica. Immediately thereafter, Cleisthenes and the seven hundred
also shown by the consternation revealed in Isagoras' reaction, families exiled with him were recalled (5. 73. I ; Ath. Pol. 20. 3)·
who knew no other recourse than to call in Cleomenes, with whom The reforms of Cleisthenes were, as we saw, passed in the
he had established friendly relations during the operations against archonship of Isagoras, and the fact that the curse on the Ale-
the Peisistratids in 511/10 B.C.2 Before intervening personally, maeonids was used as the pretext for the expulsion of Cleisthenes
Cleomenes, on instructions from Isagoras, sent a herald to Athens and his adherents suggests that Alcmaeon had already been
to demand that Cleisthenes and other Athenian families who were elected as archon for 507/6 B.C., but had not yet assumed office,
under the curse incurred by the Alemaeonid archon Megacles at for it is more likely that Isagoras would have called in Cleomenes
the time of the Cylonian conspiracy should leave Athens at once against an archon-elect than against an archon in power. We
(5. 70. 2-71; Ath. Pol. 20. 2).3 Cleisthenes complied, but the may, therefore, place the intervention of Cleomenes in the late
others whose banishment Isagoras had instigated Cleomenes to spring or early summer of 507 B.C., after Alcmaeon's election but
demand departed only after Cleomenes entered Athens with before he actually began to serve. We may further assume that
a small force (5. 72. I; Ath. Pol. 20. 3).4 Cleomenes next tried to Alcmaeon assumed office immediately after the return of the
disband the Council, which was still the old Solonian Council of Alemaeonid exiles and that the business of implementing Cleis-
Four Hundred and which must have played a key role in getting thenes' reforms was begun at once. But in addition to laying the
Cleisthenes' reforms adopted, and to entrust the government to an foundations for the internal stability of the state, the Athenians
oligarchy consisting of three hundred ofIsagoras' partisans.5 How- also had to protect themselves against external threats. Realizing
ever, the Council refused to be intimidated and, with the support that Cleomenes would wish to avenge his defeat, they sent an
of the common people, besieged the acropolis, where Cleomenes embassy to Sardis to ask for an alliance with Persia, the tradi-
and Isagoras had taken refuge. On the third day Cleomenes and tional enemy of Sparta (S. 73. 1).1 Artaphernes, the Persian
Isagoras capitulated, and Cleomenes and his men were given safe- satrap, agreed to the alliance on condition that the Athenians
conduct out of Attica.6 Some ofIsagoras' partisans were arrested give earth and water as a sign of submission to Darius. The
and executed, but Isagoras himself and probably also others of ambassadors accepted the condition but were disowned upon
his supporters escaped punishment,7 probably by fleeing from their return to Athens (5·73·2-3)·
I Pollux 8. 110, with Cadoux, op. cit. 114 with n. 248, who suggests that Ale- When the attack came, presumably in the spring of 506 B.C.,
maeon may have been a cousin of Cleisthenes and the father of Leobotes, who, the Athenians had to face it alone. Cleomenes had not only
according to Pluto Them. 23. I, became the accuser of Themistocles in 471 B.C.
gathered a force from the whole of the Peloponnese, in order, as
2 Hdt. 5. 70. I, where the friendly relations extend also to Isagoras' wife; Ath.
Pol. 20. 2. Herodotus says, to punish the Athenian people and to instal
3 Cf. Thuc. I. 126. 12. For a similar demand, directed at Pericles and made by Isagoras as tyrant in Athens, but he also arranged with Boeotia
the Spartans before the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War, see Thuc. I. 126. 2 and Chalcis to make a concerted attack on Attica from west,
and 127. I.
4 See Endnote, p. 185 below. north, and east at the same time. Accordingly, while he occupied
S That it was an attempt to establish an oligarchy and not merely to reduce the Eleusis, the Boeotians captured Oinoe and Hysiae and the Chal-
number of Councillors is indicated by Herodotus' Tlh· apXa.<; EVEXdp'~E and by
Aristotle's KVp{OVS KaOu'Tava, TfjS 1TO'\EWS.
cidians raided the north-eastern coast of Attica (5·74. 1-2).
6 Wade-Gery, Essays 136, interprets Aristotle as including Isagoras and the The Athenians decided to face their opponents in turn, one at a
Athenians in the safe-conduct. However, while it is true that Isagoras and some of time, beginning with the Peloponnesians. They were helped by
his supporters must have escaped the death penalty inflicted on the rest of the
Athenians, since Cleomenes soon tried to reinstate him (Hdt. 5. 74. I), Aristotle's I The Spartans had concluded an alliance with Croesus against Persia (Hdt. I.

TOV'; /-LET' athoil 7TclvTas, like Herodotus' DaoL 7}aav aUTwv AaKEOUL/L6vWL, refers only 69. 3), and after the conquest of Lydia had sent an ambassador to Cyrus to warn
to the followers of Cleomenes. him not to destroy any Greek city (I. 152. 3)' It is also worth noting in this connec-
7 The fact that Hdt. 5. 72.4-73. 1 mentions Timesitheos of Delphi as one of the tion that Demaratus fled to Persia after he was deprived of his kingship (6. 67· I,
executed guarantees the accuracy of that part of his story. On Isagoras' fate see 70).- That the question of medism is irrelevant to this Athenian embassy is rightly
the preceding note. stressed by A. W. Gomme, AJP 65 (1944) 321-2.
814277 L
146 NOMOE AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIA:'\ DEMOCRACY IEONOMI A, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOE 147

dissension, which split not only the Peloponnesian alliance but the Since ZfI7]YOPL7] is not attested earlier than this passage, we do not
Spartans as well: the Corinthians, immediately before battle, know whether it played any part in the events we have just
expressed disagreement with Cleomenes' purpose and went home, described. But we do know that ZfIovop,La, the adjective of which
followed in rapid succession by Cleomenes' royal colleague, is attested in the Harmodius skolia, is contemporary with these
Demaratus, and by the rest of the allies (5. 75. I, 3). The events, and we may be able to assign it a place by briefly
Athenians were now free to turn against their other enemies, examining the role played by the people, the oijp,o~ or TrA.ijeo~, in
internal and external. We learn that the houses of those Athen- this period.
ians who had joined Cleomenes at Eleusis were destroyed, their Both politically and economically the common people seem to
property confiscated, and they themselves condemned to death. I have fared reasonably well under the tyranny. Our knowledge
Of their external enemies, Herodotus informs us, the intention of details is agonizingly sketchy, but it seems certain that Peisis-
was to handle the Chalcidians first, but when the Athenians tratus based his power originally on the formal approval of the
heard that the Boeotians were marching toward the Euripus to Assembly. At any rate, it was the oijp,o~ which in 561/0 B.C. on the
help Chalcis, they changed their plan in order to intercept motion of Aristion voted him his first bodyguard (Ath. Pol. 14. I),
Boeotian help before it could become effective. The battle which and it is not insignificant that the first bodyguard consisted of
ensued was a decisive Athenian victory, which claimed many citizens (Hdt. 1. 59. 4-5). Although this is the only specific ex-
Boeotian lives and the loss of seven hundred prisoners. On the ample of a popular Assembly meeting that has come down to
very day of victory the Athenians crossed over into Euboea and us from this time, the fact that Herodotus (I. 59. 6), Thucydides
defeated the Chalcidians. Four thousand Athenian cleruchs were (6.54.5-6), and Aristotle (Ath. Pol. 14.3, 16.8) agree that public
settled on lands taken from the wealthiest Chalcidians, the officesand the laws were left intact and that he ruled like a states-
prisoners taken from both Chalcidians and Boeotians were later man and not like a tyrant suggests that the organs of government
ransomed at two mnai per person, and their fetters dedicated on as constituted by Solon continued to function, that is, that there
the Athenian acropolis (5. 77. 1-2).2 were meetings of the Assembly and of the lawcourts, and that the
The words which Herodotus chooses to indicate that the vic- people had at least a formal voice in the election of the magis-
tories of 506 B.C. constituted the baptism of fire of the Athenian trates. Moreover, there are several other indications of his popu-
democracy bring us back to the question which prompted us to larity. Aristotle explicitly remarks several times on his geniality
digress into an account of the factual framework of the end of toward humble folk (Ath. Pol. 13. 4, 14. I, 16. 8)1 as well as
tyranny and the beginning of democracy in Athens.3 Herodotus toward the nobles (16. 9). It is further shown in that the common
regards the victories as showing that ZfI7]YOPL7] is a 'good thing' people seem to have had no part in the two exiles of Peisistratus
(XP'TJP,a fITrOVOatov), because it enabled the Athenians to surpass but, on the contrary, welcomed him when 'Athene' returned him
their neighbours in warfare to a degree to which they had never to Athens after his first exile (Hdt. 1. 60. 5; Ath. Pol. 14·4).
surpassed them under the tyranny, and he attributes this develop- Economically, the farmers do not appear to have grumbled
ment in Athens to the enthusiasm of a free person to accomplish about the five-per-cent tax he imposed on their produce (Thuc.
something for himself as contrasted with the deliberately bad 6. 54. 5),2 and when one of them did, on the occasion of one of
performance of a suppressed person working for a master (5. 78).4 Peisistratus' inspection tours, Peisistratus granted him exemption
(Ath. Pol. 16. 6). In short, the peace and tranquillity which he
I Schol. Ar. Lys. 273. It is a reasonable assumption that Isagoras was among
them; see Wade-Gery, Essays 136-7.
brought to Attica earned his regime later the reputation of the
2 These cIeruchs were sent to the aid of Eretria against the Persians in 490 B.C. ;
see Hdt. 6. 100. I. I In these passages, if anywhere, do we have proof that 01)!"OTLKOS does not
3 That Herodotus regarded Cleisthenes' achievement as consisting in the simply mean 'democratic'.
establishment of the Athenian democracy is evident from 6. 13 I. I. 2 This figure seems more likely than the ten pe,. cent reported by Arist. A/h. Pol.
• On iUT]yop{T] cf. above, p. 109 n. 2, and below, p. 157 n. 2. 16.4 and 6.
'48 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY II:ONOMI A, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOI: '49

'life of the age of Cronus' (Ath. Pol. 16. 7). The more shadowy 508/7 B.C. Herodotus describes Cleisthenes' appeal to the people
sides of the tyranny do not seem to have bothered the common as a radically new departure in policy by saying that up to that
people too much. And if the Solonian laws which, according to point the Athenian oijfLos had been spurned, presumably by
Aristotle (Ath. Pol. 22. I), were eclipsed under the tyranny were Cleisthenes as well as by the rest of the nobility.' Our purpose
laws concerned with the election of magistrates, 1 it is improbable here is not to speculate about Cleisthenes' motives when he took
that the lower classes,who were not themselves eligible for election this revolutionary step. Suffice it to say that the durability of
to high offices,anyway, would get exercised over this curtailment his reforms and the success he had in getting them adopted show
of their rights. that he combined the vision of a statesman with the ingenuity
The friendly attitude of the common people toward the tyrants of a politician to use the political machinery available to him
and their political approval or indifference is corroborated by the toward the realization of his goals. Herodotus' statement ?]V TE
complete silence of our sources about popular participation in TOV OijfLov 17poaBEfLEvoS 170'\'\0 KUTV7TEpBETWV dvnaTumwTEwv,2 indi-
the various attempts to overthrow the tyranny. Harmodius and cates what common sense demands, anyway, namely, that the
Aristogeiton belonged to the nobility, and the repressive measures people were won over before the reforms were passed, and his
which followed their attempt must have been directed primarily strength over against that of his opponents surely refers to the
-if not exclusively-at the nobility.2 Moreover, the epigrams on passing of the reforms, to the election of AIcmaeon, and to
Kedon and on the dead of Leipsydrium make a special point of Isagoras' inability to control the situation without the help of
the fact that they were nobles,3 and 'those Athenians who wanted Cleomenes. Perhaps the most amazing aspect of Cleisthenes'
to be free', who joined Cleomenes in 511/10 B.C. in besieging the success is that within a year, that is between the elections of 508
tyrants within the Pelargic Wall (Hdt. 5. 64. 2), were doubtless and those of 507 B.C., he gained not merely the fleeting popularity
also predominantly members of the nobility.4 The struggle be- of the masses, but a loyalty deep enough to make the people join
tween Cleisthenes and Isagoras, whose beginnings may date to the Council in resisting Isagoras and Cleomenes-and that at
the period immediately after Hippias' ouster, seems to have been a time when Cleisthenes was himself in exile, unable to provide
initially no more than a dynastic struggle between two factions of leadership-and instilled in them a morale high enough to cope
noblemen, one of whom had been exiled from Athens during the with an invasion on three fronts in 506 B.C.
last years of the tyranny, while the other had been able to stay in The crucial question for our purpose is one which, to the best
the city.s of my knowledge, has only recently been seriously raised for the
The first time that the common people enter into the picture in first time by D. M. Lewis:3 what was the secret of Cleisthenes'
this period is after Cleisthenes' defeat by Isagoras, that is, after success? How did he go about wooing the favour of a people
Isagoras' election, in the spring of 508 B.C., to be archon for which had prospered under the tyranny, whose disposition to-
I This is suggested by Thuc. 6. 54. 6: Tn OE "AAa aVT~ ~ lTOALS TOrS lTplv KELfl-€VOLS
ward the tyrants was friendly, and which had presumably not
v6JLOCS EXpfjTO, 1T)..~V Ka8' aaav aiEl TLva E7TEP..€ADV'TO ac/Jwv aVTwv €V Tai~ apxais flvat. cared very much about politics? What promises did he make to
For a different interpretation see Hignett, HAC 115-16. enlist their support?
2 Hdt. 5. 55 and 62. 2; Thuc. 6. 59. 2; Arist. Ath. Pol. 19. I.
3 The Kedon epigram, Arist. Ath. Pol. 20. 5, speaks of ayaBors avopacuv, and the
Aristotle explains the trust of the people in Cleisthenes as due
~,eipsydr!um sko~ion, ~bid. 19. 3, of "vopas .•. / ayaBovs TE Kal EVlTaTploas, / at TOT' I 5. 69. 2: <Cleisthenes) TaV l1B1Jvalwv ofifl-OV lTPOTEPOV alTW0fl-€VOV TOTE lTaVTWS
e:ongav OtWv 7TQ'TEPWV (Gay. 7TpaS T~V €WVTOV fl-orpav lTpooEB~KaTO. It is not entirely clear whether the participle
4 These may have included Leogoras and Charias, ancestors of Andocides, if a7Tw0fl-€VOV is to be interpreted as a rejection of the people by Cleisthenes or by the
this is the battle ElTl IIaAA1Jvlep of which he speaks at I. 106, c)'. 2. 26; see Mac- ruling classes as a whole. The latter was true as a historical fact but, although either
Dowell, Andokides: On the Mysteries 140 and 212-13. interpretation is grammatically possible, it is easier to take the subject of the
5 That Isagoras had stayed in Athens during the tyranny is inferred by G. Busolt, sentence, Cleisthenes, as the agent who had formerly spurned the people.
GG 22• 401 n. 2, and Wade-Gery, Essays 138-9 with 139 n. I, from a combination 2 5. 69. 2: 'After he had won over the people he was much stronger than his
of Arist. Ath. Pol. 20. I, "'lAOS cOv TWV Tvpavvwv, with Hdt. 5. 70 and I. 64 respec- political opponents.'
tively. For their struggle as a dynastic affair see above, pp. 142-3, on the haLpEraL. 3 'Cleisthenes and Attica', HistoTia 12 (1963) 22-40, esp. 38.
150 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY II:ONOMIA, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOI: 151

to (a) his opening the political life in the city to the people as of Attica. I While this may be the programme of a great statesman
a whole, I (b) Isagoras' mistake in calling in Cleomenes and in who had recognized the weakness of the Solonian system, would
trying to establish an oligarchy, and (c) the role the Alcmaeonids it have had a strong appeal to people who had been indifferent to
had played in the overthrow of the tyranny.2 The last of these politics and who would find little in common with their fellow
factors, (c), is of doubtful validity, unless we assume that the tribesmen from a different region?
common people had changed from indifferent supporters of the It is probable that certain aspects of the deme system, which
tyranny in 511110 B.C. to its bitter opponents by 508/7 B.C. provided the substructure of the tribal reforms and presumably
Isagoras' mistakes, (b), can chronologically only have exacerbated preceded it, had a better chance of engendering popular en-
a populace already won over by Cleisthenes or, at least, alienated thusiasm. The most immediate result of making the deme rather
by an oligarchical policy pursued by Isagoras. The only factor than the phratry the smallest political unit (Hdt. 5. 69. 2; Arist.
which remains, (a), the extension of participation in political life Ath. Pol. 2 I. 4) was that residence in a given locality rather than
to the people as a whole, shows the effect of Cleisthenes' political membership in a kinship group now became the criterion of
activity3 and only hints at the general character of the propa- citizenship. One of the consequences of this must have been to
ganda he may have used to win the people over and at the general offset the effects of the OLUI/l'YJepLafLOS of 51019 B.C. There is no
tenor of his reforms. But the question of the devices used to rouse indication that the descendants of those foreigners whom the
popular support remains unanswered, and we have to find more tyrants had admitted to Attica were told to leave the country
indirect ways of finding an answer to it. To do this we first have when they were deprived of their civic status after the overthrow
to turn to the reforms to examine not only what the common of the tyranny. Accordingly, the presumption is that they still
people stood to gain from them, but particularly what features in resided in the demes in which they or their parents had settled
them will have fired the popular imagination sufficiently to and that they were admitted as demesmen and thus as citizens in
explain the enthusiastic support which the people gave Cleis- the same way in which all other deme residents were admitted.
thenes. These are probably the people of whom Aristotle speaks as
The institutional innovations which the reforms brought to VWTrOALTUL (Ath. Pol. 2 I. 4), and to whom he refers in the Politics
Athens do not in themselves provide a satisfying answer. Hero- (3·2, 1275b36-7), when he says that Cleisthenes 'admitted into
dotus regarded the increase in the number of tribes from four to the tribes many foreigners and slaves resident <in Attica)'.2 While
ten as tantamount to the establishment of democracy (5. 66. 2, this enfranchisement looms large in Aristotle's account of Cleis-
69. 2; 6. 131. I); but it is hard to see why the mere fact of an thenes' reforms, it is improbable that large numbers were in-
increased number of tribes should have evoked such a spirited volved and that the measure was anything but incidental to
response. The same is true of the aims which Aristotle attri- his reforms.3 That these people would become his loyal and
butes to Cleisthenes' tribal reforms, namely the desire to mix up devoted followers is obvious. But they alone could not have
the population so as to have a wider participation in political carried the reforms in the Assembly, and if, as has been sug-
life4 and to have represented in each tribe all the different regions gested,4 they had tried to intimidate those assembled on the Pnyx
I This, I believe with Wade-Gery, Essays 147-8, is the sense of Ath. Pol. 20. I: [ Ibid. 2 I. 4: ihrws EKaaTTj J1;€TEXTJ 1TavTlLIv TWL' T07TWV.
Q.7TOOtOOVs T~ 1TA.:rjfJ€t, 'T~V TTO).,,"'T'€Lav. 2 J. H. Oliver, Historia 9 (1960) 503-7, followed by F. R. Wiist, Historia '3
2 Ath. Pol. 20, with the opening of 2 I. I: o,,1 /-,€V ovv 7'au7'a, 7'11,aiT{a, <1T{U7'£U£V (1964) 370-3, denies the enfranchisement of aliens by Cleisthenes by giving
" ofj/-,o, 7'0 KA«uO,v«, where the /-,€V ovv refers to the main points of the preceding <</>VAfT£VU£in this passage the sense of 'formed into a separate class'-impossibly,
chapter; see E. Kapp and K. von Fritz, Aristotle's Constitution of Athens and Related since there is no example of a loose use of </>vA1in any of Aristotle's works, and since
Texts 180-1 n. 117. he does not use </>OAOVat all. Oliver's arguments have been effectively answered by
3 Note particularly the force of the present participle a1TooLooUS with the aorist D. Kagan, Historia 12 (1963) 41-6; cf. also D. M. Lewis, ibid. 37 n. 135.-The
main verb 1TpouTJyay£7'o, which implies that the extension of political participation 'slaves' mentioned here are probably the descendants of manumitted slaves who,
stretched over a period of time, sc. at least from ~pring 508 to spring 507 B.C. by the time of the reforms, would have attained metic status; see Hignett, HAC 133.
• Ath. Pol. 2 I. 2 : ava/-,£r~aL !3ovAO/-,£VOS, 01TWS /-,£7'aUXWUL 1TA£{OVS 7'fjs 1TOAL7'das. 3 Wade-Gery, Essays 148-5°; Hignett, HAC 133. • See Lewis, op. cit. 38.
152 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY IEONOMIA, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOI: 153

into voting for the reforms, the effect would have been the very not seem to have enjoyed. The demes had their own chiefs, the
opposite of that which they had intended, and they would have demarchs (ibid.),! who held office for one year and were subject
lost rather than gained support for Cleisthenes. to an audit; they had shrines and cults of their own, kept an
A further consequence of making the demes the basic political official register of their members (A1)ttaPXtKOV ypafLfLaTEtOv), had
unit was to undermine the hold which the noble families had had special advocates and financial assessors of their own, supervised
on the political life of Athens. The noble gene had exercised their the education and training of their own youth, and, above all,
political influence through the phratries,I which, though left in- met locally rather than in the city for their de me assemblies.
tact as religious units, were now eclipsed in political importance Moreover, there was a direct link between the demes and the
by the demes,2 and membership in the deme was made heredi- central government in that the demes rather than the trittyes or
tary.3 If the names of the newly-created demes indicate Cleis- the tribes chose the candidates for the Council (Ath. Pol. 62. r).
thenes' desire to undercut the influence of the nobility,4 and if the While it is hard to believe that all the de me institutions attested
demes were grouped into trittyes in such a way as to constitute for the fourth century owe their inception to Cleisthenes, it
'an attack on organisations which held a locality by religious ties, would be very strange indeed if the most basic of them, such as
some of them in areas attached to political opponents of Cleis- the office of demarch and the deme assembly, did not go back to
thenes',5 the purpose was not to weaken the noble families as him. This means that, by guaranteeing a substantial amount of
such or to deprive them of their religious centres, but to dissociate local autonomy, Cleisthenes gave the demesmen a local pride
political influence from religious institutions. Can Cleisthenes' which they had not previously had, especially if, as we must
popularity be accounted for by assuming a desire on the part of assume, they had in the past looked for political leadership to the
the commons pour epater I' aristocrate? If this played a part at all, it noble gene, under whose influence the various localities as well as
must have been a very small one, for if it had been a wholesale the phratries must have stood. But it is hard to believe that the
attack, Cleisthenes could not have made the people stop at de- promise of a measure of local self-government would in itself
priving the foci of aristocratic power of only their political role, have won Cleisthenes the support he needed, unless the promise
and if he wanted to use popular support merely to indulge in was made in the name of a principle larger than anyone par-
a personal vendetta against his political opponents, he will have ticular institution, which would hold out hope for a new political
had to endear himself to the people in some other way first before way of life.
using them for his personal ends. The circumstance that we have in the Harmodius skolia a con-
There is a further aspect of the deme reform, however, which, temporary document which contains in adjectival form a political
I believe, gets us closer toward an explanation of the popular principle which is 'more of a banner than a label'2 suggests that
enthusiasm which Cleisthenes evoked. We know that in the late laovofLla may well have been the slogan by means of which Cleis-
fifth century and in the fourth the demes enjoyed a certain thenes rallied the people to the support of his reforms. I know no
amount of local self-government of a kind which the naukraries, other word-not even 81)fLOKpaTla-which would have served
which they are said to have replaced (Arist. Ath. Pol. 21. 5),6 do equally well to describe the salient features of Cleisthenes' pro-
I See the excellent article of A. Andrewes, 'Phi!ochoros on Phratries', JHS 81 gramme and at the same time to differentiate that programme
(1961) 1-15· from those of his opponents. Practically every trait of the reforms
2 Arist. Ath. Pol. 21. 4 and 6. This did not mean, apparently, that the phratries shows that Cleisthenes was less interested in establishing a 'rule
were deprived of all their importance: in a citizenship grant of 409 B.C. the person
honoured is invited to choose his phratry as well as tribe and deme; see IG 12• 110
(= Tod, GHI 12, No. 86) 15-17. were increased to fifty. Their function after the reforms remains, however, uncer-
3 BS 2. 875 with n. 2. 4 See Lewis, op. cit. 26-7. tain. See Hignett, HAC 142.
5 Ibid., esp. 27~36 and 37. I For the following see R. J. Hopper, The Basis of the Athenian Democracy 14-15
6 This does not necessarily mean that the naukraries were abolished, for Cleide- with nn. 88-126. Cf. also BS 2. 966-72 and Hignett, HAC 136-7.
mus, frg. 8, states that as a by-product of Cleisthenes' tribal reforms the naukraries 2 Vlastos, IP 8.
154 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY II:ONOMI A, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOI: 155

of the people' (oYJ/-LOKpaTta) than in creating a balanced form of in connection with Cleisthenes' reforms (Ath. Pol. 2 I. 2 and 3;
government by giving all citizens equally the right to participate Pol. 6.4, 1319b2S-6) is in fact nothing but an aspect of the laovo/-Lla
in the political life of the state and by eliminating the political established when city, coast, and inland were, through the trittyes,
monopoly which birth and wealth had enjoyed so far. If, in given equal weight in each tribe. I
doing so, he laid the groundwork for the Athenian democracy of This is sufficient to show that laovo/-Lla would have been an
the fifth and fourth centuries, this was an organic development appropriate slogan for Cleisthenes to use in trying to win the
from Cleisthenes' achievement, it was not the achievement itself. common people over to his programme. There are two points
The achievement was to give the common people 'equality of which suggest that an appeal to laovo/-Lta would and could have
rights and power' with birth and wealth by organizing them in had the effect of enlisting the immediate and fervent support
the demes, in the tribes, and in the state as a whole in a way to of the people for Cleisthenes' cause. In the first place, no prin-
provide an effective check on those who, in accordance with the ciple and no slogan could have served to differentiate Cleisthenes
census classification of the Solonian constitution, were alone more strikingly and more correctly from his political opponents
eligible to the archonship and other high offices.We have already than laovo/-Lta. Certainly the tyrants, popular though they may
noted that the use of the deme as the smallest political unit and the have been, never practised iaovo/-Lla. On the contrary, they had
way in which a number of demes are arranged in a trittys tended arrogated unto themselves rights which no other citizen enjoyed,
to undercut what political influence religious and kinship organi- not even the nobles. And if the attempted establishment of an
zations may have had. But at the same time, the religious functions oligarchy of three hundred is any indication of the kind of
of the kinship groups were left intact (Arist. Ath. Pol. 2 I. 6). This political aims espoused by Isagoras, these, too, would hardly
is shown by the facts that Probalinthus and Hecale were politically qualify as bringing political equality to the citizens of Athens. In
separated from the cult organizations to which they continued to other words, no other term would have served Cleisthenes better
belong long after the reforms of Cleisthenes, by the splitting up than iaovo/-Lla to suppress any sympathy for the tyrants that may
of the Tetrakomoi among three trittyes, and by the division of still have lingered and at the same time win the people over to
Pallene among at least three demes, all contrived, according to his side in his struggle against Isagoras. That the citizenry would
D. M. Lewis, 'to create units which would be sufficiently distinct have responded favourably to this prospect of greater political
from existing local units to compete with them and to destroy the freedom in the face oflsagoras' desire to limit their participation
influence which they gained from possessing a common cult in a in public life requires no explanation.
common locality'. Thus the influence of the nobility was frag-
I The second point emerges from a consideration of the pro-
mented over a number of demes and trittyes, where it had as its cedure followed by Cleisthenes in his attempt to get the reforms
counterweight the votes of the common demesmen, and in this adopted. Wade-Gery tried to show more than three decades ago
way laovo/-Lta was created within the demes. On a larger scale, it that 'Kleisthenes found in the Ekklesia the authority with which
was established in the tribes in that the membership of each tribe to defeat the reigning Archon', 2 and although the grounds of his
was balanced among one trittys from each of the three regions,2
resulted in numerically unequal tribes. It remains, however, questionable whether
and the 'mixing' process of which Aristotle speaks three times the lot would really have created any instances of considerable inequality: on the
I Lewis, op. cit. 30-4, quotation from 34-5. In the case of Probalinthus an basis of Eliot's chart on p. 143 there is only one chance in one thousand that
alternative interpretation of its detachment from the Tetrapolis is that with it the a tribe would consist of three small trittyes and no chance at all that three large
Tetrapolis would have become too large a trittys; see C. W.]. Eliot, Coastal Dernes trittyes would form one tribe. On this point see also the cogent arguments of
of Attika (= Phoenix, suppl. 5) 144-5; but this is rather superficial and fails to take 'V. E. Thompson, Historia 13 (1964) 400-13, esp. 402-8, who concludes on p. 408
account of the political factors involved in its attachment to the coast-trittys of that there is 'no secure evidence for rejecting Aristotle's statement that <Cleis-
Pandionis, which are stressed by Lewis, op. cit. 31. thenes) did assign the trittyes to the phylai by lot'. Eliot modifies but does not
2 Arist. Ath. Pol. 21. 4, where Cleisthenes is said to have used the lot in assigning essentially alter his position in his reply to Thompson in Phoenix 22 (1968) 3-17·
one trittys from each region to each of the ten tribes. The use of the lot for this I Cf. Arist. Ath. Pol. 21. 4: 01rW, EKauT1J ,.,.<TEXTI 1raVTWV TWV T,l1rWV.
purpose is doubted by Eliot, op. cit. 141-5, on the ground that it might have 2 Essays 139-48, esp. 142.
156 NOMOE AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY IEONOMIA, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOE 157

