You are on page 1of 13

Geoforum, Vol. 16 No. 2, pp. 191~203.1985. 001&7185!85 s3.w + 0.

00
Printed in Great Britain. Pergamon Press Ltd.

Geography and General System Theory,


Philosophical Homologies and Current
Practice

MARTIN J. HAIGH,* Oxford, U.K.

Abstract: General system science, like geography, is an integrative discipline that


spans the divide between the physical and social sciences. Geography, like general
system science, seeks to examine the universe of observation as a functioning whole
and attempts to study together the things other disciplines study separately.
However, within both geography and the system sciences at large, there are many
different philosophies and methodologies. A special attribute of the general system
approach is an explicit adoption of an organismic rather than a mechanistic world
view. This has caused general system practitioners to develop theory in more
bioscienti~c areas of concern such as growth, hierarchical organisation and the
theory of evolution. To date, much of the systems science in geography has
preferredthe static, mechanistic ethos of systems analysis and systems engineering.
However, general system science’s concern with historic processes and the dynamic
self-determined relationships between systems structure, functioning and self-
creation may be more appropriate to geographical research. A search is made for
general system methodologies in current geographical research and for particular
applications of aspects of the new general systems theory of evolution and theory of
systems attractors as defined by Ilya Prigogine and Erich Jantsch to geography.

Today, we seem to be at the tip of an iceberg of scientific change . . Every


discipline is in the midst of a revolution . . . What is exciting about this theoretical
chaos is not that each discipline will emerge with a new paradigm to guide future
investigations but that a new grand paradigm may be forming, one that will
integrate all structure and processes from the farthest reaches of the Universe to
the reasonances of subatomic particles. The Grand Paradigm is somewhere in the
future and we may live to see it THEISEN, (1981, p. 758).

Introduction aware, fragmentation of knowledge limits our


understanding of the ‘harmonious unity of the
Two centuries ago the whole of science could be cosmos’. In Russia during the 187Os, Dokuchayev
invested in a single individual, a ‘natural philo- battled against further fragmentation, arguing that
sopher’, who could take a holistic view. The although the science of the nineteenth century had
proliferation of knowledge and the development of achieved success in the study of individual objects
distinct academic disciplines and subdisciplines have and phenomena, it had, as a result, lost view of the
fragmented science into hundreds of tiny indepen- interrelationships of nature, the study of which was
dent subjects, each working in isolation, Given the “the best and highest beauty of natural science”
fact that the world’s scientific literature is increasing (ISACHENKO, 1973, p. 25). Dokuchayev’s legacy
at an inexorable 11.13% per year, specialisation has includes much of modern Soviet thinking in ecology
become inevitable. But as the early philosophers of and the distinctive Russian School of landscape
geography, such as HUMBOLDT (1845), were well science, but his work did little to staunch the
general trend of scientific fragmentation.

*Oxford Polytechnic, Oxford, U.K. To BERTALANFFY (1950, 1969, 1975), founder

191
192 Geoforu~Volume 16 Number 211985

of the general system movement, the history of hierarchy of higher and lower order centres with
twentieth-century science remains a history of their hinterlands, so the fluvial landscape can be
specialisation, the achievements of which reflect a examined as a spatially nested hierarchy of drainage
philosophy of dissection as the route to progress. systems. Throughout each level of each of these
Reductionism, the belief that the whole can be hierarchies the small market centre, the mid-order
explained through the examination of its compo- drainage basin, exists as a functioning whole with
nents, has been the cutting edge of twentieth- respect to its parts and as a part within a greater
century science. However, BERTALANFFY whole.
(1950) believed it was possible to detect a counter-
current of thought, based on arguments which
suggest that the whole is more than just an Systems and System Science
aggregation of parts. Engels gave early expression
to such ideas in his dialectics of nature, where he A system, then, is a wholeness that is created by the
calls the whole of nature an: “interconnected integration of its component parts. It is an entity
totality including all material from stars to atoms” containing a structured set of components whose
(Engels in GVISHIANI, 1984, p. 5). Like Engels, structural and functional inter-relationships create
system scientists believe that the greater wholeness an entireness which was not implied by those
of the universe is composed of a hierarchically components in disaggregation. A system is a
ranked sequence of lower order wholes (cf. functioning organ within reality, conceived at a
LASZLO, 1983). KOESTLER (1967) sees the convenient scale and level of organisation. It is also
universe of observation as a ‘holarchy’, incorporat- a very personal construct. Systems have no absolute
ing layers of discrete entities which he names existence. They are abstractions from reality con-
‘holons’. Each ‘holon’ is a functioning wholeness ceived by the observer for the purposes of con-
that emerges from the structure and interaction of ceptualisation or investigation and at a level of
its constituent parts, which is in turn integrated complexity which permits study as a whole.
within a larger order whole. MILLER (1978) has
illustrated the nature of the ‘holarchy’ within living System science is the study of complexity and
systems, while the geographers CHORLEY and integration. Its prime focus of attention is not the
KENNEDY (1971, p. 252) have provided another object components contained by a system but the
example from the drainage system (Figure 1). inter-relationships between those components. Its
Hillslope systems are components of river valleys function is to search for laws which govern those
which are included within drainage basins which, in inter-relationships between components and which
turn, are included in higher order drainage basins. affect the way those components become integrated
In the same way that the urban-economic ge- and disaggregated as different system holons. In
ography of an area can be examined as a nested sum, systems science is about the patterns of
interaction and integration within and between
systems and the ways in which systems evolve and
decay.
High order
rover basin
system
General System Laws

