You are on page 1of 62

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982) 5, 407-467

Printed in the United States of America

Toward a general psychobiological


theory of emotions
Jaak Panksepp
Department of Psychology, Bowling Green
State University, Bowling Green, Ohio 43403

Abstract: Emotions seem to arise ultimately from hard-wired neural circuits in the visceral-limbic brain that facilitate diverse and
adaptive behavioral and physiological responses to major classes of environmental challenges. Presumably these circuits developed
early in mammalian brain evolution, and the underlying control mechanisms remain similar in humans and "lower" mammals. This
would suggest that theoretically guided studies of the animal brain can reveal how primitive emotions are organized in the human
brain. Conversely, granted this cross-species heritage, it is arguable that human introspective access to emotional states may provide
direct information concerning operations of emotive circuits and thus be a primary source of hypotheses for animal brain research. In
this article the possibility that emotions are elaborated by transhypothalamic executive (command) circuits that concurrently activate
related behavior patterns is assessed. Current neurobehavioral evidence indicates that there are at least four executive circuits of this
type - those which elaborate central states of expectancy, rage, fear, and panic. The manner in which learning and psychiatric
disorders may arise from activities of such circuits is also discussed.

Keywords: affect; brain theory; command circuits; emotion; expectancy; fear; hypothalamus; panic; psychiatric disorders; rage;
reinforcement

The scientific study of emotions is beset by more than the more knowledge concerning the nature of emotions may
usual number of methodological and conceptual prob- be derived than from either approach taken alone. This is
lems. It is difficult to agree how, within the constraints of not to say that we can measure the subjective awareness
scientific objectivity, we can derive substantive under- of other animals, but to assert that basic emotions may
Standing of phenomena that appear intimately linked to have obligatory internal dynamics, which humans share
the internal experiences of organisms. In animal re- with other mammals. By using our subjective sources of
search, the traditional solution (and compromise) has insight concerning these dynamics, we may be able to
been to study the objective behavioral and physiological resolve some of the subtleties of brain organization more
manifestations of presumed emotional states, with an readily than if we follow the dictum that all we can know
exclusive focus on behavior and a calculated disregard of are the behavioral and physiological symptoms of emotive
the underlying states. Conversely, at the human level states.
there is abundant discussion of the various emotional In any event, it should be self-evident that the use of
states and little knowledge concerning their sources in anthropomorphism in the study of mammalian emotions
the brain. Thus, while major concepts concerning the cannot be arbitrarily ruled out. Although its application
nature of emotions arise from human introspection, most may be risky under the best of circumstances, its validity
knowledge concerning the mechanisms underlying emo- depends on the degree of evolutionary continuity among
tionality arises from animal brain research. This paper is brain mechanisms that elaborate emotions in humans and
based on the conviction that the study of emotions, in animals. Hence, the degree of anthropomorphism that
both humans and animals, continues to be impoverished can have scientific utility in mammalian brain research
by our failure to blend these two sources of knowledge. should be directly related to the extent that emotions
The major obstacles to achieving the above synthesis reflect class-typical mechanisms as opposed to species-
are our inability to read the animal mind as directly as we typical ones.
can read our own and the subtleties of emotional nuance Although a definitive statement concerning the degree
that can evolve during the course of social learning in of similarity between neural systems that mediate emo-
humans. Accordingly, introspection and the consequent tions in animals and humans cannot be made, available
tendency to anthropomorphize remain anathema in ani- evidence suggests that fundamental emotional circuits
mal research. However, the fundamental organization of are inherited components of the limbic brain, which are
emotions in the brain may be quite similar in humans and to a substantial degree a shared mammalian heritage
other mammals. If this is so, recent advances in brain (Crosby & Showers 1969; MacLean 1973; Parent 1979).
research may permit anthropomorphism to become a Species-typical instinctual behaviors remain intact even
more useful strategy for understanding certain primitive after radical decortication soon after birth (e.g., Murphy,
psychological processes in animals than it has been in the MacLean, & Hamilton 1981), and, with few exceptions,
past. Through the conjoint application of an- trauma to subcortical tissue in humans yields behavioral
thropomorphic reasoning and animal brain research, changes similar to those which result from experimental

© 1982 Cambridge University Press 0140-525X1821030407-61 IS06.00 407


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
manipulation of these circuits in other mammals. For individual emotive circuits. (4) The most efficient and
instance, animals with ventromedial hypothalamic le- reasonable way to obtain an initial neurotaxonomy of the
sions exhibit voraciousness and rage (Heatherington & hard-wired emotional processes in the mammalian brain
Ranson 1942; Wheatley 1944), as do humans (Reeves & is through introspection. (5) The scientific understanding
Plum 1969). Posterior hypothalamic damage brings on of emotional processes must arise from a clarification of
somnolence, and anterior hypothalamic damage insom- how they are organized in the brain (and hence, out of
nia, in both animals and humans (McGinty & Sterman "ethical" necessity, the animal brain).
1968; Nauta 1946; Ranson 1939; von Economo 1930). On the basis of these assumptions, the substantive aims
Electrical stimulation of the amygdala can yield rage in of this paper are to propose a taxonomy of emotions that is
both (de Molina & Hunsperger 1963; King 1961). Al- supported by existing neurobehavioral data; to provide an
though exceptions to such apparent homologies could approximate neural scheme of how emotions may be
also be cited, the general conclusion appears to be that organized in the brain; and to discuss the implications of
the functional terrain of the subcortical limbic brain such circuits for the understanding of learning and emo-
across mammalian species is remarkably similar, in kind if tional disorders. Admittedly, each successive aim is
not in precise organization. Accordingly, the study of based on increasingly large measures of speculation. In
these parts of the emotional brain in animals should general, I shall argue that "the mammalian brain" con-
provide a credible outline for understanding the primi- tains at least four primitive executive (command) circuits
tive emotional functions of the human brain. Conversely, that initiate the distinct subjective emotional states of
it should follow that some properties of these circuits in expectancy, fear, rage, and panic in humans and that
the animal brain could be deciphered by judicious intro- trigger the corresponding emotive processes in animals.
spection. Although it is not evident how a clear path First, however, I shall trace some of the historical roots of
through the possibilities of human imagination is to be this endeavor.
achieved, anthropomorphic excesses can be checked by
the constraint that verifiable consequences must be gen-
erated with the accepted empirical tools of behavioral Historical overview
brain research. By insisting that introspectively derived
conceptions of animal emotion be linked simultaneously A great deal has been written on emotions through the
to specific behaviors and brain processes, the testability ages, and one who attempts the journey through that
of the resulting ideas could help stave off the terminally material may soon concur with James (1892, p. 241) that
debilitating scholastic debates, which have immobilized "the varieties of emotion are innumerable" and that the
this important area of inquiry in the past. descriptive literature on the subject "is one of the most
Although behavioral and physiological effects of emo- tedious parts of psychology. And not only is it tedious, but
tional states may be all that can ever be empirically you feel that its subdivisions are to a great extent either
measured in animals, some of these could be used as fictitious or unimportant, and that its pretences to ac-
indicator variables for more hidden central processes that curacy are a sham," so that "reading of classic works on
may be operative in certain situations. Indeed, such an the subject" is as interesting as "verbal descriptions of the
indirect theoretical analysis of certain neural systems may shapes of the rocks on a New Hampshire farm."
be essential, because the field of inquiry is confronted by Still, at the conceptual Jevel, an inquiry into emotions
experimental difficulties similar to those encountered in must start with a taxonomy of emotional experience in
particle physics, where the clarification of intranuclear humans. Were it not for the consensus that such subjec-
forces has to proceed through indirect observations that tive states exist in humans, emotion as a construct would
yield only indirect affirmative or negative evidence about never have arisen in the study of animal behavior. Many
the nature of the underlying processes. In a similar way, plausible taxonomies of emotions have come from the
the functions of certain brain circuits may be sufficiently consideration of such subjective states, and it is reason-
internalized in the fabric of the brain so that their normal able to expect that a cogent physiological theory of emo-
operations and intersystemic cleavage lines need to be tion should subsume the best organizational principles
derived initially by introspectively based theoretical in- generated from that perspective. Historically, the con-
ference. Of course, our initial conceptualizations will struction of taxonomies of emotional experience, though
invariably be simplifications, which fail to do full justice to not strictly empirical, led directly to the study of emo-
the actual circuit configurations in the brain. With such tional expression in humans and kindred animals and,
qualifications in mind, the overall aim of this paper is to recently, to attempts to specify how various emotional
outline a testable theory of how emotional processes may processes are related to physiological changes in both
be organized in the central nervous system of mammals. brain and body.
Because they will receive little further emphasis here,
I shall reiterate the theoretical assumptions underlying Taxonomies of emotion. In one of the earliest major
this proposal. They are: (1) Distinct emotional processes treatises to attempt to relate brain and mind, Willis (1683,
reflect activity in specific hard-wired brain circuits. (2) p. 49) began his ninth chapter on "Two Discourses
Humans share essentially similar primitive emotional Concerning the Soul of Brutes" as follows:
processes with all other mammals and perhaps some Concerning the Number of the Passions, as it hath
related vertebrates. (3) The number of fundamental emo- been variously disputed among Philosophers, so in
tional circuits is limited, but through their intermixtures famous Schools, this Division into Eleven Passions,
and social learning, emotions in humans have a much long since grew of use; to wit, the Sensitive Appetite is
richer phenomenological texture than is contained in the distinguished into Concupiscible and Irascible, to the

408 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
first, are counted commonly six Passions, viz. Pleasure Table 1. Taxonomy of the passions (Cogan, 1802)
and Grief, Desire and Aversions, Love and Hatred; but
to the latter five, viz. Anger, Boldness, Fear, Hope, Class I Passions arising from principle of self-love
and Desperation, are wont to be attributed. Order I From the idea of good
Foreshadowing future controversies, Willis disagreed: Genus 1 Good in possession (JOY: gladness, cheerful-
But this distribution of the Affections is not only in- ness, mirth, satisfaction, contentment, com-
congruous, for that Hope is but ill referred to the placency)
Irascible Appetite, and Hatred and Aversion, seem Genus 2 Good in expectancy—DESIRE
rather to belong to this, than to the Concupiscible: But Order II From the idea of evil
it is also very insufficient, because some more noted Genus 1 Losses and disappointment—SORROW
Affections, as Shame, Pity, Emulation, Envy, and Genus 2 Evils which are apprehensive—FEAR
many others, are wholly omitted: Wherefore the An- Genus 3 Conduct which deserves reprehension—
cient Philosophers did determinate the Primary to a ANGER
certain Number, then they placed under their several
Kinds, very many indefinite Species. Class II Passions and affections derived from the so-
Perhaps as a reaction to the categorical excesses of cial principle
medieval scholastics, Descartes, in his discourse on "the Order I Excited by ideas of benevolence
passions of the soul" (1650), reduced emotional life to six Genus I Benevolent desires (generosity, condolence,
primary passions: wonder, love, hate, desire, joy, and pity, charity, liberality)
sadness, with all the rest being "made up of some of these Genus 2 Good opinion (gratitude, thankfulness, admi-
six or at least are species of them" (cf. Ruckmick 1936, p. ration)
39). The idea that primary emotional processes are lim- Order II Excited by idea of evil
ited to a relatively small group of fundamental systems is Genus 1 Malevolence (malice, envy, rancor, cruelty,
still with us, with the number of primary emotions usually prejudice, jealousy, resentment, revenge)
ranging from three to eight; the father of behaviorism Genus 2 Unfavorable opinion (horror, contempt, dis-
suggested that three, namely, fear, rage, and sexual love, dain)
characterized the fundamental nature of man (Watson
1924). However, except for general suggestions of where
emotions may be elaborated in the brain (e.g., Papez
1937), as well as highly concrete neurophysiological hy- overcome, straightforward, testable hypotheses can be
potheses concerning the genesis of specific emotions
generated, and refutations can be decisive.
(e.g., anxiety, in Gray, 1979), there has been little at-
tempt to relate any of the well articulated taxonomies of The expression of emotion. Perhaps as a response to the
emotion to specific brain circuits. The aim of this paper is endlessly equivocal nature of introspectively derived
to attempt such a synthesis. [See also BBS multiple book taxonomies of emotions, as well as the development of
review of Gray: The Neuropsychology of Anxiety, BBS 5 new intellectual disciplines, such as physiognomy (Lava-
(3) 1982, this issue.] ter 1789-98) and phrenology (Gall 1835; Spurzheim
After the ideas expressed in this paper had crystallized, 1832), the nineteenth century saw the rise of descriptive
I discovered a forgotten system closely resembling it in analysis of emotional expression, ranging from detailed
form, if not specific content. This system, proposed by studies of the facial musculature generating the emotional
Cogan (1802) and summarized in Table 1, viewed emo- countenance (Bell 1806) to the recognition that the ste-
tions from the subjective perspective, and thus contained reotyped character of emotional expression in animals
the existential virtues (or mentalistic excesses, depending and humans indicates the common inheritance of mecha-
on one's point of view) that have traditionally proved nisms that govern the elaboration of emotions (Darwin
troublesome in the scientific analysis of emotion. Howev- 1872). At the end of the century, the emphasis on emo-
er, it will be argued that the scheme contains the seed of tional expression, as opposed to emotional experiences or
truth that any credible psychobiological theory of emo- processes, led to the renowned James-Lange theory
tion must ultimately nurture. Cogan suggested that hu- (James 1884), which entertained placing anger inside the
mans inherit five primitive passions - those of desire, fist rather than behind it. By proposing that the bodily
anger, fear, sorrow, and joy. Under somewhat different changes occurring during emotive acts might be causes
labels, expectancy, rage, fear, and panic, I shall attempt rather than consequences of emotions, the James-Lange
to relate the first four of these passions to the circuitry of theory challenged common reason and reaped a harvest
the visceral brain. of negative evidence and critical counterargument (Can-
Since Cogan's time, many other taxonomies have been non 1927, 1931; Sherrington 1900), though perhaps none
proposed, but in the absence of concurrent analyses of sufficiently compelling as to be decisive, especially if one
brain mechanisms, they remain on the fringes of science. wished to entertain an infinite regress into the potential
Recent thought on the subject has been well summarized subjective awareness of a brain disconnected of its inputs
by Ruckmick (1936) and Plutchik (1980). Without phys- and outputs. Although it is likely that peripheral auto-
iological anchor points, theories of emotion remain gra- nomic feedback influences the labeling of emotional
tuitous because they cannot escape from fatal cir- states in humans and provides reafferent feedback that
cularities, although they can generate useful experimen- intensifies emotional experience (Schachter & Singer
tation (Strongman 1973). With clearly specified 1962) and behavior (Baccelli, Guazzi, Libretti, & Zan-
physiological anchor points, however, circularity can be chetti 1965), it now seems likely that the James-Lange

