You are on page 1of 3

Why Modeling Cultural Evolution Is Still Such a

Challenge

Dan Sperber and Nicolas Claidière have been studied in depth by neuroscientists, psychologists,
Institut Jean-Nicod (CNRS, EHESS, ENS), Paris, France linguists, anthropologists, and sociologists. Drawing on their
Correspondence to: dan@sperber.com work, one can state with confidence that cultural propagation
differs from biological propagation in crucial respects.
The idea that cultural evolution exhibits variation, competi- Among the various mechanisms involved in biologi-
tion, and inheritance and therefore can be studied by adjusting cal heritability (cytoplasmic heritability, sex linkage dise-
the Darwinian theory of evolution by natural selection is an quilibrium, epigenetic transmission, niche construction, and
attractive one. It has been argued by a number of authors (e.g., so on), replication of DNA is the most important and
Campbell 1960; Monod 1970; Dawkins 1976; Cavalli-Sforza central one because it allows the faithful conservation of ge-
and Feldman 1981; Boyd and Richerson 1985; Durham 1991; netic information, and therefore the propagation of successful
Aunger 2002; Mesoudi et al. 2004) and pursued in a variety genotypes. Other mechanisms involved in biological inheri-
of ways, some (Dawkins and memeticists) staying close to tance play a role by contributing to this central phenomenon.
the Darwinian model, others (e.g., Boyd, Richerson, and their Cultural propagation, on the other hand, is achieved through
collaborators) being more innovative. We agree that there are many different and independent mechanisms, none of which is
relevant analogies between biological and cultural evolution central and none of which is a robust replication mechanism.
and, in particular, that cultural items do exhibit variation, com-
Limits of Imitation
petition, and cumulative modification. On the other hand, we
believe that a proper understanding of the mechanisms of cul- Imitation is often presented as the main mechanism of cultural
tural propagation drawing on the work of cognitive and social propagation, but, in fact, the notion is stretched to cover a wide
scientists (see Sperber and Hirschfeld 1999 for a review) con- variety of quite different processes. It might seem reasonable,
tradicts the idea that culture exhibits inheritance in the strict for instance, to suggest that both the sounds of words and their
sense needed for the theory of evolution by natural selection written shapes are culturally transmitted through imitation. In
to apply straightforwardly to it. If so, it will take more than fact, learning the sounds of words is a universal, automatic,
adjusting the Darwinian model to be faithful to the Darwinian highly canalized process taking place in early childhood and
inspiration. needing no explicit teaching. Learning the shapes of written
words, on the other hand, is specific to certain cultural groups,
Peculiarities of Cultural Propagation takes place in later childhood or in adulthood and involves
deliberate effort on the part of learners and teachers. Speech
Whereas the mechanisms of biological inheritance operate at a
sounds and writing are cultural items that involve different
molecular level, invisible to the naked eye, and their discovery,
cognitive and social mechanisms, and also different brain ar-
from Mendel to Crick and Watson and beyond, has taken the
eas (Mazoyer et al. 1993; Cohen and Dehaene 2004). As for
form of a series of major scientific advances, the mechanisms
the meaning of words, it cannot be perceived and therefore
of cultural inheritance are, to a significant extent, accessi-
cannot be imitated. Its cultural transmission involves yet other
ble to ordinary observation. Cultural propagation—learning,
cognitive and social mechanisms (Bloom 2000).
teaching, sharing of attitudes and values, and so on—takes
place through the ordinary channels of information trans-
The Argument from Macrostability
mission, and in particular through imitation and communi-
cation. Imitation, communication, and also memory (without Still, the diversity of mechanisms involved in cultural propa-
which cultural information would not survive to propagate) gation would not matter too much to the Darwinian program
July 23, 2005; accepted August 2, 2005
20 Biological Theory 1(1) 2006, 20–22. 
c 2006 Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research
Dan Sperber and Nicolas Claidière