BERTALANFFY (1950, pp. 138-139) postulated


that it should be possible to discover laws that
govern particular types of interaction. Such laws,
often already existing in the isolation of the
individual disciplines, would be common to many of
Riti the object topics presently studied separately by
( system
these different sciences. The recognition of such
mathematically equivalent, structurally similar and
functionally identical ‘isomorphic’ laws, he argued,
Figure 1. Relationship between evolution and hierarch-
ical structures in the drainage basin. All systems be, might prove an efficient route towards the creation
behave and so become (from CHORLEY and KEN- of a new metatheory of science, transcending the
NEDY, 1971). traditional object-oriented sciences and which could
GeoforumiVolume 16 Number 211985 193

deal with the blindspots of reductionist research. meet” (Thomas Arnold of Rugby, 1842 in FREE-
The newly identified general system laws would be MAN, 1961, p. 81).
principles that governed patterns of inter-relation,
integration and organisation. This new basic scien- Since geography cuts a section through all of the
tific superstructure would stretch across the current systematic sciences, there is an intimate and mutual
relation between it and each of those fields . . [so]
spectrum of knowledge and its laws would subsume . . . geography must integrate the material that other
much that has already been developed in the sciences study separately
myopic, object-specific subdisciplines of modern
science. BERTALANFFY (1950, p. 138) con- (HARTSHORNE, 1939, p. 460). WOOLDRIDGE
cludes: “There exist therefore General System Laws and EAST (1951) carry this argument several steps
which apply to any system of a certain type further:
irrespective of the particular properties of that
system or the entities involved.” For example, the The present need for integration in the divergent and
logistic law proposed by Verhulst in 1789 to multiplying fields of human knowledge is urgently
describe population growth becomes, in physical acclaimed. Geography offers such an integration over
part of the field and the character of its spirit and
chemistry, the equation of autocatalytic reaction, manner must be judged in the light of this fact . _ . The
while in geography the same equation is used to geographer’s real claim is . . . that he is attempting to
model the spread of a disease or the diffusion of an see things together.
innovation. The law of logistic growth states that
growth which has the capacity to become exponen- ANUCHIN (1977, p. 17) completes the argument:
tial is eventually inhibited by some kind of limiting
condition. The result, expressed graphically, is an Geography . . . is an integrated science, a system of
‘S-shaped, sigmoid curve. sciences, and the amalgamation of all the geographic
sciences into one common system is substantive and
not nominal in character. It is based on the unity of the
LASZLO (1983, p. 5) has summarised the main object of study (the earth’s landscape/envelope) and
aims of the general system movement. Its ambition the definitely common methodoIogy (the geographica
is to develop unifying laws and principles running method) . . . thus the geographic environment, in-
‘vertically’ through the universe of the individual cluding not only pure nature, but also man with the
results of his activity, is a complex of elements with
sciences. These laws and principles would be part of different qualities. It is the interaction of these
a unified metatheory (SADOVSKY, 1984, pp. elements . . . that cause the formation and further
22-27), which would Iead to a much needed development of the geographic environment,
integration in scientific education and would pro-
vide an important vehicle for the generation of
exact theory in the non-physical fields of science. Philosophies of Systems Geography
This would be accomplished, initially, by the
transference of scientific laws and theoretical struc- Geography retains the tradition that it is a unified
tures from the exact sciences. The ultimate goal discipline in spirit, if less often in practice, and this
would be the synthesis of a unified science in- contrasts sharply with the current condition of
corporating many fields of study presently con- systems science. In truth, there is no such thing as
sidered to be beyond the scope of ‘science’. systems science; instead, there is a whole family of
overlapping system sciences (LILENFIELD, 1978;
CHECKLAND, 1978). These include: general sys-
Philosophical Convergences between tem theory, ecological systems theory, systems
Geography and General System Theory engineering, operations research, information sys-
tems science, and many others. Each retains in its
Geographers have frequently expressed concern philosophical and methodological traditions, ves-
that a liberal education should not degenerate into tiges of its original ambitions and disciplinary
the presentation of disparate sets of information origins: biology, electronics, business and manage-
and have called “for a simpler and more unified ment, or whatever. Each borrows freely, if often
approach to scientific problems” (BODE ef al., erratically from the theory of its neighbours. All
1949). Further, geography, like general systems display distressing tendencies to schismogenesis,
theory, aspires towards the synthesis of diverse and to develop small schools which cling to the
disciplines and claims to be “that part of knowledge philosophies of a particular charismatic leader
where students of the physical and moral sciences (JACKSON et al., 1982).
194 Geoforum/Volume 16 Number 20985

Geographers have played a very minor role in the Increasmgpersonalcontrol over world
overall development of systems science. Systems
thinking in geography tends to be both derivative
and heterodox but, like much of systems science, it
is a loosely integrated assemblage of ideas borrowed
I “. Dogmotlsm

from some or all of the different systems traditions


and is clumped around the writings of a small
number of philosopher-leaders. Several different
traditions can be detected (cf KRCHO, 1978;
STRAHLER, 1980; COFFEY, 1981; TIVY and
O’HARE, 1981; WILSON, 1981; MAZUR, 1983).
REDDY and UTTARA PRABHU (1983, p. 54)
rightly describe the present situation as ‘confused’. Contextua!sm
However, they may be wrong to suggest that most
problems are due to semantics, even though systems
terminology has grown rather battered through use
and abuse in its several disciplinary homes (WIL-
BANKS and SYMANSKI, 1968). In geography, as Figure 2. Pepper’s world hypotheses as an evolutionary
elsewhere in the systems movement, the processes hysteresis.
of disciplinary convergence continue, and the frag-
ments may now be approaching a new threshold of
unification. From the many traditions, two distinct dogmatism, formism, mechanism and contextualism
new syntheses are emerging: on the one hand, there to organicism.
are the systems analysts who adhere to a
mechanistic/contextualist approach; and on the Although mysticism, dogmatism and formism have
other, there are those who hold to an organicist a role to play in geography and systems science, it is
world hypothesis. the last three world hypotheses that are really
important.
The notion of world hypotheses is developed from
Stephen Pepper, who writes The world hypothesis of the mechanist has its roots
in the conceptual framework of Newton, Victorian
A man desiring to understand the world, looks about Science and Stalinist Marxism. The world is
for a clue to its comprehension. He pitches upon some
area of common sense . . . this area becomes, then, regarded as a machine whose operations can be
his basic analogy or root metaphor. He describes, as precisely determined by physical and mathematical
best he can, the characteristics of this area . A list laws. Such a view still underpins much modern
of its structural characteristics become his basic con- technology and it leads to the notion that human
cepts of explanation and description” (PEPPER, 1942, beings can, by gaining a thorough understanding of
p. 91).
the physical laws, take over the control mechanisms
Pepper calls these, essentially metaphysical, view- and impose a new order on the world machine.
points ‘world hypotheses’ (Figure 2). He recognises However, by the mid-twentieth century strict
six, all of which are drawn from some form of mechanistic explanations were giving way to contex-
common sense, or self-evident truth, and all extend tualism. Scientists came to view the world as a
through experience by some form of initially complex of change and stability, order and disorder;
analogical thinking to provide a method for examin- too grand for its operations to be predicted and
ing reality and/or other types of experience. These controlled precisely. Nevertheless, within this
hypotheses can be mapped along two conceptual complexity they found discernible structures, con-
axes. The first axis concerns the degree to which the textual organising principles, which could be used to
hypothesis is founded in self-evidence rather than guide human attempts to manage the world system.
external evidence. The second records the level of
personal control of the world which the hypothesis Organicism, which BECK (1952) calls the oldest
permits. Who is in command of the world, the alternative to mechanism, draws a clear distinction
observer or something higher? Pepper’s six world between organisms and machines. The essence of
hypotheses are mapped on these axes as an evolu- this distinction lies in ALEXANDER’s (1939)
tionary sequence running from mysticism, through concept of emergent quality, defined as a quality
GeoforumiVolume 16 Number 211985 195