conclusion may be questioned, the conclusion itself hardly admits Assembly was consulted on this occasion was the comparatively
doubt. Cleisthenes' motive for wishing to establish laovofl,{a can minor one of giving special protection to a distinguished citizen;
most satisfactorily be explained as a desire to eliminate from the people did not know that they were in fact voting for the
Athenian politics the dynastic feuds which had in the past helped establishment of tyranny. This means that Cleisthenes was taking
to bring Peisistratus to power I and which had erupted again after a very extraordinary step indeed when, after his defeat by Isa-
the overthrow of the tyranny. This accounts not only for the goras, TOV SijJLOV1TpOa€TaLpl'€TaL, I which may be translated 'made
new regional tribes, but also for the institution of ostracism, which the people into his political partners' and which may well refer to
Aristotle (Ath. Pol. 22. I) attributes to him, and the primary aim the procedure Cleisthenes adopted in choosing the Assembly as
of which seems to have been the prevention of aTom, before it the forum in which the fate of his proposals was to be deter-
should become rife. For through the institution of ostracism the mined. If this reconstruction of Cleisthenes' procedure and of the
collective judgement of the people, acting on the principle of motives for it is correct, it would be the first application in prac-
laovo}-tla, could be invoked to judge any political disputes between tice in Athens of the principle of laovoJLla. For in submitting his
two opposed dynasts before they came to harm the state. It is programme to the Assembly he gave the common people 'equal
possible and, in fact, probable that Cleisthenes first tried to get political rights' with the noble and wealthy to decide the way in
his programme adopted through a forum other than the As- which Athens should be governed. That he submitted his entire
sembly. This, at any rate, seems to be the best interpretation of programme to the Assembly at once is unlikely, and it is equally
Herodotus' assertion (5. 69. 2) that Cleisthenes, like the other unlikely that he won over the people by proposing to make the
nobles, initially 'spurned the Ofj}-t0,',2 hoping that he could per- deme the smallest political unit in Attica. For the number of
suade the rest of the political nobility of the merits of his plan. those who would have grasped the significance of the deme re-
Only when he saw that the interests of birth and wealth were too form immediately would have been too small to explain the
firmly and too narrowly entrenched to adopt a programme which impressive support implied by the words 'made the people his
alone, in his opinion, would be a permanent safeguard against political partners'. But the prospect of laovoJLla must have ap-
aTom" did he take the revolutionary step of submitting his plans peared as something very attractive to the common people, and
to the Assembly, appealing to the Sij}-to, in the name of laovo}-tla. if we assume, as we have good reason to do, that it was the
The institution of a popular assembly is in the Greek world as old principle of laovo}-tla which Cleisthenes used from the very begin-
as Homer. That an Assembly functioned under the constitution ning as the slogan or as one of the slogans in submitting his pro-
of Solon is indicated by the fact that the thetes were included posals to the Assembly, we can explain the enthusiastic reception
among its members (Arist. Ath. Pol. 7. 3; Pluto Solon 18. 2), and by which he received.2
the report that Peisistratus' first bodyguard was voted by the We may take a further step. Our analysis of the various
SijJLO, on the motion of Aristion (Ath. Pol. 14. I; c£ Hdt. I. 59. -VO}-to, compounds that are attested before 464/3 B.C. has shown
4-5)·But we know nothing about the powers of the Assembly I Hdt. 5. 66. 2; cr. 69. 2: 'TOV J40"lvaLWV o~fLov ••• 'TO'TE71'1lV'TWS7TPOS'T~V EWV'TOV
before Cleisthenes. It is worth noting that it is not one of the fLolpav 7TpoUEO~Ka'TO; and Arist. Ath. Pol. 20. I : 7TPOU"Iy6.YE'TO 'TOV o~fLOV.
2 lU"IyoPLa may have been another slogan used in Cleisthenes' propaganda,
three Solonian institutions which Aristotle (Ath. Pol. 9. I) singles although, unlike luovofLLa, this expression is not attested before Herodotus. We
out as 'favouring the common people', and in the case ofPeisis- have no evidence for the powers of the Assembly before Cleisthenes, but it is
tratus' bodyguard, the impression created by Herodotus and probable that only members of the upper classes could address it; on the other
hand, we know that in the late fifth and in the fourth century every citizen had the
Aristotle is that the Assembly gave its assent in much the same right to do so, see Aeschines 1.23; Ar. Ach. 45, Thesm. 379, and Eeei. 130. It is not
way as the Spartan assembly did: it listened and approved, impossible that this right goes back to Cleisthenes; if it does, it would explain the
but probably did not discuss. Moreover, the issue on which the peculiar use of the term in Hdt. 5. 78, cf. above, pp. 109 n. 2, and 146 n. 4·
G. T. Griffith, 'Isegoria in the Assembly at Athens', Ancient Society and Institutions:
J Hdt. I. 59. 3, 60. 1-3,61. 2,62. I; Arist. Ath. Pol. 13.4, 14.3-4, 15. I. Studies Presented to Victor Ehrenberg ... I 15-38, wants to assign it to Ephialtes in
2 Cf. above, p. 149 n. I. 462 B.C.
158 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY II:ONOMI A, CLEISTHENES, AND NOMOI: 159

that laovop,ta is the only one which has itself exclusively political themselves. We may have a small measure of confirmation for
connotations and reflects the political senses of vop,o, as the this view in Aristotle's statement (Ath. Pol. 22. I) that Cleisthenes
authority to issue norms and as the political norms and regula- enacted new VOp,Ot, aTOxa~Op,€voV TOU 7TA~Bov,. What these VOp,Ot
tions which a people accepts as valid and binding for itself.1 It is were Aristotle does not say except that he mentions the vop,o, on
rather unlikely that the suffix should have assumed a political ostracism. References to Cleisthenean VOp,Ot are conspicuously
sense without a prior or concomitant assumption of a political absent from the fourth-century orators,! and Hignett has drawn
meaning on the part of vop,o,. The last use of BEap,tov for 'statute' is from that fact the conclusion that none existed.2 But the fact that
attested for the period immediately following 511/IO B.C.2 If Aristotle mentions their existence must give us pause, and it is
Cleisthenes used laovop,ta both as the principle of his constitution by no means unlikely that the tjrryeptap,aTa by which, according to
and as the propaganda catchword through which he enlisted \Vade-Gery, Cleisthenes created his 7TOAtnta were called VOp,Ot
popular support for his programme, is it not probable that he by Cleisthenes himself.
was the first Athenian to substitute vop,o, for BEap,o, as the tech- The second consideration favouring the adoption of vop,o, by
nical term for 'statute'? Two considerations lend weight to this Cleisthenes is of a more general nature. If laovop,ta literally means
assumption, one expressing the conversative and one the revolu- 'equality of vop,o,', that is if the term signifies that what is re-
tionary aspect of Cleisthenes' measures. garded as valid and binding is so regarded by and for all classes
All indications suggest that Cleisthenes scrupulously avoided of society, no moment in Athenian history seems to be more
creating an impression that he was trying to nullify the work of appropriate for the substitution of vop,o, for BEap,o, than the
Solon. He abolished none of the institutions of the Solonian period immediately preceding and immediately following the
constitution, such as Council, Assembly, the archonships, and the reforms of Cleisthenes. The overthrow of the tyranny and the
Council of the Areopagus.3 He retained the Heliaia and kept the reforms which followed four years later filled the people with
names epVA~ and TptTTV, for his own political units even while a self-confidence which they had never experienced before. One
changing their structure, and he left the four Ionian epvAat as well reflection of that is the glorification of Harmodius and Aristo-
as gene, phratries, and priesthoods the religious functions they had geiton in sculpture and song in order to make the liberation and
before and under Solon. He left intact the Solonian property its consequences an Athenian achievement and gloss over the part
qualifications for office, and, above all, he did not abolish the played by Sparta,3 and, as we saw, it is not impossible that Cleis-
Solonian statutes, published on the axones, and constantly re- thenes may have used the glory of the tyrannicides to promote
ferred to as Solon's by the fourth-century orators. Since Cleis- his reforms by presenting them as the continuation of their work.4
thenes did not impose his measures as Solon did, but, as is most A further example, remarked on by Herodotus (5. 78), is the
probable, proposed and had them ratified by Council and As- success with which the young democracy defended itself on three
sembly,4 it seems to me extremely likely that he offered them as fronts against external enemies in 506 B.C. Much of the credit for
VOp,Ot to the Assembly to differentiate them at once from the this surge in morale goes to Cleisthenes, for by taking the people
BEap,ot of Solon and to indicate that he wanted to offer nothing as as his political partners he recognized as vop,o, for the people
a statute that had not first been ratified by the people as some- what had previously been vop,o, for the nobility only, namely, the
thing that they would promise to regard as valid and binding for making of important political decisions. At the same time, by
proposing his reforms in the Assembly, he made it clear that he
I See above, pp. 119-20. 2 See above, pp. 4 and 59.

3 These and the following facts are too well known to require detailed documen-
was not acting as a lawgiver in the sense in which Lycurgus
tation. For a convenient summary see Hignett, HAC 129-58, esp. 156-7. My only or Solon had imposed their legislation on Sparta and Athens,
major disagreement with Hignett is that I do not believe that the Council was an respectively, but that the people were themselves to take the
innovation of Cleisthenes (pp. 148-53).
4 I see no reasonable alternative in this respect to the view of Wade-Gery, [ V. Ehrenberg, Neugriinder des Staates 60-1. 2 Hignett, HAC 129-30.
Essays 135-54, esp. 139-48. 3 See above, p. 134. 4 See above, p. 135.
lOa NOMO;; AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

responsibility of accepting and implementing the measures pro-


posed by him. I If Cleisthenes himself did not make that point, the
subsequent presence in Athens of Cleomenes and his Spartan
troops on the side ofIsagoras will have driven it home; for that it
was driven home is proved by the resistance which the Council
and the people offered to Isagoras and the Spartans even when
~.,leisthenes' greatness as a statesman as well as a

W
Cleisthenes was not present to provide leadership. Is it not HI~~

probable that the experience of tyranny and of arams among the pohtlclan can be regarded as assured, it still remains to
I

noble families, on the one hand, and the function of acting as raise the question of his originality in using laovofLLa
their own lawgivers, assumed by the people under the guidance of both to help him promote his political programme and as a
Cleisthenes, on the other, brought with them a deliberate rejection description of its content, and in using vOfLoS to describe his
of 8wfLoS as being something imposed by a third party, in favour measures. Both terms, as we saw, are found in Athens before we
of vOfLoS as the ratification of what they wished to regard as valid hear of them in other states: no form of laovofLLa is attested before
and binding? No proof is possible that the reforms of Cleisthenes the Harmodius skolia and the earliest occurrence of vOfLoS as
are responsible for this change in terminology, but the indications 'statute' is in Aeschylus' Supplices.2 But it does not necessarily fol-
are that, since the change did take place at some point between low from this that the concept of laovofLLa was invented in Athens,
5II/1a and 464/3 B.C., it took place at this time and against this or that there were no other Greek states which called their
background. And if the Cleisthenean reforms do indeed provide statutes VOfLOL before the term took root in Athens. The survival
the background for the change from 8WfLOS to vOfLoS, it explains of more literature and more inscriptions from Athens than from
also why, in preference to the other possible terms for 'statute', any other part of the Greek world often makes us oblivious of our
the Athenians adopted vOfLoS, the most democratic word for ignorance of the history of the rest of Greece, and the silence of
'law' in any language. our sources for other states is not a sufficient argument for the
originality of Athens. In short, we lack the information which
would enable us to affirm or deny with any confidence that the
ideas of laovofLLa, or of vOfLoS as 'statute', or of both originated in
Athens in connection with Cleisthenes' reforms.
Still, there are some considerations which may help us to clarify
the problem of originality, even if they cannot solve it. Although
Cleisthenes' was the first successful attempt of which we know to
establish a democratic system of government in the Western
World, we know of democratic features in at least three other
Greek states before him. Is there any hint that laovofLLa and/or
vOfLoS may have played a sufficiently important part in any of
these to suggest that Cleisthenes borrowed either the terms or the
ideas inherent in them from one or more of these states?
The earliest piece of evidence that has come down to us is
a constitutional document from Chios, which reveals the exis-
tence of a number of democratic institutions on that island as
, This estimate is not shared by K.J. Beloch, Griechische Geschichte ,2. 2 318~33,
and by U. Kahrstedt, RE s.v. 'Kleisthen,.s'. .
2 S,.e above, pp. 43, 58--9, and 121-30.

K1 j :277 "I
162 NOMa}; AND BEGI"'~INGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY THE ORIGINALITY OF CLEISTHENES 163

early as about 575-550 B.C.lHowever, the institutions mentioned shows, FJ'ijTpat. Moreover, since these beginnings of democracy do
in this document do not seem to go beyond those attested for not seem to have led very far in Chios, it is improbable that
I

Athens under the Solonian constitution. Just as Solon made pro- Cleisthenes took his cue from them when he proposed his reforms
vision for appeals against magisterial decisions to be lodged before in Athens.
the Assembly sitting as a court oflaw, the Heliaia,2 so the Chian The Cleisthenean reforms have been related by several scholars
inscription provides for meetings of the popular assembly in some to the reforms which Demonax of Mantinea is said to have
judicial capacity, perhaps to hear the report of an auditor,3 or to enacted at Cyrene about the middle of the sixth century B.C.2
hear the appeal of a dissatisfied litigant;4 and in addition has Demonax was called in, according to Herodotus, to settle a num-
a popular council (f3ovA~ DYj/-wa{YJ) consisting of fifty members ber of problems, which began with the immigration of people
from each tribe, which meets once every month to hear appeals. from the Peloponnese, Crete, and the Greek islands. These immi-
The epithet DYJJ-watYjwhich this council bears is generally taken as grants had come at the invitation of Battus II Eudaimon. But
an indication that there existed in Chios also a second council, their arrival had led to difficulties with the neighbouring Libyans,
which was dominated by the nobility. If this is so, we have here who allied themselves with the Egyptians and, after an initial
a further parallel to Solonian Athens, which had both the Areo- reverse in the battle of Irasa, inflicted a crushing defeat upon the
pagus and, most probably, a popular council of four hundred Cyrenaeans at Leucon in the reign of Arcesilaus II. This defeat
members elected on a tribal basis (Arist. Ath. Pol. 8. 4; Pluto had been caused largely by intrigues of Arcesilaus' brothers, who
Solon 19. 1).5 after quarrelling with the king, fomented revolt among the
Although the inscription gives us information about the judicial Libyans. Arcesilaus met a violent end and, to add further to
system only, we may conclude that any 'democracy' Chios may Cyrene's troubles, his son and successor, Battus III, was a cripple.3
have enjoyed in the second quarter of the sixth century B.C.went It was to solve these problems that Demonax came to Cyrene.
no further than the institutions of the Solonian constitution in After a survey of the situation, he organized the population into
Athens, which it is more likely to have imitated than to have three tribes, one fLoLpa consisting of the descendants of the original
prefigured as a pattern. The Chian constitution of the sixth cen- settlers from Thera,4 one of the descendants of the Peloponnesian
tury does not, therefore, seem to have embodied the principle of and Cretan immigrants, and one of the descendants of those who
laovofLta. Its statutes were not v6fLoL in the sense in which we have had come from the islands. The powers previously wielded by the
interpreted that term, but, as the second line of the inscription king were turned over to the people,5 except that the king was
I First published by P. Jacobsthal and U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff,
permitted to retain his domains and his priesthoods. The language
'Nordionische Steine', Abh. d. kgl. preuss. Ak. d. Wiss. Philos.-hist. Cl. (Berlin, 1909) used by Herodotus to describe Demonax' grant of popular
64-71. The fundamental modern publication is L. H. Jeffery, 'The Courts of power, ES fLEaov Tip 8~fLqJ EBYjKE, is close enough to the language
Justice in Archaic Chios', BSA 51 (1956) 157~67, with full bibliography of earlier
work on p. 157 and date on epigraphical grounds on p. 160. Cf. id. LSAG 336~7.
which Otanes uses to propose the establishment of laovofLtYj in
See also J. H. Oliver, 'Text of the So-called Constitution of Chios from the First
Half of the Sixth Century B.C.', AJP 80 (1959) 296-,\01, and W. G. Forrest, 'The I Sce \V. G. Forrest, loco cit.
Tribal Organization of Chios', BSA 55 (1960) 172-89, esp. 180- 1. 2 The chief source is Hdt. 4. 161 ; see also Diodorus 8. 30. 2. The establishment of
Z Arist. Ath. Pol. 9. I; Lysias 10. 16; and Dem. 24. 105, as cited by Hignett, this relation may be due to Arist. Pol. 6. 4, 1319bI9-27, if the tribal reforms at
HAC 97-8. E. Ruschenbuscl{ has recently tried to show, Historia 14 (1965) 381-4, Cyrene to which he refers are indeed those of Demonax.-For the date of Demonax'
that the Solonian Heliaia was not instituted to hear appeals but to conduct trials reforms see F. Chamoux, Cyrene sous la monarchie des Battiades 138-42 and 151 n. 2.
de novo. 3 Hdl. 4. 159-61, with Chamoux, op. cit. 134-9.
3 So Oliver, op. cit. 299. 4 That 7TEp{OLKO' at Hdt. 4. 161. 3 refers to the descendants of those who were
4 H. T. Wade-Gery apud L. H. Jeffery, BSA 51 (1956) 163-4. 7TEp{OLKOL in Thera at the time when the expedition for Cyrene was organized has
5 The existence of a popular council under Solon is disbelieved by Hignett, been convincingly argued by L. H. Jeffery, 'The Pact of the First Settlers at
HAC 92-6, but his arguments are far from conclusive. A. Andrewes, Probouleusis: Cyrene', Historia 10 (1961) 139-47, esp. 142-4.
Sparta's Contribution to the Technique of Government 22, thinks that the Solonian council 5 Helt. 4. 161. 3: 7'd a,\,\a 7TCIVTa 7'd 7TPOUPOV dxov ot {3aaLME, ., /LEaov 7'0 (j~/Ltp
served as a model for Chi os. '0'1KE•
164 NOMO}; AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY THE ORIGINALITY OF CLEISTHENES 165
Persia and in which Maeandrius couches his offer of laollofl,{YJ to indeed many other lawgivers of that period were, 1 constitutes the
the Samians' to justify Chamoux's description of the constitu- most profound difference between him and Cleisthenes2 and
tion of Demonax as 'un regime d'isonomie ou plut6t d'isocratie',2 makes it impossible to believe that he called his enactments
and to explain why Aristotle may have been thinking of Demon ax llOfLOt; they were impositions of an outsider, not ratifications of
when he bracketed 7Tf'P~ KVP~llYJll Ot TOll MifLOll KuetaTUllT(<; with the popular will.
Clcisthenes (Pol. 6. 4, Iglgb22-g).3 Finally, the attempt of Maeandrius to establish an equalitarian
Unfortunately, we lack the information we need for a detailed system of government in Samos after the death of Polycrates in
comparison of the reforms of Demonax with those ofCleisthenes, 522 B.C. might have been a possible source of Cleisthenes' lao-
and we cannot tell from the little we know whether the latter may llofLtu.3 The incident itself sounds credible enough, especially
have borrowed from the former. But what we do know suggests since Herodotus mentions the name of an otherwise unknown
that borrowing is unlikely to have taken place and that, their Telesarchus as that of the man most vocal in frustrating Maean-
democratic features notwithstanding, the purpose of Demonax' drius' plans (g. 142. 5-14g. 1) and states that Maeandrius dedi-
reforms differed radically from that of Cleisthenes'. For while cated the valuables from Polycrates' apartments at the Heraeum,
Demonax was faced with the problem of integrating into the where, we may assume, Herodotus himself had seen them
citizen body recent immigrants who had not been absorbed into (g. 12g. r). The possibility of Maeandrius' influence on Athens
the three Doric tribes, in which the first settlers were presumably receives some support from numismatic evidence which suggests
organized, Cleisthenes' problem was to bring together different that the 'reign of Maeandrius marked a return to the friendship
regional and economic interests in the same tribe by means of his with Athens which his predecessor had abandoned.'4 However,
trittyes so as to eliminate rivalries which might lead to aTCI.aL<;.4 two considerations argue against an influence on Cleisthenes. In
Demonax' solution was to perpetuate the heterogeneity of the the first place, Maeandrius' flirtation with laollofLtYJ can only have
state by the creation of three new ethnic tribes (to replace the old lasted a very short time, so that any influence he might have had
Doric tribes), which received apparently each an equal voice in on Athens is likely to have come after he had given up his initial
the management of affairs; Cleisthenes' aim, on the other hand, plan and assumed the tyranny (Hdt. g. 14g. r-148. I). And
was to create homogeneous tribes.s In other words, if it is just to secondly, during his reign, Athens was still under the rule of
attribute laovofLtu to the reforms of Demonax at all, it will have Hippias who would not have taken enthusiastically to the cause of
to be in the sense that each new tribe received the same rights laollofL{u, and we know of no opposition to Hippias in Athens
and the same power. But since he did not go so far as to abolish in 522 B.C. that may have wished to use Maeandrius' principle
the kingship, he cannot be said to have established laollofLtu of political equality against the tyrant. For, as far as we know,
throughout the state as Cleisthenes did. Moreover, the fact that
I Scillus, Miletus, Thebes, and the Chalcidice are cited by Chamoux, op. cit.
Demonax came to Cyrene as a lawgiver imported from abroad, as
139 n. I, as having called in foreign lawgivers about the middle of the sixth century.
2 On the significance of this see also Leveque and Vidal-Naquet, op. cit. 68.
I Hdt. 3. 80. 2 and 142. 3, with pp. 107-9 and Iii -12 above; cf. also 7 164. I, 3 Hdt. 3. 142, discussed above, pp. 107-9.-]. P. Barron, 'The Sixth-Century
where Cadmus gives up his tyranny in Cos and goes to Sicily tJ1TO O'Katoavv"1~ .~ Tyranny at Samos', CQ N.S. 14 (1964) 210-29, esp. 211-12, does not carry convic-
p.€aov Kc/>OLUt Ka'Ta8£~s 'T~V apx~v. tion with his argument that Samos enjoyed a democratic form of government also
2 Op. cit. '4I. Unfortunately, Chamoux does not provide an interpretation of earlier in the sixth century, viz. after the overthrow of the oligarchy of the geomoroi
the meaning of isocratie. and before the revolution of Syloson 1. Our only authority for that event, Plut.
3 But it is uncertain whether the passage refers to Demonax; sec ,,y. W. How and
Quaest. Gr. 57 (= Mar. 303 e-304 c), says nothing about the establishment of
J. Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus 12• 355. Aristotle's reference may equally well a democracy or of any other kind of government following the overthrow, a~ is
be to a settlement following a'Tcfa,~ in 40' B.C., mentioned by Diodorus '4. 34. 6. pointed out correctly by M. E. White, 'The Duration of the Samian Tyranny',
4 See B. M. Mitchell, 'Cyrene and Persia', ]HS 86 (1966) 99-' 13, esp. 99. ]HS 74 (1954) 36-43, esp. 38. Moreover, the adjective 0WLO'TLKO" as applied to
5 Cf. D. M. Lewis, 'Cleisthenes and Attica', Historia 12 (1963) 39 with n. '46, Syloson by Polyaenus 6. 45, means no more 'democratic' than it does when used of
where I concur with Lewis's criticism of the mixed tribes suggested by Miss Peisistratus by Arist. A/h. Pol. 13.4, '4. I, and 16.8.
Jeffery, Historia 10 (1961) '43-4. 4 ]. P. Barron, The Silver Coins of Samos 35-6 n. 56.
THE ORIGINALITY OF CLEISTHENES 167
166 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

Hippias was still firmly entrenched in power in 522 B.C., on good was current in Ionia before it came to Athens. This view is
terms with the other nobles, and supported by the people. corroborated by the only other laovoiLty) passage in Herodotus,
As far as a specific programme is concerned, we know even less Aristagoras' grant of laovoiLty) to Miletus (5. 37. 2), which,
about Maeandrius than we do about the reform proposed by although its historical context is later than the Cleisthenean
Demonax. Maeandrius' proposal resembles Cleisthenes' pro- reforms, still reflects the currency of democratic aspirations, sub-
gramme in that it involves political equality for all citizens. But sumed under the name of laovoiLty), in Ionia about the same time.
it differs from it in two important respects. Unlike Cleisthenes, As we saw earlier (above, p. 109), a similar democratic under-
Maeandrius requested for himself and his descendants a pre- current in Ionia was also recognized by Histiaeus in 512 B.C. and
rogative that went beyond even that reserved by Demonax for the again by Mardonius in 492 B.C. (Hdt.4. 137. 2; 6. 43·3).
kings of Cyrene. For while Cleisthenes asked nothing for himself The cumulative effect of this evidence makes it likely that
and left the traditional priesthoods intact, and while Demonax Athens, whose ties with Ionia were always strong KUTa TO gvy-
reserved for the kings only their traditional domains and priest- yEvEe;, came under the influence of this Zeitgeist even before the
hoods, Maeandrius claimed in perpetuity the priesthood of a cult reforms of Cleisthenes. But we must not forget that we know of
which he had himself established and a payment of six talents in the relation of this spirit to laovoiLtu only through Herodotus. We
addition. 1 Still, despite the privilege claimed, Herodotus feels do not know whether in attributing it to the sixth-cenTury Ionians
justified in applying the name of laovoiLty) to the proposal, because he was not applying to the past a concept of his own time, per-
politically Maeandrius would remain on the same footing as haps even a concept he had encountered in Athens. The question
the other Samians. The second difference is more striking. The whether laovoiLtu travelled from Ionia to Athens or whether it was
reason Herodotus gives for Maeandrius' failure is that the Samians first coined in Athens and then applied to pre-Cleisthenic Ionia
were not ready for political equality: ou yap 8~, we; oLKum, must, therefore, remain open.
Ef30DAOVTO ElvUL EAED8EpOL (3. 143. 2). Cleisthenes' Athenians, on The situation is similar with regard to vOiLoe;. One of its earliest
the contrary, were ready, and we may interpret the difference uses in a legal text is to be found in an inscription from Herodotus'
as meaning that while Cleisthenes' laovoiLtu was supported by native Halicarnassus, written in the Ionic dialect and usually
vOiLoe; and succeeded, Maeandrius failed because the vOiLoe; of the dated about 460-455 B.C.I It embodies the outcome of delibera-
Samians was not on his side. tions by a meeting of the Halicarnassians, the Salmacitae, and
Still, this does not rule out the possibility that Cleisthenes Lygdamis, almost certainly the same Lygdamis who, according
learned from Maeandrius' mistakes, because he was a better to the Suda, was the tyrant ofHalicarnassus second in succession
politician than the Samian had been; and even if he did not to Artemisia and because of whom Herodotus left his native city
learn specifically from Maeandrius, it is possible that he was for Samos.2 It is concerned with the disposition of real estate in
influenced by events and currents pervading Ionia in the last lands and houses-whose possessions arc involved we are not
quarter of the sixth century. Although the {'vidence that Maean- told-and with the procedure of preferring claims for it. As we
drius preached laovoiLty) is no earlier than Herodotus, the use of noted above, the fact that the text twice refers to itself as vOiLoe;
the same word also by Otanes in the Debate of the conspirators (lines 32 and 34-5) shows that the term designates a written
(which is assigned to the same year as Maeandrius' proposal and statute.3 But this is not the only way of self-reference. In line 19
which Herodotus probably owes either to Persians whose Hel- I Tod, CHI 12, No. 25; Buck, CD, No.2. 2 Suda, s.v. 'HpoooTo<;.