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 409


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
theory reversed primary cause and consequence. Yet, only medial and temporal cortex were left intact, amend-
unlike earlier inquiries such as Darwin's, in which little ing the earlier idea that the cortex generally inhibited
heed was given to the nature of proximal causes, the emotional responsivity (Bard & Mountcastle 1948). Since
James-Lange perspective emphasized the need for such heightened emotionality emerged gradually following
a level of analysis if emotions were ever to be probed damage to those remaining cortical areas, it was sug-
experimentally. gested that inhibition of emotional responsivity might be
The study of emotional expression, as reflected in due specifically to limbic cortical influences, but this
somatic and visceral changes, has remained a hallmark of conclusion remained tenuous, because it was outwardly
the scientific analysis of emotions (Ax 1953; Eibl- inconsistent with the emotional placidity that appeared
Eibesfeldt 1979; Ekman 1973; Grings & Dawson 1978). after temporal lobe damage in monkeys (Kluver & Bucy
Unfortunately, brain research generally continues to 1937) and cats (Schreiner & Kling 1953). More recently,
cling to the tenet that the only credible scientific ap- wildness has been induced by cingulate cortical damage
proach to this area is the study of emotional expression. in neodecorticate animals (Murphy et al. 1981), suggest-
Although the approach has yielded many elegant facts ing that disinhibition of rage may have resulted from
(Flynn 1976; Hess 1957), it is my contention that such a damage to medial limbic cortex.
single-minded focus on emotional expression without Although many questions concerning decorticate rage
concurrent consideration of underlying emotional pro- remain, it is now clear that both excitatory and inhibitory
cess has outlived its usefulness in psychobiology and may influences on emotional behavior are elaborated through
be currently hindering progress in understanding the limbic cortex and ganglia (Ursin 1965; Ursin & Kaada
neural organization of emotion. 1960). The early studies definitively localized the elabora-
tion of primitive emotional tendencies in the vis-
Brain organization of emotive processes. Since range ceral-limbic brain, and the old controversies concerning
could be precipitated in animals by decerebration (Goltz whether the emotional changes observed in some of those
1892), the suspicion arose that certain subcortical parts of early studies were devoid of emotional content, whether
the brain were important for organizing emotions. How- they were "sham" or "real," have become less pertinent
ever, it was not until after the turn of the century that with the recognition that hierarchical levels of organiza-
experimental evidence was found that indicated that tion exist within functionally continuous psycho-
certain areas of the brain, especially those near the behavioral organ systems of the brain (Bernston & Micco
ventral surface, are critical for organizing the autonomic 1976). Indeed, questions of animal awareness were
changes that accompany emotional states and behaviors. shelved as basically unanswerable, and the mainstream of
Further study of decorticate rage by Bard (1928; 1934), investigation continued to focus on the actual brain cir-
Cannon (1929), and others established that the expression cuits that participate in the expression of "emotive"
of anger could be initiated subcortically, suggesting that behaviors. It became clear that the functions of higher
the neocortex tonically inhibits circuits that mediate this brain areas >vere mediated through lower systems (de
emotional behavior. This discovery led to the hypothesis Molina & Hunsperger 1962), and it came to be widely
that endogenous brain systems elaborate emotions and, assumed by psychobiological investigators that the elu-
specifically, that thalamic circuits mediate emotional ex- cidation of hard-wired brainstem circuits would provide
periences (Cannon 1929). Concurrently, Karplus and the basic information through which higher functions
Kreidl (1909; 1927), followed by Kabat (1936), Ranson and were ultimately to be understood. At the same time, the
Magoun (1939), and others, were demonstrating dramatic likely relevance of these circuits to the emotional life of
changes in the autonomic responsivity of anesthetized humans was implicitly accepted but generally treated
cats during localized electrical stimulation of the hypo- with benign neglect. The translation between the two was
thalamus. This response suggested that the ventral part of understood to be empirically impossible, and hence, in
the upper brainstem was a head ganglion of the autonom- some ultimate logical sense, gratuitous.
ic nervous system, which participated in the genesis of Thus, even though there has been a great deal of
emotional behavior and experience. The fact that excellent work on brainstem mediation of emotive behav-
thalamic damage did not eliminate decorticate rage in iors, especially aggression, there has been little attempt
cats (Bard & Macht 1958) affirmed the probability that the to integrate concepts from the taxonomy of human emo-
hypothalamus was essential for elaborating emotional tional experience with data concerning the limbic circuit-
responsivity. Hess's studies (1925-49, and English sum- ry of the animal brain. Although the work on brain
mary in 1957) established that rage and other well coordi- organization of aggression has yielded a harvest of knowl-
nated emotive behaviors could be instigated by localized edge (Adams 1979; Flynn 1976; Siegel & Edinger 1981),
electrical stimulation of the hypothalamus in a conscious as has the analysis of autonomic changes that typically
animal. This work solidly established the concept that the accompany such agonistic emotive states (Mancia &
emotional nervous system is embedded in the visceral Zanchetti 1981), other affective processes that do not
nervous system. Later, with the recognition of the di- have such dramatic somatic and autonomic manifesta-
verse anterior connectivities of hypothalamic systems tions remain largely unstudied.
(Papez 1937) and the emotional changes resulting from
damage to those circuits (Bard & Mountcastle 1948;
Kluver & Bucy 1939), the concept of a visceral-emotional
brain was generalized to the entire limbic system (Mac- A definition of emotions
Lean 1949).
On the assumption that emotions arise from the activities
Further study of restricted decortications in cats indi- of brain circuits, a general definition of emotion would
cated an insensitivity to emotion-provoking stimuli when consist of a list of attributes such brain circuits possess. In

410 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
the absence of extensive knowledge concerning these a distinction between affective "feelings" and "emotions"
circuits, the list must first be constructed rationally. I may be made on the basis of the degree of arousal within
propose that such circuits have at least the following six an emotive system. Thus, environmental stimuli that
attributes: (1) They are genetically hard-wired and de- provoke weak interactions with primitive emotive cir-
signed to respond unconditionally to stimuli arising from cuits without generating sustained reverberatory feed-
major life-challenging circumstances (Figure 1). (2) They back may be considered to have simply provoked an
organize behavior by activating or inhibiting classes of affective "feeling." Furthermore, the fact that there are a
related actions (and concurrent autonomic/hormonal variety of homeostatic interoreceptors in the hypo-
changes) that have proved adaptive in the face of those thalamus, designed to monitor various bodily states,
types of life-challenging circumstances during the evolu- which not only interact with emotive systems but which
tionary history of the species (Figure 2). (3) Through surely also have distinct sensory attributes, further ampli-
recurrent feedback, emotive circuits change the sen- fies the variety of discriminable "feelings" that can be
sitivities and responsivities of sensory systems relevant elaborated by the brain. By assuming that most of the
for those behavior sequences. (4) The activity in the internal and external stimuli encountered in everyday life
underlying neural systems can outlast the precipitating interact with a limited number of primitive emotive
circumstances (i.e., there is either substantial positive circuits, the list of distinct emotions can be kept much
feedback or long-term neuromodulation in the circuits). shorter than the list of distinct feelings. Accordingly,
(5) Activity in these circuits can come under the condi- questions of how the affective coloring of each human
tional control of emotionally neutral environmental stim- subjective experience is achieved can be shelved until the
uli via a reinforcement process that is a design feature of primitive emotional circuitries of the brain are deline-
each emotive circuit. (6) Activity in such circuits has ated, and the analysis of basic emotive systems need not
access to and reciprocal interactions with brain mecha- be paralyzed by the vast variety of human affective
nisms that elaborate consciousness (to provide higher- experience in the real world.
order response selection among the specific behavioral Moreover, several primitive affective states, which
acts that are sensitized by arousal of an emotive system). have been incorporated in past taxonomies of emotional
It is only this last aspect of emotions, so evident in human life, will be ignored because they do not appear to fulfill
mental life, which remains so untestable in animal re- all of the criteria mentioned above. For instance, neither
search. However, since all mammals seem to share funda- "surprise" and "disgust," both of which have clear behav-
mentally similar emotive brain circuits, this last attribute ioral referents in animals (e.g., Davis 1979; Grill &
may prove to be the "Rosetta stone" via which the general Norgren 1978) and may be controlled by specific brain-
organization of the primitive hard-wired emotional sys- stem circuits (the "stimulus-bound" startle and retching
tems of the mammalian brain can be deciphered. described by Hess, 1957), are included as major emo-
Thefirstfour criteria should help delimit the number of tional states in the present context (powerful affects as
emotive circuits in the mammalian brain and help gener- they may be in humans), because they do not activate
ate distinctions among the many vague terms that have diverse classes of species-typical behaviors (permitting
been used in discussions of the affective life. For instance, adaptive response selection among alternatives) and be-
cause their underlying states appear to be largely time-
locked to the precipitating stimuli, with no sustained
regenerative feedback in the underlying brain systems.
In other words, "startle" and "disgust" may be more
reflexive in character than the brain processes that are
herein considered to be truly emotional.
For similar reasons, the concepts of pleasure/relief and
displeasure/distress are not included in the present analy-
sis. Such states do not appear to generate unique behav-
ioral manifestations, and such generalized affects may cut
across many distinct emotive states and probably arise
secondarily from changes in activity of the discrete emo-
PAIN .ndTHREAT tive systems to be discussed. For instance, pleasure and
Of M>RM
DESTRUCTION relief may be states which accompany stimuli that tend to
return organisms toward physiological homeostasis and
emotional equilibrium, while unpleasantness and dis-
tress may arise from stimuli that remove an organism
from those respective conditions (Aristotle in "Nic-
homachean Ethics"; Cabanac 1971). Although such con-
cepts can yield general behavioral predictions in animal
research (as generalized response guiding principles) and
may even operate through discrete neurochemical sys-
tems of the brain, such as dopamine (Wise 1982) or
endorphins (Panksepp 1981b; Stein & Belluzzi 1978),
they will not be discussed further here because currently
Figure 1. Major classes of environmental stimuli that require their behavioral indicators in animals are rather subtle
rapid behavioral adjustments presumably converge upon com- and diffuse; incisive approaches to the neurobiological
mand systems of the brain to trigger species-typical sensory- analysis of these more generalized phenomena may first
motor patterns.

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 411


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

FOREWARD LOCOMOTION, SNIFFING, INVESTIGATION

STIMULUS-BOUND-
APPETITIVE
BEHAVIOR
AND
SELF-STIMULATION

a.
U

o STIMULUS-BOUND
FLIGHT
"STIMULUS-BOUND
DISTRESS VOCALIZATION
AND AND
ESCAPE BEHAVIORS EXPLOSIVE BEHAVIORS

i
N
Ui
Ul

STIMULUS-BOUND-
BITING
AND
AFFECTIVE ATTACK

ATTACK, B I T I N G , FIGHTING

Figure 2. Emotive-command systems are defined primarily by neural circuits from which well-organized behavioral sequences can
be elicited by localized stimulation of brain tissue. The approximate locations of these systems are depicted on hemifrontal
hypothalamic sections of the rat brain; cp - cerebral peduncle; dm - dorsomedial nucleus; mf - medial forebrain bundle; mt
-mammillothalamic tract; ot - optic tract; re - nucleus reuniens; vm - ventromedial nucleus; x - fornix; zi - zona incerta. The major
behavioral outputs of each command system are indicated. The various command systems are anatomically close to each other and
presumably interact so as to maintain behavioral focus on a single class of behaviors. It is assumed that the various possible
interactions among systems lead to second-order emotive states consisting of blended activities across the primary systems. Some
possible interactions are outlined. Some systems may also have biphasic interactions depending on the level of activity within an
emotive system and the past experiences of the animal.

require clarifying the mechanisms that organize the more Emotive circuits of the brain: The theory
discrete emotive states of the brain.
Within these constraints, the analysis of the brain Emotional concepts can be tied to specific brain mecha-
mechanisms mediating emotions becomes a more man- nisms through a variety of maneuvers. The idea that
ageable undertaking. Only certain neural circuits begin emotions simply arouse (Duffy 1941) served as a theoreti-
to fulfill the definitional requirements of emotive sys- cal basis for proposing that the ascending reticular activat-
tems, and many of the fuzzier dimensions of affective life ing system is a physiological substrate for emotion
can be temporarily excluded from consideration. (Lindsley 1950). The fact that localized stimulation of the

412 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
limbic system could induce both positive and negative discrete behaviors that can be observed during such
affective states, as indicated by species-typical approach stimulation appears to be greater than the number of
and escape behaviors, suggested that emotions and rein- discrete command systems actually present under the
forcements are intrinsically organized by dichotomous stimulating electrodes. Of course, this is reasonable if one
affective circuits of the brain (Glickman & Schiff 1967). considers that the function of such executive systems may
Although the most illuminating results, with regard to be to facilitate simultaneously a number of related behav-
how emotions are organized in the nervous system, have ioral options so that reinforcement processes can mold
been obtained using localized electrical stimulation of adaptive behavior sequences for a variety of related life
brain tissue with indwelling electrodes in awake animals circumstances (Figure 1), which differ in detail.
(Hess 1957), I believe the evidence supports the exis- In any event, this discrepancy poses great problems for
tence of a more highly articulated emotive "phrenology" accurate categorization, as is apparent in recent contro-
in the limbic system than has been postulated before. versies over the nature of the circuits which mediate
It is astounding that the simple application of electrical "stimulus-bound" appetitive behaviors in the hypo-
"noise" to certain brain areas can yield a variety of well- thalamus. For instance, from a relatively diffuse zone
coordinated species-typical behavior sequences, most centered around the dorsolateral hypothalamus of the rat,
notably ones which appear to reflect emotional states. By we can evoke feeding, drinking, gnawing, hoarding, pup
stimulating specific areas in the hypothalamus, we can retrieving, predatory aggression, and copulation. Are
induce animals to exhibit ragelike behaviors, explorato- there discrete circuits under our electrodes for each of
ry-investigative behaviors, flight, and several other be- these behavioral acts (the specificity hypothesis), or are
havior patterns indicative of complex neuropsychological they all induced by a unitary neural influence (the non-
integration. The waveform of the electricity applied to specificity hypothesis)? Without going into details, which
the brain tissue does not seem to be orchestrating the can be found elsewhere (Panksepp 1981a), current evi-
actual sequences of the artificially elicited behavior. The dence overwhelmingly supports the nonspecificity hy-
simplest explanation for these remarkable effects is that pothesis for such stimulus-bound appetitive behaviors.
we are stimulating neural networks that can facilitate Aside from the basic demonstration of behavioral mal-
(command) activity in distant sensory filtering systems leability after lateral hypothalamic stimulation (i.e., one
and motor patterning circuits governing the sequencing appetitive behavior can be changed to another through
of emotive acts. experience: Valenstein et al. 1970), the most important
The activation of these systems not only induces emo- evidence supporting such a conclusion is: (1) "Stim-
tional behaviors and concurrent visceral and hormonal ulus-bound" appetitive behaviors do not change when an
changes (Mancia & Zanchetti 1981), but it also sensitizes electrode is passed through the relevant lateral hypothal-
sensoryfieldson the body surfaces. In cats, hypothalamic amic field of a single animal (Wise 1971). (2) The type of
stimulation yielding attack, increases perioral biting re- behavior elicited from an electrode does not change when
flexes, the probability that touch to the arm will induce the tissue under the electrode is damaged; instead, the
lashing out, and aggressive responsivity of the con- threshold for elicitation of the behavior is increased
tralateral eye (Flynn 1976). In rats, hypothalamic stimula- (Bachus & Valenstein 1979). (3) The temperament of the
tion that induces stimulus-bound appetitive behaviors test animal may be more important in determining the
can increase perioral (Smith 1972) and visual (Beagley & stimulus-bound appetitive behavior observed than the
Holley 1977) sensitivity, and damage to these systems is exact location of the stimulating electrode in the active
accompanied by sensory-motor neglect (Balagura, zone within the dorsolateral hypothalamus (e.g., stim-
Wilcox, & Coscina 1969; Frigyesi, Ige, Iulo, & Schwartz ulus-bound predatory attack in rats is most easily ob-
1971; Marshall & Teitelbaum 1974). Also, even though tained in animals that exhibit some tendency to spon-
the most spectacular kinds of stimulus-bound behavior taneously emit this behavior: Panksepp 1971a).
are strictly limited to the duration of brain stimulation, Still, this is not to suggest that several distinct emotive
more subtle behavioral changes persist for a while. For circuits do not course through the lateral hypothalamic
instance, Hess (1957) and Nakao (1958) detected affective field where stimulus-bound behaviors are most fre-
changes in their cats for minutes following hypothalamic quently encountered, for there appear to be several
stimulation. Similarly, the increased motor activity in- distinct classes of behavior that can be activated (Figure
duced by stimulation of lateral hypothalamic reward sites 2). Also, the present conception of nonspecificity does not
decays gradually during the minute following stimulation imply that the functions of the underlying circuits are not
(Rolls & Kelly 1972). The general functions of these genetically determined. Although each emotive circuit
circuits appear to be genetically coded (Roberts & Ber- may be nonspecific in the sense that it can provoke
quist 1968), although the exact behavioral expressions of several distinct emotive actions, they may all be specific
each system may be quite malleable (Valenstein, Cox, & (hard-wired), in the sense that each generates a single,
Kakolewski 1970). homogeneous psychobehavioral tendency (Figures 1 and
This paper is based on the assumption that these 2). Presumably, an analysis of these partially interdigitat-
ing, transhypothalamic emotive command circuits pres-
"stimulus-bound" behaviors reflect species-typical ex-
ently provides the best foundation for neurophysiological
pressions of class-typical brain circuits which mediate understanding of emotions in both animals and humans.
emotions, and, hence, that a realistic and scientifically To some investigators in the field this may be self-
useful taxonomy of emotions, in humans as well as other evident, but the scarcity of neuro-psycho-behavioral
mammals, could be based upon the number of distinct investigations based on this assumption suggests that it
behavioral control systems that can be activated in this has not yet been widely accepted.
manner. However, difficulties arise in enumerating the
number of emotive command systems, for the number of Herein I propose four fundamental transdiencephalic