belonging to the whole which could not have been preface the course by a gloss on ‘the world’s natural
predicted from its separate parts. Thus the organis- systems’. So
tic world hypothesis contains the expectation that
the complexity of reality can contain components, the natural environment can be divided into five easily
which have the capacity to become organized into recognisable subsystems . . and organised accord-
ingly. The first three subsystems, weather-climate,
entities with new properties. Alone among the water and landforms comprise the abiotic physical
systems sciences, general system theory is explicitly environment. They provide the setting, the physical
organicist. To understand the theory and its support, and sustenance for the two remaining subsys-
method, one must accept a universe based on an tems: soils and biota (RUSSWURM, 1974, p. 2).
hypothesis which is inherently more mystical and
inherently less certain about the ‘controlling of Once these points are established, the author can
nature’ than either systems science at large or the retreat into the examination of topics from the
Victorian sciences which preceded it. separate physical disciplines in their traditional
isolation (HIDORE, 1974; STRAHLER, 1980;
Although systems thinking in geography does dis- DURY, 1981; NEWSON and HANWELL, 1982).
play signs of the same division between the The status quo in research and practice is
mechanist/contextualist and organicist world views, unaffected.
the former has dominated the subject. Five differ-
ent traditions of systems thinking can be identified The second school of systems thinking in geography
within geography (Figure 3). is far more important. This is a major influence both
in physical and in human geography. For a time
The first (and most primitive) is explicitly reduc- during the 1970s it looked as if it might become the
tionist. The root problem of physical geography is dominant geographical paradigm. The fact that it
that it has long since divided into its component has not (yet) succeeded is due to its attachment to
specialisms: geomorphology, climatology, bioge- the sterile mechanist/contextualist root metaphor
ography and so on. However, most academic units and to a technical sophistication which remains far
still recognise and teach physical geography as an beyond the grasp of most geographers. It is the
integrated study, at least at an introductory level. geographical answer to systems engineering and
Teaching physical geography as it really is, a cybernetics. It includes the methodology known as
collection of discrete, subdisciplinary packages, is spatial analysis, which is essentially concerned with
not a comfortable experience, since those packages computer simulation and the mechanistic modelling
are very obviously related. One solution is to of contextual structures. The systems theoretic
aspects of the kind of study have evolved from
origins in physical geography (CHORLEY, 1962;
Mechanism w ~Cantextualism I Organlcism CHORLEY and KENNEDY, 1971) to broader
$1 ‘I
Tradlttanal Tradltlanal aspects of geography (HUGGETT, 1980; WILSON
geography regianai 1981). However, the movement has its detractors
physlcal- human geography who protest that, in their search for abstract
II mathematical purity, these systems writers have lost
Physlcai
touch with reality and/or humanity (LA PATRA,
geagraphlc
systems II 1973; LANGTON, 1980).
II
Spatial
( reglanal I
Ecalaglcal
madelllng II
II
Ecological systems thinking is a third distinct theme
analysis in geography. Biogeography, one of the smaller
II schisms of physical geography, is very heavily
and Landscape
suence dominated by the philosophies and methods of its
Geagraphlc II larger neighbour: ecology. Here there exists a
systems II
11
curious contextualist approach to the study of
analysts
II organic systems which is based on energy account-
II
ing. This means the charting of the movement of
‘I
11 General systems energy through a system often using the techniques
11approach
of systems engineering (SCHUGART and
Figure 3. Conceptual map of systems thinking in O’NEILL, 1979). Once again, the essence of
geography. systems ecology may be gleaned from its definition
196 GeoforumNolume 16 Number 2/1985