lenism was derived from eastern Greeks or from eastern Greeks 3 See p. 44 above, where we pointed out that it is doubtful whether the oath,
who were familiar with Persian affairs)Zsuggests that the concept which, according to lines 19-20, the judges are to administer "o/-,'!', was laic! down in
some written legislation other than the present law. Most probably the expression
is no more than the Halicarnassian equivalent of "0/-,'/-,0<; 0PKO<;, a customary oath
I Cf. Hdt. 3. 142. 2 and 4 with 4. 161. 3 and with Arist. Ath. Pol. 21. 6.
formula, which in some cases at Athens was and in others was not specified ver-
2 Hdt. 3. 80. 6 and 83. I, discussed above, pp. 107 and III, with Endnote on
batim in the written statutes.
pp. 178-9.
168 NOMa}; AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

the term aDos is apparently used of the same inscription. What is was not transplanted to Halicarnassus from Athens, as it was
the relation between the two terms? The tone of the last section probably transplanted later to other parts of the Athenian Em-
of the inscription (lines 32-41) leaves little doubt that voj.to, en- pire. The reason is not the one usually given in dating this law.
joys a higher status than aDo, and comes, therefore, closer to Most scholars date it before 454 B.C.,because we know from the
describing the kind of 'statute' this is. Since aDo, is derived from tribute lists that Halicarnassus was by that time and remained
avOuvw = 'please', it may, like t//~1Jwfla at Athens, denote the henceforth one of the most reliable Athenian allies, and it is
form of the enactment, namely, the fact that 'it has pleased the assumed that Athens would not have accepted into the Delian
aVAAoyoS" to make this decision, or else it may refer to some League a city governed by a tyrant.I This assumption, however,
formality in the enactment, such as its ratification by some plenary is unwarranted, since we have no evidence that membership
assemblies of the Halicarnassians and the Salmacitae. I in the League was initially contingent on internal ideological con-
While it is not surprising to see in the course of the fifth century siderations; and since, moreover, the Athenians could tolerate an
the spread ofl1oj.toS' over many points of the Athenian Empire,2 it oligarchical regime in Miletus even after her revolt had been
is remarkable to find it in the early 450S as the description of crushed in 450/449 B.C.,2could it not have tolerated a tyranny in
a document to which a tyrant is a party. Still, it is not without Halicarnassus, provided that the tyrant would not medize?3 The
significance that we are here faced not with a decree enacted by later loyalty of Halicarnassus suggests that she may have joined
a tyrant, but with a statute which has resulted from the delibera- the League a considerable time before the fall of Lygdamis, per-
tions of a aVAAoyoS' of three parties, of which the tyrant is merely haps soon after its foundation. If this made her amenable to
one. There is nothing here to contradict our contention that voj.toS' Athenian influence in, inter alia, legal terminology, one might
is the ratification of something agreed upon as valid and binding. suspect that she adopted the Athenian term voj.to, for her own
Moreover, Lygdamis cannot here be acting in the name of his statutes and take perhaps the peculiarity of the use of the Ionic
subjects, for the Halicarnassians and the Salmacitae are separate dialect in a Doric community as corroborative evidence for that.
signatories to the law, and both are obviously included in the However, the use of aDoS' in the same inscription speaks against
expression .:4ALKapvaaaEwv DE TWS' aVj.t7TUVTLOV in lines 41-2 of the that. If voj.toS' had really been an Athenian importation, we
inscription.3 Since it is based on a negotiated agreement, it cer- should also expect to find the Athenian f~1Jwj.ta in place of aDoS',
tainly is a voj.toS' rather than a (Jwj.toS'. However, we cannot infer which is not Attic. The fact that Erythrae, after her revolt had
from this that voj.to, was the exclusive technical term for 'statute' been crushed, used both voj.toS' and f~1Jwfla in the same law in the
in Halicarnassus: it is possible that the Halicarnassians had two same sense as these terms bore at Athens4 shows the nature of an
different words for 'statute', one to denote the enactments of the Athenian influence that does not appear in this Halicarnassian
tyrant alone and voj.toS' to describe regulations such as the present, measure. While this suggests that voj.toS' = 'statute arrived at by
enacted after deliberation by a aVAAoyoS'. Moreover, we do not common agreement' was as indigenous to Halicarnassus as was
know whether the Halicarnassians began to use voj.toS' before or aDoS', we have no indication whether the term started in Hali-
after the reforms of Cleisthenes. carnassus early enough to assume an influence on the Cleis-
However, there is one consideration which suggests that voj.toS' thenean reforms and whether it described the only kind of
I Cf. a similar use of 0:80, (but without VOiLO,) in an inscription from Thasos of 'statute' known in Halicarnassus. Yet we can be confident that, as
412/1 I B.C., IG 12.8, 263. 7. For the use of the verb in a similar sense see BS I.
455 with n. 3. I See Tod, GHI 12, p. 38, and I. M.]. Valeton, Mnemosyne N.S. 36 (1908) 289.
2 e.g. in Erythrae c. 450 B.C. in Meiggs and Andrewes B 116. A 2 I, 27, and B 19- Z Meiggs and Andrewes B 30 and [Xen.] Ath. Pol. 3. I I, with ATL 3. 150, 151
20; in regulations for Colophon of 447/6 B.C. in IG 12• 15.30-1, with above, p. 42 with n. 10, 153, 154, and 255-6.
n. I; and in the assessment of 425 B.C. in Meiggs and Andrewes B 87. 15 (restored). 3 As did, apparently, the tyrants of Erythrae; see Meiggs and Andrewes B 26. 27
3 For the relation of Salmacis to Halicarnassus see F. Gschnitzer, 'Zur Ge- and 33.
schichte der griechischen Staatenverbindungen : Halikarnassos und Salmakis (SylJ3. 4 Meiggs and Andrewes B 116. A 21, 27, and B 19-20 for ,-ofLo,; B 1-2 for
45)', RhM 104 (1961) 237-41. f~"'LaiLa. Cf. above, pp. 45-6.
170 NOMO}; AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY
THE ORIGINALITY OF CLEISTHENES 171
long as Halicarnassus was ruled by tyrants, vO/-l-OS was not as- Locris (mo TWV VO/-l-LWV TWV E-TTtFOLr;>WV (line 27), which refers to
sociated with the idea of iaOVO/-l-Lu. stipulations laid down earlier in lines 19-22. It is less certain
In the case of the Halicarnassian law we have to reckon at whether written enactments are involved in what immediately
least with the possibility that v0/-l-0S had been transplanted from precedes and what follows this phrase: the property of members
Athens. Athenian influence is very unlikely in the final inscrip- of these clans left behind in Locris shall be subject to Locrian
tion we shall have to consider. It contains the foundation instru- VO/-l-LOLS and their property at Naupactus to those of that city
ment of an Eastern Locrian colony at Naupactus, which can be (lines 22-6), while upon their return home they will be subject
dated on epigraphical grounds in the first quarter of the fifth each to the VO/-l-LOLS of his city (lines 27-8). Were these regulations
century 1 and which on historical grounds must antedate the laid down in writing or are the VO/-l-LU primarily customary prac-
expulsion of the Locrians and subsequent settlement of the Mes- tices? The comparative sophistication of this 8E8/-1-LOV and the
senians by Athens about 460 B.C.2 The peculiarity of this law, parallel of Athens would again suggest that they were written.
too, is that it uses two different terms in self-reference. That the But we cannot be sure. Nor can we be sure in the case of the
term TO 8E8/-1-LOV (line 46) indicates the fundamental character of Naupactian VO/-l-LU (line 19) which are to apply in cases where a
this law as a constitution has already been mentioned (above, colonist dies without heirs in Naupactus and where the next of
p. 16). But it is interesting to note that 8w/-I-os is not used in kin in Locris fails to register his claim to the estate. Since it is
a similar regulation which Athens issued for the foundation of a matter of inheritance, the presumption would again be that the
a colony at Brea about 445 B.C.3 In addition, just as the Halicar- reference is to written legislation, especially since 'customary
nassian inscription used 0 noos of itself to describe the form of its practices' are not likely to have developed yet in the colony by
enactment, so we find TO. F€FuOYJ9oTa (line 38) at Naupactus, the time of the enactment of the present law. Another clause bars
evidently in the same sense. a delinquent tax-payer from the Locrians until he has paid TO.
What is, however, of greater interest for our purposes is that vO/-l-La before Naupactians (lines 15- 16). The reference isobviously
there is in addition one mention of vO/-l-os and six uses of different to 'lawful dues', 1 that is to the arrears which he legally owes the
forms of the adjective V0/-l-LOS. The difference between these two Naupactians. Again, we do not know whether the relevant tax
forms is hard to see. The vO/-l-OS mentioned is the law concerning laws existed in writing. Finally, there is one use of the singular in
inheritance in the various East Locrian cities which is to be in- the passage in which the judges are required to swear opr;>ov ToV
voked in cases in which a settler's brother falls heir to his property VO/-l-LOV before trying violations of this law (line 45), and it re-
in Locris (line 30). We have no way of knowing whether matters mains just as obscure here as it did in the Halicarnassian law
of inheritance were regulated by written statutes in Eastern whether a written statute embodied the traditional formula.2
Locris, but the fact that they were at Athens would suggest an The important feature of this Naupactian law for our purposes
affirmative answer. That they were written is also suggested by is that it contains three terms for 'written statute' : TO 8E8/-1-LOV, TO.
one of the uses of VO/-l-LOS in this inscription, which refers back to an F€FU07Jr;>OTU, and V0/-l-(L)OS, each with a peculiar sense of its own.
earlier clause in this law: special provisions are laid down for The fundamental constitutional character of the whole is ex-
members of the Percothariae and :Mysacheis4 who return to East pressed by TO 8E8/-1-LOV and the formal ratification it has undergone
I Tod, GHI IZ, No. 24; Buck, GD, No. 57. The epigraphical dating is in by TO. F€Fuo7Jr;>OTU, while VO/-l-(L)OS is used both of (written or un-
Jeffery, LSAG 106. For a discussion of the historical context see L. Lerat, Les
locriens de ['ouest (= Bibliotheque des Ecoles franfaises d'Athenes et de Rome, fasc. 176) written) laws concerning matters of inheritance, property, and
2. 29-33, and A. J. Graham, Colony and Mother City in Ancient Greece 45-60 with taxes not specified in the 8E8/-1-LOV, and of a clause that does form
translation on pp. 226-8.
part of it. This multiplicity of terminology demonstrates that it is
2 Thuc. I. 103. 3; Diod. II. 84. 7-8; Paus. 4. 24. 7, with Tod, GHI 12, p. 33.
3 Tod, GHI 12, No. 44. The beginning of the inscription is lost, but the end,
possible to find different words for different kinds of statute
where OWfLo, is most likely to have occurred, is very well preserved. within the legal system of one city-state and should make us
• For these see ibid. p. 34.
I See A. J. Graham, op. cit. 51 and 227. 2 Cf. above, p. 167 n. 3.
172 NOMOI: AND BEGINNINGS OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY THE ORIGINALITY OF CLEISTHENES 173
wary of supposing that words other than vOfLoS may not have Draco's law would surely have been called a BWfLo<; and not
existed in Halicarnassus to describe, for example, a 'statute' a vOfLo<; in the decree authorizing its publication in 409/8 B.C. I

which did not result from the deliberations of a av'\'\oyos but one Nor do we know of any period in which BWfLoS and vOfLoS existed
which was decreed by the fiat of the tyrant. side by side as contemporary technical terms for 'statute' as they
We know too little of the constitution of the East Locrian did in Naupactus. If these considerations suggest anything, it is
states to be able to say whether their VOfLOL or VOfLLU were arrived that the change from BWfLoS to vOfLO<; was not a gradual affair but
at by institutions in which the people could express their accep- took place at a specific point in time, since vOfLo<; is not attested
tance (or rejection) of measures that were to be valid and binding in the sense of 'statute' before 511/10 B.C. and BWfLoS no longer
for them. The indications are that such institutions existed. Aris- has that meaning after that date. That the reforms of Cleisthenes
totle's words in the Politics (3. 16, 1287"6-8) suggest that Opus constituted this point in time is not susceptible of proof, but
had a single ruler with limited powers, who may be identical I think the probability that they were is made cogent by the
with the apxos whom the Naupactian law entrusts with the circumstantial evidence we have accumulated.
arrangement of trials (lines 42-3). But the text indicates clearly What conclusions can we draw from these considerations about
that his tenure of office is limited (lines 43-4), presumably to one the originality of Cleisthenes? Although both laovofLLu and vOfLoS
year (line 35). Moreover, we can infer from the law that Opus = 'statute' are first attested in Athens, we have seen that Hero-
had an assembly of one thousand and that Naupactus had an dotus relates the democratic currents in Ionia frequently enough
assembly in which all colonists were members (lines 38-40). Old- to laovofLLY) to make possible an Ionian influence on Cleisthenes'
father suggests that the 'one thousand' means all property-owning choice of this catchword as an accurate description of his pro-
citizens and states: 'Der Form nach ist diese Verfassung zwar gramme. Similarly, we have seen that vOfLOS may conceivably have
aristokratisch, aber stark gemaBigt, und nicht weit vom Ideal der been a current term for 'statute' in Halicarnassus or in Eastern
konservativen Demokratie entfernt, da in einer so kleinen Ort- Locris before it came to Athens. Proof is impossible in these
schaft wie Opus die Anzahl der grundbesitzenden Burger nicht matters, and the position is equally defensible that it was from
vie! groBer gewesen sein kann.'1 If this is correct and if this body Athens that vOfLO<; began to spread over the Greek world as early
was, as is likely, entrusted with the enactment of the laws, the as the late sixth or early fifth century. It cannot be proved, either,
terms vOfLoS and VOfLLU would indeed be an appropriate descrip- that it was Cleisthenes who effected the substitution of vOfLo<; for
tion of their enactments, even if the system of government could BWfLoS in Athens. But since our comparison with Naupactus tends
not be characterized by laovofLLu. Still, we know no more than we to show that its adoption in Athens was the result of a deliberate
do in the case ofHalicarnassus how early this terminology started policy, Cleisthenes is the most likely candidate for having pro-
in Eastern Locris and must, therefore, leave open the question posed and implemented that policy. And even if Cleisthenes
whether Cleisthenes may have borrowed the term from there. borrowed both vOfLo<; and laovofLLu from other parts of the Greek
The lack of our knowledge of any relations between Athens and world, he was original in that he was the first to combine them in
East Locris in the sixth century makes such an influence im- a way in which no other state is likely to have combined them
probable. before, and to express through them the principle and the in-
The multiplicity of terminology also illustrates another point. strument of the Athenian democracy.
The Eastern Locrians, making proper allowance for dialectical
variation, have the same terms for 'statute' as those we encounter
in Athens, BWfLo<; and vOfLOS. But while the two terms have dif-
ferent connotations in Naupactus, there seems to be no difference
between them in Athens; for if there ever had been a difference ,
I RE s.v. 'Lokris (Staat unci KuItur)' 1248.
noun TaU, BWfLOO, in connection with Draco's activity at Ath. Pol. 4. I,
employs the adjectival TO. B€afLLU in his description of the function of
the thesmothetai, suggesting thereby that their work dealt with particu-
lar cases and was, therefore, of lesser moment than Draco's work. The
purpose alleged for the writing and preservation of the B€afLLU, sc. their
Page 12
use in settling future disputes, provides a possible clue to Aristotle's
My interpretation of Pind. Ol. 13. 29 is at variance with the tradi- notion of their nature. He seems to have thought of them as records of
tional interpretations based upon the scholia, which want BWfL6, here judicial proceedings, embodying either the decisions rendered in each
to mean either 'the institution of celebrating Olympic victors in song' case or the principles underlying particular decisions. That records of
( TE B•fLOV TOV
" VOfLOV' VOfLO,
, yup" Eanv aUTO"
,. , 0'I\UfL1TWVLKU,
, UfLVEW
, - B UL) or this kind were actually kept as early as the seventh century is not
'the song of the Olympic victors' (TO V EyKwfLLuanKOV A6yov, 0, Eanv improbable. But since they were kept only for the guidance o~ the
VfLVO, TWV VLKr;<p6pWV). Gildersleeve wants to accept the second of magistrates, they would not have satisfied the demands for codIfica-
these explanations, Sandys translates 'triumph-band', Puech 'pompe tion of the existing laws, which culminated in the appointment of
solennelle', Hirzel, TDV 326 n. I, speaks of 'Sangesweise', Lattimore Draco. The thesmothetai may thus have paved the way for the more
translates rather obscurely 'festival measure', while C. M. Bowra, systematic and comprehensive legislation of Draco. For a fuller di~-
Pindar 196, interprets it as 'the fit rite of garlands in the revel'. The cussi,m of the problems involved see A. Ledl, Studien ::;uriilteren athenz-
difficulty with all these interpretations is that they do not take sufficient schen Veifassungsgeschichte 268-7 I, and Hignett, HAC 76-7.
account of the relative clause which follows: TOV ayEL 1TEStWV €K IItau,
can refer grammatically only to TEBfL6v. That Xenophon should have Page 36
brought the institution of celebrating Olympic victors in song from
On Thuc. 2. 34. I see F. Jacoby's brilliant article 'Patrios Nomos:
the plains of Pisa is no more likely than that he imported the song
State Burial in Athens and the Public Cemetery in the Kerameikos',
itself or led the triumph-band in a fit rite all the way from Olympia to
Corinth. Tf:BfL6v is, accordingly, best taken closely with aTE<pavwv to
JHS 64 (1944) 37-66, with the criticism of Gomme, HCT 2. 94- 10 1.
The main issue between Jacoby and Gomme, viz., when in fact
refer to the wreath which was placed on his brow at Olympia, and
public burial of the war-dead started in Athens, need not concern us
which he brought home with him from the plains of Pisa.
here. What does concern us is Thucydides' use of 1TaTpw, v6fLo, to
Page 16 describe it. In calling the institution a 1TaTpLo, v6fLo" Thucydides is not
interested in the date of its origin at all, beyond saying that it has
Arist. Ath. Pol. 3·4 describes the early function of the thesmothetai as become a traditional practice (so rightly Jacoby 39-40 and 58;
01TW, avuypa!jJUVTE, TO. Biaf-LLu <puAaTTwaL 1TpO, T~V TWV afL<PLa(Jr;TOOVTWV Gomme 94 takes Thucydides as dating this law [sic] 'as early as
KptaLv. The precise character of these B€afLLU is hard to ascertain. That
Solon if not earlier') by the end of the first year of the Peloponnesian
the activity of the thesmothetai described here antedates Draco's legis- War. 'Even if, as Jacoby 52 suggests, the custom began in fact with
lation is indicated by the facts (a) that Aristotle, lac. cit., dates the a law enacted for the burial of the dead ofDrabeskos in 465/4 B.C., it is
office after the introduction of the annual archonship, sc. after 682/1 not such a law that Thucydides means by 1TaTpw, V6fLo, here, since
B.C., and (b) that Thucydides 1. 126. 8 speaks of the nine archons in
he explicitly mentions those fallen at Marathon in 490 B.C. as an
connection with the Cylonian affair. Moreover, since Arist. Ath. Pol. exception (34.5). This brings us to another point. Sin~e we know. of
41. 2 attributes to Draco the earliest publication oflaws, he must have several other instances besides Marathon where Atheman casualtIes
envisaged the original function of the thesmothetai as differing in kind were buried on the battlefield, both Jacoby (42-7) and Gomme (98)
from Draco's legislative activity. The most decisive difference between accuse Thucydides of blundering. But the yE in the expression 1TA'ljv yE
them is indicated by the use of the verb <pUAanwaL in connection with 'TaU, €V MupuBwVL is in itself sufficient proof that Thucydides had no
the thesmothetai: evidently Aristotle thought of them as keeping in their intention of giving a complete list of exceptions: there was no need for
care the B€afLLU which they had written down, whereas Draco's him to do so, and to limit himself to the most outstanding exception
statutes, as is clearly implied at Ath. Pol. 4. 4, were publicly displayed sufficed to show his awareness that the 1TaTpw, v6fLO, was not always
for all to see. It is further noteworthy that Aristotle, while using the observed. In fact, the expression mJ.Tpw, v6fLo" which Jacoby himself
176 ENDl'\OTES
in a different context calls 'an entirely vague expression which only E'\w8EpLav than V7TOV'\OV Eiwo/l-LaS', which falls rather flat. Moreover,
means "an old law", "a law from the time of our fathers'" (Atthis v7T6would serve better than a7T6 to under.score the irony in aVTovo/l-La.
244-5), does not imply that the custom was observed regularly, and Translate: 'self-determination imposed by the Athenians'.
the atd in Thucydides' statement: Kat atEt EV aVT0 [sc. T0 Ka'\'\LaTqJ
, ] 8'a7TTovaL TOVS'
7TpOaaTELqJ
" EK TWV
~ 7TOI\E/l-WV
\, can carry only the sense Page 99
of 'on each occasion' when public funerals of the war-dead take I have printed the text which is accepted as Alcmaeon, frg. 4 in DK6.
place. I translate: 'According to Alcmaeon, what constitutes the bond of
health is the isonomia of the powers, of wet and dry, cold and hot,
Page 73 bitter and sweet, and the rest, while monarclzia among them causes
A loose association of aw4,pocn5vYj with EVvO/l-La as a condition appears disease, since monarclzia of either opposite causes destruction. Disease
also in the Vatican manuscript (B) of Thuc. 8. 64. 5. The context is occurs through the agency of an excess of heat or cold, with surfeit or
the abolition of the democracy in Thasos by Dieitrephes in the sum- deficiency of food as the cause, and with the blood, marrow, or brain
mer of 41 I B.C. and the subsequent revolt of Thasos from Athens as its focus. Sometimes, however, it may arise in these foci from ex-
fomented by oligarchical exiles. In Thasos, as elsewhere among th~ ternal causes, such as certain kinds of water, or a region, or fatigue,
subject allies, Thucydides continues, the Athenian oligarchs achieved or violence, or similar factors. Health, on the other hand, is the well-
the opposite effect from what they had intended: awcj>poavvYjv yap proportioned mixture of the qualities.'-I accept this text, which is
'\af3ovaaL at 7T6'\ELS' Kat a8Ewv TWV 7TpaaaO/l-EVwv ExwpYjaav E7Tt T~l' based on [Plut.] De placitis plzilosoplzorum 5. 30, 91 I a, despite the fact
" '\ 8
aVTLKpvS' EI\EV EpLav
I ...., \ ,..,
TYjS' a7TO TWV /1
'A8 YjvaLWV
/ f 1\ , "
V7TOVI\OV EVV0/l-WS' OV 7TPOTLIH;-
I
that the corresponding text in Stob. Flor. 4.37.2+36.29 (Wachsmuth-
aavTE~: 'for on.ce the cities accepted moderation and immunity in the Hense 5) omits cj>80P07TOLOV yap EKaTEpov /l-0vapXLav and the last sen-
pursUIt of theIr own course of action, they progressed toward out- tence, T~V 8EvyELav T~V aV/l-/l-ETpOV TWV 7TOLWV Kpiimv. In reconstructing
right freedom, paying no attention to the sham of law-and-order the text of Aetius there is in general little to choose between [Plutarch]
coming from Athens.' In accepting this reading, both Hude and and Stobaeus, as H. Diels has shown in his fundamental discussion in
Stuart Jones reject the text of the majority of manuscripts (A, E, F, Doxograplzi Graeci 56-69' On the one hand, 'Plutarchi epitome veram
G, and M) : T~V {mo TWV J18YjvaLwv V7TOV'\OV aVTovO/l-Lav. Their reason for Aetii imaginem reddit sed in angustiorem multo formam redactam'
doing so is that the text ofB concurs with a quotation by Dionysius of (ibid. 61); on the other, 'in excerpendi negotio Stobaeo neglegen-
Halicarnassus,. Epistula ad Ammaeum 2. I I, who cites it as an example tior et liberior est Plutarchus' (ibid. 63). In this particular instance,
of (a) a peculIar use of the genitive and of (b) an imprecise use of the reasons for preferring [Plutarch]'s version are the following:
a masculine participle agreeing with a feminine subject. That this is (a) [Plutarch] preserves the logical order of the fragment in proper
s~f?ciently co~ent to accept the genitives and the masculine par- sequence, while Stobaeus breaks it in two, putting the second part,
tICIple as genume has been convincingly demonstrated by W. Rhys which he starts with MYEL 8ETaS' v6aovS' aV/l-7TL7TTELV ... , first. (b) In view
Roberts, CR 14 (1900) 244-6. But this does not exclude the possibility of that, the omission of the last sentence (T~V 8E vyELav ... ) is easily
that dVO/l-LaS' is a misquotation of aVTOVO/l-LaS', the kind of mistake of explained, since it makes sense only in relation to the first part of the
which there are many examples in Dionysius; see, for example, a7To- fragment. (c) Similarly, the omission of cj>80P07TOLOV ydp ••. may be
Td"J!.LaLS' (op. cit. 5) for 7TEpLTELXLaLS' (Thuc. 3. 95. 2), where the con- due to Stobaeus' failure to take the fragment as one unit, since it
fUSIOnalso affects the prefix, cf. Roberts, op. cit. 245. I believe for two forms the last sentence of the first part. (d) The clause cj>80P07TOLOVyap
reasons th~t a~TOVO/l-.LaS' (which, incidentally, also appears as a margi- EKaTEpov /l-ovaPXLav adds nothing new to the thought of the fragment,
~al c~rr~ctIOnm B) IS the correct r~~ding. In the first place, the adjec- for both [Plutarch] and Stobaeus go on to ascribe disease to the
tIve V7TOV'\OV makes us expect a polItIcal catchword used by Athenian domination of one in a pair of opposites over the other, [Plutarch]
propaganda, and aVTOVO/l-La is far more likely to have been held out to naming the domination of heat over cold or vice versa, and Stobaeus
the·Thasian 8ijp.oS' than EVVO/l-La, which is not attested as part of the naming the supremacy of heat or dryness [sc. over cold or wetness,
vocabul~ry of the psychological warfare between Athens and Sparta respectively]. The additional clause in [Plutarch] is, therefore, merely
concernlll?, .the subject allies. Secondly, V7TOV'\OV aVToVO/l-LaS' would a clarifying statement which connects the monarclzia image of the
serve stylIstIcally better to create a balance with E7Tt T~V aVTLKpvS' first part with the explicit definition of disease in the second, and it
814277 N
,~ ENDNOTES
ENDNOTES '79
may well have come from Aetius or from his source. (e) The last
Herodotus believed in the veracity of those who had told him about
clause of the [Plutarch] fragment does no more than define health in
it. That his informants were hellenized Persians may be inferred from
terms analogous to the preceding definition of disease. These terms,
3.87, and Jacoby, RE, suppl. 2 (1913) s.v. 'Herodotus', 414-15, has
moreover, are so close to those used by Theophrastus as well as by
even suggested possible names. Still, the Greek tenor of the discussion
Aetius in their discussions of Presocratic thinkers (especially Em-
does not exclude the possibility that Asiatic Greeks may have been
pedocles, Anaxagoras, Diogenes, and Democritus) that it may well be
Herodotus' immediate source, although the Greek (perhaps, more
a genuine piece of doxographic tradition.
specifically, Sophistic) tone can equally well be explained as due to
Herodotus' associations at Athens and/or Thurii. Apart from the
Page 105
form of the Debate and apart from most of the arguments used, it
The earliest uses of lao/Lotp{a and related terms refer to the balanced seems by no means intrinsically improbable that a discussion on the
distribution of shares or an inheritance among several members, as, future form of government for Persia was actually held by the con-
e.g., the distribution of the universe among Zeus, Hades, and Poseidon spirators of 522 B.C. That monarchy, the traditional constitutional
in II. 15. 209 (cf. 186-95); cf. Solon, frg. 23. 2 I, where only two parties form which eventually prevailed (see Darius at 3. 82. 5: TTaTp{OVS
are involved-the KaKo{ and the €a8.\o{-whom Solon does not want v6/LovS /LTJ.\tinv ExovTas EV) would have come up in such a discussion
to have an equal share in the good lands. In this sense, the concept is goes without saying. Similarly, there is no reason to doubt that one of
especially common in legal questions of inheritance by several heirs: the conspirators might have proposed the abolition of monarchy and
LawsofGortynX. 53 (mostaccessibleinBuck,GD,No. II7,P.32I); the establishment in its place of an oligarchy including the seven
Isaeus I. 2 and 35 ; and [Dem.] 48. 19 (where only two heirs exist). In .
conspIrators (8 ' ,,-
3. I. 3: avopwv - aptaTWV
TWV , I , \ 'i: '\ I
ETTtl\EsaVTES 0/Ltl\tYjV ..•
,
EV
Athenagoras' speech, Thuc. 6. 39. I, the verb lao/Lotpdv denotes the
ydp 3~ TotiTotat Kat aVTOt €Vw6/LE8a). Otanes' advocacy of democracy
political equality of the rich, the intelligent, and the many in a
may have been made credible to Herodotus (a) by the privileged
democracy; cf. Agrippa's statement, Dio Cassius 52.4. 3, that equality
position which his descendants still enjoyed in Herodotus' own time (3·
of birth demands equality of rights. The noun as well as the verb can
83.2-84. I); (b) by the generous way in which Otanes initially acted
also refer to a balance of political influence in international affairs, as
toward Maeandrius, who had wanted to establish laovo/L{Yj on Samos
in Thuc. 5. 69. I or Isocrates 5. 39. Furthermore, both verb and noun
(3. 142-4) ; and (c) by the fact that later on a Persian, Mardonius, was
are used by Thucydides for the moral sharing of misfortune, e.g. in
instrumental in replacing the Ionian tyrannies by democracies (6·43·
Aleibiades' speech at 6. 16. 4 and in connection with the miseries
3)' The last point (c) is made by Herodotus himself. If the informants
shared by the soldiers in Sicily at 7.75.6; cr. also Dionysius ofHalicar-
were in fact Persians or Asiatic Greeks, Herodotus may still have cast
nassus 6. 66. 4. Finally, in a number of passages in Xenophon, noun,
the content of what they told him into a form and conceptual frame-
verb, and adjective are used of an equal sharing of honours, prizes, or
work current in the intellectual circles in which he moved in Athens
privileges, e.g. Apology 21, Cyropaedia 2.1. 31; 2.2.18; 2. 2. 21; 2. 3.5;
and Thurii. In this connection, he may well have discussed the issues
and 4.6. 12.
with Protagoras and may have been influenced by him. I see no need
to assume with E. Maass, Hermes 22 (1887) 581-95, restated by W.
Page 107
Nestle, Vom Mythos zum Logos2 291-5, that Herodotus depends on
In view of the controversy concerning the source(s) of Hdt. 3. 80. a published treatise by Protagoras, the Antilogiai; nor need one pre-
2-82, I should like to state my position. I see no need to assume that suppose a specific elaborate Sophistic discussion by someone like
the Debate is taken by Herodotus, either verbatim or in paraphrase, Protagoras, as envisaged by K. F. Strohecker, Historia 2 (1953-4) 381-
from a previously published Sophistic work. If it were, it would be the 412. The case for a Persian source is most strongly stated-perhaps
only known instance of extensive borrowing on the part of Herodotus, even overstated-by H. Apffel, Die Veifassungsdebatte bei Herodot, esp.
and his twice-repeated avowal of the accuracy of his report, made in
48-83, where also an exhaustive survey of the literature on the Debate
the face of the incredulity of his contemporaries (3. 80. I and 6. 43·3),
between 1930 and 1957 is to be found on pp. 9-23. For the discussions
is sufficient evidence to show that he is not merely copying from some-
up to 1935 see K. Wiist, Politisches Denken bei Herodot 47-50. H. Erbse
one else. This does not of course imply that the fact and the content
in Glotta 39 (196 I) 228-30 has presented strong arguments against
of the Debate are objectively true history; but it does mean that
Herodotus' borrowing of the Debate from another author.
Page 118 comprehensible as a thoroughly respectable principle of political
\Ve do not know whether the capital assets of a Theban citizen had to equality, of which freedom of speech was one of the main characteris-
consist entirely or predominantly of agricultural real estate, or tics in the fourth century. In Panathenaicus 178 the laovofLia and
87JfLoKparia which the Spartans are said to have adopted for them-
whether monetary or other kinds of wealth were recognized; see
Cloche, op. cit. 74, and Moretti, op. cit. 133. Larsen, op. cit. 32, selves are contrasted with the oligarchical way (d"iyovs OVTas, ibid.
suggests that a law, cited by Arist. Pol. 3. 5, 1278'25-6, may belong 179) in which they deprived the 8ijfLos of the perioikoi of their lands and
to this constitution, which excluded from office anyone who had their political power (ibid. 179-80). I would not go as far as Vlastos,
engaged in trade within the preceding ten years. That the hoplite IP 18-'2I, in reading a moral norm into the lao- prefix here; the
census was the minimum property requirement is suggested by a moral censure is directed at the Spartans not for lacking equalitarian
number of considerations. In the first place, since each councillor principles themselves but for their refusal to apply these principles to
was a member of the executive for one quarter of his tenure of office, the perioikoi.
he would have to have an income sufficient to free him from the Plato is the only other fourth-century author in whose works
laovofLia occurs. The general tenor of the context in which the noun
necessity of having to work for his living for at least that period. This
argument is used for the federal councillors by Cloche, op. cit. 73, appears in Menexenus 239 a has been well discussed by C. H. Kahn,
but it no doubt also applies to the local councils. Secondly, as Larsen, 'Plato's Funeral Oration', CP 58 (1963) 220-34., esp. 225-6, as well as
op. cit. 32 with p. 203 n. 2 I, has pointed out, the prominence of by Vlastos, IP 22-33, esp. 31-3. I have nothing to add to Vlastos'
infantry in the Boeotian army suggests the hoplite census as a mini- analysis of laovofLia here, but I should like to emphasize the following
mum requirement for full citizenship. And third, the constitution points. Plato treats lcrovofLia in the Menexenus as a principle which will
'drafted for the future' by the Athenian oligarchs of 41 I B.C., which result in the appointment of the wisest and best, i.e. it embodies the
contained, according to Arist. Ath. Pol. 30, such features of the 'geometric' kind of equality based on merit, hinted at in Gorgias
Boeotian system as the four councils, limited eligibility to the councils 508 a and fully developed in Laws 6. 756 e-758 a. Of particular
to the Five Thousand, who belonged to the hoplite census, see Arist. interest from our point of view is the demand that laovofLla be sought
Ath. Pol. 33. 1-2 and Thuc. 8.65' 3. The parallel with Athens in 41 II 'in terms of law' (Kard vOfLOV). If, as I believe, the written statutes
IO B.C. is most instructive for our purposes, especially if G. E. M. de are meant here, we have in this passage the most explicit statement
Ste. Croix is right in arguing-as I believe he is-that the lower we have so far encountered of a close relation between lcrovofLla and
classes retained the franchise under the Five Thousand, making the 'statute'.
'oligarchy' considerably more 'democratic' than is generally believed, Very similar to the use of laovofLia in the Menexenus is its meaning in
although I would not go as far as he does in calling it 'basically two passages in the Seventh Epistle, where it is not only applied to an
democratic', see Historia 5 (1956) 1-23. That the lower-class Thebans as-yet-unattained principle, but apparently also related to the enact-
also had the franchise is quite possible (p. I 18 n. 3 above). ment of statutes. The relation to statute is possibly, but not necessarily,
envisaged in the earlier of these passages (326 d), where laovofLos is
Page 119 coupled with oiKaws as an epithet of a form of government opposed
Any difficulties about the meaning of laovofLla in the fourth century to the ever-changing tyrannies, oligarchies, and democracies. That
vanish once we realize, as I have tried to show above, that (a) it is the the adjective may mean 'having equitable laws' is suggested by the
principle of political equality and not a form of government, that it is, second passage, in which Dion's friends are exhorted to invite men
therefore, (b) more closely related to democracy than to any other from Sicily, the Peloponnese, and even Athens bT~ 7TC1.a7JS };LKE"las