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 413


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

emotion-mediating circuits passing between midbrain, major label for this system, because it is assumed that the
limbic system, and basal ganglia of the mammalian brain. circuit readily comes under the conditional control of
Based on the extreme emotional experiences that these environmental cues and is thereby essential for elaborat-
systems are presumed to mediate in humans, they are ing anticipatory appetitive behaviors. Accordingly,
labeled the "expectancy," "rage," "fear," and "panic" throughout this paper expectancy is intended only in the
circuits. Their specific neuronal projections and interac- positive sense, as hope, desire - joyful anticipation,
tions can only be surmised, but from localized rather than in the negative sense in which it can also be
brain-stimulation studies we do know the approximate used.
locations of these circuits in the several species. Although
sites have been identified in diverse areas of the brain, at Fear. It is proposed that sites in the hypothalamus from
present the hypothalamus is the best site in which to which flight and unconditional escape behaviors can be
pursue systematic study of the properties of these cir- elicited represent the trajectory of fear circuitry, the
cuits. Such executive circuits (Figure 3) are likely to be major adaptive function of which is to respond to all
activated by sensory information concerning various external stimuli that have the potential of harming or
classes of environmental events (Figure 1), as well as hurting the body.
stimuli arising from internal states (autonomic reafferents
and homeostatic states of the body). Once activated, Rage. It is proposed that sites from which angry emo-
these circuits arouse and organize related arrays of soma- tional displays and affective attack can be elicited repre-
tic (Figure 2), hormonal, and visceral sensory-motor sent the location of a rage circuit, the major adaptive
processes. This paper will focus on the psychobehavioral function of which is to invigorate behavior when activity
attributes of these circuits. in the expectancy circuit diminishes rapidly as well as
when the body is irritated or uncomfortably restrained.
Expectancy. It is proposed that through the medial fore-
brain bundle of the lateral hypothalamus passes a gener- Panic. It is proposed that sites from which distress vocal-
alized "foraging-expectancy" circuit, which is sensitized izations and explosive agitated behavior can be elicited
by major homeostatic imbalances in the body and their represent the approximate trajectories of panic circuitry,
respective environmental incentives. The major adaptive the major adaptive function of which is to sustain social
function of this circuit is to produce a specific type of cohesion among organisms whose survival depends on
motor arousal - characterized by exploratory and investi- reciprocity of care-soliciting and care-giving behaviors.
gative (i.e., foraging) activities - which induces an animal The approximate hypothalamic locations of these cir-
to move from where it is to where it should be in order to cuits are depicted in the hemifrontal sections through a
consume the substances needed for survival. In artificial rat hypothalamus in Figure 2. It is assumed that these
experimental situations, this circuit can also mediate a four life-challenges (Figure 1) are archetypal, and that
highly energized form of electrical self-stimulation of the the evolution of such extensive systems in the brain was
brain. The term expectancy has been selected as the dictated by the adaptive advantage of rapidly acting

Figure 3. A simplified schematic of the trajectory of a transdiencephalic emotive command system on a parasaggital view of a rat
brain. The system collects various type of processed sensory information along its trajectory; for instance: (1) perceptual influences
from temporal and frontal lobes and various basal ganglia; (2) somatosensory inputs from the thalamus; (3) homeostatic inputs from
body-state detectors in the hypothalamus; (4) decoded olfactory, vomeronasal, and other perceptual inputs from midline thalamic
nuclei; and (5) simple sensory controls such as those arising from taste, touch, sound, and pain from lower brainstem levels. The
system is conceived as elaborating motor control by ascending influences (e.g., behavior sequencing mechanisms of basal ganglia) as
well as by descending control of emotion-appropriate autonomic and somatic reflex control circuits (6).

414 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
command circuits, which could simultaneously recruit used to derive biological significance for such traditional
multiple body systems to meet major environmental behavioral concepts as reward and reinforcement, as well
emergencies. as for psychological states such as pleasure (see Panksepp,
The command-system construct has been much used 1981a, for review of the literature), the highly energized
in the analysis of stereotyped motor patterns in inverte- behavior of an animal electrically stimulating its own
brates, although it remains surrounded by many contro- lateral hypothalamus has remained enigmatic from such
versies (Kupfermann & Weiss 1978). The analogous na- perspectives. Although there may be considerable diver-
ture of "stimulus-bound" behaviors evoked by sity in the response topographies that individual animals
hypothalamic stimulation suggests that this principle can exhibit during self-stimulation (perhaps partially because
guide investigation of certain brain systems in mammals. of overlap with other emotional command systems), most
Although the neural trajectories and the exact functions of animals move forward, sniff intensely, and interact with
these circuits have yet to be mapped accurately, I shall many objects in the environment, especially those ob-
attempt to summarize existing knowledge of these puta- jects with strong intrinsic connections with the activated
tive emotive command systems. This review is highly circuits (e.g, odors). The invigorated explorato-
selective and emphasizes only materials most influential ry-investigative activity of such animals is just what
in my own thinking. A more comprehensive coverage of would be expected if a nonspecific circuit specialized for
past work related to many of these issues, can be found in the generation of incentive-directed (foraging) behavior
Panksepp (1981a). were activated. On a priori grounds, it would be advan-
tageous for activity in such a circuit to be amplified by
The "expectancy" command system. A unified executive internal need states as well as in response to positive
sensory-motor system for the mediation of explora- incentives, until contact with an appropriate consumma-
tion-approach-investigation (i.e., foraging) is proposed tory object was achieved and until internal homeostatic
to be isomorphic with neural circuits mediating electrical detectors provided satiety and inhibition of further
self-stimulation of the lateral hypothalamus (LH). In rats, foraging.
LH self-stimulation is characterized by increased forward Many of the unusual behavioral characteristics that can
locomotion with persistent sniffing, exploration, and ma- be obtained by stimulating this emotive system (e.g., the
nipulation of prominent objects in the environment unusual motivational characteristics discussed by Trowill
(Christopher & Butter 1968). Activity in this circuit may et al., 1969, and the behavioral "plasticity" described by
mediate the incentive attributes of rewards (Trowill, Valenstein et al., 1970) can be explained by the way in
Panksepp, & Gandelman 1969), and it is now known that which normal control gates in the circuit are superseded.
its cell are highly responsive to both external incentives Artificial activation of the circuit could override normal
and internal homeostatic imbalances (Oomura 1980; input signals, such as the inhibition that may arise di-
Panksepp 1981a; Rolls 1980). It is apparent that activity in rectly from consummatory acts as well as those arising
this circuit promotes an animal's capacity to seek out from replenishment of body needs. This would not only
biologically important stimuli in the environment, in part make stimulus-bound appetitive behavior more agitated
by invigorating motor behavior (Wayner, Barone, & than that normally seen in animals (i.e, foraging arousal
Loullis 1981) and also by modifying sensory acuity being sustained during reward consummation), but due
(Gellhorn, Koella, & Ballin 1955; Marshall 1979; Smith to the absence of accruing negative feedback signals,
1972). A fundamental requirement for survival is that an there would be a relative absence of satiation during self-
animal move from where it is to where life-sustaining stimulation of the circuit. Also, since the underlying
objects are located. Lateral hypothalamic stimulation system is nonspecific - subserving a general behavioral
potentiates the requisite behavioral tendencies in all function, which can be accessed by various positive en-
vertebrates studied, suggesting that a primitive executive vironmental incentives as well as by homeostatic need
system designed to trigger foraging activities courses detectors - enforced activation of this system could lead
through the forebrain bundles of the ventral dien- to a variety of specific stimulus—bound consummatory
cephalon. Although the behavioral expressions of arousal behaviors. These would be interchangeable, depending
not only on the availability of goal-objects but also on
in this circuit, such as genus-typical consummatory ac-
each animal's past foraging history. Furthermore, since
tivities (including feeding, drinking, gnawing, object car- the stimulation evokes a generalized emotive state, which
rying, hoarding, predatory aggression, and copulatory is artificially uncoupled from homeostatic inputs, the
behavior), may vary substantially across genera, the com- specific stimulus-bound behaviors observed during ar-
mand structure appears to have been comparatively re- tificial activation of the circuit could develop characteris-
sistant to evolutionary modification; this persistance sug- tics that are independent of momentary physiological
gests that an effective solution for coordinating bodily needs.
activities in response to archetypal survival needs was
sustained, functionally intact, during the diversification Expectancy was selected as a label for this neuronal
of vertebrate species into different ecological niches. network to emphasize the fact that this system mediates
However, the variety of genus-typical expressions of anticipatory appetitive behaviors and, presumably, the
activity in this system could explain the relative ease or corresponding subjective state in humans. In animals,
difficulty with which self-stimulation has been observed the activity of this system comes spontaneously under the
in various species - it being readily obtained in rats conditional control of correlated environmental cues
(because they exhibit energetic foraging) but not so read- (Clarke & Trowill 1971; Olds 1975; Rolls 1980). Lateral
ily in cats (because they exhibit a more restrained form of hypothalamic cells of rats fire with increasing frequency
stalking). when the animal is approaching food; they slow down
Although the phenomenon of self-stimulation has been dramatically when the animal starts to eat, but promptly

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 415


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
resume rapid activity when its food is taken away (Ham- stances, rendering untenable the conclusion that this
burg 1971). Moreover, anticipatory enhancement of circuit simply triggers vacuous emotional displays.
motor activity induced by signals predicting food is Hypothalamic stimulation that generates affective at-
markedly attenuated by lateral hypothalamic lesions tack has been found to be aversive in cats (Nakao 1958),
(Campbell & Baez 1974). monkeys (Plotnick, Mir, & Delgado 1971), and rats
The postulated existence of a discrete circuit, designed (Panksepp 1971a). However, this circuit overlaps sub-
to energize appetitive foraging behaviors, readily ex- stantially with expectancy systems. Thus, both stim-
plains most of the behavioral changes that have been ulus-bound "affective" attack and agitated self-stimula-
observed following manipulations of the lateral hypo- tion (characterized by vigorous biting of the
thalamus and suggests a variety of behavioral and neu- manipulandum) can be obtained from hypothalamic
rophysiological hypotheses. At a behavioral level, manip- zones in which these systems presumably intermingle.
ulation of the system should generally modify the capacity Circuit overlap appears to be especially dense in tissue
of an organism to seek out biologically important stimuli just ventrolateral to the fornix columns, with the active
in its environment; and changes in the cellular activities field for rage extending ventrally and medially and the
of the system during appetitive tasks (e.g., Hamburg most sensitivefieldfor self-stimulation extending dorsally
1971) should generalize across different positive rewards. and laterally (Panksepp 1971a).
Perhaps the most objective physiological-behavioral in- Such mingling may complicate the dissection of under-
dicator of the state of this system in rats and other species lying circuitries, but it also points to the probable interac-
in which olfaction predominates would be the level of tion of these systems in the control of behavior. Adaptive
sniffing, not only during spontaneous exploration, but as considerations suggest that rage and expectancy circuits
correlated with environmental cues that predict environ- should strongly inhibit each other. A high level of forag-
mental rewards (Clarke, Panksepp, & Trowill 1971; ing and anticipation should dampen aggressive impulses,
Clarke & Trowill 1972). Indeed, for the past decade we whereas anger, and the resulting increased vigor of be-
have routinely identified lateral hypothalamic self-stim- havior, should be intensified when expected rewards are
ulation sites in anesthetized animals during surgery by not forthcoming. Thus, the increased responding ob-
monitoring sniffing evoked by electrical stimulation of
served at the beginning of extinction (i.e., the "frustra-
hypothalamic tissues. This measure could be used as a
straightforward behavioral assay for tapping the momen- tion effect") may be due to a release of the rage circuit,
tary state of the "foraging-expectancy" system. and selective damage to that circuit should reduce the
effect. Electrical stimulation applied to zones of overlap
This conception does not preclude the possibility that in these circuits may yield other unusual behavioral
specific neuronal circuits for the various motivational symptoms, for, typically, the two systems should not be
states (e.g., thirst, hunger, salt appetite, sexual behavior) active concurrently. For instance, self-stimulation at
exist in the hypothalamus. Homeostatic receptor systems these sites may be sensitive to stimulus duration, with
appear to exist in medial strata of the hypothalamus; these animals exhibiting vigorous responding for short pulse
systems presumably modulate activity in the generalized
durations and poor self-stimulation for long durations.
foraging system of the lateral hypothalamus and probably
have drive-specific interconnections to brain circuits Also, such animals may exhibit vigorous biting of the
which control consummatory acts (for a review, see Pank- manipulandum during self-stimulation.
sepp, 1981a). The most objective and easily quantified behavioral
indicators of activity in the rage system are vocal displays,
such as growling (Jiirgens & Ploog 1970), hissing, and the
The "rage" command system. The first hypothalamic potentiation of striking and biting behaviors (Flynn, Ed-
emotive system to be discovered was the one mediating wards, & Bandler 1971). This last measure has yielded
rage (Hess 1932; Ranson 1934), although the idea that this data that are highly consistent with the proposed reci-
system elaborated a true emotional state was not accepted procity of the rage and expectancy systems. Both the
by all (Masserman 1941). It is now clear that, even though activation of hypothalamic attack sites and the deactiva-
occasional electrode sites are encountered, which may tion of self-stimulation sites induce biting (Hutchinson &
generate affective displays apparently void of true emo- Renfrew 1978). Accordingly, with the use of such mea-
tional content, most electrodes placed in this circuit sures (summarized in Figure 2), clear predictions can be
generate an "affective" attack, which is well integrated made concerning the interactions that should be ob-
with environmental events (Nakao 1958). Indeed, in served during concurrent activation of "pure sites" within
monkeys, hypothalamically elicited aggression is di- these systems.
rected along dominance lines established prior to stim- Few investigations have sought to evaluate the effect
ulation. Robinson, Alexander, and Browne (1969) report on naturally occurring aggression of precise surgical
that submissive animals direct their attacks primarily damage to the rage command system at the hypothalamic
toward dominant ones, even to the point where stable level. This omission may be due, in part, to the fact that
dominance reversals are established. Delgado (1969) and lateral hypothalamic lesions precipitate a severe gener-
Alexander and Perachio (1973) have also found stim- alized amotivational syndrome (Ranson 1939; Strieker &
ulus-bound aggression to be guided by preexisting social Zigmond 1976), which makes it difficult to interpret
rank, but they observed attack to be directed most fre- experiments with large LH lesions (e.g., Karli & Vergnes
quently toward submissive animals. In general, most 1964; Panksepp 1971c). Still, no thorough investigation
recent studies indicate that artificial activation of the has been conducted that has behaviorally verified the
hypothalamic rage circuit precipitates aggression, which placement of electrodes before making of lesions; from a
is well integrated with an animal's normal life circum- command-system perspective, such a verification seems