of the term system. WATTS (1966, p. 2) writes: “a phenomena. Two widely discussed exampes include
system is an interlocking complex of processes applications of the biological law of proportional
characterised by many reciprocal cause effect path- growth (allometry) to discussions of landscape
ways” which should be examined by computer evolution (BULL, 1975; TOKUNAGA, 1978;
simulation and model building (JEFFERS, 1978; OLYPHANT, 1981) as well as to aspects of urban
TIVY and O’HARE, 1981). regional science (COFFEY, 1979) and applications
of queue theory in geomorphology (THORNES,
Fourthly, we may identify landscape science as a 1971; DAUKSA and KORTARBA, 1973). In sum,
systematic theme. ISACHENKO (1973, p. 28) the general system theorist geographer seeks to
writes “To a Dokuchayevian geographer it neces- treat all systems as if they were organisms while
arily became obvious that the surface of the earth mechanist/contextualist geographers follow ZIPF
consists of objectively existing territorial units, each (1949) in seeking to examine organic systems
of which constitutes a regular and specific combi- (including human behaviour) as if they were phys-
nation of the objects and phenomena of nature”. ical phenomena.
Similar ideas were expressed by HERBERTSON
(1905) and more recently in the writings of Western
terrain analysts (CHRISTIAN, 1958; BECKET and Organisational Invariances of Systems
WEBSTER, 1965; MITCHELL, 1973). However,
the main development of landscape science has The philosopher LASZLO (1972) has attempted to
followed the work of BERG (1913) on geographical define the general system concept of a system and to
zones, and is presently invested in the larger scale elaborate the implications of the organicist concep-
notion of the region-sized geocomplex, and geosys- tion. He expresses his ideas as a series of four
tern. General system theory became a potent force ‘organisational invariances’, each specifying key
in the U.S.S.R. in the 1970s (GVISHIANI, 1984) characteristics of natural systems. As with all
and by the mid 1970s was strongly influencing the systems properties, these ‘invariances’ are inter-
writings of Soviet landscape scientists (GERASI- related.
MOV et al., 1978). Most recently the discipline has
reappeared in the international arena through the (1) Structured wholeness. First, systems are wholes;
activities of the International Geographical Union’s functioning entities rather like organisms, with
Working Group on Landscape Synthesis (MAZUR, properties that are irreducible by dissection. These
1983). These writings make it clear that the thinking irreducible properties are those which result from,
of landscape scientists straddles the divide between or emerge through, the integration of system
the contextualist stance of Western ecology and a components. All systems, by definition, are formal
truly organicist general system world view (cf. structures, not random agglomerations of elements.
ZONNEVELD, 1983; PREOBRAZHENSKIY, It is this structure which is most easily lost in
1983). Preobrazhenskiy describes the geosystem as dissection and which has led some to assert incor-
hierarchically structured, as possessing the emer- rectly that the concepts of ‘the whole’ and the
gent property of environmental quality, but remains concept of ‘the system’ are identical. BLAUBERG
enigmatically ambiguous on the topic of the ‘co- (1984, p. 53) describes the relationship as a ‘pro-
creation’ of man and nature. found kinship’. However, systems study, unlike a
conventional (reductionist) analysis, implies motion
Finally, we note the general system tradition, not from the parts to the whole, but from the whole
although it must be admitted that explicit state- to the parts (Figure 4). In the systems approach, the
ments of organicism are rare even in the writings of ‘whole object’ is the ultimate unit of interpretation,
geography’s mainstream general system theorists. and it is a functioning entity with emergent pro-
At present the major diagnostic characteristics of perties. These emergent properties must themselves
these writers is their explicit adoption of a Bertan- be resultant parts of a wholeness which lies beyond
lanffian strategy for the promotion of scientific present knowledge, but the system exists only to
unification. Their work seeks out logical homolo- represent present, perceived knowledge as an integ-
gies between geographic system processes and ral whole object. GVISHIANI (1984, p. 12) empha-
members of the corpus of established general sises that the recognition of the organic unity
system laws (NORDBECK, 1965). Frequently, between the formalised and non-formalised - the
these laws are explicitly organicist in conception, known and yet-to-be-known - is a major principle
and often they are applied to explicitly inorganic of system conceptualisation.
Geofomm/Volume 16 Number 2/1985 197

(2) ~~e~~~~. Second, systems have an identity which challenge of the environment; they have the capac-
they will tend to maintain in a changing environ- ity to evolve new structures and new functions. In
ment. This identity is contained by the equilibrium open systems which exchange mass-energy with
state: past, present, future and final, to which the their environment, the self-creation process can be
system adheres. In simple systems and some com- profoundly affected by the operations of other
plex systems, this state may represent the condition systems in the system environment, and by chance,
which offers least resistance to the throughput of accidents of innovation and mutation, or indeed by
energy. In more complex systems this equilibrium anything which can disturb the energy stream and
identity may be preserved by internal system force the system to adapt.
structures (homeostatic regulators, negative feed-
back loops and energy stores). In some complex (4) Hierarchical structure. Systems can be identified
systems the machinery of self-regulation may at all scales of magnitude such that each system
become so sophisticated that the system becomes contains subsystems components which may be
able to separate its identity from the environment. examined as systems in their own right. Similarly
As such, it develops self-referential qualities which each natural system is itself the component of a
are independent of the original energetic state. This larger scale system in which it plays the role of
condition is a feature of many organisms, more subsystem. LASZLO f1972, p. 67) notes that the
social systems and all ecosystems, but it is limited to organisation of the natural world resembles a
systems existing in an environent which can supply complex multi-level pyramid with many relatively
them with more energy than their present functions simple systems at the bottom and ‘ultimately one’
and structures require. compiex system at the top (Figure 4). Indeed,
PATTEE (1973, p. 73) writes “hierarchical organis-
(3) Self-creation. LASZLO (3972, p. 46) stresses ation is so universal that we usually pass it off as the
seif-creativity as the third of his list of fundamental natural way . . .” The reason it is natural is easily
system characteristics. IIis third ‘invariance’ is that conceived. Consider what woufd be the result of a
natural systems create themselves in response to the reduction of energy and an increase in disorganis-

H Mocroh!erarchy
h’ Microhrerarchy Iterrestnal i
h” Muohierarchles (the UDPW
leveis ore,of course, purely
hypothetml i

Fundamentai energy
condensations Lquorksl

Figure 4. Hierarchical universe (LASZLO, 1983).