form of government, but not confined to democracy nor identical KaroLKwfLoV rE Ka~ laovofLlav (336 d). This may of course refer to
with it, and that (c) political rights include the potential exercise of a 'resettlement of all Sicily on the basis of political equality'; but
political power. Isocrates, Areopagiticus 20, only mentioned in passing since laovofLla is placed into the context of Plato's hope for an end of
by Vlastos, IP 9 n. 2, matches the 7Tapp7Jala of his contemporary faction in Sicily and the establishment of VOfLOLKowol, which regard
democracy against the laovofLla which, he claims, prevailed in the the interests of victors and vanquished alike (337 a), he may well
'good old' democracy (of Solon and Cleisthenes, ibid. 16). Although have had in mind 'equitable laws' for all, which, if Dion's plans had
la7Jyopla would have been a more natural contrast, laovofLla is quite succeeded, would have resulted in 'most men having the same opinion
182 ENDNOTES
concerning excellence, which, once accepted, would have saved' the swords in boughs of myrtle before they drew them against Hip-
state (336 b). As in the Menexenus, we have here an laovofL{a related to parchus. The obvious objection to this is that it would have been a
equality based on merit and realized, it seems, through the enactment singularly inept way of trying to hide swords and would have been
of statutes. more likely to attract attention than to escape detection. In fact, if we
The value attached to laovofL{a in the Menexenus and in the Seventh are to take the singular literally (although there is no need to do so),
Epistle stands in sharp contrast to the negative treatment which Plato one bough or branch would hardly have sufficed. Moreover, there is
gives it in Republic 8, where it is ridiculed as tl:e principle ?f an no evidence for young men carrying boughs of any kind at the Pan-
equalitarian democracy which 'deals out some kmd of equalIty to athcnaic festival: only the carrying of olive branches by old men is
equals and unequals alike' (558 c): the democratic man, who sur- attested (Etym. Mag., s.v. BaAAoq,opoS and schoI. to AI'. Vesp. 544).
renders himself indiscriminately to the necessary and the unnecessary (b) It has been assumed that the myrtle was not meant as a covering
pleasures, is said to lead the life laovOfLtKoiJ nvos clvSpos (56 Ie), and the for the sword but as a wreath for its wearer. Thus, L. Ziehen, RE s.v.
laovofL{a Kd E'AwBEp{a which exist in a democracy between men and 'Panathenaia', believes that myrtle wreaths were worn by the partici-
women are severely censured (563 b). Vlastos, IP 34-5, solves the pants in the Panathenaic procession. But since he cites no evidence
discrepancy by rejecting the Seventh Epistle as not genuine, arguing, other than the first lines of the first and third stanzas of the Harmodius
inter alia, that we should have expected an explicit statement of his skolia, this argument is a non liquet.
change of views somewhere between the Republic and the Seventh (c) Many scholars subscribe to the view that the myrtle bough
Epistle. But the rather similar use in the Menexenus makes such a solu- adorned neither the sword nor its wearer, but the person singing the
tion too radical, and the absence of laovofL{a from Plato's works skolion at a banquet. Thus, W. Vollgraff argues in Mnemosyne 49
between Republic and Seventh Epistle is no more surprising than is its (1921) 246-50 that the reference in the Harmodius skolia is to the
complete absence from the fourth-century orators and especially wreath worn by the singing banqueter. The objection to this is that,
from the works of Aristotle. The central idea inherent in it came to be although we know that wreaths were worn at banquets (see Ganszy-
subsumed under the more general concept of laoT7JS and TO taOV (see niec, RE s.v. 'Kranz'), we know of no relation between the wreath
especially Arist. Pol. 3. 9, 1280'7-25, and 5. I, 1301'19-1302'8) and and the singing of drinking songs.
Plato's change of heart on that point, recognized by Vlastos, IP 34 (d) A more sophisticated version of (c) refers to the passing of
(citing Laws 3. 694 a and 695 d), and his elaboration of the two a myrtle bough from one person to the next at banquets as an invita-
equalities at Laws 6. 756 e-758 a are sufficient to account for the tion to sing (or perhaps to cap the song of the preceding singer). This
favourable view of laovofL{a in the Seventh Epistle. Cf. Polybius 6. 8. 4, practice is attested perhaps as early as AI'. Storks, frg. 4-30,and was
who uses laoT7JS 7ToAmK~ to express the idl"'ainherent in laovofL{a. known to Plutarch (Q.uaest. conv. 1. I, 615 b) ; cf. also the scholia to AI'.
Vesp. 1222 and 1239, to Nub. 1364, the scholiast on PI. Corg. 451 e, and
Page 136 Tzetzes, IafL{3ot TEXVtKoL 7TEPL KWfLcpS{as 85-9 (in Kaibel, Comicorum
H

Any discussion of the Harmodius skolia is honour-bound to voice an Craecorum fragmenta I. 42-3). The most recent supporter of this inter-
opinion on the enigmatic first lines of stanz~s 10 and 12:. EV fLV~T~V pretation is Bowra, CLP 392 n. I, and it is perhaps the least unlikely
KAaSL TO g{q,os q,op~aw. I have deliberately aVOIdedany mentIOn of It m of the views that have so far been advanced.
the text because I believe that we know too little to base upon it any But it is open to three objections. In the first place, despite the
view with any degree of confidence, a conclusion at which Ehrenberg, parallels advanced by Vollgraff, lococit., to which Ehrenberg (HL 62
HL 6 I-5, also arrived after a searching discussion of all the opinions with nn. 13 and 14) adds a phrase from Archilochus and one from
that have been advanced. I shall, therefore, confine myself to a a fifth-century vase inscription (W. Peek, Hermes 68 [1933] II 8-2 I),
critical statement of some earlier interpretations and add a reasoned the phrase EV fLVPTOV KAaS{ seems too elliptical to suggest this kind of
conjecture of my own simply to enlarge the list of possible solutions, procedure. Secondly, it is difficult on this interpretation, as Ehren-
but without any confidence in its correctness. berg has pointed out (HL 63), to see any connection between sword
(a) The earliest and simplest solution offered is that of a scholiast on and myrtle bough, since it would be ludicrous to assume that the
AI'. Lys. 632, and ofSuda, s.vv. clyopaaw and EV fLVPTOV KAaSL TO g{q,os singer wore a sword while singing the skolion. And finally, this inter-
q,op~aw, namely that Harmodius and Aristogeiton actually hid their pretation assumes, though perhaps rightly, that the Harmodius song
originated as a skolion, sung under the same conditions under which the celebration of Athens as laov6p.ovs are contemporary. But it would
skolia were sung at the time of Ar. Storks, where the passing of compel us to move the date of the third stanza (12) from 514-510
the myrtle bough is first attested, while the earliest mention of 'the B.C.to after 507 B.C.
Harmodius' as a skolion is in AI'. Vesp. 1222. If this proves that the I am aware that this reconstruction stands on very feeble legs
Harmodius was sung at banquets as early as 422 B.C., it does not indeed. Although it is free from--or at least less encumbered with-
necessarily mean that it was originally composed for that purpose the objections I raised to Vollgraff's interpretation in that it permits EV
and that the passing of the myrtle bough was an essential part of its P.VpTOV Kt..u8£ to be construed with wa7TEp :4pp.6ows KUL JiptaToyE{TWV,
recitation from the beginning. in that it establishes a closer relation between myrtle and sword, and
(e) A suggestion made but not elaborated by J. H. Jongkees, in that it does not assume that the Harmodius originated as a skolion,
Mnemosyne 3rd ser. 13 (1947) 159-60, is that the myrtle bough refers to it is a conjecture based upon a conjecture based upon five vase paint-
wreaths placed upon the heads of the statues of the tyrannicides, ings, which do not talk but depend on the judgement of the critic.
originally the group of Antenor and after 477 B.C.on the heads of the Still, since there seems to be nothing intrinsically improbable about it,
Critius and Nesiotes group. Several vase paintings with representa- its value consists in cautioning us against overconfidence in the dates
tions of these statues show Harmodius and Aristogeiton wreathed. for which we have argued above.
The earliest of these, a black-figure lekythos in Vienna (Oesterr.
Mus. Vienna, Inv. No. 5247, see C. H. E. Haspels, Attic Black-figured Page 144
Lekythoi 167; 264, No. 39) is believed by Becatti, Archeologia classica 9 Cleisthenes' reasons for complying with Cleomenes' demand remain
(1957) 97-107, esp. 100-7, to belong to the last decade of the sixth obscure: did he really regard himself as subject to the curse? And if so,
century and to represent Antenor's group. The others are all dated how did he reconcile the curse with his return to Athens in 511/10
about 400 B.C.On three Panathenaic amphorae the wreathed statues B.C. and again after the expulsion of Isagoras? Is PI. Laws I. 642 d
of Harmodius and Aristogeiton by Critius and Nesiotes appear as a right in dating the purification of Athens by Epimenides of Crete to
shield device. Two of these come from Benghazi and are at present in about ten years before the Persian Wars, i.e. to approximately the
Hildesheim (Inv. Nos. 1253 and 1254, see J. D. Beazley, A]A 47 time after the restoration of the Alcmaeonids in 507 B.C.? Or was
[1943] 454-5, The Development of Attic Black-figure 96, and Attic Black- Cleisthenes confident that his cause would prevail even in his ab-
.figure Vase-painters 412), and one from Teucheira is in the British sence? Or did he give up his reforms as a lost cause, only to be sur-
Museum (Inv. No. B 605, see CVA III H f, pI. 6, and Beazley, Develop- prised by the depth of the support he had gathered? There is also
ment, loco cit.). Finally, there is a red-figure oenochoe from the some difficulty about the other EvuyEi:S: the imperfects EtE{JUt..t..E at
Dexileos grave, which is now in the :Museum of Fine Arts in Boston Hdt. 5. 70. 2 and 72. I suggest that initially Cleomenes merely de-
(Inv. No. 98'936, see W. Hahland, Vasen urn Meidias 6-7, pI. 6a). manded the expulsion of other families with Cleisthenes and that
Brunnsaker, who discusses all these vases on pp. 102-6 in greater Cleisthenes was the only one to comply voluntarily before Cleomenes'
detail and with ampler bibliography than can be done here, concludes arrival in Athens. The P.ET' UVTOV at..t..ovs 7TOt..t..OUS
Ji(JTJvu{wv (70. 2) and
from these representations that there may have been an occasion on TOUS EVUyEUS (72. I) are thus identical with the seven hundred families
which real wreaths were placed upon the statues, and he suggests the expelled after Cleomenes' arrival, of which both Herodotus and
'Panathenaic festival with which the memory of Harmodios and Aristotle speak. The number seven hundred seems rather large and
Aristogeiton was especially closely connected' as the most likely has, therefore, been doubted, e.g. by Wilamowitz, AA I. 31-2; but
occasion (p. 150). If there is any merit to this suggestion, and if the Wade-Gery, Essays 150 n. I, may be right in pointing out that 'the
wreaths were made of myrtle boughs (for which there is no evidence Curse had passed for three or four generations in both lines, male and
whatever), the first lines of stanzas 10 and 12 might be taken as refer- female ... and was shared in the original generation by all who had
ring to this event, celebrating the anniversary of their attempt. accepted the surrender of the Kylonians'.
The consequence of this would be that the group of Antenor and the
first institution of the wreathing ceremony would become the terminus
post quem for the composition of these two stanzas. This would not
affect our date for the first stanza (10), since the Antenor group and
DEUBNER,L. Attische Feste. Berlin, 1932.
DIELS, H. Doxographi Graeci. Berlin, 1879.
DITTENBERGER,W. Sylloge inscriptionum Graecarulll3• Leipzig, 1915.
EHRENBERG,V. Die Rechtsidee im jrilhen Griechentum. Leipzig, 192 I .
-- Neugrilnder des Staates. Munich, 1925.
On.ly wo~k~ cite~ in the text 01' in the notes are listed here. Special -- Aspects oj the ancient world. Oxford, 1946.
lexica, dlctlOnanes, and collections are not included. Sec also the -- Sophocles and Pericles. Oxford, 1954.
Index Locorum for classical tcxts and collections of fragments. -- The Greek state. Oxford, 1960.
-- Polis und Imperium. ZUrich, 1965.
A. BOOKS ELIOT, C. W.]. Coastal demes oj Attica (= Phoenix Supp!. 5)' Toronto,
ADCOCK,F. E. Thucydides and his history. Cambridge, 1963. 1962.
FESTUGIERE,A.-]. Hippocrate: L'ancienne medecine (= Etudes et Com-
ALLEN, T. W., HALLIDAY, W. R., and SIKES, E. E. (cdd.). The
mentaires 4). Paris, 1948.
Homeric hymnsz. Oxford, 1936.
FRAENKEL,E. (ed.). Aeschylus: Agamemnon. 3 vols. Oxford, 1950.
ANDREWES, A. Probouleusis: Sparta's contribution to the technique of
FRANKEL, H. Wege und Formen jrilhgriechischen Denkens2• Munich,
government. Inaug. lecture, Oxford, 1954.
-- The Greek tyrants. London, 1956. 1960.
FRISK, H. Griechisches etymologisches Worterbuch. Heidelberg, 196o--
APFFEL, H. Die Verfassungsdebatte bei Herodot. Diss. Erlangen, 1957.
GIGANTE, M. Nomos basileus. Naples, 1956.
BARRON,]. P. The silver coins of Sam os. London, 1966.
GIGON, O. Der Ursprung der griechischen Philosophie. Basel, 1945·
BEAZLEY.']. D. The development oj Attic black-figure. Berkeley, 1951.
GOMME,A. W. A historical commentary on Thucydides. 3 vols. Oxford,
-- Attxc black-figure vase-painters. Oxford, 1956.
BELOCH, K.]. Griechische Geschichte2, I and 2. Strasbourg, 1912--16. I945~56.
GRAHAM, A. ]. Colony and mother city in ancient Greece. Manchester,
Vo!' 3, Berlin and Leipzig, 1922-7.
BENGTSON,H. (ed.). Die Staatsvertrage des Altertums, 2. Munich, 1962. 1964.
GROSSMANN,G. Politische Schlagworter aus der Zeit des Peloponnesischen
BENVENISTE,E. Noms d'agent et noms d'action en indo-europeen. Paris,
Krieges. Diss. Basel, 1945.
1948. GUTHRIE, W. K. C. A history oj Greek philosophy. 2 vols. Cambridge,
BOER, W. DEN, Laconian studies. Amsterdam, 1954.
1962 and 1965.
BOWRA, C. M. Problems in Greek poetry. Oxford, 1953.
HAHLAND,W. Vasen um Meidias. Berlin-Wilmersdorf, 1930.
-- Greek lyric poetryz. Oxford, 1961.
HASPELS,C. H. E. Attic black-figured lekythoi. Paris, 1936.
-- Pindar. Oxford, 1964.
HEIDEL, W. A. Hippocratic medicine. New York, 1941.
BRUCE, 1. A. F. An historical commentary on the Hellenica Oxyrhynchia.
HEINIMANN,F. Nomos und Physis. Basel, 1945·
Cambridge, 1967.
HIGNETT, C. A history of the Athenian constitution to the end oj the fifth
BRUNNSA.KER, S. The tyrant slayers of Kritios and Nesiotes. Lund, 1955.
century B.C. Oxford, 1952.
BUCK, C. D. The Greek dialects. Chicago, 1955.
HIRZEL, R. Themis, Dike und Verwandtes. Leipzig, 1907·
BUSOLT, G. Griechische Geschichte2, 1-2. Gotha, 1893-5. Vo!' 31,
HOFMANN,W. De iurandi apud Athenienses jormulis. Diss. Strasbourg,
Gotha, 1897-19°4.
1886.
-- and SWOBODA, H. Griechische Staatskunde. 2 vols. Munich,
HOPPER, R.]. The basis oj the Athenian democracy. Inaug. lecture,
1920-6.
CHAMOUX,F. Cyrene sous la monarchie des Battiades (= Bibliotheque des Sheffield, 1957·
How, W. W., and WELLS, ]. A commentary on Herodotus2• 2 vols.
Ecoles franc;aises d'Athenes et de Rome, Fasc. In). Paris, 1953.
CLOCHE, P. Thebes de Beotie. Louvain and Paris, I952? Oxford, 1928.
HUMBERT,]. Syntaxe grecque3• Paris, 1960.
DALE, A. M. (ed.). Euripides: Helen, Oxford, 1967.
HUXLEY, G. Early Sparta. London, 1962.
DENNISTON,]. D., and PAGE, D. L. (edd.). Aeschylus: Agamemnon.
]ACOBY, F. (ed.). Das Marmor Parium. Berlin, 1904·
Oxford, 1957.
JACOBY, F. (ed.). Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker. Berlin and l\IASARACCHIA,A. Solone. Florence, 1958.
Leiden, 1923- MEIGGS, R., and ANDREWESA., (edd.). Sources jor Greek history
-- Atthis: The local chronicles of ancient Athens. Oxford, 1949. between the Persian and Peloponnesian wars, collated and arranged
JAEGER, W. Paideia. English translation by G. Highet, 13• Oxford, by G. F. Hill. Oxford, 1951.
1946.2-3, Oxford, 1944-5· MERITT, B. D., \'\TADE-GERY, H. T., and MCGREGOR, M. F. The
-- The theology of the early Greek philosophers. Oxford, 1947. Athenian tribute lists. 3 vols. Cambridge (Mass.), 1939-5°·
JEFFERY, L. H. The local scrij)ts oj archaic Greece. Oxford, 1961. MERKELBACH,R. Untersuchungen zur Odyssee (= Zetemata 2). l'vlunich,
KAIBEL, G. Comicorum Graecorumfragmenta, 1. Berlin, 1899. 1951.
KAKRIDIS, J. T. Der thukydideische EjJitaplzios (= Zetemata 26). MORETTI, L. Ricerche sulle leghe greche. Rome, 1962.
Munich, 1961. MORPURGO,A. Mycenaeae Graecitatis lexicon. Rome, 1963. . .
KALINKA, E. Die pseudoxenophontische Af9HNAIQN IIOAITEIA. MULLER, C. \'\T. Gleiches ::;u Gleichem: Ein Prinzip jriihgrzechlschen
Leipzig and Berlin, 1913. Denkens (=Klassisch-philologische Studien 3 I). Wiesbaden, 1965.
KAPP, E., and FRITZ, K. VON. Aristotle's Constitution of Athens and NESTLE, W. Vom Mythos zum Logos2. Stuttgart, 1942.
related texts. New York, 1950. NILSSON,M. P. Geschichte der griechischen Religion, 12• Munich, 1955·
KEIL, B. Griechische Staatsaltertiimer, in Gercke-Norden, Einleitung in NORTH, H. Sophrosyne: Self-knowledge and self-restraint in Greek litera-
die Altertulllswissenschaji, 32• Leipzig and Berlin, 1914. ture. Ithaca, N.Y., 1966.
KIECHLE, F. Lakonien und !:>parta (= Vestigia: Beitriige zur alten OLIVER, J. H. Demokratia, the gods, and thejree world. Baltimor~, 1960.
Geschichte 5). Munich and Berlin, 1963. OTTO, W., and HERBIG, R. (edd.). Handbuch der Archiiologze, 3· 1.
KIERDORF, W. Erlebnis und Darstellung der Perserkriege (= Hypo- Munich, 1950.
mnemata 16). Gottingen, 1966. PAGE, D. L. Greek literary pap)'ri, 1. London and Cambridge (Mass.),
KIRK, G. S. Heraclitus: The cosmicjragments. Cambridge, 1954. 1942.
-- and RAVEN,J. E. The Presocratic philosophers. Cambridge, 1957. -- The Homeric Odyssey. Oxford, 1955·
KOHLER, J., and ZIEBARTH, E. Das Stadtrecht von Gortyn. Gottingen, -- Sappho and Alcaeus. Oxford, 1955·
1912. -- Poetae melici Graeci. Oxford, 1962.
KUHNER, R., and GERTH, B. Ausfiihrliche Grammatik der griechischen PALMER, L. R. The interpretation oj Mycenaean Greek texts. Oxford,
Sprache3• 2 vols. Hannover and Leipzig, 189°-19°4. 1963.
LAROCHE,E. Histoire de la racine NEM- en grec ancien. Paris, 1949. POHLENZ, M. Hippokrates und die Begriindung der wissenschaftlicllen
LARSEN,J. A. O. Representative government in Greek and Roman history. Medi::;in. Berlin, 1938.
Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1955. PREUSS S. Index Demosthenicus. Leipzig, 1892.
LEDL, A. Studien zur iilteren athenischen Veifassungsgeschichte. Heidelberg, RAUBI;SCHEK,A. E. Dedicationsjrom the Athenian Acropolis. Cambridge
1914. (Mass.), 1949.
LERAT, L. Les locriens de l'ouest (= Bibliotheque des Ecole franc,:aises REINHARDT,K. Parmenides2. Frankfurt/Main, 1959·
d'AthCnes et de Rome, Fasc. 176). Paris, 1952. REITZENSTEIN,R. Epigramm und Skolion. Giessen, 1893.
LESKY, A. Greek tragedy. English translation by H. A. Frankfort. ROSE, H. J. A commentary on the surviving plays oj Aeschylus. 2 vols.
London and New York, 1965. Amsterdam, 1957-8.
LEVEQUE,P., and VIDAL-NAQUET,P. Clisthenel'atMnien. Paris, 1964. SARTORI, F. Le eterie nella vita politica ateniese del VI e V secolo a. C.
LINFORTH, I. 1'1. Solon the Athenian. Berkeley, 1919. Rome, 1957.
LIPSIUS,J. H. Das attische Recht und Rechtsveifahren, 3 vols. Leipzig, SCHAEFER,H. Staatsform und Politik. Leipzig, ~93~· .
19°5-15. SCHMID,W., and STAHLIN,O. Geschichte der grzechlschen Llteratur, I. I.
LLOYD, G. E. R. Polarity and analogy. Cambridge, 1966. Munich, 1929.
LOBEL, E., and PAGE, D. <L.). Poetarum Lesbiorumjragmenta. Oxford, SCHREINER,J. De corpore iuris Atheniensium. Diss. Bo~n, 19.13. .
1955· SCHWYZER, E. Dialectorum Graecarum exempla eplgraphlca potLOra.
1,IAcDoWELL, D. Andokides: On the lvf.ysteries. Oxford, 1962 Leipzig, 1923.
BIBLIOGRAPHY IgI

BECATTIG. 'I tirannicidi di Antenore', Archeologia Classica 9 (1957)