416 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
essential for deriving meaningful conclusions from lesion the hypothalamus has been recognized since Hess's pi-
work. oneering work, the fact that this behavior has not been
Although the rage command system is viewed as the extensively used to analyze the brain organization of fear
substrate for affective attack, diverse forms of aggression (and, hence, anxiety) suggests that it has not generally
can be distinguished in terms of their eliciting conditions been regarded as reflecting a true emotional state, but
(Moyer 1976). Presumably many of these stimuli con- rather only as a motor patterning mechanism. Such an
verge upon a common executive system, although certain interpretation has probably been reinforced by the many
forms of aggression, such as predation, need not arise failures to condition avoidance behaviors with hypothala-
from the activity of this system. The hypothalamic circuit- mically elicited flight as the unconditioned stimulus (e.g.,
ry mediating these behaviors has been distinguished Bower & Miller 1958; Roberts 1958; Wada & Matsuda
anatomically (Flynn 1976) and affectively (Panksepp 1970). But such conditioned avoidance has been obtained
1971a). Indeed, from the present perspective, quiet- by others (Delgado, Roberts, & Miller 1954; Nakao 1958),
biting attack forms of predatory aggression are considered and it may be essential to have "pure" fear sites, or
to be expressions of the foraging-expectancy system, or perhaps some concurrent stimulation of pain inputs, to
perhaps a mixture of activity in several systems. Similar- obtain efficient avoidance behavior. This may explain
ly, defensive aggression may be a mixture of concurrent why flight behavior obtained from the periventricular
activity in the fear and rage systems (Panksepp 1979a). gray has proved more readily conditionable (Wada, Mat-
suda, Jung, & Hamm 1970).
The "fear" command system. In comparison to lateral Even though "anxiety has been considered the alpha
hypothalamic expectancy and rage systems, the proper- and omega of psychiatry" (Delgado 1969, p. 131), hypo-
ties of circuits that mediate escape and flight behaviors thalamically elicited flight remains to be used as a general
(i.e., the fear emotive system) are poorly understood. model for analyzing neural substrates of anxiety. Nor has
Although the feeling of anxiety has been precipitated in any substantial attempt been made yet to analyze the role
humans by stimulation of several brain areas, especially of this neural system in the elaboration of natural avoid-
in the temporal lobe (Chapman 1958; Heath, Monroe, & ance and conditioned emotional responses. If such a
Mickle 1955; Jasper & Rasmussen 1958), the most ex- command system plays a cardinal role in the elaboration
pressive displays of fear in rats are observed during of fear, it is to be expected that selective damage to the
stimulation of the anteroventral hypothalamus (Panksepp circuit (as might be obtained with the use of behaviorally
1971a). Anxiety is also precipitated by electrical stimula- verified electrode placements) would markedly attenuate
tion of this zone in humans (Grinker & Serota 1938; the development of conditioned fear, as well as those
Monroe & Heath 1954). unconditional fear responses that are initiated by percep-
Hypothalamic sites that provoke flight surround the tual inputs rostral to the level of brain damage. There is
core system for which rage (threat behavior) is elicited (de substantial evidence that deficits in the elaboration of fear
Molina & Hunsperger 1962), and there appears to be result from damage to ascending projections of this sys-
substantial anatomical overlap and functional interaction tem in the amygdala (Kliiver & Bucy 1937; Ursin 1965).
between these systems. Accordingly, many of the behav-
ioral patterns elicited from this area are characterized by a The "panic" command system. This may be the most
mixture of flight and threat (i.e., defensive behavior). controversial of the emotive systems to be proposed in
Although stimulation of the intermediate zones typically this paper. It is not typically found among the traditional
elicits flight, defensive attack often ensues, if no avenue of lists of emotional responses attributed to the visceral
escape is available. Concurrent activation of the two brain via brain stimulation techniques. However, Cogan
systems with independently placed electrodes can yield (1802) and many others have entertained the idea that
synergistic effects, with either threat or flight being sorrow may be a fundamental emotion (Table 1), and, in
intensified (Hunsperger, Brown, & Rosvold 1964). the present context, sorrow (defined as the diminutive
The affective state elicited by stimulation of sites pro- form of panic, in the same manner that anxiety may be a
ducing flight is aversive, even though self-stimulation can diminutive form of fear, and anger a diminutive form of
also be obtained from some sites. However, self-stimula- rage) appears to reflect activity in a basic emotive system
tion behavior obtained from such electrodes is accom- of the brain. Our past work on separation-induced dis-
panied by flight responses (Panksepp 1971a). In rats, such tress in various species has been premised on the exis-
self-stimulation is characterized by crescendos of lever tence of such an emotion. The characteristic and univer-
pressing interspersed with frequent running away from sal emotional consequence of socially isolating young
the lever and energetic leaps upward. animals is protest, especially as reflected in the objective
Because the simple behavioral measure of aversion behavior of crying. This response appears to be mediated
does not readily discriminate between several trans- by an innate brain system that is attuned to the presence
hypothalamic emotive systems, the best indicator vari- and absence of social stimuli.
ables for the state of the fear system may be derived from Our work in this area (summarized in Panksepp, Her-
the response topographies of species-typical flight re- man, Vilberg, Bishop, & DeEskinazi 1980; Panksepp
sponses. In the rat, one highly characteristic response 1981b) affirms that similarities exist between the underly-
elaborated by this system is an upward leap. At anterior ing neurochemical dynamics of opiate addiction and of
lateral hypothalamic sites, this response is so systematic social dependence. This suggests that some of the neural
that it can be used quantitatively with repeated brief processes of this emotive system may involve brain
stimulations (Panksepp 1971b). opioids; this has been confirmed by brain stimulation
Although the existence of flight patterns elicited from studies (Herman 1979;.Herman & Panksepp 1981). Dis-

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 417


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

tress vocalizations in guinea pigs can be elicited by evoked from the hypothalamus (e.g., Berntson 1972).
stimulating many opioid-rich sites, including the dor- Although the details of the underlying systems remain
somedial thalamus, ventral septal, and preoptic areas, to be determined, these putative command systems
and less dense zones in the amygdala and medial hypo- probably run from the mesencepahlon, through the re-
thalamus. However, these vocalizations follow the termi- ticular fields of the hypothalamus and, perhaps,
nation of brain stimulation, and therefore may not clearly thalamus, to basal ganglia and higher limbic areas (Figure
indicate the localization of the command circuit for this 3). Each command system probably emits ascending and
emotive system. Stimulus-bound distress calls have descending controls throughout its trajectory, not only to
been elicited in the vicinity of the central gray, suggesting interconnect with other behavior control circuits and to
that the executive system for this emotional state inter- bias sensory and motor processes, but also to coordinate
mingles with the other emotive systems at the level of the the activity of each system with homeostatic and autono-
medial mesencephalon. mic states of the body. Thus the trajectory of emotive
Although rats do not exhibit marked separation-in- command circuits through the hypothalamus may repre-
duced crying, stimulation of the anterior basal hypoth- sent a design feature that permits diverse bodily states to
alamus yields a stimulus—bound aversive response, be brought in line rapidly with behavioral demands.
which seems distinct from fear- and rage-related behav- Some of the above issues are highlighted in the sche-
iors. This response consists of a freezing reaction, accom- matized command network in Figure 3. Were this to
panied by apparently strong negative affect, which culmi- represent the command system for panic, it would be
nates suddenly in explosive behavior, during which the activated normally by social separation. It might bias
animal exhibits violent leaping about the test chamber ascending sensory projection areas in the cortex, tuning
(Panksepp 1971a). Unlike stimulus-bound flight, this certain systems to be especially sensitive to social stimuli;
behavioral response typically habituates rapidly, and, it might activate behavior sequencing mechanisms in the
with closely spaced trials, ever-increasing current levels basal ganglia specialized to generate discrete social sig-
are needed to reelicit the explosive component of the nals (e.g., MacLean 1981); it might establish hypoth-
behavior sequence. These behaviors may be homologous alamo-pituitary balances to increase ability to cope bet-
to the emotional disturbance known as "panic" attacks ter with stress; and perhaps, via descending influences, it
(Klein 1981), and this response may thereby indicate the might bias specific somatic motor tendencies, such as
hypothalamic location of the emotive command system increased agitation, distress vocalization, and the sensi-
that is attuned to social loss. It is noteworthy that similar tization of other care-soliciting behavior patterns. At the
explosive behavior patterns occur in addicted animals same time, overall autonomic balance may be shifted
during opiate withdrawal. toward parasympathetic dominance so as to conserve
Although activity of the panic system may be reflected bodily energy resources. The command system itself
in a variety of agitated behavioral patterns, separation- would be modulated by various sensory inputs along its
induced distress vocalization is currently the best indica- trajectory as illustrated in Figure 3. Since the system can
tor of arousal in this system. The activity of this emotive be accessed at various levels of the neuroaxis, learned as
system should also be expressed in the tendency of well as unconditional influences could modulate the ac-
animals to exhibit social cohesion, and decreased gregari- tivity of the command circuit at diverse points along the
ousness has been observed in rats following ventromedial trajectory of the system. Conceptualizing emotive cir-
and anterolateral hypothalamic lesions (Enloe 1975). Fur- cuits in this way would permit many rudiments of goal-
ther analysis of social cohesion and separation distress directed emotive behaviors to remain operational even
after damage to the various brain areas where stim- after substantial damage to both limbic forebrain and
ulus-bound crying and explosive behaviors can be elic- hypothalamic tissues (e.g., Ellison & Flynn 1968; Huston
ited will be needed to clarify the behavioral characteris- & Borbely 1974).
tics of this emotive system.
Neurochemistry of the emotive command sys-
tems. Whether the various emotive control systems mod-
Properties of emotive systems ulate the activities of output circuits via single- or multi-
ple-command transmitters remains unknown. From
Anatomy of the emotive systems of the visceral available evidence, dopamine and acetylcholine are rea-
brain. The actual neuronal trajectories of the proposed sonable candidates as key transmitters in the expectancy
emotive systems can only be sketched in broad outline. and rage systems respectively.
Although it is clear that lateral hypothalamic neuropil The catecholamine hypothesis of self-stimulation re-
contains widely ramifying, long-axoned systems, both ward has received substantial support (for reviews, see
ascending and descending, with multiple interneuronal German & Bowden 1974; Stein 1978; Wise 1978), and
feedback loops (Millhouse 1979; Palkovits & Zaborszky both norepinephrine and dopamine facilitate self-stim-
1979), our knowledge of functional circuits in such a ulation at various sites in the lateral hypothalamus as
reticular substance remains too imperfect to attempt determined by pharmacologic studies (e.g., Herberg,
filling in the details of system connectivities. The gross Stephens, & Franklin 1976; Phillips & Fibiger 1973;
anatomy of some systems can be surmised from anatomi- Zolovick, Rossi, Davies, & Panksepp 1982), even though
cal studies of self-stimulation and stimulus-bound appe- recent anatomical studies do not support the importance
titive (e.g., Gallistel, Karreman, &Reivich 1977; Roberts of norepinephrine in the self-stimulation phenomenon
1980; Routtenberg & Malsbury 1969; Wise 1978) and (e.g., Clavier, Fibiger, & Phillips 1976; Corbett & Wise
attack behaviors (Siegel & Edinger 1981) as well as from 1979). Stimulus-bound object-carrying (foraging)
studies analyzing the effect of brain lesions on behaviors evoked from the lateral hypothalamus is reduced follow-

418 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
ing destruction of dopamine systems (Phillips 1975), and
pharmacological facilitation of brain dopamine activity
with d-amphetamine invigorates exploratory activities,
including forward locomotion and sniffing. A command
function for dopamine systems seems apt, because selec-
tive receptor agonists applied to the striatum can restore
behavioral competence in animals whose ascending DA
systems have been damaged (Marshall, Berrios, &
Sawyer 1980). This suggests that the system works as a
permissive response-biasing mechanism rather than as a
precise information-transfer system.
Acetylcholine may subserve a command function in the
rage system, since applying cholinomimetics into the
hypothalamus and amygdala can provoke rage responses
(Baxter 1968; MacPhail & Miller 1968; Myers 1964). The
observation that cholinergic agonists decrease self-stim-
ulation (Stark & Boyd 1963), whereas anticholinergics
increase such behavior (Pradhan & Kamat 1973) is con-
sistent with the proposed reciprocal inhibitory relations
between the expectancy and rage systems (Figure 2).
Additional evidence for such an interaction is provided by
the tendency of catecholamine depletion in the brain to
make animals irritable (Coscina, Seggie, Godse, &
Stancer 1973; Eichelman, Thoa, & Ng 1972; Nakamura &
Thoenen 1972). Furthermore, a reciprocal action of these
neurochemical systems is apparent in the nigrostria-
tal-striatonigral neuronal loop where dopamine appears
to inhibit acetylcholine cells, and acetylcholine, through
a GABA interneuron, inhibits dopamine cells (see Carls-
son 1965; Groves, Wilson, Young, & Rebec 1975; Iversen
1978; Pradhan & Bose 1978).
Command transmitter candidates for panic and fear
systems remain more elusive, but major inhibitory influ-
ences on these emotive systems may arise via the ben-
zodiazepine receptor (Braestrup & Squires 1977) and Figure 4. Biogenic amines that are widely dispersed through-
endorphin systems (see Panksepp et al., 1980, for re- out the brain may provide nonspecific excitatory and inhibitory
view). Further investigation of the various peptide net- control over emotive command circuits. The frontal sections
works of the limbic-enteric nervous system may reveal depict approximate locations of brain serotonin (5-HT) and
command transmitters for these circuits. norepinephrine (NE) systems at the mid-hypothalamic level as
If emotive systems have strong reciprocal interactions determined by autoradiographic localization of (14C), 5-HT,
with each other, a broad range of specificity in neu- and NE uptakes in the mouse brain. (Photomicrographs accord-
rochemical controls can be expected, ranging from non- ing to Masuoka and Alcaraz, 1975, reprinted by permission).
specific modulatory controls to quite precise coding with-
in a single emotive pathway. It appears that the major
brain amines, serotonin and norepinephrine, exert non- behavioral functions (for review, see Panksepp, 1981b).
specific modulatory control over these circuits (Figure 4). Still, it may eventually be possible to extract functional
Facilitation of brain serotonin activity typically reduces subsystems from such transmitter thickets by the use of
all waking activities, whereas decreases in serotonin ac- new approaches such as "subtractive autoradiography"
tivity can increase many motivated behaviors (see Pan- (Panksepp & Bishop 1981).
ksepp, 1981a, for review). Modulation of brain nor-
epinephrine generally has opposite effects, even though Interactions among emotive systems. The limitless vari-
the evidence is not so clear-cut as for serotonin, especially ety of human emotional experience no doubt beggars
with respect to the fear and panic systems. No doubt detailed description. Yet the rich tapestry of human
there are exceptions to this generalization, but the classic emotion may arise largely from interactions among primi-
idea that these amines provide nonspecific inhibitory and tive emotive systems. For instance, emotions that Cogan
excitatory control over behavior (Brodie & Shore 1957) (1802) included in his Class II are likely to be socially
remains generally consistent with existing evidence. Sim- learned interblendings of the basic emotions of Class I
ilarly, it is to be anticipated that most of the other putative (Table 1), yielding impressive subtleties of human feel-
transmitters that have been identified have multiple ing. The emotion of jealousy may arise from some admix-
functions, and this overlapping may preclude identifica- ture of panic, rage, and expectancy. Resentment may
tion of functional systems by the simple analysis of overall result from a blend of activities in the rage, fear, and
neurochemical geographies in the brain. For instance,
expectancy systems. Joy may be the fulfillment of expec-
brain opiate receptor systems are widespread, and pres-
ently the endorphins are being implicated in a host of tancies, and so on with other affective alchemy. How
complex emotions may arise from the intermixtures of