198 Geoforu~Volume 16 Number 211985

ation (entropy) upon two complex systems, one senility, as the energy of uplift is consumed
hierarchically structured, the other not. Increased (WIDACKI 1979). The long profile of the ideal
disorganisation could only have one impact on the ‘graded stream’ can be modelled as a negative
non-hierarchical system; it would completely disin- exponential curve and as a physical manifestation of
tegrate. The hierarchical system, however, would thermodynamic decay (LEOPOLD and LANG-
include subsystems and components. An increase in BEIN, 1962). In his presidential address to the
disorganisation might disrupt the system as a whole, Society for General Systems Research, MILSUM
but it might not result in complete disaggregation. (1967) comments that ‘this washing away of the land
Instead, there would be a tendency for the system to into the oceans is, of course, in accord with the
be reduced to a collection of subsystem compo- second law of thermodynamics, namely that closed
nents. Some of these subsystem components might systems tend towards a state of uniformly low
have the capacity to continue to function as systems order.”
in their own right. If subsequently, energy and
organisation (negentropy) were reinvested in the Open systems are those which import as well as
system, the subsystem building blocks of a more export energy and mass. Open systems exhibit one
organised {lower entropy) structure would already of two different relationships to the stream of mass
exist. Re-organisation could proceed more rapidly. and energy in which they exist. Either they achieve
Hierarchical organisation, then,‘ is the natural way an equilibrium state by balancing inputs and outputs
to achieve efficiency and stability in a large collec- passively, or they store some of the energy received,
tion of interacting elements. in which case they may evolve. Simple open
systems, like the river channel cross-section system
beloved of geomorphologists (LEOPOLD and
Energy and Systems Behaviour MADDOCK, 1953; SCHUMM, 1977), do not have
any capacity for the storage of energy or for the
The essential control over the behaviour of a system regulation of energy inputs by feedback mechan-
is the energy budget. A system can exist in one of isms. Their response to being buffeted by the
three instantaneous states with regard to its through~ow of energy is simply to develop a
throughput of energy: it loses energy, gains energy configuration which offers least resistance to the
or precisely balances the input and output of energy stream, and which allows the most efficient
energy. throughput of energy. In a steady energy stream this
form will be a kind of steady-state equilibrium
A closed system is one whose boundaries are closed condition. In a fluctuating energy stream it may be a
to the import of mass and energy (BERTA- statistical steady state. In a pulsating energy stream
LANFFY, 1969). A closed system, by definition, it may be a stable oscillation like the seasonal and
has a fixed supply of energy which diminishes as it is diurnal patterns of earth surface temperature.
consumed by systems operation. As a closed system
operates, internal energy differences, the forces Organic systems are part of the larger closed system
which power the system, decline. The system’s of the Earth and Sun. For them there is no obvious
operation slows down and parts of the system break limit to the progression of organisation. Organismic
down or cease to function. In many cases the systems evolve by the storage of energy as
pattern of energy consumption in such a system can increasingly complex structures and organisations
be approximated as a negative exponential func- (JANTSCH, 1980). So three impacts of energy on
tion. The process conforms to the expectations of systems may be defined: (1) if a system can
the Second Law of Thermodynamics, and may be assimilate energy, then it may evolve, becoming
modelled as thermodynamic decay. For most of this more organised and complex, until it reaches a
century, the most characteristic theory of physical minimum entropic level which represents the max-
geography, has been the geographical cycle of W. imum energy differentiation achievable by the
M. Davis. This is a model of the evolution of a strategy of energy incorporation; (2) if a system
river-controlled landscape as a closed system loses energy then it devolves, becoming less organ-
(DAVIS, 1885). The ideal cycle (cf. SCHUMM, ised and complex, until it reaches the maximum
1979) is about the consumption of a single unit of entropic level which represents the minimum
energy supplied as the uplift of a land mass above energy differentiation achievable by the energy
sea level. The cycle uses an organismic analogy: it output; and (3) if a system exists in balance with its
charts the evolution of the landscape from youth to energy flow, then it preserves a level of organisation
GeoforumiVolume 16 Number 20985 199

at, or between, the maximum and minimum entro- evolution is contained in the writings of Nobel Prize
pic levels which are appropriate for its current winner Ilya Prigogine and the Brussels School, plus
energy supply. If the system has moved to its that of JANTSCH (1980) (NICOLIS and PRIGO-
current energy level from a lower energy level, then GINE 1971, 1977) have contributed the theory of
this state must be maximally entropic for the dissipative structures, and JANTSCH (1980) has
system’s current energy level. If, however, the built from this a new theory of evolution. However,
current energy level has been exceeded in the past, as Marx anticipated, the key to this new theory is in
the system may contain structures which were fact a revolution: the abrupt emergence of a new
produced by those higher energy levels but which ‘dissipative structure’.
still serve to promote the efficient operation of the
system. In this case the system is at its minimum The essence of Prigogine’s thinking is that the key
entropic state for the current energy level. to evolution is energy fluctuation in systems already
close to their own margins of stability. Systems, it
All this really says is that evolving systems move should be recalled, have an identity, an equilibrium
towards minimum entropy but exist at their max- state, and they contain regulatory mechanisms
imum entropic state for the current energy level. (feedbacks), which help them preserve that state. If
Devolving systems move towards maximum entropy these are very effective, a system becomes ‘over-
but tend to exist at a minimum entropic state for the stable’ and cannot evolve because the system
current energy levels. This, of course, assumes that corrects for all fluctuations in the environment.
it requires more energy to create a structure than it Systems evolution, therefore, only becomes poss-
requires to maintain it. The threshold of manifest- ible for systems operating at levels near the limits of
ation of a phenomenon is often well separated from the control of their homeostatic regulators. Near
the threshold of extinction for the same phe- these threshold bounds (of metastability) there is a
nomenon. The tendency to resist a change of system potential for fluctuations to trigger (positive feed-
state is called systems inertia. back) reactions and changes which do not subside
but carry the system to a new macroscopic state.
Inertial forces are one reason why the concept of Prigogine has termed such change ‘order through
system equilibrium must be so carefully qualified. fluctuation’ and given the name ‘dissipative struc-
Complex systems may contain many components tures’ to systems which dissipate energy and so
whose current operations and current energy evolve in this way.
balance are the result of past history. The same
component subsystems at the same energy level Prigogine also stresses that two types of change are
could exist in a completely different equilibrium found in nature: reversible or dynamic changes and
state and include completely different patterns of irreversible or thermodynamic changes. He argues
organisation if those systems have had a different with Max Planck that certain states, like maximum
history. entropy, tend to ‘attract’ systems and that a system
will not move to a condition which is less ‘attractive’
Karl Marx reminds us that general system theory is than the initial. From such a viewpoint, reversible
not solely in the province of the physical scientist. processes are seen as limiting cases where the
Marx writes of society: system has an equal propensity for a number of
states (cf. catastrophe theory and PRIGOGINE
This organic system as an aggregate whole has and STENGERS 1984, p. 121). Irreversibility,
underlying origins of its own and its evolution towards however, is merely recognition of the fact that open
wholeness consists precisely in subordinating to itself
all elements of society or creating therefrom the systems are influenced by their history. In stable
elements that it still lacks. Thus in the course of systems irreversibility tends to mean entropy
historical evolution, the system becomes a whole increase. Fluctuating, unstable systems, however,
entity. The development of the system into such an may sporadically develop the capacity to move
entity constitutes a moment of the systems process and
through the entropy barrier towards a new ‘attrac-
evolution (Karl Marx in GVISWIANI 1984, p. 7).
tor’, an identity associated with a lower entropy
state. The concept of the attractor is important. The
emergence of a new system structure or equilibrium
Theory of Dissipative Structures identity should not be regarded as a mystical event.
Certain foci within the range of possible system
Today the leading edge of the theory of systems states are inherently more stable than others.
200 Geoforum/Volume 16 Number 2/1985