SCHWYZER,E., and DEBRUNNER,A. Griechische Grammatik. 3 vols.
Munich, 1939-53. 97-I07·
BOWERSOCK,G. W. 'Pseudo-Xenophon', HSCP 71 (1967) 33-55·
SNELL, B. The discovery of the mind. English translation by T. G.
BOWRA, C. M. 'A prayer to the Fates', CeL 52 (= N.S. 8) (1958)
Rosenmeyer. Oxford, 1953.
231-40•
SOLMSEN,F. Hesiod and Aeschylus. Ithaca (N.Y.), 1949.
BRADEEN,D. W. 'The fifth-century archon list', Hesperia 32 (1963)
SPENGEL,L. (ed.) Rhetores Graeci, I. 2. Ed. by C. Hammer. Leipzig,
1894. 187-208. . . ,
CADOUX,T.]. 'The Athenian archons from Kreon to HypslChldes ,
STANFORD,W. B. (ed.) The Odyss~ of Homer. 2 vols. London, 1947-8.
JHS 68 (1948) 70-119. .
TaD, M. N. A selection of Greek historical inscriptions. 2 vols. Oxford
CATAUDELLA, Q. 'L'Anonymus Iamblichi e Democnto', Studi
19462 and 1948.
italiani di filologia classica N.s. 10 (1932) 5-22.
TUCKER, T. G. (ed.). The Supplices of Aeschylus. London and New
-- 'Nuove ricerche sull'Anonimo di Giamblico e sulla com-
York, 1889.
posizione del Protreptico', Rend d. R. Accad. Na::;. d. Lincei. Ser. 6,
VENTRIS, M., and CHADWICK,]. Documents in Mycenaean Greek.
Vol. 13 (1937) 182-210.
Cambridge, 1956.
-- 'Chi e l'Anonimo di Giamblico?' REG 63 (1950) 74-I06.
VURTHEIM,]. (ed.). Aischylos Schut::jlehende. Amsterdam, 1928.
COLE, A. T., Jr. 'The Anonymus Iamblichi and his place in Greek
\VACHTLER,]. De Alcmaeone Crotoniata. Leipzig, 1896.
political theory', HSCP 65 (1961) 127-63.
WADE-GERY, H. T. Essays in Greek history. Oxford, 1958.
COMPARETTI,D. 'On two inscriptions from Olympia', JHS 2(1881)
\VEISS, E. Griechisches Privatrecht, I. Leipzig, 1923.
WEST, M. L. (ed.). Hesiod: Theogony. Oxford, 1966. 365-79.
CONACHER,D.]. 'Euripides' Hecuba', AJP 82 (1961) 1-26.
WILAMOWITz-MoELLENDORFF,U. VaN. Aristoteles und Athen. 2 vols.
CORSSEN,P., in Archiiologischer An::;eiger (1903) 41. .
Berlin, 1893.
-- 'Nachrichten tiber Versammlungen: Archaologlsche Gesell-
-- Euripides Herakles2• 2 vols. Berlin, 1895.
schaft zu Berlin 1903', Berliner philologische Wochenschrift 23 (1903)
-- Pindaros. Berlin, 1922.
-- Platon: Beilagen und Textkritik. 3rd eO. by R. Stark. Berlin, 35°-1. .
DEBRUNNER,A. "L17Jfl.0KpaT{a", Festschrift fur Edouard Tzeche (Bern,
1962.
WILL, E. Korinthiaka. Paris, 1955. 1947) 11-24· .
EDELSTEIN,L. Review of L. A. Stella, Importan::;a dz Alcmeone nella
WUST, K. Politisches Denken bei Herodot. Diss. Munich, 1935.
storia del pensiero greco, in AJP 63 (1942) 371-2.
EHRENBERG,V. 'Isonomia', RE Suppl. 7 (1940) 293-301.
-- 'Origins of democracy', Historia I (1950) 5 I 5-48.
B. ARTICLES
--~ 'Das Harmodioslied', Wiener Studien 69 (1956) 57-69.
ABEL, D. H. 'Genealogies of ethical concepts from Hesiod to ELIOT, C. W. J. 'Kleisthenes and the creation of the ten phylai',
Bacchylides', TAPA 74 (1943) 92-101. Phoenix 22 (1968) 3-17.
ALLEN, T. W. 'Adversaria IV', RPh II (1937) 280-6. -- and MCGREGOR, M. F. 'Kleisthenes: Eponymous archon
ALY, W. 'Skolion', RE 2. Reihe, 5. Halbb. (1927) 558-66. 525/4 B.C.', Phoenix 14 (1960) 27-35·
--- 'Solon', RE 2. Reihe, 5. Halbb. (1927) 946-78. ERASMUS,H.]. 'Eunomia', Acta Classica 3 (1960) 53-64.
ANDREWES,A. 'Eunomia', CQ,32 (1938) 89-102. ERBSE, H. 'Anmerkungen zu Herodot', Glotta 39 (1961) 215-3°.
-- 'Philochoros on phratries', JHS 81 (1961) 1-15. EVANS,]. A. S. 'Despotes Nomos', Athenaeum N.S. 43 (1965)142-53.
-- 'The government of classical Sparta', Ancient society and institu- FORREST,<W.) G. 'The First Sacred War', BCH80 (1956) 33-52.
tions: Studies presented to Victor Ehrenberg on his 75th birthday (Oxford, -- 'The tribal organization of Chios', BSA 55 (1960) 172-89.
1966) I-20. -- 'Legislation in Sparta', Phoenix 21 (1967) 11-19·
BARRON,]. P. 'The sixth-century tyranny at Samos', CeL N.S. 14 FRANKEL, H. 'A thought pattern in Heraclitus', AJP 59 (1938)
(1964) 2IO-29·
3°9-37·
BEAZLEY,]. D. 'Panathenaica', AJA 47 (1943) 441-65.
192 BIBLIOGRAPHY
FRITZ, K. VaN. 'Pythagoras', RE 47. Halbb. (1963) 171-209. JONES, "V. H. S. 'Philosophy and medicine in ancient Greece',
-- 'Die griechische EAW8€p{a bei Herodot', Wiener Studien 78 Bulletin of the History of Medicine. Suppl. 8 (1946).
(1965) 5-31. jONGKEES,j. H. 'Note on the coinage of Athens', Mnemosyne 3rd
GANSZYNIEC,R. 'Kranz', RE 22. Halbb. (1922) 1588-1607. Ser. 13 (1947) 143-60.
GOMME,A. W. 'Athenian notes', AJP 65 (1944) 321-39. KAGAN, D. 'The enfranchisement of aliens by Cleisthenes', Historia
GOMPERZ, T. 'Nachlese zu den Bruchstilcken der griechischen 12 (1963) 41-6.
Tragiker', Sber. d. Kais. Ak. d. Wiss., Philos.-hist. Cl. (Vienna, 1888) KAHN, C. H. 'Plato's funeral oration', CP 58 (1963) 220-34.
3-52• KAHRSTEDT,U. 'Kleisthenes', RE 21. Halbb. (1921) 620-1.
GRIFFITH, G. T. 'IsegOI'ia in the Assembly at Athens', Ancient society -- 'Untersuchungen zu athenischen Behorden II: Die Nom(}~
and institutions: Studies presented to Victor Ehrenberg on his 75th birthday theten und die Legislative in Athen', Klio 31 (1938) 1-25.
(Oxford, 1966) 115-38. KIRKWOOD,G. M. 'Hecuba and Nomos', TAPA 78 (1947) 61-8.
GSCHNITZER,F. 'Zur Geschichte der griechischen Staatenverbin- KOEPP, F. 'Harmodios und Aristogeiton', Neue Jahrbucher fur das
dungen: Halikarnassos und Salmakis (Syll.3 45)', RhM 104 (1961) klassische Altertum 9 (1902) 609-34.
237-41. KOLBE, W. 'Die Anfange der attischen Arch6', Hermes 73 (1938)
HAMMOND,N. G. L. 'The Lycurgean reforms at Sparta', JHS 70 249-68.
( I 950) 42-64. LARSEN,j. A. O. 'Cleisthenes and the development of the theory of
HARRISON,A. R. W. 'Law-making at Athens at the end of the fifth democracy at Athens', Essays in political theory presented to G. H.
century B.C.', JHS 75 (1955) 26-35. Sabine (Ithaca, N.Y., 1948) 1-16.
HARVEY, A. E. 'The classification of Greek lyric poetry', CQ,N.S. 5 -- 'The Boeotian confederacy and fifth-century oligarchic theory',
(1955) 157-75· TAPA 86 (1955) 40-50.
HEIDEL, W. A. 'Pythagoreans and Greek mathematics', AJP 61 LATTIMORE,R. 'The composition of the "History" of Herodotus',
(1940) 1-33· CP 53 (1958) 9-2 I.
HEREWARD, D. 'New fragments of IG IJz :0', BSA 47 (1952) LEWIS, D. M. 'Cleisthenes and Attica', Historia 12 (1963) 22-40.
102-17. LIPSIUS, j. H. 'Zur attischen Nomothesie', Berliner philologische
HERZOG, R. 'Heilige Gesetze von Kos', Abh. d. Preuss. Ak. d. Wiss., Wochenschrift 37 (1917) 902- 12.
Philos.-hist. Kl. (Berlin, 1928). No.6. LLOYD-JONES,H. 'Aeschylus, Agamemnon 416 ff.', CQ, 47 (= N.S. 3)
HIRZEL, R. "J1.ypafl)QC; N6p.oc;", Abh. d. philol-hist. Cl. d. Kgl. Sachs. Ges. (1953) 96.
d. Wiss. 20 (Leipzig, 1900). No. I. LURIA, S. 'Zwei Demokrit-Studien', in j. Mau and E. G. Schmidt
HOHL, E. 'Zeit und Zweck der pseudoxenophontischen Athenaion (edd.), Isonomia: Studien ;:;ur GleichheitsvorsteUung im griechischen
Politeia', CP 45 (1950) 26-35. Denken (Berlin, 1964) 37-54.
HOMMEL,H. 'Naukraria', RE 32. Halbb. (1935) 1938-52. MAASS,E. 'Untersuchungen zur Geschichte der griechischen Prosa',
jAcOBSTHAL, P., and U. VaN WILAMOWITZ-MoELLENDORFF'Nord- Hermes 22 (1887) 567-95.
ionische Steine', Abh. d. Kgl. Preuss. Ak. d. Wiss., Philos.~hist. Cl. MACKINNEY, L. 'The concept of isonomia in Greek medicine', in
(Berlin, 1909), 64-7 I. j. Mau and E. G. Schmidt (edd.), Isonomia: Studien ;:;urGleich-
JACOBY, F. 'Herodotus', RE Suppl. 2 (1913) 205-520. heitsvorstellung im griechischenDenken (Berlin, 1964) 79-88.
-- 'Patrios Nomos: State burial in Athens and the public cemetery MACURDY,G. H. 'Had the Danaid trilogy a social problem?' CP
in the Kerameikos', JHS 64 (1944) 37-66. 39 (1944) 95-100.
JAEGER, W. 'Solons Eunomie', Sber. d. Preuss. Ak. d. Wiss., Philos.- MEIER, C. Drei Bemerkungen zur Vor- und Frilhgeschichte des
hist. Kl. (Berlin, 1926) 69-85. Begriffs Demokratie', Discordia concors:Festschrift fur Edgar Bonjour
JEFFERY, L. H. 'The courts of justice in archaic Chios', BSA 51 (Basel, 1968) 3-29.
(1956) 157-67. MERITT, B. D. 'Greek inscriptions', Hesperia 8 (1936) 48-82.
-- 'The pact of the first settlers at Cyrene', Historia 10 (1961) -- 'Attic inscriptions of the fifth century', Hesperia 14 (1945)
139-47· 61-133.
'94 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY '95
MERITT, B. D. 'Greek inscriptions', Hesperia 36 (1967) 57-101. SEGAL, C. P. 'Sophocles' praise of man and the conflicts of the
MITCHELL, B. M. 'Cyrene and Persia', JHS 86 (1966) 99-113. Antigone', Arion 3. 2 (1964) 46-66.
MOURELATOS,A. P. D. 'Heraclitus, fro 114', AJP 86 (1965) 258-66. SEGRE, :M. 'La legge ateniese sull'unificazione delIa moneta', Clara
MUGLER, C. 'L'Isonomie des atomistes', RPh 3e Ser. 30 (1956) Rhodos 9 (1938) 151-78.
231-50• STARR, C. G. 'The credibility of early Spartan history', Historia 14
MYRES, J. L. 'Eunomia', CR 61 (1947) 80-2. (1965) 257-72.
NESTLE,W. 'Odyssee-Interpretationen II', Hermes 77 (1942) 113-39. STIER, H. E. "Nop.o, BauIAEvs', Philologus 83 (1928) 225-58.
NORVIN, W. 'Zur Geschichte der spartanischen Eunomia', Clanim STROHECKER,K. F. 'Zu den Anfangen der monarchischen Theorie
et Mediaevalia 2 (1939) 247-93 and 3 (1940) 47-II8. in der Sophistik', Historia 2 (1953-4) 381-412.
OLDFATHER, W. A. 'Lokris (Staat und Kultur)" RE 25. Halbb. THOMPSON,W. E. 'The archonship of Cleisthenes', C] 55 (1959-
(1926) 1237-69. 60) 217-20.
OLIVER, J. H. 'Text of the so-called constitution of Chios from the -- 'Three thousand Acharnian hoplites', Historia 13 (1964)
first half of the sixth century B.C.', AJP 80 (1959) 296-30 I. 400-13.
-- 'Reforms of Cleisthenes', Historia 9 (1960) 503-7. VALETON, 1. M. J. 'Quaestiones Graecae: De inscriptione Lyg-
ORLANDINI,P. 'Antenor', Enciclopedia del!'arte antica, I (Rome, 1958) damensi', Mnemosyne N.S. 36 (1908) 289-334.
408-9. VLASTOS,G. 'Solonian justice', CP 41 (1946) 65-83.
OSTWALD, M. 'The Athenian legislation against tyranny and sub- -- 'Equality and justice in early Greek cosmologies', CP 42 (1947)
version', TAPA 86 (1955) 103-28. 156-78.
-- 'Pindar, NOMOE, and Heracles', HSCP 69 (1965) 109-38. -- 'Isonomia', AJP 74 (1953) 337-66.
PEEK, W. 'Ein attisches Skolion', Hermes 68 (1933) II8-2I. ~-" 'Iuovop.la 1ToAITIK1J",in J. Mau and E. G. Schmidt (edd.),
PHOTIADES,P. S. "llEpl Ti), Jyyv7], 1TpO' yap.ov", 1487]vii 32 (1920) Isonomia: Studien ::;ur Gleichheitsvorstel!ung im griechischen Denken
100-55· (Berlin, 1964) 1-35.
PODLECKI,A. J. 'The political significance of the Athenian "tyran- VOLLGRAFF,W. " 'Ev P.VpTOVKAaSl", Mnemosyne N.S.49 (192 I) 246-50.
nicide"-cult', Historia 15 (1966) 129-41. WASER, O. "Evvop.la", RE 6 (1909) 1129-31.
POHLENZ, M. 'Nomos', Philologus 97 (1948) 135-42. WELLMANN,M. 'Alkmaion von Kroton', Archeion I I (1929) 156-69.
-- 'Nomos und Physis', Hermes 81 (1953) 418-38. -- 'Die Schrift 1TEPL[pi), vovuov des Corpus Hippocraticum',
RAUBITSCHEK,A. E. 'Some notes on early Attic stoichedon inscrip- Archivfiir Geschichte der Medi::;in 22 (1929) 290-312.
tions', JHS 60 (1940) 50-9. WHITE, M. E. 'The duration of the Samian tyranny', ]HS 74 (1954)
-- 'Two monuments erected after the victory of Marathon', AJA 36-43.
44 (1940) 53-9· WILHELM, A. 'Inschriften aus Erythrai und Chios', Jahresh. d. Osterr.
-- 'The heroes ofPhyle', Hesperia 10 (1941) 284-95. arch. Inst. Wien 12 (1909) 126-41.
REINACH, T. 'Inscriptions grecques', REG 16 (1903) 180-92. -- 'Die lokrische Madcheninschrift', Jahresh. d. Osterr. arch. Inst.
ROBERTS, W. RHYS, 'Dionysius of Halicarnassus as an authority Wien 14 (191 I) 163-256.
for the text of Thucydides', CR 14 (1900) 244-6. WOODBURY,L. 'Apollodorus, Xenophanes, and the foundation of
RUSCHENBUSCH,E. '''HAlala: Die Tradition iiber das solonische Massilia', Phoenix 15 (196 I) 134-55.
Volksgericht", Historia 14 (1965) 381-4. WOODHEAD,A. G. "'Iu7]yopla and the Council of 500", Historia 16
STE. CROIX, G. E. M. DE. 'The constitution of the Five Thousand', (1967) 129-40.
Historia 5 (1956) 1-23. WOTKE, F. "Nop.o8€TaI", RE Supp!. 7 (1940) 578-81.
SCHEFOLD,K. 'Kleisthenes', Museum Helveticum 3 (1946) 59-93. WUST, F. R. 'Zu den 1TpvTavIE, TWV vavKpapwv und zu den alten
SCHOLL, R. 'Ueber attische Gesetzgebung', Sber. d. Philos.-philol. attischen Tritt yen' , Historia 6 (1957) 176-9 I.
Cl. d. K. Bayr. Ak. d. Wiss. (Munich, 1886) 83-139. -- 'Zu Kleisthenes', Historia 13 (1964) 370-3.
SCHROEDER, O. "N6p.o, 6 1TavTwv (3auIAEvs', Philologus 74 (1917) ZIEHEN, L. 'Panathenaia', RE 36. Halbb. (2) (1949) 457-93.
195-204.
All references to classical authors are based on the Oxford Classical Texts
or, where these are not available, on the Teubner or Bude editions. Excep-
tions are indicated by the editor's name placed in parentheses after the
name of the ancient author.
Collections of fragments are identified by the following abbreviations:

CGF G. Kaibel, Comicorum Graecorumfragmenta, I (Berlin, 1899).

DiehlJ E. Diehl, Anthologia Lyrica Graeca3, 3 fascc. (Leipzig, 1954-5)·


DK6 H. Diels, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6th ed. by W. Kranz,
3 vols. (Berlin, 1951-2).
Dox. H. Diels, Doxographi Graeci (Berlin, 1879).
Edmonds J. M. Edmonds, The Fragments of Attic Comedy, 3 vols. (Leiden,
1957-61).
F. Jacoby, Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker (Berlin and
Leiden, 1923- ).
E. Lobel and D. (L.> Page, Poetarum Lesbiorum fragmenta
(Oxford, 1955).
A. Nauck, Tragicorum Graecorumfragmenta2• Supp!. by B. Snell
(Hildesheim, 1964).
D. L. Page, Poetae Melici Graeci (Oxford, 1962).

Aelian, Varia Historia 2. 25 Eumenides 171 28


Aelius Aristides (Keil): 391-3 13 with n. 2, 18
11. 80 124 n. I 448-50 41
28. 138 3 n. 5 484 4n.5, 13, 18
Aeschines: 491 17,18
1.5 84 n. 2 571 4 n. 5, 13, 18
157 n. 2 576 41 n. I
23
84 n. 2 615 4 n. 5, 13, 18
3· 154
4 n. 5, 17 n. 3 681 4 n. 5, 13, 18
19°
Aeschylus: 693 33 n. 2
Agamemnon 151 61 n. 1,86 778-g (= 808-9) 28
221 86 Persae 693 44 n. I
312 53 Prometheus 149-50 43-4,44 n. I
25 4°2-3 43-4
594
1142 61 n. 1,86 Supplices 220 41
12°7 22 241 41
1564 15 387-g1 43,44,58-9, 120, 161
Choephoroe93 24 670-3 28, 120
7°8 15
150-1 41
22 1034 13 with n. 3
4°0
34 frg. (Nauck» 198 62 n. 3, 72
424
37 with n. with n. 2, 73
989-90 I
Aeti us, Placita 5: 6-7 Ranae 761-4 49 19 138-9
92-4 19. 125 n. 4, 148 n. 2
19·5 (Dox. 430-1) 105 n. 2 6. Thesmophoriazusae 361-2 49 I
I 92 nn. 3 and 4 130 n. I, 134
26. 4 (Dox. 438-g) 379 157 n. 2 2-6
104 n. 2 3 92 n. 3
Alcaeus, frg. (L.-P.): 947 43 2 139
4 92 n. 5 127, 129, 130, 134, 138,
6.27 120 n. I 1039 88 3
93 143 n. 2, 148 n. 3
35. I 34 n. 6 7· 12 94 n. I 1137 43
Vespae 467 49 139 n. I
72•6 34 n. 6 12-16 94 n. 2
1222-6 124 and n. I, 184 129 n. I
129.25 34 n. 6 Antiphanes, frg. (Edmonds) 85
181. I 1227 124 n. 2 139
34 n. 6 124 n. I 150 n. 2
249 127 n. 4 Antiphon, frg. (DK6) 44A: frg. (Edmonds) 430 124 n. I, 183 20

Aristophanes: Scholia to: 20. 1-3 143-5


Alemaeon, frg. (DK6) 4 I. 17-23
Acharnenses 980 123 with n. 4 I 3 n. I, 140 n. I, 142, 143
99-106, 177-8 23-31
Lysistrata 273 146 n. I n.4, 148 n. 5, 150 n. I,
Aleman, frg. (PAIG): Archilochus:
632 182 157 n. I
10.10 61 n. 1,62 n. 2 frg. (DiehI3) 22. 3 120 n. I
Nubes 1364 125 n. I, 183 144 and n. 2
4° 21 (Bude) 230 34 n. 6
Vespae 544 183 144, 145
64 64 Aristophanes:
1222 183 3 n. I
Alexander of Aphrodisias: Acharnenses 45 157 n. 2
1239 183 127, 129, 130, 134, 138
De mixtione 3 (Bruns 532 48,57
Aristotle: n. 5,148 n. 3
216.28-217.2) 773 39
Athenaion Politeia 3·4 16,18, 21 130 n. I, 143-5
Quaestiones I. 9 (Bruns 980 123, 124 n. I
174-5 21. I 3 n. I, 143, 150 n. 2
19·30-2) 1093 123 n. 4, 124 n. I
4. 3n·3,5n.2,15,175 2 3 n. I, 150 n. 4, 155
Anacreon, frg. (PMG) 61 Aves 331 4 n. 5,14 I
112 n. 2 3 155
Anaxagoras, frg. (DK6): 518 43 3
174 4 151 and n. I, 152 n. 2,
4 102 n. 3 755-9 39 4
7-12 5 154 n. 2, 155 n. I
6 102 n. 3 1038-9 49
7. I 3 and n. 3, 4 n. I, 5 n. 2, 5 152, 153
102 n. 3 1344-5 22
15 6 152 n. 2, 154, 166 n. I
102 n. 3 1346 49 148, 156, 159
17 102 n. 3 1347-8 22 n. 2 3 156 22. I

Anaximander, frg. (DK6) I 100 n. I 8. 3 6 n. 2 4 132


1353-4 22 n. 2, 48
Anaximenes (Spengel, Rhet. Gr. 4 162 5 14°
I53g-40 73
9. 156, 162 n. 2 26. 4 46 n. 3
12) 22 112 n. 2 1650 48 I
29. I 108 n. 2
Anaximenes of Lampsacus, frg. 1655--6 2 59
48 3 n. 5 108 n. 2
(FGR) 24 49 n. 2 Ecclesiazusae 130 12·4 3
157 n. 2 180
Andocides: 216 13·4 141, 147, 156 n. I, 165 3°
24 112 n. 2
I De mysteriis I 7
n. 3 30. 2
2 n. 3 609 34 n. 3 180
5 141 33.1-2
43 140 with n. 3 759 49 n. I
81 14. I 129 n. 2, 147, 156, 165 35. 2 4,5,59
3 n. 3, 5 n. 2, 15 762 49 n. I 41. 2 3,5 n. 2, 60,108 n. 3,174
82 5 n. 2 n·3
944 49 n. I 62. I 153
83 I n. 2, 3 n. 3, 5 and n. 2, 3 147, 156 n. I
987-8 53 n. I Ethica Nicomachea
1022 4 147, 156 n. I
15 49 n. I
15. I 156 n. I 5.3, 1131"23
84 In.2 1041 49 n. I
2 141 n. 4 10, 1I37b28-9
85 I n. I 1049 49 n. I
16·4 147 n. 2 AIetaphysica
86 In·4 1056 49 n. I
6 147 and n. 2, 148 A, 986"27-9 98 n. 4-
87 I, 2, 3, 5, 57 1077 49 n. I
148 29-30 97 n. 2
89 In·4 Equites 447-8 142 n. I 7
8 147, 165 n. 3 31-4 102 n. 4
97 108 n. 2 Lysistrata 63 1-3 126
147 [De Mundo] 5, 396b35 105 n. 2
106 148 n. 4 Nubes 1040 34 n. 3 9
10 4 n. 2, 16, 18, 59, 140 De Partibus Animalium
2 De reditu suo 26 138, 148 n. 4 1183-7 48
27 with n. 2 2. 7, 652b36 104 with n. I
108 n. 2 14°° 34 n. 3 103 with
Anonymus Iamblichi (DK6): 1421--6 17. 2 129 n. 2 Physica 7. 3, 246b4-6
36 139 n. I n. 5
3· I 88, 92 n. 3 Plutus 789 37 3-4
18·4 140 n. 4, 141 n. 4, 142 Politica
6 92 n. 3 795 37 n. I 2.9, 1271"6
4·3 92 n. 2 914 49
Aristotle, Politica (cont.) : 3 I~ 10. 17.2 140 n. 4 1246 42 n. 5
12, 1273b38 108 n. 2 6 127 n. 2 I I. 84. 7-8 170 n. 2 1258 42 n. 5
1274a7 108 n. 3 7 127 with n. 3 14·34.6 164 n. 3 1429 34
22-31 60 n. 2 8 127 with n. 4 Diogenes Laertius: 1561 24 n. 3
b15-16 5 n. 2 9 127 n. 2 8.26 105 n. 2 Heraclidae 141 48 n. 2
3·2, 1275b34-7 141 n. 2 10-13 96-7,121-36,182-5 83 97 n. 3, 102 n. 4 292-3 36
36-7 151 with n. 2 14-18 129 Dionysius of Halicarnassus: 963 48
5, 1278a25-6 180 19 127 n. 2 Antiquitates Romanae 1009-11 43
9, 1280a7-25 182 20-2 127 n. 2 I. 74. 6 Hercules 723 90
16, 1287a6-8 172 23-4 127 5. I. I 757 90 with n. 3, 91
4·4, 1291b34-5 108 n. 5 25 127 n. 2 6. 66. 4 778-80 26, 90 with n. 4
I 292a36-7 2 n. I Chrysippus, frg. (von Arnim 3. Epistula ad Ammaeum 2. I I 1316 25
8, 1294a3-7 84 n. 2, 94 n. 3 121) 471 103 n. 5 1322 48
9, 1294b14-34 117-18 Cicero, De Natura Deorum: Empedoc1es, frg. (DK6): 1361 42
15, 1300bl-3 112 n. 2 I. 50 96 n. I 8 102 n. 3 Hippolytus 91 38
5. I, 1301a19-1302a8 182 10 9 96 n. I 9· 5 38-g 93 38
3, 1302b29 117 n. 2 Cleidemus, frg. (FGH) 8 152 n. 6 17·4-8 102 n. 3 98 22
7, 1306b30 1I8 n. I Cratinus, frg. (Edmonds): 16-20 102 n. 3 461 53
36-1307a2 81 116 53 n. I 21 102 n. 3 866 44 n. I
38 81 n. I 127 4,15 n. 2 22 102 n. 3 1043-4 53 n. 3
1307al-2 81 n. 2 Critias, frg. (DK6): 26 102 n. 3 1046 53
9, I 31Oa28-3 2 108 n. 5 25· 5 51 100 n. I 1328 26

10, 1312b7-8 139 n. I 9 51 Ephorus, frg. (FGH) 139 60 n. 2 Ion 20 36
6.2, 1317a40-b3 106 n. 3 52 n. 1,91 n. I Etymologicum AJagnum: 25 36