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 419


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
more fundamental elements has received considerable emotive systems, leading to temporary disinhibition of
attention in literature on humans (e.g., Izard 1972; Plu- reinforcement-programming networks, which establish
tchik 1980). hierarchies among the behavior patterns just evoked by
Although experimental work testing such speculations activity in the command network; this process could
remains to be initiated, the phenomenological richness concurrently tag salient neutral stimuli present in a situa-
that may arise from blended activities of primitive emo- tion with biological values. From this perspective, the
tive systems could provide useful clues and hypotheses analysis of many types of learning may have to be based on
concerning neural interactions that transpire among the an understanding of emotive circuits of the brain, and
emotive circuits of the brain. For instance, it seems to be there should be considerable emotive state-dependence
universal human experience that positive expectations for retrieval of memories, a phenomenon recently docu-
and anger are psychologically incompatible states. From mented in humans (Bower 1981).
this, one might deduce that two hypothalamic cells, In light of recent trends toward rejection of reinforce-
electrophysiologically identified to belong to these two ment mechanisms in the genesis of learned behavior
emotive systems, would exhibit reciprocal inhibition. (Bindra 1978), the existence of emotive circuits might
Similar predictions might be generated for other system restore vitality to traditional stimulus-response (S-R) and
interactions (some personal opinions are summarized in stimulus-stimulus learning theories. The command sys-
Figure 2), but such work should be preceded by system- tem conception readily solves the "response-equiv-
atic empirical analysis of interactions that occur among alence problem" that has plagued traditional S-R rein-
emotional states in thoughtful human observers. forcement learning theory. Also, it can easily handle
many of the striking characteristics of animal learning that
Learning, reinforcement, and transhypothalamic emotive have been revealed in recent years, for instance, auto-
systems. Although stimulation of hypothalamic emotive shaping, which may be conditioned foraging, and pre-
systems can be reinforcing or punishing, as defined by the paredness, which may reflect the intrinsic inputs and
"law of effect," this fact provides no information concern- outputs of emotive systems.
ing either the nature of reinforcement or the underlying Still, there will surely be many complexities to be faced
learning that can be elaborated by these systems. Pre- when one views the activity of these systems in the
sumably, much of learning is based on the capacity of life-span of the organism. Through learning, the degree
affectively neutral stimuli (i.e., those which have weak to which emotions emerge directly from activities of
unconditional interactions with emotive command cir- emotive command systems could change. Although
cuits) to obtain increasing influence over emotive cir- transhypothalamic emotive command circuits may be
cuits. The likelihood that learning ability is an intrinsic essential for emotions to become manifest in the develop-
circuit property of emotive systems has been strikingly ing organism, higher brain areas may assimilate some
confirmed for the expectancy system. LH-stimulation-
elicited sniffing comes to be spontaneously linked to
predictive cues of the environment [for a theoretical
summary of the work of Clarke and colleagues (Clarke
1971; Clarke, Panksepp & Trowill 1970; Clarke & Trowill
1971) in this area, see Panksepp 1981a].
A MANIA
SCHIZOPHRENIA
(PARANOID)

Although there may be many types of learning (ranging


from habituation to "cognitive" mapping), for didactic
purposes, only one type will be considered here: cue
learning (whereby an emotive circuit comes under the
conditional control of previously neutral stimuli). Cue
learning may arise from the capacity of biologically neu-
tral stimuli to have weak interactions with emotive sys-
tems coupled with the capacity of emotive systems to
modify the sensitivities of sensory systems. As "biolog-
ically relevant stimuli" (i.e., incentives) have strong in-
teractions with emotive command systems (Figure 1),
sensory fields which encode neutral environmental stim-
uli are sensitized, and this neural conjunction may forge
ever stronger relations between the most salient environ-
mental stimuli and the aroused emotive system. Specifi-
cally, rapid changes in the activity of an emotive system
may lead to disinhibition of reinforcement-programming
networks situated at the terminal arborizations of each
command system. Thereby, neutral stimuli, which are
temporally linked to the fluctuating activities of emotive Figure 5. If emotional disorders ultimately arise from un-
systems, may develop stronger feedback routes to trigger balanced activities among primitive emotive systems of the
zones of a command circuit. Similarly, behavior patterns subcortical brain, then a natural taxonomy of major psychiatric
that just precede substantial reductions in the activity of disorders should be derivable from an analysis of these systems.
an emotive system may become part of the intrinsic habit At the simplest level, emotional disorders may arise from
hierarchy of an organism. In other words, habit formation under-(—) and over-(+) activity of emotive command systems. A
may operate through a rapid reduction in the activity of preliminary suggestion of the types of psychiatric disorders that
may arise from such changes is outlined.

420 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
functions of the lower circuits with experience. By such remain relatively stable in the limbic systems of all
translocations, as well as direct reafferents to the com- mammals. These labels, therefore, recognize commu-
mand circuits, cognitive appraisal may come to be an nalities in executive organization of these systems across
especially important influence in the genesis of adult mammalian species. Granted the foregoing, the perspec-
emotions. Indeed, a growing body of evidence suggests tive is advocated that human introspection can be a useful
that such translocation of instinctive behavior patterns source of information concerning the underlying nature
can occur in the animal brain. For instance, behavioral of the systems. In other words, with some luck, our
deficits resulting from damage to the lateral hypoth- conscious mind may be able to see the dynamics of our
alamus can be overcome by preoperative experiences subcortical heritage clearly. The risks attendant upon
(Ahem, Landin & Wolf 1978; Ruger & Schulkin 1980; admitting such sources of information into the scientific
Schwartz & Teitelbaum 1974). Thus, the ontogenetic endeavor are great, but failure to approach the brain with
approach may be as important for understanding the realistic experiential concepts is equally problematic.
functional elaboration of emotive processes in the brain as The stance taken herein leads inexorably toward a the-
it is in behavior (Izard & Buechler 1979). oretically based analysis of brain function, and as long as it
remains linked to identifiable neural systems and objec-
Diseases of emotive systems. Psychiatric disorders tive behaviors, the enterprise should prove as scien-
probably reflect imbalanced activities among basic emo- tifically feasible as particle physics - comfortless as that
tive circuitries of the visceral brain. For heuristic pur- may be.
poses, possible relations between the emotive systems Of course, there are alternative ways of viewing the
herein discussed and major emotional disorders are sum- organization of emotional processes in the brain, and the
marized in Figure 5. There is substantial evidence for usefulness of any approach will ultimately rest upon the
some of these possibilities and next to none for others. degree to which it promotes an empirical understanding
Because of the complex interactions that can occur among of the emotions and their role in behavior. At the most
systems (Figure 2), this scheme is offered as a stimulus to general level - a level at which too much biological
further thinking, and will not be elaborated on here. I research on the topic has become stranded - emotion
would note only that an especially large number of ail- may be seen to be a generalized arousal state from which
ments may arise from disorders of the system that medi- individual emotions evolve via a process of social learn-
ates social affect. ing. As Redmond and Hunag (1979, p. 2159) have put it:
"In normal individuals, the emotions associated with
increasing activation, therefore, might be called atten-
Concluding remarks tion, carefulness, interest, surprise, alerting, astonish-
ment, alarm, anxiety, fear, panic, or terror. Which was
Although the complexity of brain neuropil will most identified would depend on a number of situational,
assuredly humble such a simplistic attempt to understand semantic, intensity, or personality factors." Although the
emotions as was undertaken here, nevertheless, I think role of general arousal is of clear importance in the genesis
such analyses may help us progress to more sophisticated of emotions (Figure 4), the fact that an array of emotional
perspectives more rapidly than those which seek to tackle behaviors, such as those discussed herein, can be elicited
the full complexity of the problem. Moreover, there is a by hypothalamic stimulation, at various brain sites but in
distinct advantage to simple schemes in that they are similar environmental circumstances, suggests that there
usually testable, permitting clear refutations, which can is substantial intrinsic articulation in the emotional cir-
facilitate construction of more viable models and cuits of the brain. As an alternative, one might wish to
theories. seek separate and distinct hard-wired neural representa-
The present approach has been based on two funda- tions for each and every emotional nuance that exists, and
mental assumptions. The first, commonly accepted in this surely single-unit studies could bear out those concep-
area of research, is that the evolutionary pressure for the tualizations. However, those approaches may also be
genesis of emotive circuits emerged from general life- misguided if additional evidence indicates an overriding
challenging circumstances, which are to some degree the coherent operation of brain systems in which these indi-
shared evolutionary heritage of all mammalian species. vidual cells are located. At this stage, it seems most
The other, perhaps not so commonly accepted, is that in practical to steer a middle course between these ex-
order to be scientifically substantive, psychological emo- tremes. This middle way means recognizing that certain
tional constructs need to be tied, to some extent, to classes of distinct behaviors always go together in the
specific circuits within the brain. Certainly such designa- normal organism, as though basic control of each rested in
tions must be based initially on circular reasoning and a common circuit with its genetically determined activity
anthropomorphism. However, further specification and modulated by prior experiences, momentary perceptual
testing of the biobehavioral ramifications of these circuits inputs, and prevailing homeostatic conditions, thereby
and their interactions should permit an escape from affording the possibility of innumerable specific behav-
circularity. ioral expressions of activity in the circuit.
The anthropomorphic terms that I selected for discus- In summary, then, the main thesis of this paper is that
sion of emotive systems may be objectionable to those the natural order of brain emotive systems is to be found
committed to the behaviorist tradition, but they were among a limited number of translimbic command circuits
chosen because it is assumed that, even though the that act to bring a variety of specific behavioral acts and
species-typical expressions and species-characteristic concurrent physiological changes under common execu-
vigor of these executive systems may have undergone tive influence. Of course, the existence of emotional
great diversification during evolution, their basic natures states in animals must remain an assumption based on the

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 421


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

recognition of such processes in our human experience Following application of an aversive stimulus, such as
and on the probability that similar mechanisms exist in footshock, some strains or lines of mice exhibit intense immo-
the limbic systems of related species. Without such an bility, whereas other strains display high levels of locomotor
assumption, one is left with few scientific options but to activity (Anisman 1975; Anisman, Grimmer, Irwin, Remington,
tally the movements of animals and their constitutent & Sklar 1979). Likewise, some strains of mice tend to vocalize,
while others do not (Wahlsten 1972). Does this imply that a
parts in the hope that predictive algorithms will emerge given stressor provokes different levels of emotions or different
from accumulated facts. However, if one makes that emotions entirely across strains, or that the stimuli are not
assumption (and, to my knowledge, no data exist to equally aversive across strains, or that the same emotional
compromise its credibility), then subjective human expe- response is generated in each strain, but the behavioral corre-
rience should be a useful guide for categorizing and lates (the defensive repertoire) of these strains differ? As a
analyzing the emotive circuitries of the brain. Such a second example, rats exposed to footshock display a transient
source of knowledge can not only provide a list of primi- period of response excitation followed by freezing. Pinel and his
tive emotive states that the brain elaborates (e.g., Table associates (Pinel &Treit 1978; Treit, Pinel, & Fibiger 1981) have
1), but it can also help establish some dynamic properties reported that if shock is delivered through a probe, rats will
of such circuits. A substantial amount of past work in this approach and sniff the probe (expectancy?), back away from it
area has been implicitly guided by conceptions such as (fear?), and then bury the probe (rage?) with material that might
be at hand (at paw). The behavior of the organism varies
these. Yet, because of methodological and conceptual temporally, and as a function of the stimuli present in the
limitations imposed on the study of behavior by an era environment. One could hardly assume, however, that the
predating the flowering of neuroscience, the implications behavioral changes were indicative of rapid alterations of emo-
of such approaches for understanding how the brain tional state.
organizes behavior (and mind) remain largely unex- The behavioral topography of an animal might be dictated by
plored. antecedent stimulus events and by the opportunities to respond
to environmental stimuli. For instance, cues that signal aversive
events may come to produce an "expectancy" of the primary
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS aversive stimulus (Bolles 1970) or the conditioning of a fear
I appreciate comments by Robert Conner, Michael Doherty, response (Rescorla & Solomon 1967). The cognitive or emo-
John Jalowiec, and Kenneth Pargament on an earlier draft of this tional state may lead to immobility or flight, depending on
paper, and I thank Ryan Tweney for introducing me to the several situational variables (Bolles 1971). If other defensive
original versions of Cogan (1802) and Willis (1683). behaviors are unavailable or ineffective in terminating the
aversive stimulation, aggressive behavior may result, particu-
larly if the behavior can be directed at a significant stimulus. The
aggressive act, in this instance, may simply represent a compo-
nent of the animal's defensive repertoire (like freezing or flight),
and it need not be assumed that it was precipitated by rage.
Open Peer Commentary In considering the appetitively motivated behaviors, Pank-
sepp suggests that responding for self-stimulation is representa-
tive of the expectancy/foraging emotion. However, there is
Commentaries submitted by the qualified professional readership of reason to believe that stimulation of specific neuronal circuits
this journal will be considered for publication in a later issue as such as those subserving "stimulus-bound" appetitive behav-
Continuing Commentary on this article. Integrative overviews and iors provide the arousal (activation) necessary to engage in
syntheses are especially encouraged. appetitive acts given the presence of relevant environmental
cues (Valenstein, Cox, & Kakolewski 1970). Further, to the
same point, Panksepp suggests that agitated self-stimulation
(vigorous biting of the manipulandum) reflects the intermin-
gling of the expectancy and rage systems. An alternative and
Assessing internal affairs possibly more parsimonious account of the agitated self-stimula-
tion is that licking and biting the manipulandum is representa-
Hymie Anisman and Robert M. Zacharko tive of part of the consummatory sequence induced by brain
Department of Psychology, Carleton University, Ottawa, Ontario, Canada stimulation. When rats are given long pulse stimulation (30 sec.)
K1S 5B6 with food available, they typically engage in consummatory acts
In his provocative paper, Panksepp has provided an exciting during the period of stimulation. Animals treated with high
formulation of a difficult issue. Yet it seems that there may be too doses of amphetamine will not show a decline of feeding rates
few equations to solve for too many unknown variables. Even if induced by the stimulation, nor will they exhibit a decline of
one were to assume that emotions, being derivedfromprimitive food-related behaviors (e.g., gnawing at the grid floor, lever, or
systems, are fundamentally similar in human and infrahuman foodcup). However, such animals do not consume the available
species, it is questionable whether we can identify these emo- food (Wishart & Walls 1974). Unpublished data collected by
tions in infrahumans with the precision that would be necessary Wishart and Zacharko have revealed that, as pulse-duration was
to assess unequivocally the propositions advanced by Panksepp. shortened in either programmed or self-administered para-
Particular behavioral events are taken by Panksepp as indices of digms, the consummatory acts came to be directed toward the
certain emotions; freezing and flight, for example, are assumed lever (chewing or licking), rather than the available food. It is
to represent fear; attack and fighting reflect rage; distress vocal- not necessary to hypothesize that these behaviors arose because
ization is indicative of panic; forward locomotion and sniffing of frustration; rather, they are indicative of the consummatory
signify expectation. Such operational definitions are fine if one sequence and are maximally evident as the time available for
wishes either to distinguish between or to categorize a series of stimulus-bound feeding is decreased.
behaviors, but it would be inappropriate to assume that these Attributing particular emotional changes to animals may be as
behaviors actually represent the emotions as humans might misleading as attempts to attribute cognitive changes to animals
interpret them. exposed to environmental events. When animals are exposed to