Climatologists, for example, might suggest that Function Structure


there are several stable states for the Earth’s \ /
climatic systems: such as the ‘frozen globe’, the ‘ice Fluctuation
age earth’ and the present climate (LORENZ,
1976; LAMB, 1979). One system, then, may have NICOLIS and PRIGOGINE (1977, pp. 429-474)
several stable conditions, several entropic states, explore at length the concept that order is achieved
that it can switch between. In some cases such through fluctuation, especially the introduction of
attractors can be predicted from the patterns of mutations or innovations. The formation and
system dynamics (eg: the ‘Brusselator’: PRIGO- maintenance of self-organising systems is seen as
GINE and STENGERS, 1984, pp. 146-153). the result of fluctuation, non-linear couplings within
the system and competition between the entities
Prigogine, then, argues for a new emphasis in within the system.
systems evaluation. This extends beyond an
appreciation of irreversible processes towards a The development of any complex system, then,
concern for the property of ‘intrinsic randomness’. involves two contrapoised processes: the preserv-
Prigogine’s primary interest is in power surge ation of identity and temporary differential disturb-
fluctuations which carry systems beyond their upper ance. In a system the concept of systems equilib-
bounds of metastability and creates more organised rium is designed to indicate a capacity to resist
structures (lower entropic levels). This kind of disturbance by compensating, homeostatic adjust-
interaction is only possible in a system which ment, but this can inhibit its development. Instabil-
receives inputs from its environment and where ity, emerging in the course of systems operation,
fluctuations in inputs lead to instability which can allows a system to change to a new state. Fre-
create a more ordered structure. The creation of a quently, this change is not a gradual evolution but a
gully system on a hillside, the evolution of a radical restructuring, the coalescence of a new
structure, perhaps at a new hierarchical level.
convectional storm or tornado and the emergence
of an ecological niche in a geocomplex are all Frequently also, it is not the result of internal
examples of the emergence dissipative structures of processes, though such changes can be triggered by
low entropy. gradual accumulations within a system, they can
also be the result of an external trigger, a mutation
or power surge which can lead either to system
It has already been suggested that closed systems decomposition or system restructuring in a more
undergo entropy maximisation along the curve of organised form.
thermodynamic decay. This charts a negative
exponential curve. In the fluvial system it receives a YABLONSKY (1984, pp. 225-226) has attempted
physical manifestation as the long profile of the to model the evolution of science in terms of the
(graded) river channel, but the same curve has been steady-state dynamic equilibrium of ‘normal sci-
used to chart the decay of radium and the obsolesc- ence’ and the sudden instabilities of ‘scientific
ence of information. The curve expresses a general revolutions’ due to a power surge of unusual
conception of the probability of decomposition of a scientific creativity operating in a scientific environ-
system containing a large number of elements with a ment near the upper limit of its present equilibrium
fixed probability of failure (YABLONSKY, 1984). metastability (cf. KUHN, 1962). There remains
However, this probability of decomposition or room to wonder if this particular scientific revolu-
dissipation is the same for all systems, open or tion will break through into geography. Geog-
closed. It follows, therefore, that in open systems raphers experiment with the theory of thresholds
component failure must be compensated by compo- (SCHUMM, 1977; COATES and VITEK, 1980,
nent evolution or development. Systems which esp. pp. 209-226) and with catastrophe theory
cannot replace components or compensate for their (WAGSTAFF, 1978; GRAF, 1979). There is a little
loss by the development of new components must, interest in hierarchy theory (WOLDENBERG,
over an appropriate time-scale, degrade and dis- 1979) but the topic of hierarchical restructuring is
organise. neglected. Again, the problems of systems evolu-
tion, self-organisation and the emergence of new
Prigogine believes that no system is structurally dissipative structures are receiving attention. The
stable. The evolution of a dissipative structure is a spatial analysts have attempted to carry Prigogine’s
self-determined sequence of the form. ideas into the analysis of migration patterns, innov-
GeoforumNolume 16 Number 20985 201