40-b17 108 n. 5 S.v. Bu>..>..oq,opos 183 2~ ~
b18-20 106 n. 3 Democritus, frg. (DK6): VEf-LW lon.2 442-3 48, 91 with n. I
4, 1319b19-27 163 n. 2 9 Euripides: 643 43 with n. 2
22-3 164 with n. 3 125 Alcestis 56-7 23 1047 26
25-6 155 266 683 25 125°-6 48 n. 2
Rhetorica 3. 18, 1419a31 112 n. 3 Demosthenes: Andromache I 76 48 1312-13 42
Topica 15.18 109 n. 2 243 33 1322 29
4.2, 122b26-31 103 n. 2 20·92 2 n. I 491 87 Iphigenia Aulidensis 399 87 with
123a4 103 n. 2 158 5 n. 3 Bacchae 331 34 n. I n. 4, 88 n. 2, 89 n. I
6.2, 139b21 103 n. 5 23·51 5 n. 3 387 87 694 23
6, 145b8 103 n. 5 62 5 n. I 484 33 734 42
Arrian, Anabasis: 24. 20-3 In.2 891 34 n. 3 1°95 26,90
3. 16·7-8 132 n. 3 3° I n. I 995-6 (= 1015-16) 87 with n. Iphigenia Taurica 35 43
7. 19,2 132 n. 3 105 162 n. 2 3,89 n. I 38 48
Athenaeus, Deipnosophistae: 139 84 n. 2 C)clops 299 25 275 9°,91
15.667 f 53 n. I 149 45 n. 4 338 48 277 48
693 f 127 27· 5 59 n. 3 Electra 234 34 n. 3 465 43
694 c-695 f 96 with n. 3, 36. 8 59 n. 3 905-6 53 with n. 4 586 48
126-9 [43] 59 n. 2 1268-9 48 958-60 42,52-3
695 a-b (= PMG, Nos. 893-6) [43]. 57 5 n. I Hecuba 291 48 97° 48
96 with n. 3, 121-36, 182-5 [44] 59 n. 2 799-801 29,38 1I62 44 n. I
[46]. 18 59 846-g 39 1189 48
Bacchylides (Snell B): [48]. 19 178 864-7 47 1458 42,53
13·186-9 72 with n. 4 Dio Cassius 52. 4·3 178 866 57 Medea 238 25
15·53-6 72 with n. 3 Dio Chrysostom 2. 63 127 974 36 494 4 n. 5,15
Diodorus Siculus: Helena 800 42 n. 3 538 32
Carmina Convivialia (PMG, frgg. 7. 12 81 n. 5 866 12 with n. 6 812 25
884-g(7) : 12. I 82 n. 3 871 42 1000 89
No. 1-5 128-9 8. 30. 2 163 n. 2 1241-3 42 n. 5 Orestes 429 42
202 INDEX LOCOR UM INDEX LOCORUM 2°3
Euripides, Orestes (cont.): Galen, De TemjJeramentis (Helmreich): 3-4 76 6 II 112, 114-15, 115
I,

487 34 n. 3 1.2 101 n. 4 n. I, 166 n. 6


67. 1-68.6 76
495 33 4 105 n. 2 69·3 145 n. I 81. I I I I, II5 n. I
5°3 25 6 104 n. 6 82. 7-8 35 3 I I I, 179
523 33 n. I 8 104 n. 6 25 82. 1-2 115 n. I

571 36 9 105 n. 2 94. I 34 n. 4 4 III
892 53 2. I 105 n. 2 96. 2-97· 3 73-5,89 5 34 n. 4, 179
941 48 2 104 n. 6 97·3 62,89 83. I I I 1,166 n. 2
1426 34 n. 4 4 104 n. 6 131. I 41 2-84. I 179
1455 88 n. I 3·4 104 n. 6 132.3 41 2 115 n. I
Phoenissae 18-20 87 Gorgias, [rg. (DK6): 136. 2-137. I 35 3 34 n. 4
294 36 6 26,51 140. 3 35 n. I 87 179
380 87 II. 7 89 144. I 91 118. I 47 n. I
Stheneboea (Page, Greek Literary I I a. 30 51 n. 5 3 41 123. I 165
Papyri 1. 128) 15 15 n. I, 18 36 88,89 n. I 52 142-3 107-9, 165-6
Supplices 45 86 n. 3
- 146.3
152.3 145 n. I 142-4 179
313 32 Hellenica Oxyrhynchia (Bartoletti) 16.2 158.2 II5 n. I 142.2 108 and n. I, 166 n. I
377-8 22 118 with n. 3 162. I 88 3 107 n. 6, 164 n. I
4°6-8 106 n. 3 Heraclitus, [rg. (DK6): 172. I 34 n. 4 4 108, 166 n. I
43° 34 n. 3 I 27 n. 4 173- 4 34 n. 4 5-143. I 165
431-2 29 32 27 195.2 35 n. 2 143. 1-148. I 165
433 47 33 3° 196.1-4 35 n. 2 2 108 n. 4, 166
526 42 n. 4 44- 30, 33 197 35 n. 2 4.26. I 35
540-1 42 n. 4 5::; 100 n. I 199·1-5 35 n. 2, 41 39. I 39
563 42 n. 4 80 100 n. I 200 35 n. 2 68.2 35 n. 3
671 42 n. 4 94 100 n. I 216. I 35 78.4 41
Troades 231 44 n. I 114 26-8, 30, 33, 100 n. I, 120 2.35.2 34 n. 4 80. 5 34 n. 4
266-7 4 n. 5, 17,42 n. 5 [HerodesJ, Peri politeias 30-1 118 36. I 41 103. I 35 n. 3
324 42 n. 5 37. I 35 105. I 34 n. 4
1031 53 Herodotus: 39·4 41 106 31
1210 25 1. 8. 3-4 88 42. 3 41 107 34 n. 4
[rg. (Nauck2) 52. 8 38 n. 3 29 5 n. 4, 46, 60 n. 3 45. 2 34 n. 4 117 35 n. 3
122. I I 88 35. I 41 65·3 41 137·2 109 n. 3, 167
141 39 59-61 14° 79. I 34 n. 4 159-61 163 with n. 3, 163-5
172 48 n. 4 59·3 156 n. I 92. I 34 n. 4 161 163-5
228.8 36,53 4-5 141 n. 4, 147, 156 113·2-3 41 161. 3 163 nn. 4 and 5, 166 n. I
252 32 59. 6 4, 15, 147 124. I 73 with n. 3 168. I 34 n. 4
282. 13 36 60.1-3 156 n. I 136.2 47 n. 2 169.2 34 n. 4
292.4-6 38 n. 4 5 147 147·3-4 53 17° 34 n. 4
337 25 61. I 24 177·2 47 n. 2 171 34 n. 4
346 25,36 2 156 n. I 180 138 172.2 35 n. 3
360.45 4 n. 5,15 4 141 n. 4 3.2.2 24 187. I 34 n. 4
388.3 25-6 62. I 156 n. I 16. 3-4 41 19° 35 n. 3
4°2 48 n. 3 64 141 n. 4, 148 n. 5 20.2 34 n. 4 200. I 115 n. I
433 33 65-8 75-9 31. 2-5 47 n. I 201.2 44 n. I
469 36 65. I 76 3 14,18 5·3·2 34 n. 4
530.9 36 2 76 with n. 2, 85 4 35 n. I 6.1-2 35 n. 3
597 48 2-66. I 76-7 38.4 33,37-8 16.2 24
853 33 3 82 n. 3 47. I 77 n. I 18. 2-3 35 n. I
920 22 n. 4 4 77 with n. 2 80. I 178 19.2 44 n. I
1049.2 42 n. 3 5 77 with n. 3, 78 with n. I 2-82 107, II 1-13, 178-g 37.2 109-1 I, 167
1064. I 26 66. I 78 nn. 2 and 4, 80 n. I 2 107 n. 7, 164 n. I 38.2 110 and n. I
1091 26 n. I [-2 76 3-5 112 42. 2 46 n. 4, 60 n. 3
2°4
Herodotus 5 (cont.): I I I. I 46 22 Nicodemus of Heracleia (Anthol.
23
49. 8 77 n. I 123.2 139 24 22 Gr. 6) 316 70 n. 2
55 131 n. I, 138 n. 4,139 n. 2, 13°.2 41 De Morbo Sacro 17 39
148 n. 2 131. I 108 n. 2, III n. I, 130 Parmenides, frg. (DK6):
20 39
57· I 131 n. I n. I, 146 n. 3, 150 De Natura Hominis 4 103 n. 4 8.55-61 102 n. 3
62-5 130 n. I, 134, 138-9 7.2. I 47 n. I De Prisca lvfedicina 5 103 n. 3 9 102 n. 3
62.2 125 n. 4, 127 n. 5, 148 8 a. I 34 n. 4 De Victu I. I I 22 n. 4 12 102 n. 3
n. 2 41. I 24 103 n. 3 16 102 n. 3
3· 69
63· 2-4 129 n. I 102. I 33 Homer: Pausanias:
64. 2 148 103. I 35 n. 4 Iliad 5. 70 27 n. I 1.8·5 132 nn. 3 and 4, 133
66-730 I 143-5 104·4 31,32 27 n. I 27. 2 129
555
66. I 140 n. I 104.4-5 109 I I. 741 27 n. I 4·24·7 170 n. 2
2 3 n. I, 130 n. I, 142, 136. 1 34 n. I 15. 186-95 178 10·5·13 138
143 and n. I, 150, 157 n. I 164. I 164 n. I 178 Pherecydes of Syros, frg. (DK6) 2,
2°9
69·2 3 n. I, 130 n. I, 149 nn. 209.3 35 O,ryssey I. 3 21 n. 2 co!' 2
I and 2, 150, 151, 156, 157 n. I 238. 2 91 n. 2 Philo, De Sacrificiis Abelis et Caini
9.106 77
70 148 n. 5 8. 34 II5 n. 1 112-15 77 (II p. 268 M) 5 79 n. I
70. I 144 n. 2 55 129 63,65 n. 4 Philochorus, frg. (FGH) 67 129
17·487
2 185 65 128 n. 4 18.130 27 n. I Philoponus on Aristotle, De Anima
2-71 144 89. I 24 19.482 27 n. I 405"29 97 n. 4
72. I 144, 185 106·3 53 23. 177-230 12 Pindar (Sne1l3):
4-73. I 144 n. 7 9·41. 4 34 n. 4 183-204 18 Isthmians 2. 38 24
73.1 I~ 48. 2 24 296 12 and n. 2 5.22 62n·3,71
2-3 145 78--g 91 n. 2 27 n. I 43 30 n. 4
325
74. I 144 n. 6 99·3 44 n. I Scholia to Odyssey 23. 296 12 n.2 ~ 20 15, 18
1-2 145 104 44 n. I Homeric Hymns: Nemeans I. 72 29
75. I 146 I I I. I 35 n. I 8.16 12 n. I 3.55 24
2 46 n. 4, 60 n. 3 Hesiod: 30. II-12 69 n. 7 4. 33 15, 18
3 146 Opera et Dies 11-16 65 n. 6, 66 9. 29-30 62 n. 3, 7 I
76 115 n. I n. 5 Iamblichus, De Vita Pythagorica: 10.33 13, 18
77. 1-2 146 219-24 65 n. 6, 66 n. 5 104 97 n. 3, 98 n. 3 11.27 13n·4,18
78 109, 135, 146, 157 n. 2, 159 236-7 70 n. I 257 100 n. 4 Olympians I. 37-8 62 n. 3, 70
88. 2 35 n. 4, 52 250 65 n. 6, 66 n. 5 267 97 n. 3 6.69 13,18
92. I 115 n. I 259-64 65 n. 6, 66 n. 5 Isaeus: 7.88 13
1/.5 108 n. 2 276-80 21 1.2 178 8. 25-7 13 n. 5, 18
94. I 129 n. 2 276 52 n. 2 178 78 4°
35
99.2 110 n. 2 388 23,94 10. 13 59 n. 3 9. 15-16 64 n. 1,71
103. I 110 Theogonia 63-7 2 I n. 5 Isocrates: 13.6-8 64 with n. 1,69 n. 7
6. I I. 3 61 n. 2 74 21 n. 5 6-10 71
5·39
38. I 23 217-19 63 n. 3 7.16 29 12, 18, 174
39. I 138 n. 3 226-32 66-8 20 40 13,18
43·3 107 n. 4, 108 n. 2, 109 307 86, 89 n. I 12. 178-80 Paeans I. 10 72 with n. I, 73
n.4, III and n. I, 167, 178, 179 417 4° Pythians I. 62 34
52. 3 46 n. 4, 60 n. 3 901-6 63-4, 66-8, 71 n. 3 Lysias: 64 14,18
58. 2 41 frg. (Rzach3) 221 40 n. 3 2.18 108 n. 2 2.43 29
67. I 145 n. I Hesychius, S.V. ;4pp.o8iov 10.16 162 n. 2 86-8 30-1
70 145 n. I p.€>.o, 12.42 108 n. 2 5.67 61 n. I
86 {3. 2 33 [Hippocrates] : 13. 12 108 n. 2 10. 70-1 34 n. 2
89 47,60 n. 3 De Aiire, Aquis, Locis frg. 169 20, 37-8, 40 n. I
100. 1 146 n. 2 12. 18-19 105 n. 2 Melica Adespota, frg. (PMG): Scholia to Nemeans I. 72 29 n. I
103. 3 138 n. 3 14 35 937. 11-15 69 n. 7 Olympians 13. 29 174-
105 128 n. I 16 22
13 71 n. I Plato:
106. 3 41 19 35 n. 6 1018 (b). 6-7 64 n. 2 Cratylus 384 d 7
Plato, Cratylus (cont.): Gorgias 45 I e 125 n. I, 183 Sirnonides, frg. (PMG) 65 I 127 368 34 n. 3
388 d 12 In·3 Leges I. 629 a 82 n. I with n. 3 382 31 n. I, 47 n. 3, 58 n. 2
Epistulae 7. 326 d 181 Pliny, Naturalis Historia: Sirnplicius on Aristotle, De Anima 449 31 n. 1,47 n. 3, 58 n. 2
182 4°5a29 97 n. 4 45°-2 22
336 b 34· 17 132-3, 142
d 181 132 n. 3 Solon, frg. (DiehIJ): 454-5 58

181 Plutarch: 3 64-9 481 47 n. 3, 58 n. 2
337 a
Gorgias 482 e G I n. 3 Agis 5 7 n. 2 3. 1-10 67 519 41
482 e--484 c 8 7 n. 2 5 68 n. I 613-14 23

51 7 n. 2 7 68 n. I 663 47 n. 3
483 b 9
II 8 68 Il. I 797 16 Il. 8
e 23 7 Il. 2
508 a 181 8-g 65 n. 5 800-1 4 n. 5, 14 with n. 4
Lycurgus 5·4 75 n. 1,82 n. 3
Hippias lUaior 284 d-e 51 n. 6 6 7 n. 2 9 68 n. I 847 47 n. 3, 58 n. 2
Leges I. 642 d 185 6.10 81 n. 5 II 68 n. I 908 53
2. 674 b 7 In·3 13 7 n. 2 14-25 67 914 25
3·694 a 182 13. I 46,49
16 68 n. 2 1113-14 31
182 Pericles 37·3 19 68 n. I Electra 87 105 n. 2
695 d 46 n. 3
10 n. 2 Solon 3. 5 26-g 67 580-1 52 with n. 3
4·714 a 3 n. 5,15
6. 756 e-758 a 181, 182 II 138 n. 6 3° 68 with n. 5 1043 53
780 d 5 In·3 15 3 n. 5 31-2 65n.l,gon.1 1506 31
18.2 156 33 68 n. I Ichneutae 189 24
7. 795 a I In·3
8.835 e 5 19. I 162 33-8 65 n. 3, 85 n. I Oedipus Coloneus 125-37 87
In·3
3 n. 4, 15, 18 34 65 n. 4, 68 n. I 142 86-7,91
836 e 4 In·3 4
10.889 e 6 20.2 36 65 n. 6, 66 168 25
In·3 59
8go d 4 In·3 24 141 n. 5 37-8 65 n. 6, 66, 68 n. I 337-8 34 n. 4
6 In·3 4 n. I 38-9 65 n. 2, 68 n. I 548 47
25·3
904 a 9 In·3 30.3 141 n. 4 3a 81 n. 5 907-8 52
cg In·3 Themistocles 23. I 144 n. I 3b 81 n. 5 914 31
I I. 927 b 6 74 n. 2 Moralia 303 e-304 c (Quaest. 5·9-10 65 n. 5 1382 29
Menexenus 239 a 181 6 81 n. 5 Oedipus Tyrannus 579 61 n. 2
Gr. 57) 165 n. 3
Phaedo 58 b 5 In·3 615 b-c (Quaest. Conv. I. I) 23. 21 178 863-71 29
Phaedrus 235 d 4 n. I 125 n. I, 183 24. 15-16 3 n. 5, 43 n. 3 Trachiniae 616 25
644 c (Quaest. Conv. 2. 10) 18-20 3 n. 5, 15, 18 682 4 n. 5,17,18
256 d 7 In·3
Politicus 29 I e 2 10 n. 2 Sophocles: 1095-6 86 with n. 4, 8g n. I
In·3
Protagoras 337 a 61 n. 2 833 d (Vit. X Or. Antiph. 2O) Ajax 350 25 1I77 25
22 n. 4 2 n. 3 548 25 Stobaeus, Florilegium (Wachsmuth-
c-338 b
Respublica 2. 369 c-4. 445 c 862 b-c (De Malig. Her. 26) 712 17 Hense):
713 7°-1,87 n. 2 I. 1.5: see Tragica Adespota, frg. 471
100 n. 5 128 n. 2
108 n. 3 91 I a (De Plac. Phil. 5. 30) 1°73 34 n. 3 4. 2: see Tragica Adespota, frg. 502
8.555 b
61 n. 2, 182 177-8 11°4 4 n. 5,17 4. I. 48 4 n. 3
558 c
119 n. 4,182 Pollux: 1108 83 n. 3 138 10 n. 2
561 e
562 a 108 n. 3 8.91 128 n. 2 113° 41 36. 29 177
563 b 182 106 4 n. 3 1160 83 n. 3 37·2 177
1I0 143,144 n. I 1247 47 Strabo:
9. 587 a 10 In·3
c 2 Polyaenus: 1343 41 6. I. 8: see Ephorus, frg. 139
In·3
10.604 a 10 I. 22 140 n. 4 Antigone 24 41 8.4.10 81-2
In·3
b6 165 n. 3 59 31 Suda: S.V. ayopa.uw 182
In·3 6. 45
Polybius 6. 8. 4 182 156 44 n. I EV f£VP'TOVKAa81 'TO g !1'o,
9 In·3
Polyclitus (DK6 I. 391) 24, 177 29 q,op~aw 182
607 a 7 In·3
Symposium 182 a 7 29-36 102 n. 6 178-91 38 'Hp68o'To, 167 with n. 2
In·3
186 d 104 n. 7 Porphyry, De Abstinentia 4. 22 3 n. 3 191 34 n. I OvSbroT ' €yw Toihov
Timaeus 60 e 2 213 29 imo8.gof£uL 123 n. 4
In·3
Plato: Scholia to: Sextus Ernpiricus 9 (Ad". 282-8 41 n. 2 71'apOLVOS 123 n. 4
Alcibiades I. 121 e 97 n. 4 Physicos I) 54 52 n. I 285-7 41 n. 2 po/paL 7 nn. 2 and 4
INDEX LOCORUM

Theognis (Young) : 45 5° 36 502 29 n. 5



54 30, 94 46. 4 5° 84·3 I15 n. 2 Tyrtaeus, frg. (DiehI3):
55-6 3° 47. 2 115 n. 2 85. I I15 n. 2 2 81 n.4
289-9° 22 56. 2 23 105.2 23,52 3 a, b 81 n. 5
Theophrastus: 58. 3 23 n. I 6.14 5° 6 81 n. 5
De Sensibus (Dox. 502-3) 12-15 62. 3 I13, 114 16.2 38 Tzetzes, Jllap..{joL T€XVLKOl 7TEpl KWP.c.{JOtUS
104 n. 2 3-4 115,116-19 4 173 (CGF 42-3) 85-9 183
(Dox. 508) 32 104 n. 3 3-5 32 18·7 34 n. 3
(Dox. 510) 39 104 n. 4 64·3 32 n. I 33. 2 115 n. 2
(Dox. 5I1) 41 104 n. 4 65.1-2 88 with n. 3 5 49, I 14 with nn. I and 4,
(Dox. 512) 46 104 n. 4 66.2 23,88 115
(Dox. 515) 58 104 n. 5 3 88 39. I 114 n. 4,178 Xenarchus, frg. (Edmonds) 4. 22
Metaphysica (DK6 58. B 14) 33 67·5 88 54·5 147 5 n. 3
105 n. 2 6 23 n. 1,88 6 33 n. 2,14°,147,148 n. I Xenophanes, frg. (DiehI3):
Thucydides: 70. 5-6 49,60 n. 4 55. 1-2 140 with n. 2 2 69-70
1·9·2 I15 n. 3 6 115 n. 2 3 141 n. 4 2. 19 69 n. 4,71
12 44 n. I 82.6 31,41 57. I 141 n. 4 22 69 n. 5
17 80 n. 2 8 I14, 115 4 140 n. 4, 142 n. I Xenophon:
18. I 79-80, 139 n. I [84]. 2 31 n. 2 58.2 141 n. 4 Anabasis 4. 6. 14 I18 n. I
24. 2 36 3 22 n. 3 59. 2 138 n. 4, 148 n. 2 6. 6. 28 7 n. 2
4° 52 95. 2 176 2-3 139 n. I Apologia 21 178
41 33 4·21. 3 115 n. 3 4 139 and n. 2 Cyropaedia:
72•2 115 n. 2 22.2 115 n. 2 60.4 115 n. 2 2. I. 31
77. I 5° 3 115 n. 2 89.4 I15n.2 2. 18

3 32 38. I 49 n. 3, 60 n. 4 7.75.6 178 21

84· 3 32 66. I 115 n. 2 8. 9. 3 115 n. 2 3·5


103.3 170 n. 2 74·3 108 n. 2 48. 3 I15 n. 3 4.6. 12
115·3 108 n. 2 76.2 108 n. 3,119 53.2 33 n. 2 Alemorabilia:
125. I 115 n. 2 78.2-3 115 64·5 176-77 I. 2.4°-6 51 n. 6
126.2 144 n. 3 3 113,114 n. 2 65·3 180 42 2 n. 3, 5 I n. 6
8 174 84. 2 I15 n. 2 72 108 n. 2 4·4·13 5 I n. 6
12 144 n. 3 92.7 89,91 75.2 108 n. 3 Oeconomicus 14. 4 5 n. 3
127. I 144 n. 3 93·3 I18 n. 5 76.6 33 n. 2 Respublica Lacedaemoniorum 10. 7
2. 3. 2 115 n. 3 97-101 91 n. 2 31. I I15 n. 2 118 n. I
34. I 36, 175-{) 97. 2 36 n. I 92.9 115n.2 [Respublica Atheniensium] :
5 175 98.2 36 97. 2 103 n. 3, 106 1.8 79 n. I
35·I 49 105. I 115 n. 2 Timotheus, Persae (P !vIG, frg. 8-9 82-5
37·I 34 n. 3, 50,114 n. 3 106.2 115 n. 2 791) 237-40 69 n. 7 9 50 n. 3
3 50 with n. 1,58 118 42 Tragica Adespota, frg. (Nauck2): 10 50 n. 3
39·4 5° 133·3 49 26 39 n. 2 18 50 n. 3
52.4 42 5·27·2 I15 n. 2 99 33 n. I 3·2 2 n. 3, 50 n. 3
53·I 90 with n. 2 30. I I15 n. 2 471 29n·5 II 117 n. 2,169 n. 2
4 5° 31. 6 119
65.8 115 n. 2 41.3 115 n. 2
72.2 115 n. 2 45·I 115 n. 2
73. I I15 n. 2 49·I 49
97·4 36 60. I I15 n. 2
3·34·4 33 n. 2 2 34 n. I
37·3 5° 5 115 n. 2
4 33 n. 2 63·4 49 n. 3, 60 n. 4
5 115 n. 2 66. 2-3 49 n. 3, 60 n. 4
42. 6 115 n. 2 69·I 178
43. 2 115 n. 2 2 36
INDEX LOCOR UM 211