422 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentary IP&nVsepp: Psychobiology of emotions

unpredictable aversive events over which control is not possi- of brain stimulation must satisfy several criteria before they can
ble, the animals, it has been frequently observed, adopt a be identified as emotion circuits. They must be evolutionary
passive response style characterized by repeated failures to acquisitions; they must be involved in adaptive behavior; they
avoid or escape the aversive stimulus. Some theorists have must affect the sensitivity of relevant sensory systems and be
assumed that the passivity is due to "learned helplessness" active beyond the stimulus duration. Since some affects, like
(Maier & Seligman 1976), whereas others have attributed the surprise, disgust, pleasure and displeasure, do not fulfill these
behavioral changes to response styles engendered by alterations criteria, Panksepp simply ignores them.
in central neurochemical lability (Anisman, Kokkinidis, & Sklar Panksepp proposes four emotion-mediating circuits, located
1981; Weiss, Glazer, Pohorecky, Bailey, & Schneider 1979). mainly in the hypothalamus: expectancy, rage, fear, and panic
Inasmuch as cognitions in animals cannot be directly measured command circuits, which are activated by sensory information
and neurochemical events can, the former approach appears to from the environment and internal states. He insists that the
us to be a sterile one that does not lend itself to empirical emotion of expectancy is involved in anticipatory appetitive
validation in infrahuman animals. In the case of the analysis behavior; its circuit is "designed to energize appetitive foraging
presented by Panksepp, it may have been preferable simply to behaviors." And he suggests that the sudden violent leaping
document behavioral changes occurring in various experimental seen sometimes in rats after brain stimulation is a form of panic.
settings and to delineate the physiological and neurochemical Its "diminutive form" is sorrow, inferred from the distress call
mechanisms subserving these behaviors. After all, the brain evoked by brain stimulation. Such distress calls can be evoked in
amine changes that may be related to coping processes or various species but not in rats; and only in rats does brain
necessary to prepare the organism for further insults need not stimulation evoke the explosive behavior Panksepp calls panic.
be interpreted in terms of emotional states. The use of labels There is no evidence for a connection between separation
such as fear, panic, or rage may, in the long run, be coun- distress (sorrow) and panic. Panksepp infers rage from attack
terproductive. To be sure, Panksepp has repeatedly indicated evoked by brain stimulation; and fear, from blind running.
the difficulties involved in attempting to infer emotional These two emotions are the ones most easily recognized in
changes in animals on the basis of some behavioral events. subjective experience. According to Panksepp's Figure 1, these
Unfortunately, simply recognizing the difficulty of the problem four emotions represent extremes. While rage is an extreme
is not sufficient to eliminate it. Despite our misgivings, we form of anger, and fear may be an extreme form of alarm or
hasten to add that the polythetic approach adopted by Panksepp foreboding, as he says, expectancy is hardly an extreme form of
is an exciting one and removes the problem from the narrow hope or desire, nor is panic an extreme form of sorrow or
confines within which it is often considered. separation distress.
Panksepp not only fails to use subjective experience in work-
ing out his taxonomy of emotions, he flatly disregards such
Emotions - inferences from hypothetical experience if it does not fit the behavior patterns evoked by
hypothalamic circuits? brain stimulation. Since he includes sorrow, he should logically
also include joy in his system, yet he never mentions it. He also
Magda B. Arnold has no room for love or affection, although this emotion is
obviously involved in social cohesion. For Panksepp, the panic
5863 Montford Rd., Mobile, Ala. 36608
circuit functions "to sustain social cohesion," yet distress vocal-
According to Panksepp, "while major concepts concerning the ization (and panic?) surely is a sign of the breakdown of social
nature of emotions arise from human introspection, most knowl- cohesion, while love is the bond that maintains it.
edge concerning the mechanisms underlying emotionality Instead of providing a neural scheme of how emotions are
arises from animal brain research." Hence he suggests that more organized in the brain, Panksepp merely mentions the generally
knowledge about emotion might be derived from introspection accepted connections from midbrain through the hypothalamus
combined with the results of brain research than from either and thalamus to the basal ganglia and higher limbic area and
approach alone. I am entirely in accord with this premise, which suggests that there are also connections with other behavior
underlies the author's theory. control circuits; and that various levels of the neuraxis have
However, there are safeguards that must be observed if these access to emotion circuits. After his explanation we are no closer
two approaches are to be valid. First, introspective evidence to understanding how social separation, for instance, activates
must be derived from general human experience. That is, the the panic circuit. The infant animal must realize its mother's
emotions proposed in a theory should be generally accepted. absence before making distress calls - but just how does that
Also, a taxonomy of emotions should include the most important realization activate the hypothalamic panic circuit? What is
simple emotions. Finally, the emotion circuits inferred from needed is a viable circuit from sensory areas through the hy-
brain research should have demonstrable connections with pothalamus to motor areas to distinguish emotion from motor
relevant sensory and motor functions. We know that we must circuits. The observed behavior patterns are not themselves
perceive a situation before we can react to it emotionally and emotions, and the circuits that mediate them are not necessarily
express these emotions in behavior. Ideally, a theory based on emotion circuits, even if they satisfy the criteria Panksepp has
brain research would indicate how the neural structures and set up.
connections involved in emotion are activated by sensory expe- Panksepp deplores the failure of earlier theorists to use the
rience and in turn activate motor functions. results of brain research in presenting their taxonomies of
Panksepp's proposal to "outline a testable theory of how emotions. Apparently, he has never examined Arnold's
emotional processes may be organized in the central nervous (1960a;b) theory, which uses subjective experience to identify
system of mammals" seems to promise such an integrated emotions, but then outlines specific brain circuits and connec-
system. He proposes "a taxonomy of emotions that is supported tions involved in the sequence from perception to emotion and
by existing neurobehavioral data" and promises "to provide an action. The theory may need to be corrected or supplemented,
approximate neural scheme of how emotions may be organized but it does use the results of modern brain research and is the
in the brain." most extensive attempt to reconcile evidence from brain re-
However, the execution of this laudable proposal leaves much search with subjective experience. If the theory is inadequate, it
to be desired. First of all, Panksepp's taxonomy of emotions is is open to criticism and correction. But to disregard it, and then
derived from rather than supported by the results of brain deplore the absence of such an attempt, is hardly good scientific
research. He stipulates that the circuits inferred from the results practice.

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 423


Commentart//Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

Emotions: Hard- or soft-wired? motivated (i.e., intended to help rather than harm the target);
and it is based on the appraisal of events as right or wrong,
James R. Averill justified or unjustified (Averill 1979). Clearly, not all aggressive
Department of Psychology, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, Mass. acts can be categorized as angry (cf. envy, jealousy, and instru-
01003 mental aggression, to mention a few possibilities). Panksepp,
Panksepp's argument proceeds on two levels. Thefirstis a thesis however, tends to gloss over such differences and indis-
about general strategy for behavioral and brain research, using criminately lumps into a single category such diverse states as
emotion as a paradigm; the second is a series of propositions "rage," "anger," "wildness," and "affective attack." Moreover,
concerning possible neural circuits that are presumably "hard- he assumes that there is a homologous class of behaviors in most,
wired" and that mediate four broad classes of emotion (expec- if not all, mammalian species. Panksepp maybe right, although
tancy, rage, fear, and panic). Much could be said about the I doubt it. The only point I wish to make is that his conclusions
argument at both levels, but I will limit my comments to a few are not based on a careful conceptual or introspective analysis of
observations on Panksepp's more general thesis and its implica- human emotions, that is, on the kind of analysis that he is
tions for the study of emotion. The central proposition of this advocating.
thesis is that we should make greater use of our own introspec- Panksepp might reply that I am quibbling about words. And
tive awareness as a guide to research and theory. I agree with indeed I am. Our experience and behavior is intimately related
this proposition. Computer scientists have profitably used intro- to the way we categorize the world, as reflected in our language;
spective reports in the development of programs (minitheories, and I assume that this fact has important implications for behav-
in a sense) that simulate "higher" thought processes. Why cant ioral and brain research.
neuroscientists do the same when studying the brain? The Panksepp accounts for the "impressive subtleties of human
analogy between computer and brain sciences is far from exact, feeling" in terms of the interblending of the four basic emotions.
of course. Nevertheless, Panksepp seems to be on firm ground Thus, jealousy "may arise from some admixture of panic, rage,
when he asserts than an unwarranted fear of anthropomorphism and expectancy . . . and so on with other affective alchemy."
can have - and has had - a stifling effect. The alchemic metaphor is more appropriate than Panksepp
But having granted Panksepp his general thesis, I must perhaps realizes. He might have pursued it further. For one
question his application of it. Panksepp cites favorably the great thing, alchemists recognized that, if a baser metal were to be
seventeenth century anatomist, Willis, who used introspective transformed into a more noble one, the former would cease to
analyses to guide his neurophysiological investigations of the exist in any meaningful sense. In Panksepp's affective alchemy,
emotions. Panksepp does not, however, describe the conclusion the basic emotions are evidently preserved in the admixture.
reached by Willis, namely, that emotional processes are lo- But preserved or not, the process by which the transformation
calized within the cerebellum. Willis based this conclusion on occurs remains mysterious.
"Analogy and Frequent Ratiocination" followed by "Anatomical Panksepp's failure adequately to follow his own program is
investigation" (1664/1965, p. 111). More specifically, Willis also illustrated by his assertion that "it seems to be universal
reasoned that since emotions are often involuntary and irra- human experience that positive expectations and anger are
tional, they should be located in a part of the brain that is only psychologically incompatible states." From this he infers that
narrowly connected to the cerebrum and that is relatively the corresponding neural circuits should exhibit reciprocal inhi-
similar in animals and humans. His anatomical investigations bition. But it is simply not the case that positive expectations are
suggested that the cerebellum meets these criteria. universally considered incompatible with anger. Aristotle, re-
flecting an even more common view, maintained that anger
The line of reasoning pursued by Willis is both ancient and "must always be attended by a certain pleasure - that which
modern. A similar view (but with a different localization) can be arises from the expectation of revenge" ("Rhetoric," 13781').
found in Plato. (For a historical review of psychophysiological
theories of emotion, see Averill 1974.) Panksepp's article illus- What kind of neurophysiological theory of emotion might
trates a modern variation on the same theme. That is, introspec- emerge if we took Panksepp's general thesis seriously and
tion apparently suggests to Panksepp that the emotions are systematically analyzed our emotional concepts and experi-
largely noncognitive and involuntary; he therefore concludes ences? A careful analysis would lead, I believe, to a theory that
that the emotions must be mediated by "command circuits" that emphasized the plasticity of neural circuits (as opposed to the
are hard-wired into the more primitive parts of the brain, such hard-wiring proposed by Panksepp), even in the case of "basic
as the hypothalamus and the limbic system. emotions"; that stressed the hierarchical and heterarchical in-
teractions among circuits (which Panksepp discusses only super-
But is this the direction a careful introspective analysis of ficially); and that laid greater importance on socialization than on
emotional phenomena would lead us? Are the emotions as natural selection as a systematizing influence (at least as far as
immutable, as divorced from higher thought processes, and as human emotions are concerned). In other words, it would
primitive as they are often portrayed? Or is this merely a part of suggest an approach to the localization of function more along
their legitimation, that is, the manner in which they are ra- the lines adumbrated by Luria (1973) than along the lines
tionalized in society (because of the types of functions they tend proposed by Panksepp.
to serve)? Obviously, there is not the space here to pursue the
kind of analysis that would be required to answer these ques-
tions. At the risk of sounding dogmatic, therefore, I will simply
state what I believe such an analysis would reveal, namely, that
the emotions are exquisitely variable, both across individuals
and across cultures; that they are fundamentally dependent Specific human emotions are psychobiologic
upon cognitive processes; and that they are typically quite entities: Psychobiologic coherence between
purposeful. (For detailed arguments in support of these claims, emotion and its dynamic expression
see Averill 1980a; 1980b; Solomon 1976.)
Panksepp would, of course, disagree with these last conten- Manfred Clynes
tions. Where does the source of the disagreement lie? Let us Music Research Center, N.S.W. State Conservatorium of Music, Sydney
consider for a moment the case of anger, one of the emotional 2000, Australia
"command systems" (rage) postulated by Panksepp. A typical A plan to study specific emotions as psychobiologic entities is
episode of anger can be manifested in any of a great variety of timely and appropriate, particularly if one attempts, where
ways, depending upon the person and situation; it seldom leads possible, to supplement exploration of brain function with
to physical aggression; it is more often than not constructively observation of human subjective experience. Specific subjective

424 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

entities have long been implicated in the scientific study of pression (Clynes 1973; 1980). It is found that subjects may be
animal sensory physiology: No one doubts the existence of sated with respect to one specific emotion but quite fresh with
stereovision, of the perceived sensations of tone, of smell, and so respect to another specific one, until sated with respect to the
on, in various animals. In the spectrum of specific emotions, next one, but ready for a third, and so on through a series of what
however, specific sensing or "command" structures are not appear to be by this criterion basic emotions. (This does not
obviously at the periphery of the nervous system, but appear to occur with "mixed' emotions.) This selective satiety was consid-
be discoverable elsewhere in the brain. Categories of subjective ered likely to be related to specific chemical receptor sites.
experience here too can help, and can even be essential to Since then, endorphins and encephalins have been discovered;
systematic scientific categorization and investigation: As we however, their possible role in mediating emotions is not ade-
progress in the study of brain function, the subjective in- quately treated by Panksepp - he devotes less than a paragraph
creasingly becomes objective. to this.
Though the most salient emotions are named in practically all Like Panksepp, we too have found it desirable to discard the
human languages, and function in dreams, the neuroscientific single-dimensional continuum of pleasure/displeasure as a de-
study of their nature has not received the attention warranted by scriptor of specific emotion-entities; in Panksepp's article it
their importance in everyday life, in music, drama, and art reappears, however, in the different guise of "positive" and
(Langer 1973; Piechowski 1981). Emphasis has been on general "negative" emotions, a nomenclature that is not further ex-
arousal, mediated by catecholamines, on "drives," on "domi- plained. (A "negative " emotion such as anger, for example, can
nance versus submission." [See also Bernstein: "Dominance: give pleasure under some circumstances.) We have named
The Baby and the Bathwater" BBS 4 (3) 1981 and Vandervolf & "negative' those emotions that have a horizontal component of
Robinson: "Reticulo-Cortical Activity and Behavior" BBS 4 (3) expressive pressure away from the body.
1981.] In humans, specific emotions can be experienced in two
One regrets that in the theoretical formulations of Panksepp's distinct ways or "modes': (1) the "animalistic" Dionysian way
target article "negative" emotions predominate, reflecting the and (2) "'considered' as qualities," the Apollonian way, as in
prevalent orientation of the literature. Three out of four of his great music and art. The latter (probably using "command"
major "distinct" specific categories are rage, fear, and panic routes other than those involving only the limbic system) allows
("freezing" is described as occurring both in fear and in panic)! us, paradoxically, to enjoy a piece of music expressing grief- the
The fourth, expectancy, is left to shoulder whatever worthwhile sadder, the better! It is not known if even the highest mammals
emotional experiences life may have to offer, to animals or to are capable of any such degree of "imaginative" use of the
man. No mention, let alone study, is made of love, of wonder, qualities of emotion and their communication. A third mode in
courage, for example; and joy is encountered by Panksepp's which the expression of specific emotion can be produced in
system only as a result of fulfilled expectation. This probably humans is mimicry. Panksepp's "elaboration" seems an insuffi-
reflects the paucity of readily available animal (and human) cient concept for the study of the implications of such modes, in
experimental evidence about distinct "positive" emotions animals or man.
rather than a lack of discernment. But if we indeed share Recent work has indicated that in humans the dynamic forms
genetically "hard-wired" emotion programs with mammals, as of expression of specific emotions appear to be independent of
Panksepp, probably correctly, suggests, we would hardly be sensory mode. Touch and sound are found to share the same
likely to share only those of "negative" emotions with them. dynamic form for specific emotions. Transformations were
An important omission in the theoretical formulation is the found which turn a tactile expression of specific emotion into an
inherent communicative function of emotion: the contagion acoustic expression of the same emotion: The transform con-
across individuals. The study of a specific emotion-entity can- serves the dynamic form, changing pressure form into frequen-
not ignore the auto- and cross-communicative and contagious cy contour with appropriate specific scaling (Clynes & Nettheim
aspects of its expression; there is evidence that these are biolog- 1982; Clynes & Walker 1980; Clynes, Walker, & Nettheim
ically integral parts of the entity of each specific emotion (e.g., 1981). The sounds so transformed from touch experiences of
sexual mating rituals and dances as genetic programs in many seven specific emotions were tested on over three hundred
animals, as well as later-evolved emotion-entities also, as yawn- subjects in the United States and Australia, including a group of
ing or laughter). [See also Eibl-Eibesfeldt: "Human Ethology" 40 central Australian aborigines. Recognition was similar in all
BBS 2(1) 1979.] three groups (p < .0001).
It is here that there is psychobiologic evidence concerning It would appear that important parts of the "hard-wired"
human emotions that substantially overlaps and strengthens programs for the dynamic expression of specific emotions are
Panksepp's position. The characteristic expression and the state independent of sensory mode for both production and recogni-
of a specific emotion inherently interact psychobiologically in tion of emotion expression and thus also for communicative
ways that can be experimentally clarified. contagion of emotion generation. This also readily lends itself to
In our work of over a decade with the expressive generation of study through animal experiments.
specific emotions through touch and sound, we found, broadly, In view of these and otherfindings,Panksepp's suggestion of a
that the "purity" of the expressive form strongly affects its ability cross-fertilization between animal and human studies of taxon-
to both auto- and cross-generate emotion; it appears that there omy and properties of specific emotion programs should be
are specific dynamic forms of expression to each "basic" emotion productive.
in humans. We have experimentally determined the durations
and dynamic shapes of these forms - called essentic forms
(Clynes 1969; 1973; 1975). We find that there is a biologically
given coherence between the specific dynamic form and the Animal and human emotionality
emotion that it can express. These properties are made evident
also in music and account for the "living quality" of good musical Jos6 M. R. Delgado
performances. (Moreover, "mixed" emotions appear to be ex- Departamento de Investigacidn, Centro "Ramdn y Cajal," Madrid 34,
pressed not by an algebraic sum but by a temporal telescoping of Spain
separate portions of the component forms into single expressive One valuable aspect of Panksepp's paper is the attempt to
forms.) identify specific emotions with brain circuitry. This possibility is
One aspect of this evidence concerning distinct emotions is testable; and even if his proposed "general psychobiological
the dynamics of selective satiation that have been observed theory of emotions" may be debatable, experimental facts are
when specific emotions are generated through iterative ex- established, and his approach "can facilitate construction of