ation diffusion and spatial econometrics, while, tion to Philosophy. Prentice Hall, Engelwood Cliffs,
alone in physical geography, CULLING (1985) NJ.
BECKETT, P. H. and WEBSTER, R. (1965) A classifi-
works with the notions of chaos, order and strange
cation system for terrain: units and principles, Report
attractors. ALLEN and SANGLIER (1979a, 1981), 872 Military Experimental Establishment (M. E. X. E.),
who are physical chemists from Prigogine’s own Christchurch, U.K.
school, explore the emergence of structure and BERG, L. S. (1913) A proposed classification of Siberia
self-organisation in urban growth. Their analyses and Turkestan into landscape and morphological
begin with biological models of logistic growth and units, In: Collected Papers in Honour of Prof. D. N.
Anuchin’s 70th Birthday. Moscow.
carrying capacity. They argue for a model of urban BERTALANFFY, L. VON (1950) An outline of General
evolution that includes aspects of both chance and Systems Theory, Br. J. Phil. Sci., 1, 134-165.
determinism but which discards the mechanism of BERTALANFFY, L. VON (1969) General System
economic optimisation (ALLEN and SANGLIER, Theory: Foundations, Development, Applications.
Braziller, New York.
1978, 1979b).
BERTALANFFY, L. VON (1975) History and develop-
ment of General System Theory, In: E. Taschdjian
(Ed.). Perspectives on General System Theory, pp.
Conclusion 149170. Braziller, New York.
BLAUBERG, I. V. (1984) System and wholeness con-
Geography remains in a state of methodological cept, In: J. M. Gvishiani et al. (Eds), Systems
Research: Methodological Problems. pp. 49-61. Per-
turmoil. Throughout its history it has undergone gamon Press, Oxford.
paradigm drift (cf. COX, 1976), but today it is BULL, W. B. (1975) Allometric change of landforms,
seeing paradigm multiplication. Geographers have Geol. Sot. Am. Bull. 86, 1489-1498.
reduced not only where they study and what they BODE, H., MOSTELLER, F., TUKEY, F. and WIN-
specialise in studying, but also how they study, SOR, C. (1949) The education of a scientific general-
ist, Science, 109, 553.
possibly to its furthest elementary fragments. The CHECKLAND, P. B. (1978) The origins and nature of
situation is becoming untenable. This paper may do ‘hard’ systems thinking, J. Appl. Sys. Anal., 5,
no more than delimit one more paradigm fragment, 99-110.
but at least this belongs to a new species, one that CHORLEY, R. J. (1962) Geomorphology and general
seeks methodological unification. General system systems theory, United States Geological Survey,
Professional Paper 500-B, pp. l-10.
theory represents an exciting and challenging route- CHORLEY, R. J. and KENNEDY, B. A. (1971)
way, not just to the reunification of geo- Physical Geography: A Systems Approach. Prentice
graphy, but to a new unified understanding of the Hall, Engelwood Cliffs, NJ.
unity of nature, science and society. CHRISTIAN, C. S. (1958) The concept of land units and
land systems. Proceedings of the Ninth Pacific Science
Congress, Vol. 2, pp. 74-81.
COATES, D. R. and VITEK, J. D. (Eds) (1980)
References Thresholds in Geomorphology. George Allen &
Unwin, London.
ALEXANDER, S. (1939) Space, Time and Deity in: COFFEY, W. J. (1979) Allometric growth in urban and
Philosophical and Literary Pieces. Macmillan, Lon- regional social-economic systems, Can. J. reg. Sci., 2,
don. 4965.
ALLEN, P. M. and SANGLIER, M. (1979a) A dynamic COFFEY, W. J. (1981) Geography: Towards a General
model of growth in a central place system, Geogr. Spatial Systems Appproach. Methuen Paperback,
Anal., 11, 256272. London.
ALLEN, P. M. and SANGLIER, M. (1979b) A dynamic COX, K. (1976) American geography: social science
model of urban growth - II, J. sot. biol. Struct., 2, emergent, Sot. Sci. Q., 57, 182-207.
269-278. CULLING, W. E. H. (1985) Equifinality: chaos, dimen-
ALLEN, P. M. and SANGLIER, M. (1978) Dynamic sion and pattern, in preparation.
models of urban growth, J. sot. biol. Struct, 1, DAUKSA, L. and KORTARBA, A. (1973) An analysis
265-280. of the influence of fluvial erosion in the development
ALLEN, P. M. and SANGLIER, M. (1981) Urban of a landslide slope (using the application of the
evolution, self-organisation, and decision-making, queueing theory), Studia Geomorph. Carpatho-
Envir. Plan., A13, 167-183. Balcanica, 7, 91-103.
ANUCHIN, V. A. (1977) Teoreticheskiye problemy DAVIS, W. M. (1885) Geographic classification, illustr-
geografi. State Publishing House, Geographical Liter- ated by a study of plains, plateaux and their deriva-
ature, Moscow; trans. S, Shabad. Theoretical Prob- tives, Proc. Am. Assoc. Adv. Sci., 33, 428432.
lems in Geography, Ohio State University Press, DURY, G. H. (1981) An Introduction to Environmental
Columbus, OH. Systems. Heinemann, London.
BECK, L. W. (1952) Philosophic Inquiry: an Introduc- FREEMAN, T. W. (1961) A Hundred Years of Geo-
202 Geoforum/Volume 16 Number 211985

graphy, Duckworth, London. concept of entropy in landscape evolution, U.S.


GERASIMOV, I. P. et al. (1978) International geo- Geological Survey, Professional Paper 500-A, pp.
graphy, Proceedings of the 23rd International 3-20.
Geographical Congress, Moscow, 1976, Vol. 1. LEOPOLD, L. B. and MADDOCK, T. (1953) Hydraulic
GRAF. W. (1979) Catastrophe theory as a model for geometry of stream channels and some physiographic
change in fluvial systems, In: D. D. Rhodes and G. P. implications. U.S. Geological Survey, Professional
Williams (Eds), Adjustment of the Fluv~a~System, pp. Paper 252 A.
13-32. Kendall/Hunt, Dubuque, IA. LILENFIELD, R. (1978) Rise of Systems Theory. Wiley,
GVISHIANI, J. M. (1984) Materialist dialectics as a New York.
philosophical basis for systems research, In: J. M. LORENZ, E. N. (1976) Nondeterministic theories of
Gvishiani, et al. (Eds), Systems Research: climate change, Quat. Res., 6, 495-506.
Methodological Problems, pp. 3-15. U.S.S.R. State MAZUR, E. (Ed.) Landscape synthesis, Geojournal, 7,
Committee for Science and Technology, U.S.S.R. 99-188.
Academy of Sciences, Institute for Systems Studies/ MILLER, J. G. (1978) Living Systems. McGraw-fill,
Pergamon Press, Oxford. New York.
HARTSHORNE, R. (1939) The nature of geography: a MILSUM, J. H. (1967) Technosphere, biosphere and
critical study of current thought in the light of the sociosphere: an approach to their systems modelling
past, Ann. Assoc. Am. Geogr., 29 (3/4), l-482. and optimisation, In: J. Beishon and G. Peters (Eds),
HERBERTSON, A. J. (1905) The major natural regions: Systems Behaviour, pp. 187-199. Harper & Row,
an essay on systematic geography, Geogr. J., 25, Lond.
300-312. MITCHELL, C. W. (1973) Terrain evaluation, Long-
HIDORE, J. J. (1974) Physical Geography: Earth Sys- mans, London.
tems. Scott, Foresmann & Co., Glenview, IL. NEWSON, M. D. and HANWELL, J. D. (1982)
HUGGETT, R. (1980) Systems Analysis in Geography. Systematic Physical Geography. Macmillan, London.
Clarendon Press, Oxford. NICOLIS, G. and PRIGOGINE, I. (1971) Fluctuations
HUMBOLDT, A. VON (1845) Kosmos: Entwurf einer in non-equilibrium systems, Proc. natn. Acad. Sci.
Physichphysichen Weltbeschreibung (cited in Hart- U.S.A., 68, 2102-2107.
shorne, 1939). NICOLIS, G. and PRIGOGINE, I. (1977) Self
ISACHENKO, A. G. (1973) Principles of Landscape organization in non-Equilibrium Systems: from Dis-
Science and Physical-Geographic Regionalization. sipative Structures to order Through Fluctuations.
Melbourne University Press; Carlton, AU. Wiley Interscience, New York.
JACKSON, M. C. (ACKOFF, R. L., CHURCHMAN, NORDBECK, S. (1965) The law of allometric growth,
C. W. and CHECKLAND, P. B.) (1982) The nature Mich. Inter. univ. Comm. math. Geogr., 7.
of ‘soft’ systems thinking: the work of Churchman, OLYPHANT, G. (1981) Allometry and cirque form-
Ackoff, and Checkland (including three replies to ation, Bull. geol. Sot. Am., 92, 479-685.
Jackson), J. Appt. Systems Anal., 9, 17-39. PATTEE, H. H. (Ed.) (1973) Hierarchy Theory: the
JANTSCH, E. (1980) The Self-organising Universe: Challenge of Complex Systems, Braziller, New York.
Scientific and Human Implications of the Emerging PEPPER, S. (1942) World Hypotheses. University of
Paradigm of Evolution. Pergamon Press, Oxford. California, Berkeley, LA.
JEFFERS, J. N. R. (1978) An Introduction to Sysrems PREOBRAZHENSKIY, U.S. (1983) Geosystem as an
Analysts with Ecological App~icatior~s. Edward object of landscape study, Geojournal, 7, 131-134.
Arnold, London. PRIGOGINE, I. and STENGERS, I. (3984). Order out
KOESTLER, A. (1967) The Ghost in the Machine. of Chaos: Man’s New Dialogue with Nature (trans-
Hutchinson, London. lation of: La Nouvelle Alliance, Galimard, Paris,
KRCHO, J. (1978) The spatial organization of the 1979. Heinemann, London.
physical geographical sphere as a cybernetic system REDDY, N. B. K. and UTI’ARA PRABHU, M. (1983)
expressed by means of measures of entropy. Acta Fat. Systems theory in geography: a review, Ind. geogr. J.‘,
Rerum nat. Univ. comen., Bratisl., 10, Geograph~cu, 58. s%f%
--I -- ---