B 1-2 45, 169 n. 4 27 45


16-24 46 28 45
19-20 168 n. 2, 169 n. 4 3° 45 n. 2
Hesperia: 45 45
ATL D 14 III. 14-15 50 n. 2
8 n. 6, 16 n.
D 15.41-2 42 n. I 8 (1939) 59-65 135 n. 2, 137
POxy: 46
2256, frg. 3 59 n. 4 5,18,45
48 101 n. I, 120 n. 2 10 (1941) 284-95 17 n. 3
2450, frg. I 37 n. 2, 38 25 44, 167-70
14 (1945), No. II. 7 51 n. 2
25·19 8 n. 3, 167-8
Bengtson, Staatsvertriige 2, No. 145 32 (1963) 187-208 135 n. 2
Schwyzer, DCE: 19-20 44, 167 n. 3
42 n. I 36 (1967), No. 15 4 n. 4, 16 n. 6,
No. 51 42 n. 2 32 44,167
Buck, CD, 18
NO.2 44 n. 3, 167-70 7 n. 6 34-5 44,167
4°9
2.19-20 44, 167 n. 2, 167-8 8 n. I 170 with n. 3
IC: 410.5 44
32 44,167 41 I. 3 14 with nn. I and 2 86. 15-17 152 n. 2
12• I. I 2n. 3
34-5 44,167 412 7 n. 6, 8 n. I 87·4-5 5 n. I
3. 16 2n. 3
23·28-g 7 n. 7 413 7 n. 6, 8 n. I 5 51 n. I
52. C. 19 16 n. 7, 18 4. 26 2 n. 3
414 7 n. 6 19-20 3 n. 2, 5 n. I,
15·30-1 42, 168 n. 2
57 170-3 418.19 8 n. I 51 n. I
16 n. 5, 18, 170 37 102 n. I, 120 n. 2
57· 46 424. 10-1 I 8 n. I 96. 15-16 34 n. I
59. A. I 8 n. 6, 16 n. 3, 18 77 48-9 2, No. 100.6 In·4
77-6 59 n. 2
SEC:
13-14 16 n. 4,18 10, No. 17 42 n. I 1I6.21 In·4
8 n. 6, 16 n. 3, 18 94. 17-18 51 n. 3
14 103 51 n. 3 137·13-14 In·4
178 23-5 51 n. 3
352 135 n. 2, 137 162. 15 In·4
110.15-17 152 n. 2
II, No. 1178 14 with nn. I and 2 [36] In·4
1I5·4-5 5 n. I
181. 25 In·4
5-6 51
Tod, CHI: 200.217 In·4
5 51 n. I, 173 with
12, No. I 161-3 246 In·4
n. I
1.2 7 n. I, 162-3 204. 11-14 14 with n. 3,
3 n. 2, 5 n. I, 15,
24 45, 170-3 18
Gortyn, Law of (Kohler-Ziebarth): 18,51 n. I, 173 n. I
24. 26 45 12 4 n. 3
III. 20 8 n. 2 485 133 n. 2
29-30 8 n. 2 22• 10.6-7 51 n·4
IV. II 8 n. 2 4·493 7 n. 8
31 8 n. 2 5. 1,20.2-3 7 n. 2
45-6 8 n. 2 1I55 42 n. 2
48 8 n. 2 1498.12 7 n. 3
50-I 8 n. 2 5.2, 159 A. 8 8 n. 5, 17 n. 2, 18
VI. 15 8 n. 2 B.20 8n·5,I7n.2,I8
31 8 n. 2 12. 8, 263. 7 168 n. I
VII. 47-8 8 n. 2 14·645· 145-6 7 n. 5
VIII. 10 8 n. 2 151 7 n. 5
25-6 8 n. 2
29-30 8 n. 2 J1cfarmor Parium (Jacoby):
35-6 8 n. 2 ep. 46 142 with n. 2
40 8 n. 2 54 132 n. 4
IX. 15-16 8 n. 2 Meiggs and Andrewes:
23-4 8 n. 2 B 26. 27 169 n. 3
X.44-5 8 n. 2 33 169 n. 3
46 8 n. 2 30 169 n. 2
53 178 87·15 168 n. 2
XI. 19-23 8 n. 2 116 45-6
26-7 8 n. 2 116. A 21-2 45, 168 n. 2, 169
28-9 8 n. 2 n·4
XII. 15-19 8 n. 2 45-6, 168 n. 2,
22-3 8 n. 2 169 n. 4
'>.wIJEpLa, associated with vop.os, 109. personification of, 63, 64-7, 71,
associated with 100vop.La, 108, 166, 72-3.
182. as title of Solon, frg. 3, 64.
associated with democracy, 108. as title of Tyrtaeus, frg. 2, 81-2.
£TalpELal, in Athens, 142-3. Eilvop.os, musical sense of, 61 n. I.
£vOuva, I 12. in Aeschylus, 61 n. 1,62,72, 73.
aypa1rTa vop.lp.a, in Sophocles, 58. (3am>'EVS, title survives institution of Evvop.Eop.al, in Aeschines and Demos- in Aleman, 6 I n. I.
ayparpos vop.os, in Andocides, I with n. 4. kingship, 6. thenes, 84 n. 2. in Pindar, 61 n. 1,62,7°,71-2.
in Thucydides, 58. (3ov>'r, 0TJP.OOLTJ,in sixth-century Chios, in Anonymus Iamblichi, 93.
aOlKos, associated with avop.os, 87, 88, 162. in Herodotus, 62, 73-4, 76. Tel FEFaOTJPoTa, legal term in Naupactus,
89,92 n. 3· in Thucydides, 79-80. 17°,171.
aoos, legal term in Halicarnassus, 8, ypap.p.aTa, in Gortyn code, 8.
in [Xenophon], 82-5.
167-8, 169, 170. yparpr, 1rapavop.wv, 2 with n. 3.
Evvop.La, 62-85, 92-5. IJEIJP.WV, see IJEOP.WV.
in Thasos, 168 n. I. yparpos, term for 'statute' in Olympia, 8.
etymology of, 61, 73 n. 3. IJEIJ(r)p.os, see IJwJLos.
alJEOs, associated with avop.os, 87, 88. yparpw-derivatives in Gortyn code, 8.
as a quality of personal behaviour, IJEOJLWV, IJEOJLla, Nemean Games as
a[vos, legal term in Epidaurus and 62,63,65, 70-1,94. TEIJJLWV of Heracles, 13 n. 4.
0TJp.oKpaTEop.al, in Herodotus, 107 n. 4,
Delphi,8. as condition oflaw-and-order, 62, 63, constitution of Naupactus as IJEIJJLWV,
109 n. 3, I I I.
dJ)aypa4>€;~ rwv vO/LWV, in Athens, 5 I. 16,45, 170-3·
opposed to TvpavvEvop.al, 109 n. 3. 64, 65, 69, 70, 73, 74-5, 76-8, 80,
dvaKaAv1TT~pLa, 40. 0TJp.oKpaTLa, not identical with 100vop.La, in Aeschylus, 15, 17.
83,94·
avop.Ew, in Anonymus Iamblichi, 93. associated with owrppoovvTJ, 72-3, in Euripides, 15, 17.
120.
in Herodotus, 91. in Herodotus, 15.
relation to 100vop.La, 107, 111-13, 181. 176-7.
avop.La, etymology of, 61. TEIJJLWS in Pindar, 15.
not appropriate name for Cleisthenes' opposed to iJ(3plS, 63, 65, 7 I, 72.
meaning of, 85-94. opposed to avop.La, 70, 94. of Athens, 4, 16,59, 140, 174-5·
reforms, 153-4.
opposite of Evvop.La, 70, 94. describes Plataean constitution dur- opposed to ovovop.La, 65-9, 70, 94· last used of 'statute' 511/10 B.C., 4,
relation to Ovovop.La, 70. association with wealth not an essen- 59, 158.
ing Persian Wars, I 17.
associated with iJ(3plS, 86, 89. not used in Alemaeon, frg. 4, 106. tial attribute of, 69-70, 80. IJWJLolJha,,6, 16, 174-5.
religious overtones in, 86-7, 88, 89, first attested in Herodotus, 120 n. 2. constitutional change not implied in, IJWJLOS, basic idea in, 18-19, 55.
90, 91. 74-5,82. etymology of, 9- 10.
in Herodotus, 109 n. 4, I I I n. I,
does not imply vop.os = 'statute', 85, 120 n. I. associated with constitutional work- not found on Linear B tablets,
86, 89, 90, 94· in Athenian treaty with Colophon ings of the state, 84. 10 n. 3.
meaning of influenced by vop.os = religious overtones in, 68, 7 I with not necessarily written, 16-17.
447/6 B.C., 120 n. 2.
'statute', 91, 92-4. 0TJP.OTlKOs, 147 with n. I, 165 n. 3. n. I. used of Draco's statutes, 3, 5, 15,51,
in Anonymus Iamblichi, 92-4, 95. OlmpTJrplop.OS, 141-2, 151. does not imply 'statute' before 57,59, 175·
in Euripides, 26, 90-I. [Xenophon], 68, 70, 74-5, 78, 80. used of Solon's statutes, 3-5, IS, 57·
OLKTJ, in Hesiod, 2 I.
in Herodotus, 73, 74, 89-90. related to vop.os, 2 I, 94. meaning of affected by vop.os = uses of, before end of fifth century
not in Solon, 69 n. I, 90 n. I. 'statute', 62, 82-5, 92-4. B.C., 17-18.
ooPVrpOPOl, 141 n. 4, 142 n. I.
in Thucydides, 90. = thing placed in significant loca-
OvvaoTELa, form of oligarchy in Thucy- EuvofLla:
avop.os, in musical sense, 61 n. I, 86. in Egypt, 73. tion, 12.
dides, 113.
associated with aOlKos, 87, 88, 89, rules Thebes during Persian Wars, in Media, 73-5. = something stored away, treasure,
92 n. 3. 113, 115, 116-19. in Sparta, 64, 75-82, 82 n. 3, 84 n. I. 12.
associated with aIJEOS, 87, 88. in Aleman, 64. = place of burial, 13 n. I.
opposed to democracy and to d>'ly-
in Aeschylus, 61 n. 1,86. in Anonymus Iamblichi, 92-4. = fundamental regulation, 13-15.
apXLa loovop.os, 113, 116-17.
in Anonymus Iamblichi, 88. in Aristophanes, 73. = establishment of fundamental in-
Ovovop.La, 65-9.
in Aristophanes, 88. etymology of, 6 I. defined by Aristotle, 84 n. 2, 94. stitution, 13.
in Euripides, 87-8. in Bacchylides, 72-3. = institution of celebrating victors in
opposite of Evvop.La, 65-9, 70, 94.
in Gorgias, 88. relation to avop.La, 70. in Herodotus, 73, 76, 78. song, 13, 174·
in Herodotus, 88. in Hesiod, 63-4, 65, 69-70. = establishment of athletic games,
relation to KaKovop.La, 85 n. I.
in Hesiod, 86. in Homer, 63, 64, 65· 13·
in Hesiod, 65-7.
in Sophocles, 86-7. in Pindar, 64, 71, 72, 73· = founding act, 13.
in Solon, 65-9, 90.
in Thucydides, 88. in Solon, 64-9, 84. = status conferred by external
personification of, 66-7.
a"op.ws, in Euripides, 89. in Sophocles, 70- I. agency, 13.
in Gorgias, 89. Tel .zpTJp.Eva, term for 'statute' in Myce- in Xenophanes, 69-70, 7 I. = rule of propriety and good be-
in Thucydides, 89. nae,7· in [Xenophon], 62, 82-5, 95. haviour, 15.
O£a/-,os (cont.): as principle of political equality, 97, inhibits human freedom of action,
Vfo1ToAi'TaL, 151.
= specific religious or political regu- 106, 108-9, III, 113, 115, 116 47-8, 50.
v£oXpoos, revolutionary connotations of,
lation, 4 with n. 4, 15-17. with n. I, 117, II8-19, 121. depreciation of, begins in philosophy
44 with n. I.
= written statute, 6, 15-16, 57. alleged association with nobility, and science, 38-9.
vopoas, 9-10.
= written statute: 122-3· vOJ.L€V~, g. in Antiphon, 37.
in Locris (nO/-,os or T£TO/-,OS), 8, 16. as propaganda term, 113-14, 115, in Aristophanes, 36-7, 39.
"opo~, 9·
at Olympia (O£O(T)/-,OS) 14. 135, 153-5, 158. ,'o/-,La,
in Naupactus and Eastern LOCl'is, in Democritus, 39.
in Tegea, 8,17. attempted establishment of, in Samos, in Empedocles, 33-9.
45, 170-2.
last used in Athens 5 I 1/ IO B.C., 4, 107-9, 165-6. vopoLpoa, in Sparta, changed by Lycur- in Euripides, 36, 38, 39, 42, 47-8.
59,158. granted to Miletus by Aristagoras, gus, 77, 78. in Herodotus, 39.
replaced by vo/-,os in Athens, 55-6, 109-1 I. in Sophocles, 58. in Hippocratic writings, 39.
57, 96, 158-60, 173· in Athens, in Cleisthenes' reforms, 96, vopooOw{a, I with n. 2. in Athens and Corcyra, 42.
in Aeschylus, 13, 17. 101,122-3, 130, 135, 137, 153-7. = way of life, 21-2.
VOPOOL,of all Greeks, 33, 36, 39, 41, 43·
in Anacreon, 12. possible models of, 161-6. = normal order of things, 22-3.
of non-Greeks, 33.
in Aristophanes, 14. in AIcmaeon of Croton, 99-106, 107, of Aegina, 52. = normal way in which something is
in Democritus, 17. II3, II9· of Aetolia, 36. done, 23-4, 94·
in Euripides, 12 with n. 6. in Herodotus, 107-13, 114, 116, = normal or proper conduct of in-
of Argos, 35, 49, 52.
in Herodotus, 14. I r9-2o, 166-7. dividual, I n. 3, 24-6, 62, 85,
of Athens, 36, 41, 42, 46, 60.
in Homer, 12, 13. in Isocrates, r80-I. of Babylonia, 35, 4 I. 86, 87, 90, 93, 94·
in Pindar (nO/-,os), 12, 13-14, 15, in Plato, 181-2. of Caria, 52. treated like statutory enactment,
174· in Thucydides, 113, 114, 115, 116, of Corcyra, 42, 49, 60. 26, 91.
in Sophocles, 14, 17. 120. of Corinth, 47, 60. = source issuing and guaranteeing
in ephebic oath in Athens, 4, 14. laovo/-,LKOs, in Plato, 182. norms, 26-9, 120, 158.
of Egypt, 35,41,43,47,53.
in Phyle epigram, 17. laovopoos, in Harmodius skolia, 96-7, of Erechtheids, 36. = law-and-order, I n. 3, 30-3, 62,
Ow/-,oq,opos, attribute of Demeter, 13 101, 107, 113, 121-36, 161. of Issedones, 35. 85,94·
with n. 1. in Plato, 181. = mores of a social or political group,
of Libya, 35 n. 3.
in Thucydides, 113, 114, 116-19. of Makrokephaloi, 35. 33-4·
laTJyop{a, 109, 135, 146-7, 157 n. 2,180. laorT]S, 182. of Massagetae, 35. = custom, social practice, I n. 3,
lao/-,oLp{a, 105, 178.
of Nasamones, 35 n. 3· 34-7·
TO raov, 182. KaO{aTTJfLL, 77, 108. of Odrysians, 36. treated like statutory enactment,
laovo/-,Eo/-,aL, in Thucydides, 114 n. I. KaKovopo{a, relation to ovavofL{a,85 n. I. of Olympia, 49. 36-7, 48 n. 3.
laovo/-,{a, 96-120, 180-2. in [Xenophon], 82-5, 95. = conventional belief, I n. 3, 37-
of Persia, 35, 41, 47·
in Epicurean philosophy, 96 n. I. KaKOVOJLOS, 61 n. I. of Phoenicians, 36.
etymology of, 61.
4°·
in Herodotus, 76-7, 78-9, 85. of Sauromatians, 35 n. 3· = religious practice, custom, or be-
reflects political senses of vO/-,os, KoAa~w, 83 n. 3. of Scythians, 35 nn. 3 and 6, 41. lief, I n. 3, 40-3, 87·
119-20, 158. KOPOS, opposed to £vvofL{a, 65, 7 I. of Sparta, 35-6, 46, 49, 60. = precedent, 52-3.
affected by vO/-,os = 'statute' in KOPVVTJq,0POL, 141 n. 4, 147. of Syracuse, 49. = rule, as in a game, 53.
fourth century, 119, 181-2. KpaatS, see aupopo£TpOSKpaaLS. of Taurians, 35 n. 3, 43, 48. = statute, as political and judicial
laovoJLla: KwAaKpETaL, title survives original func- of Thracians, 35 n. 3. regulation, 43-52, 120, 158.
and democracy, 96, 97, 106, 107, tions,6 and n. 3. VOfLOS, = pasture, abode, district, 9. indifference in fifth century
1°9-11, 111-13, 113-14, 115, 120, vOfLoS, = melody, tune, 10, 21-2, 86. whether or not it is written,
121, 130, 135-6, 137, 147. VOfLOS, basic idea in, 20-1, 54, 55· 43-52, 60, I7 I.
associated but not identical with etymology of, 9-10, 61. in Athens, relation to 1~q,wpoa,
0TJ/-,oKpaT{a, 120, 18I. wO{aTTJfLL, 77, 108. 1-3, 168, 169.
compounds of, 60-1, 62-136, 157--8.
associated with JAwO£p{a, 108, 166, po£Taf3aAAw, 108 n. 3. not on Linear B tablets, 10 n. 3. possible antecedents of, 167-
182. poofpa, division in Cyrene in Demonax' not in Solon, 3 n. 5. 73-
associated with TrAijOos, 114-16. reform, 163. may have beginning in time, 52-3. used of Draco's and Solon's
opposed to tyranny, 97, 101, 107, poovapx{a, opposed to laovopo{a, 99-102, may be god-given, 21. laws only by later authors,
109-1 I, II3. 106. may control the gods, 29. 3,5,51, 173·
opposed to /-,ovapx{a, 99-102, 106. related to O{KTJ, 2 I, 94. used of Cleisthenes' laws, 3,
opposed to oligarchy, 107, 113, 114. vaUKpapoL, title survives original func- associated with JAevO£p{a, lO9. 158-60.
associated with oligarchy, 114, 116- tions, 6. opposed to tyranny and narrow not used before 5II/1O B.C., 6,
19· VEfLW, 9-10, 61, 73 n. 3,81. oligarchy, 32, 47. 59·
vOjJ,o<; (cont.): See also aypaq,os vOjJoos and written
=statute in Athens (cont.) : legislation.
replaces BEajJoos, 55-6, vOjJoos-q,va,s controversy, 22, 23, 35, 36,
158-60, 173· 39-40, 51.
first attested 464/3 B.C., 43, 58- oA,yapx1a, first attested in Herodotus,
9, 95, 161. 120 n. 2.
.\dlllctuS, Attic skolion on, 129. Anaxagoras, contemporary of late
first explicit mention as written, 57. o>.,yapx1a in Thebes 427 B.C.,
laovojJoos,
Aeacidae, 15. years of Alcmaeon of Croton,
established as written by 403/2 B.C., 113, II{, 115, 116-19.
1,2,5,7, 10,57,96. Aegina, 13, 15· 98-9'
opposed to democracy and Dvvaaula, aUjJojJo€Tpla and KpaaLS in doctrine of,
identified by name of proposer, 51. vOjJoos of, 52.
affects connotations of £!JvojJola, 62,
"3· called EUVOjJoOSby Pindar, 7 I. 104.
as political slogan, 114. Anaxandrides and Ariston, kings of
Aesehines, .tJvojJo€ojJoa, in, 84 n. 2.
8,2-5', 92-4. as appropriate name for Spartan con-
Aeschylus, avojJoos in, 6 I n. I, 86. Sparta, defeat Tegea, 76.
of aV0jJo,a, 9 I, 92-4. stitution, I 17- I 8.
€uvojJoos in, 62, 72, 73· Anchimolius, leads Spartan troops
of laovojJola, I 19-20, 158.
in Aeschylus, 22-3, 24, 25, 28, 33 n. 2,
34,37,41,43,53,58-9, 120, 161.
0PPos °
See also laovojJoos.
VOjJoLOS,in Naupactus, 45, 171.
(JEup.,ta in, 15, 17.
BwjJoos in, 13.
against Hippias, 129, 139.
Andocides, cites law of 403/2 B.C.,
1TapavojJo€w, 88, 9 I. vOjJoos in, 22-3, 24, 25, 28, 33 n. 2, 31, differentiating between vOjJoos and
in Aleaeus, 34 n. 6.
1TapavojJola, 85. 37,41,43,53,58-9,120,161. ifi~q,wjJoa, I, 3, 5, 7, 57·
in Aleman, 21-2.
1TapavojJows, 23, 88. Aetolians, I n. 4, 36. uses BwjJoos and vOjJoos indifferently of
in Antiphon, 37, 51.
1T<1.TpLOSvOjJoos, 36, 175-6. Agariste, daughter of Cleisthenes of Draco's laws, 5.
in Archilochus, 34 n. 6.
1TMiBos, associated with laovojJola,1 14-16. Sieyon,41. Anonymus Iambliehi, alleged author-
in Aristophanes, 22, 24, 34 n. 3, 36-7,
in Herodotus, I I 1-12, 114-15. Agis, king of Sparta, 49 n. 3· ship of, 92 n. I.
39, 43, 48-9, 53 n. I, 57·
used by Callicles, 23, 40, 5 I. in Thucydides, 115-16. Ajax, Attic skolion on, 129. avop.€w in, 93.
1TpoaETa,pl'ojJoa"inHerodotus,1 42-3, I 57. Aleaeus, author of Attic skolion, 127· avojJola in, 92-4,95.
in Critias, 51-2.
vOjJoos in, 34 n. 6. avojJoos in, 88.
in Democritus, 39. p~Tpa, legal term in Chios, 7, 162-3.
in Cyprus, 7. Aleibiades, 38. €Vvop.EOfl-at in, 93.
in Empedocles, 38-9.
in Heracleia, 7. Alemaeon, Athenian commander in €vvopia in, 92-4.
in Euripides, 22, 23, 24 n. 3, 25-6, 29,
in Messenia, 7. First Sacred War, 138. Antenor, see tyrannicides.
32-3, 34, 36, 38, 39, 42, 47-8,
in Olympia, 7, 8. Alemaeon, archon 50716 B.C., 143-4, Anthesteria, 42.
52-3, 57·
145,149· Antiphon, speech against Demosthenes,
in Gorgias, 26, 51. in Sparta, 7.
Alcmaeon of Croton, dates of, 97-9· 2 n. 3.
in Heraclitus, 26-8, 30, 33, 120. in Tarentum, 7.
relation to Croton, 106. vOjJoos in, 37, 51.
in Herodotus, 23, 24, 25, 31, 33, a1TovDoq,opo" I n. 4.
not a Pythagorean, 97-8. Aphrodite, sexual relations as BwjJoos of,
34 n. 4, 35, 39, 41, 46-7, 52, 53· av>'>'oyos, in Halicarnassus, 168, 172.
in Hesiod, 21, 23-4,4°. frg. 4, textual problems, 177-8. 13·
aVjJojJoETpOS KpaaLS,meaning of, 102-5. Arcadia, Spartan designs against, 76.
in Hippocratic writings, 22, 35, 39. laovojJola in, 99-106, 107, 113,
in Alemaeon, frg. 4, 102-5. scene of Philippides' vision of Pan,
in Pherecydes of Syros, 40. in Aristotle, 103-4. "9·
aVjJojJoETpOSKpaa,s in, 102-5· 128.
in Pindar, 20, 24,29,3°-1,34,37-8, in doxography, 103-4.
Alemaeonids, curse on, 144, 145, 185. Arcesilaus II of Cyrene, 163.
41. in Galen, 104.
exiled by Hippias, 138. Archedemides, archon 464/3 B.C., 59·
in Plato, I n. 3, 23, 40. awq,poavvTJ, associated with .tJvojJola,
led opponents of Peisistratids at Leip- Archestratus, enacted vOjJoo, at Athens,
in Sophocles, 22, 23, 24, 25, 29, 31, 72-3,176-7.
32, 34nn. 3 and 4, 38, 41,47, 52, 53· sydrium, 138. 5·
Tagl,s,20. influence in Delphi, 138. Archidamus, praises Spartan adherence
in Theognis, 22, 30, 94.
T€BjJoLOS, see B€ajJoLOV. role in liberating Athens from tyr- to vOjJoo" 32.
in Thucydides, 23, 31-2, 33, 34 n. 3,
uBjJoos, see BwjJoos. anny, 130, 134, 138-9, 150. Archilochus, vojJoos in, 34 n. 6.
36,38,42,49-50,58,60, 175-6.
T€TBjJoos, see BwjJoos. alleged opposition to, in 507 B.C., archons, Athenian, oath exacted from,
in Erythrae c. 450 B.C., 45-6, 168 n. 2,
TupavvEvojJoa" opposed to DTJjJooKpaTfojJoa" 131, 132 n. I, 134-5. 3-4·
169.
109 n. 3. See also Cleisthenes. Areopagus, Council of the, under
in Halicarnassus c. 460-455 B.C., 44,
v{3p,s,associated with avojJola, 86, 89. Aleman, EvvojJola in, 64. Solon, 162.
167-70, 172.
opposed to £!JvojJola, 63, 65, 71, 72. in, 6 I n. I. as BwjJoos for trials of homicide estab-
in treaty between Athens and Colo- EVVOJLOS