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 425


Commentan//Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
more viable models and theories." In reality, this is the orienta- and clarify the many aspects not shared, which are the most
tion of many investigators, and when emotional manifestations important emotional characteristics of man. Primitive in-
are elicited by electrical stimulation of certain brain structures, stinctive emotions should be differentiated from cultural, intel-
it is accepted that some anatomical-functional correlation ligent, cultivated emotional responsiveness. This separation is
exists. essential for the understanding and the education of human
Another interesting aspect of Panksepp's article is the blend- beings and for finding solutions to present emotional conflicts. It
ing of the two sources of knowledge about emotions, namely is also essential for any psychobiological theory of emotions.
objective manifestations in animals and subjective experience in Another concept on which I would like to comment concerns
humans. It is asserted that "basic emotions may have obligatory the existence of "executive (command) circuits that concur-
internal dynamics, which humans share with other mammals, " rently activate related behavior patterns." This idea is in agree-
and also that "control mechanisms remain similar in humans and ment with our thesis that "brain stimulation triggers physiologi-
'lower' animals." The problem with this thesis, however, is that cal mechanisms" and that we may consider an "electrical
the most important human emotions are based on ethics, esthet- activation of the will" (Delgado 1969, chaps. 17 and 18). This
ics, and cultural learning that have no parallels in animal idea is also in agreement with our theory of "fragmental repre-
experience, and also that the most important human expression sentation of behavior" (Delgado 1964), and with our proposed
is related to language, which, again, cannot be equated with organization of behavioral responses including three functional
primitive animal communication. sets, namely, the starter, organizer, and performer (Delgado
It is true that the limbic system is a shared mammalian 1969). I do not think, however, that the initial command post for
heritage, but we also share the motor system, reticular forma- emotions must necessarily be located in the hypothalamus (and
tion, cerebellum, and many other structures. There are sen- perhaps not even in the limbic system). As an alternative
sorimotor neuronal similarities among rats, monkeys, and hu- hypothesis we have proposed that specific sets of structures are
mans, but the sensitivity, knowledge, and skills necessary for located in different areas of the brain, forming a functional
outer space travel are not shared with animals. The finding that constellation with reciprocal facilitatory, and inhibitory rela-
ventromedial hypothalamic lesions increase appetite and rage in tions (Delgado 1979). The concept of algebraic summation of
both animals and humans means that the hypothalamus does dynamic influences triggering a final response is preferable to
play some role in some of these behavioral manifestations which the idea of a single specific center. Panksepp indicates in his
are not necessarily equivalent: the ingestion of food pellets may article that the command systems may run "from mesen-
be an instinctive act which cannot be compared to the enjoy- cephalon, through the reticular fields of the hypothalamus and,
ment of a banquet. Mouse-killing behavior in the rat has very perhaps, thalamus to basal ganglia and higher limbic areas,"
little in common with organized crime. One of the fallacies to with other ascending and descending controls. This is the
come out of conferences on animal aggression is the frequent concept of a functional constellation, and perhaps the difference
implication that causality and cerebral mechanisms are similar of opinion lies only in giving more or less emphasis to the
in animal fighting and in the strategies of modern warfare. command value of specific parts of the circuit.
Area 4 cortical lesions produce contralateral motor paralysis Experimental evidence indicates that, in cats and monkeys,
in different species, but the anatomical, functional, and motor aggressive behavior can be elicited by electrical stimulation of
organization are probably different. Even within the same the reticular formation, tectum, thalamus, hypothalamus,
species, man, it is doubtful that a farmer and a guitar player have amygdala, and other structures; and it can be inhibited by
equivalent motor representation of their hands. stimulation of the caudate nucleus, pallidum, and other areas of
We should not generalize animal experimentation to human the brain. All these structures are functionally interconnected,
behavior unduly, and we should analyze similarities and dif- and in our studies, we have been able to give to each structure a
ferences of the phenomenon under consideration. At the core of mathematical coefficient expressing the value of its activation
this problem is the understanding of the ontogeny of emotions: with respect to a specific behavioral response (Delgado 1980).
Panksepp states, "Emotions seem to arise ultimately from hard- This experimental approach is more neutral and factual than
wired neural circuits in the visceral-limbic brain," and that the attempt to relate brain physiology to ill-defined psychologi-
"these circuits developed early in mammalian brain evolution." cal classifications. This is one of the most controversial aspects of
Certainly there is genetic determination of the main hard-wired Panksepp's article: Why classify emotions in terms of only four
neural circuits, but human beings are born with very immature categories, leaving out pain, pleasure, sex, hunger, and many
brains, and software information received through sensory in- others? No convincing explanation is given, nor is this classifica-
puts is decisive for neuronal sprouting and for the establishment tion in agreement with experimental facts. Distress vocaliza-
of synaptic connections, neurochemical structuring, and other tions may be associated with fear and rage; they are not ex-
aspects essential to the final hard-wiring. Also, the frame of clusively expressions of panic. Our present investigations
reference necessary for emotional reactivity and many aspects of (Martin-Ramirez, Blanco, Alonso & Delgado, 1982) show that,
emotional expression are learned and not inborn. Motor path- in the cat, hissing can be evoked by stimulation of many points
ways develop early in mammalian brain evolution, but their located from the reticular formation up to the hypothalamus,
anatomical and functional development requires individual with reciprocal potentiating and inhibiting influences; the effect
learning and training. Harlow's motherless monkeys were born is in many cases an isolated, out-of-context behavioral module,
with normal brains, but in the absence of maternal care and and does not involve attacks against cats or rats.
suitable sensory inputs, emotional development was disrupted. In monkey colonies, electrical stimulation of the central gray
Genetic hard-wiring was not enough. in the same animal with the same parameters evoked different
In some of the available literature there is a tendency to effects depending on the social status of the animal: aggression
generalize experimental findings among rats and cats to when it was dominant, and submissive behavior, including
monkeys and man. In many aspects of nerve depolarization or grimacing, when its rank was low. [See also Bernstein: "Domi-
muscle contraction this is acceptable, but in many other man- nance" BBS 4(3) 1981.] Processing of sensory information
ifestations, including emotional reactivity and expression, this is proved essential for the response, and the idea of hard-wiring
not valid. Rats do not have a sense of humor, and man does not cannot be accepted in this case. Aggressive behavior will be very
usually chase mice. different depending on whether the subject is a black-belt judo
The conclusion I am reaching is that, in agreement with champion or a sedentary clerk. Learned motor skills and ide-
Panksepp, it is very useful to investigate mechanisms shared by okinetic formulas are very different, being stored as motor
animals and humans, ranging from unitary neuronal activity to fragments to be used when needed, for different purposes. It is
social behavior, but that at the same time we must investigate very doubtful that motor displays are specific to fear, rage,

426 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

panic, and other emotions; it is more probable that, as postu- Table 1 (de Rivera). Basic states in a dyadic system of
lated in our theory of fragmental representation of behavior, emotions
there is an emotionally bound starter, which activates a differ-
ent set: the organizer responsible for the choice of the complex
motor response, which in turn fires another set: the performer, The emotion
which puts in action previously learned formulas of motor
response. Transforms
One of the merits of Panksepp's paper is that it provides an Transforms the other the self
excellent review of the subject and a wealth of ideas, which
should trigger emotionality in the readers, and, one hopes for the self (desire) (elation)
experimental actions to support, refute, and clarify the impor- Into something good
in its own right (love) (security)
tant material that he lucidly presents. for the self (fear) (anxiety)
Into something bad
in its own right (anger) (depression)

Relating experience to the brain


control or "command" systems that are related to specific
Joseph de Rivera
situational events such as the presence of an incentive or a social
Department of Psychology, Clark University, Worcester, Mass. 01610
loss. However, we do not experience emotions as responses to
I enjoyed reading this article. One might take issue with a environmental stimuli. Rather, emotions transform our rela-
number of points: Studies on the recovery of brain function tionship with the world. Thus, anger is not a set of aggressive
suggest that even subcortical structures must be less "hard- responses to frustration, but a transformation of our situation so
wired" than is usually imagined (Fass, Jordan, Rubman, Seibel, that we perceive a challenge to the way things ought to be (cf. de
& Stein 1975; Mclntyre and Stein 1973), and the suggestion of Rivera 1981). In this regard, the brain model proposed by
four primary emotional processes rather neglects both Pribram and Melges (1969) is truer to experience. Further,
Tomkins's (1962) and Plutchik's (1980) attempts to specify basic there is no experiental evidence for a small set of basic emotions.
emotional behavior patterns. However, I like Panksepp's treat- On the contrary, we have names in English for several hundred
ment of emotions as separate systems with specific structures, emotions, and close examination of these different emotions
functions, and properties, and I appreciate his audacity in reveals that they are not blends of more primitive basic emo-
attempting to combine neurobehavioral and introspective data tions. Each has unique structures (cf. Lindsay-Hartz's, 1981,
to come up with a "psychobiological" theory. As a phe- description of the unique properties of joy, elation, and glad-
nomenological psychologist, I want to respond to this openness ness). Thus, rather than a few basic elemental systems, an
toward the data of human experience. What if we really take investigation of our experience of emotions suggests hundreds
human experience seriously? What is our conscious experience of discrete structures, each involving a unique way of perceiving
of emotions? Does this experience suggest any particular organi- the situation, a specific transformation of the way our body
zation to the emotions? Could such an organization be related to relates to the world, unique "command" instructions about how
the model proposed by Panksepp? I want to comment briefly on to behave, and a particular way of functioning in our lives.
each of these four questions. However, our experience does suggest that these hundreds of
If we take consciousness seriously, we must conclude that it is discrete emotions are organized in a particular way. Rather than
inaccurate to say that "eyes see" or "the brain thinks"; rather, there being a few relatively unrelated basic emotional systems
we use our eyes to see with and our brain to think with (cf. Straus that tell the individual organism how to respond to its environ-
1963). Similarly, from the viewpoint of conscious experience, ment, our emotions appear to come in mirror-image structures
brains don't have emotions, persons do. Emotions are not in the that reflect the different possible states of one dyadic system
brain, they are how we are in the world. They are not states that relates the organism to other organisms, or the self to the
produced by neuronal circuits to which we somehow have other. At the most rudimentary level, this system may be
introspective access. Rather, they are transformations of how we described by specifying eight basic transformations of the self
are situated in the world. Thus, strictly speaking, we should not other dyad generated when emotions: (1) transform the other or
ask how emotions are organized in the brain, but how emotional the self, (2) into something good or something bad, (3) for the self
organization is related to the organization of neural activity in or in its own right (cf. de Rivera 1977).
the brain. These basic transformations may be illustrated by the emo-
Our experience of the emotions concurs with Panksepp's tions listed in Table 1. The hundreds of other emotions reflect
theory insofar as he regards emotions as distinct behavioral still other permutations of these self/other relations.

Table 2 (de Rivera). Possible integration of neural and emotional organizations

Panksepp's de Rivera's eight basic states in


subcortical systems dyadic organization of emotions

Emotion transforms other - • Emotion transforms self


"Panic" love (give to other)
• anxiety (hold on to other)
"Fear" —fear (pull back from other)-
• security (move out)
"Expectancy" desire (go out and get)
• elation (take in)
"Rage" '—anger (remove other)
- depression (remove self)

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 427


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

Is it possible to relate such an emotional organization, which experience but "upon the number of distinct behavioral control
is based primarily on conscious experience, to Panksepp's systems that can be activated . . . " (cf. caption to Figure 2).
model of brain organization, which is based primarily on stim- While the names of these circuits are suggestive of our common-
ulation of the limbic system? I believe so, and some specific sense emotional vocabulary, the principles of distinction be-
predictions follow from the attempt. We have only to modify his tween them owe more to general biological and ethological
conceptualization of the four systems so that all of the systems commonplaces about the nature and kinds of "life-challenging
and not only the "panic" system involve social relationships. We circumstances" faced by mammals. I see nothing especially
may then specify two states for each system and view the anthropomorphic about those ethological assumptions. No
separate systems as subsystems of a general system that controls doubt "emotion as a construct . . . in the study of animal behav-
dyadic relationships. The adaptive significance of such a system ior" owes its existence to the analogies of consciousness, but is
is almost self-evident, at least in mammalian species where the this of any more psychological relevance than the analogous
infant-mother relationship is crucial for species survival. observation about the Newtonian construct of force?
The proposed system is outlined in Table 2, where the In the detail of its elaboration Panksepp's taxonomy begins to
emotion's "command" is given in parentheses. look rather arbitrary. Why should the desire for social contact
belong to a basic command system different from the one for the
In short, if my phenomenological analysis (presented in detail fear (which is not Panksepp's "fear") of its loss? Why should
in de Rivera, 1977) is accurate, and if Panksepp is right in anxiety be part of "fear" and not of "panic?" How are the
assuming that "subjective human experience should be a useful "explosive behaviors" of panic different from manifestations of
guide for categorizing and analyzing the emotive circuitries of rage? (cf. Figure 2). As far as I can tell, answers to these
the brain," then the brain should be organized in a way that questions are decided entirely in terms of operational pragmat-
reflects dyadic, mirror-image relationships. Specifically, it ics. Yet surely here, if anywhere, phenomenology is relevant.
should be possible to delineate at least four other subsystems in We need criteria of identity and difference among the different
the brain: a "love" system that encourages affiliative behavior, a emotions: But all that neurological investigation can identify are
"security" system that encourages the exploration of strange reasonably coherent patterns of behavioral responses. To find
surroundings, a "depression" system that inhibits behavior and their phenomenological correlates there is no substitute for
promotes submission by inhibiting aggressiveness, and an "ela- direct introspection.
tion" system that promotes consummatory behavior. I hope But introspection is no Rosetta stone. The trouble is not only
(using my own "expectancy" system) that this commentary will that it is unreliable, but that what modest access it provides is to
help guide further exploration of the ways in which brain phenomena belonging to a level of analysis different from those
organization may be related to our emotions. with which they would need "correlating." In general, this
problem of levels is an old philosophical obligate), familiar to
readers of BBS (e.g., Dennet 1978; Fowler & Turvey 1978). In
the present connection it takes two forms.
Introspection as the Rosetta stone: Millstone First, in what sense does Panksepp think the emotions "arise"
out of the command circuits (CCs) he postulates? Consider the
or fifth wheel? following claims: (a) In certain structural respects (features 1-3
above), CCs parallel the sophisticated emotions, (b) The activa-
Ronald de Sousa tion of these CCs appears to be involved in cases where emo-
Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada tions are present, (c) b explains a, so that we now understand the
M4K 2X3 mechanism of emotions. Panksepp persuades me of a and b.
Unlike some other biologically oriented treatments, Panksepp's Some of his phraseology (Abstract; the early passages on the-
definition of emotions involves features crucial to any compre- oretical assumptions and aims of the target article) suggests that
hensive theory. These include: (1) coherence and complexity of he wishes to claim c. But c does not follow. Similarities of
associated behavior; (2) an emphasis on the role of emotions in structure at different levels might be due to completely different
the determination of differential patterns of salience among mechanisms. I presume, for example, that habituation in an
stimuli and facilitated responses (cf. de Sousa 1980); (3) emo- organism both involves cell habituation in appropriate circuits,
tional inertia, as in Descartes, (1650, article 74). "The utility of and is functionally analogous to cell habituation. But it certainly
all the passions consists alone in their fortifying and perpetuat- doesn't follow that the mechanism of cell habituation must give
ing in the soul thoughts which . . . without that might easily be us insight into the mechanism of an organism's habituation.
effaced from it." I also find it promising, although this point of Second, if we start with a taxonomy of "basic" emotions, we'll
contact is not mentioned, that the "panic" system, which Pank- need an explanation of how complex ones arise. Here all that
sepp describes as perhaps "the most controversial" of his pro- Panksepp has to offer is "blending." Thus, "jealousy may arise
posals, is well supported by the clinical and theoretical work of from some admixture of panic, rage, and expectancy." But it is
John Bowlby (1980) on attachment emotions. [See also Rajecki not clear how blending could ever add logical structure. And
et al.: "Toward a General Theory of Infantile Attachment" BBS that - not merely complications of behavioral dispositions - is
1(3) 1978.] what is needed to account for complex emotions. Here, again,
Panksepp advertises a methodological innovation, which is at one expects phenomenology to contribute, but in Panksepp's
first sight attractive: He suggests looking to "judicious intro- scheme it has already signed off. What I mean by logical
spection" for the '"Rosetta stone' via which the general organi- structure is this: Roughly, an ascription of jealousy involves a
zation of the primitive hard-wired emotional systems of the quintary relation of the form: F(t,, t2, p, a,j), whose terms are: a
mammalian brain can be deciphered." But optimism soon primary (t2) and a secondary (r2) target (of whom and because of
breeds doubt. To me, the phenomenology of emotions evokes whom I'm jealous); a prepositional object (p) (what fact about
the works of Proust or Freud, whose skepticism about emotional them makes me jealous); an aim (a) (what I'd like to do about it);
self-knowledge has been amply confirmed by experimental and a formal object (/) (what it is about the putative fact that is
evidence (Nisbett & Wilson 1977). In that light, a phrase such as jealous-making?). Other emotions have different polyadicities.
"to read the animal mind as directly as we can read our own" Anger lacks a secondary target; love lacks a propositional object;
rings ironically. perhaps depression lacks an aim. It is not clear what logical
structure the phenomenal correlates of Panksepp's command
So perhaps one should be glad that Panksepp's practice does circuits have (as far as I can see, the only sort of object to which
not match his announced method. It turns out, once he gets they are relevant is their aim, the "well organized behavioral
down to business, that his taxonomy is based not on conscious