if, on the whole, these mechanisms produced the kind of replications: it would become the model. If such copying errors
heritability that makes selection possible. Darwin had good were frequent, heritability might be too low—or, equivalently,
commonsense reasons to believe in the robustness of biolog- the mutation rate might be too high—for selection to be effec-
ical inheritance and this allowed him to develop his theory tive, or for anything to propagate at all. Given that the processes
without any knowledge of the mechanisms that secured in- involved in cultural propagation are partly constructive, fail-
heritance. Is not the reality of cultural inheritance as blatant ures to faithfully reproduce the inputs of these processes are
as that of biological inheritance? Is not the very existence of not, properly speaking, “copy errors.” Rather than resulting in
culture—that is, of relatively stable representations, practices, random drift, these constructive transformations may be bi-
and artifacts distributed across generations throughout a so- ased toward producing outcomes that are more suited to the
cial group—sufficient evidence of the heritability of cultural individual’s cognitive and practical abilities and goals.
items? If the microprocesses of cultural propagation failed to Here is how the partly constructive character of the pro-
exhibit sufficient fidelity, how could the relative stability evi- cesses involved in cultural propagation helps explain cultural
denced by the very existence of culture ever be arrived at? This stability (alongside other mechanisms such as the decision bi-
argument from observed macrostability to inferred microher- ases described by Richerson and Boyd 2005; see Sperber and
itability ignores the possibility that microheritability may not Claidière in press for discussion). Many constructive biases
be the only factor capable of securing macrostability. are shared in a population. This may be due to the fact that
The various mental and social microprocesses that to- they are based on the common psychological makeup of the
gether achieve cultural propagation combine preservative and species, or to more local historical or ecological factors. Shared
constructive functions in different degrees. (We talk of “preser- biases may not only statistically compensate the low fidelity of
vative” rather than “reproductive” or “replicative” function, preservative microprocesses; they may also permit some items
because, unlike genes, cultural material does not self- to reach a cultural level of distribution and stability.
reproduce; rather, it serves as input to intra- and interindividual Here is a simple example. The region of the continuum
processes that tend to preserve their informational content in of colors referred to by a given color term, say “red,” does not
their output.) If, instead of postulating that the preservative have clear boundaries, but it has, for every user, a focal point
function of memory, imitation, and communication must be which is seen as prototypical red. In learning the meaning
effective enough to explain cultural macrostability, one pays of “red,” a child is not taking the first sample he/she hears
attention to the vast psychological and sociological literature described as “red” as prototypical red, nor is he/she averaging
on these processes, then it becomes clear that high fidelity is over all the samples that he/she hears described as “red” in
the exception rather than the rule. his/her learning period. Rather, the child’s color perception
system provides him/her with a ready-made focal point for
red on the basis of which he/she interprets the word. The child
Constructive Propagation
may depart from the samples of “red” he/she is presented with,
Outputs of individual memory, imitation, and communication in the direction of what is a more salient identification, given
processes are, quite generally, not copies but transformations his/her perceptual dispositions. Because the color focal points
of the inputs. This is due in part to the imperfection of these for red and other basic colors are similar across individuals,
mechanisms: some information is just lost in the process of they stabilize rough common meanings for basic color terms in
transmission. It is also due to the very function of these mech- any given language, and terms with the same focal points
anisms, which is never purely preservative. Even when they across many languages, in spite of the fact that interlocutors
are faithful, the microprocesses of cultural propagation are in hardly ever mean exactly the same thing by “red” (Berlin and
good part constructive rather than replicative (Sperber 1996, Kay 1969; Kay et al. 1997).
2000). The preservation of information is a means toward the
end of providing individuals with information adapted to their
Cultural Causality Is Promiscuous
mental and motor schemas and to the pursuit of their goals.
The output of the mechanisms involved is only in part based on We can now spell out the most profound disanalogy between
the input information to be remembered or transmitted; it also biological and cultural evolution. Among the causal factors
draws on general and contextual information and is shaped by determining biological evolution, there is sharp distinction be-
the constructive functions of these mechanisms. tween, on the one hand, an extraordinarily robust mechanism
The fact that processes of cultural propagation are partly of inheritance—replication—without which there would be no
preservative and partly constructive affects the ways in which biological evolution at all, and, on the other hand, a variety of
cultural stability itself can be explained. If the processes in- environmental factors (physical factors, inter- and intraspecies
volved were just preservative, an occasional error of replica- factors, intergene factors, cytoplasmic environment, and so
tion (akin to a mutation) would be preserved in further errorless on) that affect evolution by determining the relative success