VOJ.LOS in, 21-2. lished by BwjJoos of Athene, 13·


phon 44716 B.C., 41-2, 168 n. 2. ifi~q"ajJoa, in Athens, relation to vOjJoos,
Alexander the Great, restores tyranni- equal votes for and against accused
in Naupactus, 45 n. 2, 170-3. 1-3, 168, 169.
cide group to Athens, 132. result in acquittal, 48.
in tribute assessment of 425 B.C., in Erythrae c. 450 B.C., 45, 169.
Amasis, 47 n. 2. Argos, vOjJoo, of, 35, 49, 52.
168 n. 2. ifiijq,os, 2 n. 4.
Argos (cont.): source of Harmodius skolia, 96, 121, Chios, pTJTpa used for 'statute', 7, Cleisthenes of Sicyon, betroths his
source of mercenaries for Peisistratus, 123, 126-7· 162-3· daughter to Megacles, 41.
14I. Athenagoras, 114. constitution of, as possible model for Cleomenes, leads Spartans liberating
Aristagoras, grants laovofL{a to Miletus, Athene, establishes Areopagus as her Cleisthenes, 161-3. Athens from tyranny, 130, 134,
109-II, 167. OWfLOS by means of a OWfLoS, 13. Choes, festival, 42, 53. 139, 144, 148.
Aristarchus, 12, 2 I n. 2. Tritogeneia, Attic skolion to, 128. Cimon, father of Miltiades, 138. called to Athens by Isagoras 507 B.C.,
Aristion, proposes bodyguard for Peisis- Athens, vOfLO' of, 36, 41, 46, 50, 60. Cineas commander of Thessalian 144, 145, 149, 150, 160, 185.
tratus, 147, 156. regarded as written by 442 B.C., cava'lry allied with Hippias, 129, 139· withdraws from Athens under safe-
Aristogeiton, tortured after murder of 57-8. citizenship, in Erythrae, possibly de- conduct, 144.
Hipparchus, 140. abandoned during the Plague, 42. fined by law, 46. tries by force to reinstate Isagoras,
See also Harmodius and Aristogeiton. laws defining paternal authority over in Thebes, 118-19, 180. 144 n. 6, 145-6·
Ariston, see Anaxandrides and Aris- daughters, 59. granted by tyrants to their supporters, Cleon, attitude to vOfLoS, 50.
ton. laws on inheritance, 59, 170. 141. cleruchs, Athenian, established on
Aristophanes, earliest explicit mention liberation from tyranny, see tyranny, Athenian, criteria of, 141-2, 151, 154· Euboea 506 B.C., 146.
of written vOfLO' in, 57. in Athens. possible grants of by Peisistratus coinage, decree on, 422 B.C., 51.
earliest reference to Harmodius requests alliance with Persia 507 B.C., and his sons, 141-2. Colophon, treaty with Athens 447/6
skolia in, 123-4, 126. 145· Pericles' law on, 46. B.C., 41-2, 120 n. 2, 168 n. 2.
avofLos in, 88. withdraws support from Miletus in Cleisthenes, archon 525/4 B.C., 135, oath exacted by Athens, 41-2.
€uvopla in, 73. Ionian Revolt, I 10. 137· common people, see demos.
vOfLoS in, 22, 24, 34 n. 3, 36-7, 39,43, tolerates oligarchy in Miletus 450/49 exiled under the tyranny, 138, 148. Corcyra, vOfLO' of, 42, 49, 60.
48~9, 53 n. 1,57· B.C., 169. opponent of Isagoras, 131, 133, 140, Corinthian speech against, before
Aristophanes of Byzantium, 12. treaty with Colophon 447/6 B.C., 142-5, 148. Athenian Assembly, 52.
Aristotle, gives archon date for fortifica- 41-2, 120 n. 2, 168 n. 2. attitude to Athenian nobility, 152, party warfare in, 3 I .
tion of Munichia and surrender of colony sent to Brea c. 445 B.C., 170. 154, 157, 158. Corinth, VOfLO' of, 47, 60.
Peisistratids, 139. applies same commercial laws to attitude to Athenian demos before in Pindar, home of Eunomia, Dika,
account of events in Athens 508/7- herself and to her allies, 50. 508/7 B.C., 149, 156. and Eirena, 64, 7 I .
507/6 B.C., 143-5. tends to support democracies during appeals for support to demos, 143, defects from Peloponnesian army
uses OWfLOS and VOfLOS indifferently of Peioponnesian'Var, 113. 155-7· 506 B.C., 146.
Draco's and Solon's laws, 5. armistice with Sparta 423 B.C., 42. exiled by Cleomenes and Isagoras speech against Corcyra before
defines €VVOfLW, 84 n. 2, 94. 508/7 B.C., 144, 145, 185. Athenian Assembly, 52.
Babylonians, vOfLO' of, 35, 41.
aVfLfL€TpOS KpiiaLS in, 103, 104. recalled from exile, 145· Council of Five Hundred, in Athens,
Bacchylides, influenced by Hesiod, 72.
Artaphernes, satrap, 145. establishes democracy 507 B.C., 130, candidates elected by demes,
€tJVop.la in, 72-3.
Artemis, Attic skolion on, 128. 133, 135-6, 146, 150, 154, 161. 153·
Battus II Eudaimon of Cyrene, 163.
Assembly, Athenian, majority vote vali- preserves Solonian institutions and majority vote validates law, 2 with
Battus III of Cyrene, 163.
dates law, 2 n. 3, 3. statutes, 158-9. n·3·
Boeotia, defeated by Athens 506 B.C.,
under Solon, 156, 162. change from OWfLoS to vOfLOS, 55-6, in [Xenophon], Constitution rif Athens,
109, 135, 145-6.
votes bodyguard for Peisistratus, 147, 158-60. 82-4·
constitution of member states of
156-7. reforms of, 141, 143, 144, 145, 149- Council of Four Hundred, in Athens,
League, 118.
possibly attended by aliens under 60. under Solon, 162.
Brasidas, march through Thessaly
Peisistratus, 142. passed by Assembly, 155-7, 158. resists Cleomenes in 50817 B.C., 144,
424 B.C., II3, II5~I6.
instrument for passing Cleisthenes' enacted as ifiTJq,{afLaTa, 3 with n. I, 149,160.
Thracian expedition of, 82.
reforms, 155-7, 158, 159. 158-9' passes Cleisthenes' reforms, 144, 158.
Brea, Athenian colony sent to, c. 445
addressed by Corinthians to oppose tribes in, 150-1, 154-5, 156, 164. councils, in cities of Boeotian League,
B.C., 170.
Corcyrean alliance, 52. demes in, 151-3, 154, 157· II8.
in [Xenophon], Constitution of Athens, Callicles, VOfLOS used by, 23, 40, 5 I. trittyes in, 152, 154· in Thebes, 118-19.
82-4· Cambyses, 47 n. I. as expression of laovofL{a, 96, 101, Crete, source of Lycurgus' reforms in
assembly, in Halicarnassus, 8, 168. Carians, vOfLOS of, 52. 122, 132, 135, 153-7· Sparta, 77.
in Naupactus, 172. Chalcis, defeated by Athens 506 B.C., possible models for his laovofL{a, Critias, VOfLOS in, 51-2.
in Opus, I 72. 109, 135, 145-6. 161-6. Critius, see tyrannicides.
in Sparta, II2. Cheops, 73. use of lot, 154 n. 2. Croesus, relation to Delphi, 25.
Asychis, 47 n. 2. Chersonese, Thracian, 23. enfranchisement of aliens, 141 n. 2, hears of Spartan victory over Tegea,
Athenaeus, Attic skolia in, 96, 121, Miltiades despatched to, c. 516 B.C., 151-2. 76.
126-30. 138. vOfLo, in, 3, 158-60. Croton, Alcmaeon's relation to, 100.
Cyclopes, in Homer, lack O£!-"'i, 77. not likely in Samos in earlv sixth Diodotus, attitude to vO!-,os, 50. Eunomia, personifications of, 63, 64-7,
Cylonian conspiracy, 144, 174, 185. century, 165 n. 3. Diogenes, KpaUE< UV!-'!-'E'TPOSin doctrine 71, 72-3·
Cyprus, M'Tpa used for 'statute', 7. offered to Samians by Maeandrius, of, 104. sister of Dike, 63-4, 71, cf. 72.
Cyrene, reforms of Demonax as possible 108. Dionysia, reorganization of possibly sister of Eirene, 63-4, 7 I.
model for Cleisthenes, 163-5. established by Mardonius in Ionia celebrated in Attic skolion, 12g. sister of H6rai, 63-4.
4g2 B.C., 109, 110, 167, 17g. doxography, UV!-'!-'E'TPOSKpaa,s in, 103-4. sister of Moirai, 63-4.
Darius, 47 n. I, 109, 110, III, 145, desired by Miletus, 110-1 I. Drabeskos, battle of, 175. sister of Tycha, 64.
17g· in Plataea during Persian \Vars, I 17. Draco, issued first written legislation in daughter of Promatheia, 64.
Debate of Persian Conspirators in in Thebes before battle ofOenophyta, Athens, 60, 174. daughter of Themis and Zeus, 63,
Herodotus, 107, I I 1-13, 163-4, 117 n. 2. Ow!-'os as term for 'statute', 3, 4, 5, 67, 7 I.
166-7· praised by Athenagoras, 114. 51, 175· Euripides, first tragedian to speak of
source of, 166, I 78-9. supported by Athens during Pelo- vo!-'os used of his statutes by later written vo!-'o" 57.
decrees, see laws and decrees. ponnesian War, 113. authors, 5, 5 I, 173· takes background of written legisla-
Deioces, 73-5, 8g. Athenian, establishment in 507 B.C. legislation against tyranny revived tion for granted, 48.
Delium, battle of, 8g. celebrated in Harmodius skolia, 511/10 B.C., 4 with n. 2, 16, 59, avoj-Lfa in, 26, 90- I.
Delphi, uses alvos as legal term, 8. 126, 130, 133-6, 137, 153, 15g. 140. G.vo!-'os in, 87-8.
uses nOW)S as legal term, 16. establishment of brings change laws on homicide republished 409/8 avoJLw~ in, 8g.
Alcmaeonid influence in, 138. from Ow!-'os to vo!-'os, 55-.6, 158- B.C., 3, 5, 50-1,173· O£u!-'wv in, I 7.
Oracle, source of Lycurgus' reforms 60. drinking songs, see skolia. vo!-'os in, 22, 23, 24 n. 3, 25-6, 2g,
in Sparta, 77. credited with defeat of Boeotia and Dysnomie, personification of, 66-7. 32-3, 34, 36, 38, 39, 42, 47-8,
consulted by Spartans before at- Chalcis 506 B.C., 109, 135, 146, 52-3, 57·
tack on Tegea, 76. 15g· Eastern Locris, early fifth-century
consulted by Croesus, 25. rotation of office in, 106. O£O!-'wv, on colony at Naupactus, Five Thousand, government of, in
authority to dispense oracles called in [Xenophon], Constitution cif 16, 45, 170-3· Athens, 103 n. 3, 106, 180.
vO!-,os, 2g. Athens, 82-3. laws on inheritance and property, Funeral Oration, Pericles', in Thucy-
prods Sparta to liberate Athens democratic institutions, in sixth-century 170-1. dides, 58 with n. I, 114.
from tyranny, 130, 134, 138. Chios, 162. See also Naupactus.
Temple of Apollo, order of worship democratic sentiments, in late sixth- Egypt, vO!-,o' of, 35, 41, 43, 47, 53· Galen, UV!-,!-,ETpOS KpaU''i in, 104.
as vo!-'os 43. century Ionia, 109, 166-7, 173. £vvo/Lla in, 73. Gephyraei, genos of Harmodius and
destroyed 548/7 B.C., 138. Democritus, lived later than Alc- Eirene, sister of Eunomie, 63, 64, 7 I. Aristogeiton, 130- I.
operation of shrine guaranteed maeon of Croton, g8. in Solon, 67. Gerousia, 112.
423 B.C., 42. alleged author of Anonymus Iam- Eleusinian Mysteries, I n. 4. Gorgias, G.vo!-'os in, 88.
Demaratus, king of Sparta, defects at blichi, 92 n. I. Eleusis, occupied by Spartans 506 B.C., dvo!-,w'i in, 8g.
Eleusis, 46 n. 4, 146. 'well-proportioned mixture' in, 104. 145-6· vo!-'os in, 26, 5 I.
has vision before battle of Salamis, Ow!-'os in, 17. Empedocles, contemporary of late Gortyn, laws of, described as ypa!-'!-'aTa
128. vo!-'os in, 3g. years of Alcmaeon of Croton, or by ypaq,w-derivatives, 8.
attributes Spartan freedom to vO!-,os, Demonax of Mantinea, reformer at g8-g. Gytheion, vo!-'os in lex sacra of, 42 n. 2.
31, 32, 109. Cyrene, 163-5. vO!-'O'i in, 38-9.
deme, in Athens, membership as proof demos, in Athens, political role under UV!-,!-,E'Tpta Tfj'i KpauEws in doctrine of, Halai, festival of Artemis at, 42, 53.
of citizenship, 151-2. tyranny, 147-8, 156-7. 10 4. Halicarnassus, law of c. 460-55 B.C.,
self-government of, 152-3. political role after overthrow of enfranchisement, of aliens by Cleis- 44, 167-70, 172.
election of candidates for Council, tyranny, 142-5, 148-60. thenes, 141 n. 2, 151-2. uses uSos as legal term, 8, 167-8, 16g,
153· Demosthenes, general, 2 n. 3. act of 404/3 B.C., 51. '170.
Demeter and Kore, orgies in honour of, Demosthenes, orator, ElJVo!-,£o!-,a' in, ephebic oath, see oaths. uses vo!-'os = 'statute', 44, 167-70,
43· 84 n. 2. Ephialtes, enacted vO!-,o' at Athens, 5. 172•
invoked in Attic skolion, 128. Dicaeus, has VISiOn before battle of Epidaurus, uses alvos as legal term, 8. excluded from Dorian pentapolis, gl.
See also Ow!-,oq,opO'i. Salamis, 128. Erechtheids, vo!-'os of, 36. Harmodius, death of, 514 B.C., 122,
democracy, and Luovo!-,ta, g6, 97, 106, Dieitrephes, abolishes qemocracy in Erythrae, citizenship possibly defined 142 n. I.
107, 109-II, II 1-13, 113-14, 115, Thasos 41 I B.C., 176. by law, 46. and Aristogeiton, g6-7, 121-2, 124
120, 121, 130, 135-6, 137, 147. Dike, sister of Eunomie, 63, 64, 68, 7 I. medized under her tyrants, 16g n. 3. n. I, 130-1, 133-6, 148, 15g.
associated with £/o.wOEpta, 108. attendant of Eunomia and Themis, regulation of judicial procedures Harmodius skolia, Athenaeus as source
opposed to Suvaunta, I 16- I 7. 72• c. 450 B.C. contains vo!-'os and of, g6, 121, 123, 126-7.
opposed to monarchy, 112. in Solon, 67-8. .p~q,w!-,a, 45-6, 168 n. 2, 16g. date of, 97, 121-36, 185.
Harmodius skolia (cont.): laovo/1-La in, 107-13, 114, 116, 119-20 Ionia, democratic sentiments in late on allocation of funds to sanctuaries
form of, 123-5. 166-7· sixth century, 109, 166-7, 173. 418/17 B.C., 51.
first referred to in Aristophanes, 123- KaKoVO/1-0S in, 76-7, 78-9, 85. revolt of, 109- I I. revision of, under the Thirty, 5.
4, 126. vO/1-0S in, 23, 24, 25, 31, 33, 34 n. 4, !rasa, battle of, 163. of Teisamenus 403/2 B.C., I n. 2,
significance of myrtle bough in, 35, 39,41,46-7, 52, 53· Isagoras, may have stayed in Athens 3 n. 3, 5·
182-5· 7TArj(JOS in, I I 1-12, 114-15. during tyranny, 148. of 403/2 B.C., differentiating be·
as earliest testimony of laovo/1-La, 7TpOa€Ta,pL'O/1-a, in, 142-3, 157. opponent of Cleisthenes, 131, 133, tween vO/1-os and ifJ+pw/1-a, 1-3,
121-30, 161. Hesiod, influence on Solon, 65-7. 140, 142-5, 148. 5,7,57·
celebrate establishment of Athenian on Pindar, 71. archon 508/7 B.C., 142-3, 145, 148-9. of Corcyra on precinct of Zeus and
democracy in 507 B.C., 126, 130, on Bacchylides, 72. attempts to establish oligarchy at A1cinous, 49.
133-6, 137, 153, 159· aVO/1-0S in, 86. Athens, 144, 150, 155. of Corinth, 47.
laovo/1-os in, 96-7, 101, 107, 113, SlK7J in, 21. calls Cleomenes to aid against of Erythrae c. 450 B.C., 45-6, 168 n. 2,
121-36,161. c,vavo/1-La in, 65-7. Cleisthenes, 144, 145, 149, 150, 169.
Harpactides, archon 511/10 B.C., 139- Evvo/1-La in, 63-4, 65, 69-70. 160. of Gortyn, 8.
40• Vo/1-0S in, 2 I, 23-4, 40. Isocrates, laovo/1-La in, 18o-I. of Gytheion, 42 n. 2.
Hecale, 154. Hipparchus, murder of, 514 B.C., 122, Issedones, vO/1-0' of, 35. of Halicarnassus on real estate c.
Hecatompedon inscription, 2 n. 3. 125,134,138. Isthmian Games, as TE(J/1-oS of Poseidon, 460-55 B.C., 8, 44, 167-70, 172.
Hegesicles, see Leon and Hegesicles. Hippias of Elis, alleged author of 13· of Eastern Locris on inheritance and
Heliaia, Solonian, as possible model for Anonymus Iamblichi, 92 n. I. property, 170-1.
Chios, 162. use of vO/1-0S, 22, 51. Kedon, attempt against tyranny in on colony at Naupactus, 16, 45,
possibly attended by aliens under Hippias, tyrant of Athens, relations Atticskolion, 127, 129, 130, 134, 138, 170-3·
Peisistratus, 142. with Athenian nobility, 137-9, 148, 148. of Ozolian Locris on new lands and
Heracleia, uses p~Tpa for 'statute', 7. 165-6. on homicide, 16.
Heracles, establishes Olympic Games actions after Hipparchus' murder, Labyadai, phratry at Delphi, use of of Naupactus, 16,45, 170-3.
as T€(J/1-oS, 13. 125, 138, 140, 148. TE(J/1-oS by, 16. of Olympia on attack during Olym-
establishes Nemean Games as TfI· helped by Thessalian cavalry against laws and decrees, 48. pic truce, 49.
(J/1-LaV, 13 n. 4. Spartans, 129, 139. of Argos, on succession to priesthood of Sparta, 7, 46, 49.
Heraclitus, lived earlier than A1cmaeon fortifies Munichia, 139. of Hera, 49. of Syracuse, 49.
of Croton, 98. expelled from Athens 511/10 B.C., of Athens, define father's authority See also written legislation.
),oyos in, 27. 129,130,133,134,148. over daughters, 59. Leipsydrium, defeat commemorated in
Vo/1-0S in, 26-8, 30, 33, 120. See also Peisistratids. first issued in writing by Draco, 60, Attic skolion, 127, 129, 130, 134, 138,
Hermotimus, 53. Hippocratic writings, On Ancient Medi. 174· 148.
Herodotus, leaves Halicarnassus for cine later than A1cmaeon, 98. Draco's against tyranny, 4 with Leobotes, son of A1cmaeon, accuser of
Samos, 167. conjoin /1-ETPLaS and Kpiia's to express n. 2, 16, 59, 140. Themistocles, 144 n. I.
as interpreter of Pindar, 37-8. balanced mixture, 103. on homicide, 3, 5, 50-I, 173· Leogoras, great-grandfather of Andoci-
Debate of Persian Conspirators in, vO/1-osin,22,35,39. Solon's, 2, 46, 48, 59, 170. des, 138.
107, I I 1-13, 163-4, 166-7. Histiaeus, argues against revolt in left intact under the tyranny, 4, father of Andocides, 2 n. 3.
source of, 166, 178-9. 512 B.C., 109, 167. 15, 140, 147-8. Leon and Hegesicles, kings of Sparta,
account of Lycurgus' reforms at Homer, influence on Solon, 65. preserved by Cleisthenes, 158. fail at Tegea, 76.
Sparta, 75-9. attributes lack of (JE/1-'S to Cyclopes, prohibiting torture of Athenian Leucon, battle of, 163.
account of events in Athens 50817- 77- citizen, 140-1. Libyans, vO/1-0' of, 35 n. 3.
507/6 B.C., 143-6. EVVO/1-La in, 63, 64, .65, on Salamis, 2 n. 3. Linear B tablets, do not have (JW/1-oS,
fails to differentiate between written hoplite census, as requirement for on ostracism, 156, 159. or vO/1-0S, 10 n. 3.
and unwritten vO/1-0" 46-7. Theban citizenship, 118-19, 180. enacted by Ephialtes and Arches· Locris, use of TE(J/1-oS, 8, 16.
aVOfL€W in, 91. H6rai, 63-4, 67. tratus,5· See also Eastern Locris and Ozolian
aVO/1-La in, 73, 74, 8g-90. Hypoknemidian Locris, see Eastern Pericles' on citizenship, 46. Locris.
aV0/1-0S in, 88. Locris. on maintenance in Prytaneion, Lycurgus, reforms of, in Sparta, 75-82.
C,7JI-LaKpaTEO/1-a, in, 107 n. 4, 109 n. 3, Hysiae, captured by Boeotians 506 B.C., 48-9. enacts pfjTpa' in Sparta, 7 n. 2.
III. 145· treaty with Colophon 447/6 B.C., Lygdamis, tyrant of Halicarnassus,
c,7J/1-0KpaTLa in, 109 n. 4, I I I n. I, 120 41-2, 120 n. 2, 168 n. 2. 167-9.
n. I. Inheritance, laws concerning, in on colony at Brea c. 445 B.C., 170. Lysagoras, archon 509/8 B.C., 142.
"}VO/1-E0/1-a, in, 62, 73-4, 76. Athens, 59, 170. Megarian Decree, 48, 57.
"}VO/1-La in, 73, 76, 78. in Eastern Locris, 170- I. on coinage 422 B.C., 51.
Maeandrius (cont.): oath exacted in judicial proceedings, Ozolian Locris, uses T£TOP.OS for law on his exile demanded by Spartans,
Laovoll-in in Samos, 107-9, 110-11, 45, 171. homicide, 16. 144 n. 3.
164, 165-6. uses vall-La, vOJLOS, and 'Ta F€Fu81]ooru vop.os in his Funeral Oration, 49-50.
Magi, 47 n. I. as legal terms, 45, 170--3. Pagondas, speech before battle of no mention of laovofL{a in Funeral
Makrokephaloi, vop.os of, 35. Nemean Games, as dOP.LOV of Heracles, Delium,8g. Oration, 114.
Marathon, battle of, 128, 175. 13 n. 4. Pallene, battle of, 14I. Persephone, see Demeter and Kore.
vop.os gives polemarch command of N esiotes, see tyrannicides. divided among three demes in Persia, VOfLOLof, 35, 41, 47·
right wing, 46. Nicias, attitude to vop.os, 50. Cleisthenes' reforms, 154. Debate of Conspirators in, 107, 111-
vop.os prevents Spartans from partici- nobility, Athenian, alleged association Pan, establishment of cult in Athens in 13,163-4, 166-7, 178-9.
pating in, 41. with laovop.{a, 122-3. Attic skolion, 128. law of succession in, 24.
Mardonius, deposes tyrants and estab- under Peisistratus, 147. Panathenaic festival, reorganization Spartan relations with, 145 with
lishes democracies in Ionia 492 B.C., under Hippias, 137-9, 148. possibly commemorated in Attic n. I.
109, 110, 167, 179. after the fall of the tyranny, 140, skolion, 129. alliance requested by Athens 507 B.C.,
Massagetae, vop.o, of, 35. 142-3, 148, 156, 160. occasion of Hipparchus' murder 514 145·
Media, £I1vop.{a in, 73-5. Cleisthenes' attitude to, 152, 154, B.C., 125, 138, 184. Pherecydes of Syros, vOfLOS in, 40.
Megabyzus, III. 157,158. contest of men's choruses introduced Philippides, vision of Pan on his way to
Megacles, archon, 144. 509/8 B.C., 142. Sparta, 128.
father-in-law of Peisistratus, 24. oaths, at Athens, exacted from archons, Pandrosus, in Attic skolion, 128-9. Phoenicians, vop.os of, 36.
father of Cleisthenes, 41. 3-4· Parthenion mountains, scene of Philip- phratry, political role of, in Athens,
Megarian Decree, 48, 57. ephebes, 4, 14· pides' vision of Pan, 128. 141-2, 151-2.
Melian Dialogue, 23, 52. heliasts, 45 n. 4. Peisistratids, in Attic skolia, 129-3°. Phyle, epigram on the dead of, 4 n. 5,
MeJite, deme decree of, 4 n. 4. exacted by Athens from Colophon attitude to Solonian constitution, 140. 17·
Messenia, p~Tpa used for 'statute', 7. 447/6 B.C., 41-2. relations with Sparta, 138-9. Pindar, influenced by Hesiod, 71.
Spartan wars against, 77 n. I, 81-2. at Erythrae, 45. besieged on acropolis 511/10 B.C., £!JVop.{a in, 64, 71, 72, 73·
Miletus, granted laovop.{a by Arista- at Halicarnassus, 44, 167 n. 3, 171. 139, 144, 148. dlvOfLoS in, 61 n. 1,62, 70, 71-2.
goras, 109-11, 167. at Naupactus, 45, 17I. expelled from Athens 511/10 B.C., 4, vop.os in, 20, 24, 29, 30-1, 34, 37-8,
loyal to Aristagoras, I 10. Odrysians, vop.os of, 36. 130, 140, 148. 41.
oligarchical regime tolerated by Oinoe, captured by Boeotians 506 B.C., withdraw to Sigeum 511/10 B.C., 139. T£OfLoSin, 12, 13-14, 15, 174.
Athens 450/49 B.C., 169. 145· names proscribed on stele, 140. Plague, in Athens, influenced attitude
Miltiades, archon 524/3 B.C., 23, 137-8. oligarchical sympathies, in ETa'p£taL, See also Hippias. to vOfLoS, 50.
sent to Thracian Chersonese c. 516 142. Peisistratus, in Attic skolia, 129-3°. created avofL{a, 90.
B.C., 138. oligarchy, sortition and dJOuva in, 112. marries daughter of Megacles, 24. Plataea, has democratic constitution
sacrifices to Artemis after battle of not mentioned in Alemaeon, frg. 4, his rise to power, 140, 156-7. during Persian Wars, 117.
Marathon, 128. 101-2. bases his power on approval of argument against Thebes 427 B.C.,
mixture, see avp.p.£TpOS Kpaa's. relation to laovop.{a, 107, 113, 114, Assembly, 147, 156-7. 23, 32, 88, 116.
Moirai, sisters of Eunomie, 63-4, 67. 116-19. his geniality, 147. Plato, laovofL{a in, 181-2.
children of Night, 64. called lluvaaT£{a in Thucydides, 113. did not change OEafLLa of Athens, 4, laovofJ-tl<6s in, 182.
monarchy, opposed to democracy, Isagoras attempts establishment at 15, 147· laavoJLos in, IS!.
112. Athens, 144, 150, 155. develops Attic industry, 141. vOfLoS in, I n. 3, 23, 40.
Munichia, fortified by Hippias 511/10 at Miletus, tolerated by Athens may have granted citizenship to polemarch, commands right wing at
B.C., 139. 450/49 B.C., 169. aliens, 141-2. Marathon on basis of vOfLoS, 46.
Mycenae, Ta £lp"'lp.Eva used for 'statute', supported by Sparta during Pelo- relations with Athenian nobility, 147. offers sacrifice to Artemis on anni-
7· ponnesian War, 113. reorganizes Dionysiac and Pana- versary of Marathon, 128.
myrtle bough, significance of, in Har- Olympia, p~Tpa, TO yp6.q,OS, and thenaic festivals, 129. Polycrates of Samos, 107, 165.
modius skolia, 182-5. O£O<T )p.os as legal terms in, 7, 8, interest in Salamis and Troad, 129. Poseidon, establishes Isthmian Games
Mysacheis, in Naupactus, 170-1. 14· Peitho, sister of Eunomia in Aleman, as a 7£OfLoS, 13.
vop.os in, 49. 64· Probalinthus, 154.
Nasamones, vop.o, of, 35 n. 3. Olympic Games, 13, 69. Percothariae, in Naupactus, 170-I. Promatheia, mother of Eunomia in
naukraries, replaced by demes III Opus, 64 n. 1,71, 172. Pericles, defines VOfLOS as written Aleman, 64.
Cleisthenes'reforms, 152. Oracle, see Delphi. statute, 5 I. Protagoras, alleged source of Debate of
Naupactus, (UOp.,ov concerning settle- ostracism, purpose of law on, 156, 159. citizenship law in Athens, 46. Conspirators, 179.
ment of, 16,45, 170--3. Otanes, proposes democracy in Persia, Megarian Decree as written VOP.OL. alleged author of Anonymus Iam-
has assembly of all citizens, 172. 107, 111-12, 114, 163-4, 166-7, 179. 57· blichi, 92 n. I.
Prytaneion, law on public maintenance influenced by Homer, 65.
in, 48-9. includes thetes in Athenian Assem- relations with Persia, 145 with n. I. Theramenes, alleged author of Anony-
Pythagoreans, Alcmaeon of Croton bly,156. puts down tyrannies in Greece, 80. mus Iamblichi, 92 n. I.
alleged member of, 97-8. alleged originator of institution of relations with Peisistratids, 138-9. Therrikleion, phratry shrine, 4 n. 4,
Pytheas of Aegina, 72. funeral oration, 49 n. 2. prodded by Delphi to liberate 16.
Pythia, see Delphi. his constitution as possible model for Athens, 130, 134, 138. thesmothetai, in Athens, early functions
Chios, 162. invasion of Attica under Anchimolius, of, 174-5.
admits skilled craftsmen as citizens to 129,139. Thessaly, sends cavalry under Cineas to
Attica, 141 n. 5. liberates Athens from tyranny under help Hippias, 129, 139.
Salamis, Peisistratus' interest in, 129. weakness of his constitution, 151, 154. Cleomenes, 130, 134, 139, 148, Brasidas' march through, 424 B.C.,
Athenian decree on, 2 n. 3. constitution and laws left intact under 159· 113,115-16.
Salmacis, 167-8. tyranny, 4, 15, 140, 147-8. withdraws from Athens 506 B.C., sanctions ovvaaTEla rather than lao-
Samos, democracy not likely in early institutions and laws preserved by 135· vOfLla, I 13, I 15.
sixth century, 165 n. 3. Cleisthenes, 158-9. demands Pericles' expulsion, 144 n. 3. Thirty Tyrants, at Athens, revision of
attempt to establish laovofLla in, ovavofLla in, 65-9, 90. tends to support oligarchies during laws by, 5.
107-9,164. EvvofLla in, 64-9, 84. Peloponnesian War, 113. Thrace, vOfLO' of, 35 n. 3.
Sauromatians, vOfLo, of, 35 n. 3. laws of, called 8EafLol, 3-5. judges between Plataea and Thebes mercenaries of Peisistratus recruited
Scamandrius, archon 510/9 B.C., 141, called vOfLo, by later authors, 3, 5,60. 427 B.C., 23, 114, 116-19. from, 141.
142• enacted without ratification by armistice with Athens 423 B.C., 42. Thucydides, has no explicit reference to
Scythians, vOfLo, of, 35 nn. 3 and 6, 41. Council and Assembly, 2. Speusippus, accused rrapavofLWV by written legislation, 49.
called EvvofLo, by Aeschylus, 72. in Aristophanes, 48. Leogoras, 2 n. 3.
calls Thebes an oligarchy, 119.
Sigeum, 129, 139. . in Herodotus, 46, 60. Syracuse, oligarchs in, I 14, I 15.
public burial at Athens as rrD.TPtOs
Simonides, possibly author of Attic on inheritance, 59. VOfLoS bars young men from office,
vOfLos, 36, 175-6.
skolion, 127. Sophocles, ayparrTa vOfL'fLa in, 58. 49· praises government of Five Thou-
skolia, traditions concerning, 124. avofLoS in, 86-7.
sand as fLETpla gUyKpaatS, 103 n. 3,
Attic, in Athenaeus, 96, 121, 126-30. £vvofLLa in, 70- I. Tarentum, pTJTpa used for 'statute', 7. 106.
to Athene Tritogeneia, 128. 8WfLoS in, 17. Taurians, vOfLO' of, 35 n. 3, 43, 48. dvofLla in, go.
Demeter and Persephone invokedin, VOfLOS in, 22, 23, 24, 25, 29, 31, 32, Tegea, war with Sparta, 76. o.vofLOS in, 88.
128. 34 nn. 3 and 4,38,41,47,52,53. 8wfLoS used for 'statute', 8, 17.
avofLWs in, 89.
Pandrosus in, 128-9. sortition, 112. Teisamenus, decree of, 403/2 B.C., 1 3uvau'Tda in, I 13.
on Admetus, 129. Sparta, vOfLo, of, 35, 36, 46, 49, 60. n. 2, 3 n. 3, 5.
EvvofLEofLa, in, 79-80.
Ajax and Telamon in, 129. freedom of attributed to VOfLoS, 3 I, Telamon, in Attic skolion, 129.
luovop.€Oj.LUt in, 114 n. I.
Peisistratus and Peisistratids in, 10 9. Telesarchus, frustrates Maeandrius'
iaovoJ-L{a in, 113, 114, 115, 116, 120.
129-3°· prevented by vOfLoS from fighting at planned laovofLla, 165.
laovoJ.Los in, 113, 114, 116-19_
possibly commemorate reorgani~a- Marathon, 41. Tetrakomoi, 154.
VOfLoS in, 23, 31-2, 33, 34 n. 3, 36, 38,
tion of Dionysia and PanathenaIa, praised by Archidamus for adherence Thasos, uses UOOS as legal term, 168 n. I.
42,49-50,58,60,175-6.
129· to vOfLo" 32. revolt from Athens 411 B.C., 176-7. rr;>'~8osin, 115-16.
commemorateKedon,127, 129, 130, ';>7Tpa used for 'statute', 7. Thebes, constitution of, 118-19. Thyreae, 35.
134, 148. and EvvofLla, 75-82, 82 n. 3, 83, citizenship in, 118-19, 180.
tribes, in Athens, increased to ten by
commemorate battle of Leipsyd- 84 n. I. characterized by EvvofLla in Pindar,
Cleisthenes, 143, 150- I.
changed by Lycurgus, 77. 71-2.
rium, 127, 129, 130, 134, 148. vOfL'fLa Trichonians, I n. 4.
commemorate victory at Marathon, constitution as mixture of democracy justifies pro-Persian policy in 480/79
Tritogeneia, see Athene.
B.C., 32, 113, 115, 116-19.
128-9, 130. . and oligarchy, 117-18. . . Troad, Peisistratus' interest in, 129.
commemorate sacrifice to Artemis Gerousia and assembly decide poltcy, has democratic regime before Oeno-
Tycha, sister of Eunomia, 64.
vowed by Miltiades, 128. 112. phyta, 117 n. 2.
tyrannic ides, statue group by Antenor,
commemorate establishment of Pan use of Ev8vva in, I 12. argument against Plataeans 427 B.C.,
2 132-4, 142, 159, 184-5.
cult, 128. law regulating succession to army 23, 3 , 88, 113, 114, I 16-19.
by Critius and Nesiotes, 132,184.
commemorate victory at Salamis, command, 49 n. 3· ruled by o;>"yapxla laovofLos in 427
cult of, 131, 132.
law preventing Agis from command- B.C., 113, 114, 115, 116-19, 180.
128-9, 130. See also Harmodius and Aristogeiton.
See also Harmodius skolia. ing army unsupervised, 49 n. 3. Themis, mother ofEunomia, 63, 64,71.
attended by Dika, 72. tyranny, as caused by avofLla, 93-4.
slaves, in Cleisthenes' enfranchisement, during Messenian Wars, 81-2. opposed to VOfLos, 32, 47.
war with Tegea, 76. Themistocles, 131-2, 144 n. I.
151 with n. 2. opposed by iaovofLla, 97, 101, 107,
Solon, influenced by Hesiod, 65-7. war with Argos, 35. Theognis, vOfLOS in, 22, 30, 94.
109-11,113.
theokolos, official in Olympia, 14.
Spartan opposition to, 80.
tyranny (cont.): to be assumed as background of
in Samos, 107, 165. Sophocles, 17.
friendly to Persia in Erythrae, 169 of Euripides, 48.
n·3· of Aristophanes, 49.
initially no obstacle to acceptance not explicitly mentioned by Thucy-
into Delian League, 169. dides,49·
abolished in Ionia by Mardonius VOfJoOS in first explicit references to, 47,
492 B.C., 109, 110, 167, 179. 57,58.
in Athens, role of the demos under as VOfJoOS in Aristophanes, 48-9.
147~8, 156-7. VOfJoO, defined as, by Hippias and
opposition to, 122, 125-6, 127, 130, Pericles, 5 I .
134-5,138,139, 140, 165. praised by Gorgias, 51.
liberation from, 511110 B.C., 109, implied in VOfJoOS after 403/2 B.C., 57.
123,125,13°,131,133,134,135, See also V0fJo0"
139, 146, 150, 151.
Draco's law against, revived 5 I 1/10 Xenoerates of Acragas, 24.
B.C., 4 with n. 2, 16, 59, 140. Xenophanes, EVvofJo{a in, 69-70, 7 I.
Tyrtaeus, 81-2. [Xenophon], Constitution if Athens, date
of, 82.
attitude to Council and Assembly,
voting, procedure in fifth century, 2 82-4·
EVVO/L€O/LUL in, 82-5.
n·4·
EVvoll.la in, 62, 82-5, 95.
written legislation, interest in begin- KaKOVoJL{a in, 82-5, 95.
nings of, 60. Xenophon of Corinth, 12, 174.
begins in Athens with Draco, 60. Xerxes, 24, 132.
not necessarily implied in (lEap.!", 16-
17· Zenodotus, 2 I n. 2.
not necessarily implied in vOfJoOS in Zeus Eleutherios, 108.
fifth century, 43-50. Zeus Karios, 140.

You might also like