16, 57-145. RUSSWURM, L. Ii. (1974) A systems approach to the


KUHN, T. (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. natural environment, In: L. H. Russwurm and E.
University of Chicago, Chicago, IL. Summerville (Eds), Man’s Naural Environment: a
LAMB, P. J. (1979) Some perspectives on climate and System Approach, pp. l-16. Duxbury Press, North
climate dynamics, Prog. Phys. Geogr. 3, 215-235. Scituate, MA.
LANGTON, J. (1980) Potentiality and problems of SADOVSKY, V. N. (1984) Systems approach and
adapting a systems approach to the study of change in General Systems Theory - state of the art, main
human geography, Prog. human Geogr., 4, 127-171. problems and prospect for development, In: J. M.
LA PATRA, J. W. (1973) Applying the Systems Gvishiani, et al (Eds) Systems
, Research:
Approach to Urban Development. Dowden, Hutch- Methodological Problems, pp. 16-32. Pergamon
inson & Ross, Stroudsberg, PA. Press, Oxford.
LASZLO, E. (1972) The Systems View of the World. SCHUMM, S. A. (1977) The Fluvial System. Wiley, New
Braziller, New York. York.
LASZLO, E. (1983) Systems Science and World Order SCHUMM, S A. (1979) Geomophic thresholds: the
Pergamon Press, Oxford. concept and its applications, Trans. Inst. Rr, Geogr,
LEOPOLD, L. B. and LANGBEIN, W. B. (1962) The 4, 485-515.
Geoforum/Volume 16 Number 211985 203

SCHUGART, H. H. and O’NEIL, R. V. (Eds) (1979) temow, Folia Geographica; Ser: Geographica-Physica
Systems Ecology, Benchmark Papers in Ecology 9. 12, 137-146.
Dowden, Hutchinson & Ross, Stroudsberg, PA. WILBANKS, T. J. and SYMANSKI, R. (1968) What is
STRAHLER, A. N. (1980) Systems theory in physical systems analysis? Prof. Geogr. 20, 81-85.
geography, Phy. Geogr. 1, l-27. WILSON, A. G. (1981) Geography and the Environment:
THEISEN, D. D. (1981) Evolution through instability, Systems Analytical Methods. Wiley, New York.
Contemp. Psychol, 26, 758-760. WOLDENBERG, M. J. (1979) A periodic table of
THORNES, J. (1971) State, environment and attribute in spatial hierarchies, In: S. Gale and G. Olsson (Eds),
scree-slope studies. Inst. Br. Geogr. (Special Publi- Philosophy in Geography, Theory and Decision
cation), 3, 4963. Library No. 20, pp. 429-456. D. Reidel, Dordrecht.
TIVY, J. and O’HARE, G. (1981) Human Impact on the WOOLDRIDGE, S. W. and EAST, W. G. (1951) The
Ecosystem. Oliver & Boyd, Edinburgh. Spirit and Purpose of Geography. Methuen, London.
TOKUNGA, E. (1978) Consideration on the compo- YABLONSKY, A. I. (1984) The development of science
sition of drainage networks and their evolution, as an open system, In: J. M. Gvishiani (Ed.), Systems
Geogr. Rep. Tokyo Metrop. Univ., 13, l-28. Research: Methodological Problems, pp. 211-228.
WAGSTAFF, J. M. (1978) A possible interpretation of Pergamon Press, Oxford.
settlement pattern evolution in terms of ‘Catastrophe ZIPF, G. K. (1949) Human Behaviour and the Principle
Theory’, Trans. Inst. Br. Geogr., ns4, 438-444. of Least Effort An Introduction to Human Ecology.
WATTS, K. E. F. (1966) The nature of systems analysis, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
In: K. E. F. (Ed.), Systems Analysis in Ecology, pp. ZONNEVELD, J. I. S. (1983) Some basic notions in
l-16. Academic Press, New York. geographical synthesis, Geojournal, 7, 121-130.
WIDACKI, U. (1979) Uwagi u funckjonowanice geosys-

You might also like