Biological Theory 1(1) 2006 21


Why Modeling Cultural Evolution Is Still Such a Challenge

of different genes. The factors determining cultural evolution reproductive mechanisms and environmental factors. Cultural
cannot be similarly divided into replication mechanisms and causality is promiscuous and that is why modeling it is still
environmental factors. While some mechanisms (of memory, such a challenge.
imitation, and communication) have a primarily preservative
function, they themselves involve constructive processes draw-
ing extensively on contextual information delivered by other References
mechanisms (for instance mental mechanisms of perception, Aunger R (2002) The Electric Meme: A New Theory of How We Think. New
inference, or action planning, and social processes of seduc- York: Free Press.
tion, coercion, deception, bargaining, coalition formation, and Berlin B, Kay P (1969) Basic Color Terms: Their Universality and Evolution.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
so on), the primary function of which is not preservative.
Bloom P (2000) How Children Learn the Meanings of Words. Cambridge,
Constructive processes systematically intrude on preservative MA: MIT Press.
processes. Cultural contents are not replicated by one set of Boyd R, Richerson PJ (1985) Culture and the Evolutionary Process. Chicago:
inheritance mechanisms and selected by another, disjoint set University of Chicago Press.
of environmental factors—not by a long shot. Campbell DT (1960) Blind variation and selective retention in creative thought
as in other knowledge processes. Psychological Review 67: 380–400.
We are well aware of the fact that biological transmis-
Cavalli-Sforza LL, Feldman MW (1981) Cultural Transmission and Evolution.
sion is much more complex than a few sentences can indicate, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
and that it involves a variety of submechanisms that may have Cohen L, Dehaene S (2004) Specialization within the ventral stream: The case
analogues in cultural evolution. To give just one illustration, for the visual word form area. NeuroImage 22: 466–476.
consider an orally transmitted folktale. The public telling of Dawkins R (1976) The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
the tale contributes to the formation in the listeners of mental Durham W (1991) Coevolution: Genes, Culture, and Human Diversity. Stan-
ford: Stanford University Press.
representations of the tale, and these mental representations
Kay P, Berlin B, Maffi L, Merrifield W (1997) Color naming across languages.
contribute to the production of further public telling by lis- In: Color Categories in Thought and Language (Hardin CL, Maffi L, eds),
teners turned tellers. The causal chain involves an alternation 21–58. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
of mental and public events with equally potent causal roles. Mazoyer BM, Tzourio N, Frak V, Syrota A, Murayama N, Levrier O, Salamon
The case of RNA retroviruses that propagate through reverse G, Dehaene S, Cohen L, Mehler J (1993) The cortical representation of
speech. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 5: 467–479.
transcription into DNA might be seen as a biological analogue.
Mesoudi A, Whiten A, Laland K (2004) Is human cultural evolution Dar-
But how helpful would such an analogy be? winian? Evidence reviewed from the perspective of The origin of species.
Merely adjusting the general model of Darwinian selec- Evolution 58: 1–11.
tion to describe cultural evolution involves idealizing away Monod J (1970) Le hasard et la nécessité. Paris: Seuil.
properties crucial to the proper explanation of the phenomena. Richerson PJ, Boyd R (2005) Not by Genes Alone. Chicago: University of
Looking to biology for fine-grained analogies between biolog- Chicago Press.
Sperber D (1996) Explaining Culture: A Naturalistic Approach. Oxford:
ical and cultural evolution may be a source of insights but it
Blackwell.
should not take precedence over looking to the cognitive and Sperber D (2000) An objection to the memetic approach to culture. In: Dar-
social sciences for a better understanding of the actual mech- winizing Culture (Aunger R, ed), 163–174. Oxford: Oxford University
anisms and processes involved. We agree with Richerson and Press.
Boyd (2005) that Darwin-inspired population thinking pro- Sperber D, Claidière N. (in press) Defining and explaining culture (comments
on Richerson and Boyd, Not by genes alone). Biology and Philosophy.
vides the proper approach to the scientific study of cultural
Sperber D, Hirschfeld L (1999) Evolution, cognition and culture. In: MIT
evolution. However, it has yet to be generalized to cases where Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences (Keil F, Wilson R, eds), cxi–
the causal forces involved cannot be neatly separated into cxxxii. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

22 Biological Theory 1(1) 2006

You might also like