428 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
sequences" to which they give rise); but, whatever the answer, sponses depends on the excitation of corresponding brain struc-
mere blending among them won't generate different poly- tures. These are known as "emotional response centers." The
adicities. So, although Ifindit very plausible to suppose that in terms "emotional centers" and "motivational" or "drive cen-
some sense jealousy "may arise from some admixture of panic, ters" overlap widely and are even used synonymously by some
rage, and expectancy," the glue is missing that will make such a researchers. Motivation can be defined as the excitation of
mixture into a single compound. certain nervous system structures that evoke definite emotional
states and lead to directed behavior - that is, to the performance
of instrumental acts. It follows from this definition that at the
basis of motivated activity lie the emotional states, which are the
"fuel for the drive. ' On the other hand, the emotional state itself
Emotions are objective events may not lead to motivated instrumental responses. Certain
conditions are necessary to motivate behavior: (1) a certain level
Elzbieta Fonberg
of excitation of the above mentioned emotional centers; (2) the
Department of Neurophysiology, Nencki Institute of Experimental Biology,
presence of the objects that are adequate goals for the particular
02-093 Warsaw, Poland
emotional state (the nature of these responses in any situation is
I would first like to consider Panksepp's theses in terms of my determined by accompanying perceptions and by the efficacy of
own general views. I fully agree that "emotions seem to arise the ongoing action, which can be called conditioned feedback);
from hard-wired neural circuits of the visceral-limbic brain,' and (3) excitation in the centers that pattern both the innate and
and that these circuits "developed early in mammalian brain the acquired forms of activity corresponding to specific emo-
evolution." I am also convinced that animal investigations can tional states (Fonberg 1972).
shed light on the mechanisms of human emotion and that I am convinced that both the external signs of emotions and
introspective experience should be taken into account in these the behavior motivated by emotions are accessible to experi-
studies. I also agree that transhypothalamic circuits are very ment. Subjective feelings in animals can only be judged by
important, although they may not be the only circuits of impor- extrapolation, but it seems plausible that identical motor and
tance; the role of other limbic structures, and in particular the autonomic responses and facial expressions as well as complex
amygdala, may be decisive in the feeling of emotion. adaptive goal-directed forms of behavior - in both animals and
What I do not agree with, however, is Panksepp's classifica- man, and in both experimental and everyday life situations -
tion of the emotions in terms of his four arbitrary categories, correspond to identical feelings. Studies on the electrical stim-
which I do not find to be of equal importance. ulation of the human brain also indicate that stimulation of
I shall now attempt to develop my arguments in more detail. I structures similar to those from which emotional reactions can
agree with Panksepp that emotions have their concrete neural be evoked in animals produces feelings in people (Heath &
substrates and that they are objective events occurring in Mickle 1960, King 1961; Mark & Erwin 1970, Sem-Jacobsen &
humans as well as in animals. They may be ascribed to definite Torkildsen 1960.)
brain circuits that are similar (though not identical) in humans Consider that, after all, our knowledge about human feelings
and in higher animals (not only mammals). I have always argued is likewise based on extrapolation. We cannot be sure whether
with those who deny the possibility of investigating emotion and the emotions of others, even those of our friends, are similar to
who ascribe only subjective meaning to this term (Fonberg our own. When a friend smiles, shakes your hand, or kisses you,
1972; 1979a; 1981). I think that such attitudes derive from you assume that he is happy to see you. But your dog is also
idealistic and religious traditions according to which emotions "happy" to see you - "smiles," wags his tail, jumps on you, licks
belong to the soul and not to the body, and are hence inaccessi- your hand. I would even say that you can be surer about the
ble to experiment. On the other side, the attitude is reinforced emotional state of your dog than that of your friend. The friend
by the Skinnerian approach: that the only objective way to study can give you more details about his emotions verbally, but, in
stimulus-response mechanisms is to ignore the underlying reality, you count on his friendship, not on the basis of his
brain substrates. Along with the behaviorists, most physiolo- words, but on the basis of his behavior.
gists have objected strongly to using the term "emotion" in The brain of a friend is more similar to your own, but the
science. (I have always wondered why they have never denied emotional parts of the brain are also well developed in other
the objectivity of investigating the pain system while denying mammals. Similar emotional structures with similar functions
objectivity to all other emotional investigations. Is it not the can be compared in man and mammals; it is therefore reason-
same kind of extrapolation to assume that animals see colors and able to assume that similar behavior and similar brain structures
feel pain like us, as that they feel joy, rage, and fear? are the basis for similar emotions. It is true that the amygdala,
Some years ago, at a conference on emotions and psychoso- for example, is more complicated in humans than in dogs or cats,
matic illness, I presented my own point of view concerning but this is because inhibitory and coordinative mechanisms are
emotions (Fonberg 1972): It cannot be denied that emotional more developed in man.
states exist in reality, and that they must therefore depend on My high estimation of Panksepp's attempt to objectivize the
physiological mechanisms; it follows that we should be able to emotions does not preclude my pointing out that his schema is
investigate them by physiological methods. However, the psy- not superior to numerous (likewise imperfect) models of prior
chological ballast weighs particularly heavily on the definition of investigators, who were already, long ago, convinced that cer-
the word "emotional," and various authors use it in different tain neural circuits were at the basis of emotion. The Panksepp
senses (Fonberg 1972). Panksepp, too, fails to define this term model consists only of one more hypothetical neural circuit
strictly. He mixes the terms "feeling" and emotion. Feelings are joined with arbitrary classes of emotions; this does not build a
not a weaker form of emotions, but have a more specific sensory convincing bridge between the introspective feelings of emo-
aspect, whereas the word emotion includes a hedonic valence. tion in his classification and their real brain substrates. Another
According to my own view (Fonberg 1972), the term "emotion" weak point is that Panksepp's model ignores the very attractive
comprises (1) negative or positive subjective feelings; (2) exter- hypothesis of the negative and positive hedonic systems as well
nal emotional symptoms such as motor responses (including as the problem of motivation. Such an approach overlooks
facial expressions), vocalization, and various autonomic changes emotional mechanisms very important for both introspective
specific to different emotional states; and (3) complex forms of and behavioral investigations.
behavior that enable motivated actions to be performed (their
feedback being also of positive or negative emotional character). I do not accept Panksepp's classification of emotions into four
classes, three negative ones and only one (very controversial)
I also assume that the appearance of various emotional re- positive one. Let us comment on the validity of these classes.

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 429


Commentary'/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

Expectancy. This term is arbitrarily introduced by Panksepp agree with Panksepp in stressing the role of the hypothalamus
and consists of a large drawer into which many noncomparable and have myself put forward similar ideas (Fonberg 1966; 1967).
items are thrown. First of all, if one is to use the term expectancy However, our experiments on the effect of amygdala lesions
at all, why restrict it to the expectancy of positive events? There have shown that the dorsomedial part of the amygdala is proba-
can just as well be expectancy of danger, pain, distress, en- bly even more important for emotional states. After receiving
emies, even of fear; expectancy is therefore the preparatory lesions in this area, dogs, who are very good subjects for
period for all the rest of the categories in Panksepp's taxonomy studying emotion, are completely indifferent and emotionless.
rather than a separate category. Positive emotional states are not They are able to perform many difficult tasks, but they rarely do.
limited to expectancy: They are chiefly connected with achieve- They lose their affectionate behavior toward the experimenter,
ments. One does not feel joy when one possesses a lottery ticket which is reflected in deterioration on their socially reinforced
(even if one expects good fortune); one feels joy at the moment of tasks (Fonberg 1972; 1981; Fonberg & Kostarczyk 1980).
receiving the information that the number has won, when one I would rather think that the amygdala is crucial for emotion
obtains the money, and, later, spends it. According to (perhaps for the subjective evaluation of its hedonistic valence)
drive-reduction theories, expectancy (which in other terms and that the hypothalamus is involved in integrative and execu-
would be called drive) is unpleasant (this, however, not always tive functions connected with emotional behavior. In this re-
correct), and only drive-reduction (i.e., satisfaction) is pleasant. spect the hypothalamus could be regarded as a "command"
The physiological meaning of expectancy as used by Panksepp is system.
also very vague. On the one hand it is treated as a kind of general Inhibition of emotions is a problem that should also be
arousal or nonspecific motivation (with nonspecific external considered, but it is scarcely discussed by Panksepp. The
signs such as searching, sniffing, etc.). On the other hand, it existence of two functionally antagonistic systems (i.e., excitato-
includes specific behaviors - those involved in feeding, drink- ry and inhibitory) within the amygdala (Fonberg 1963; 1968)
ing, sexual behavior, etc. The fact that during stimulation suggests that emotions, although also controlled by the neo-
animals can change their behavior according to environmental cortex, may be inhibited in their own source within the emotion
stimuli does not indicate that the state evoked by brain stimula- system, and this inhibition may have a more intrinsic character.
tion is a nonspecific arousal to do anything or to expect anything; In conclusion, I did read Panksepp's article with great in-
it indicates that behavior evoked by this stimulation is not terest, for he discusses many very important points and fur-
limited to automatic motor patterns but, like normal behavior, is nishes much extremely interesting data. I have not discussed all
adaptable, and can be modified. the important topics the article called to mind (e.g., the neu-
Panic. Another quite arbitrarily introduced term is panic, rochemistry of emotions and the role of emotions in psychiatric
which, according to the dictionary as well as in psychiatry and disorders, which is very close to my own interest; see Fonberg
social psychological usage means "sudden terror, excessive, 1958; 1979a; 1981). I agree fully with his main thesis that
uncontrollable, and illogical fear, infectious fright." This corre- emotions are objective events and that they should be investi-
sponds to a generalized fear state. On the basis of my own gated by combined psychological, behavioral, anatomical, and
experiments on the generalization of fear stimuli, I have put neurochemical methods, and ascribed to definite brain sub-
forward the hypothesis that there exist separate brain mecha- strates. Panksepp's essay did not entirely fulfill my expectations
nisms for specific fears (fear of a definite imminent noxious (in the usual sense of this word), because his arbitrary taxonomy
event) and mechanisms of generalized fear (Fonberg 1961), and model do not clarify these very important issues. The article
which are also activated during neurotic states (Fonberg 1958; was, nevertheless, very interesting and stimulating to
1979a). But if we accept the division of emotions into only a few discussion.
classes, panic would surely belong to the emotion of fear. Crying
produced by the isolation of young from their mother is also
evoked by fear. Other symptoms of "panic" described by Pank-
sepp are rather similar to signs of general depression.
Fear and rage. These two classes of emotions in Panksepp's
classification are less controversial; they are widely accepted Can phenomenology contribute to brain
and based on numerous data. Most authors agree that the fear science?
and rage systems are separate, although some do think they
form one common system. My experiments on dogs indicate Gordon G. Globus
that there are quite separate points from which rage and fear University of California Irvine Psychiatry Service, Capistrano by the Sea
responses can be evoked (Fonberg 1966; 1967). These behaviors Hospital, Dana Point, Calif. 92629
were stably evoked for weeks by the stimulation of definite My aim is to comment sympathetically on Panksepp's thesis that
points and never substituted for one another. I have shown that "human introspective access to emotional states may provide
avoidance responses are easily formed to a conditional stimulus direct information concerning operations of emotive circuits and
by the stimulation of fear points, but not rage points. Other thus be a primary source of hypotheses for animal brain re-
authors have demonstrated that stimulating rage attack points search." I shall, however, consider the more general thesis that
can even have a rewarding effect (Fonberg 1979b; Perochio & human introspective access to all conscious states may provide
Alexander 1974). such direct information, namely, that the disciplined study of
The fear system is separate from the pain system (Bolles & consciousness (i.e., phenomenology) can contribute to brain
Fanselow 1980; Fonberg 1980), a fact that Panksepp seems to science. If it is so for emotional states, then it is likely so for all
overlook. But even the pain system (as shown by anatomical and conscious states as well.
physiological studies) is not uniform and can be divided into I shall expand Panksepp's framework in another way, by
three different systems (sensory, cognitive, and emotional), considering some of the conceptual morasses that he (perhaps
with different anatomical substrates. Mechanisms of aggressive wisely) avoids, especially the "world knot" of the consciousness/
behavior and rage are also very complicated and depend on brain problems, which entangles us as soon as we try to unpack
different emotional states (Adams 1979; Fonberg 1979b; Per- what Panksepp means by "direct" information. Now, contem-
ochio & Alexander 1974), but at least the term rage is much porary brain science has provided richly detailed knowledge
more understandable than expectancy and panic, and the re- regarding the covariation of consciousness and brain. But until
sults of corresponding investigations are more precise. we have a systematic account of the rules governing this covaria-
Another question I would like to raise is whether the hypo- tion, Panksepp's thesis and its present generalization are se-
thalamus is the most important brain structure for emotions. I riously compromised. In effect, depending on one's particular

430 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentan//Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
view of the consciousness/brain problems, the thesis may or may we are in a position to theorize that the highest brain system or
not be correct. "super system" has two primary modes of organization, an
For example, if consciousness is an emergent property of ordinary mode associated with what is presumably a very high-
brain functioning, as Sperry (1969) would have it, then Pank- level neural processing action and an extraordinary mode in
sepp's taxonomy of emotion does not tell brain science anything, which that action ceases. The complexity of this system's organi-
for Sperry's emergent is different from, more than, and not zation can vary continuously. There is variation in the complex-
reducible to the underlying neural operations; indeed, it would ity of this system's organization during waking and periodically
be a species of category error to make inferences/rom emergent during sleep. The study of the brain during dreaming thus
properties to properties of the interacting parts from which they provides an opportunity to understand how this system is
emerge. If consciousness is fundamentally distinct from brain, autonomously constituted, without the complications of on-
but interacting with it, as the Cartesian Eccles (1976) would going sensory input and behavior. I think it would be quite
have it, then a classification in one does not necessarily imply difficult to come to such a theory via laboratory investigation - at
anything about a classification in the other. Of course, if con- least in the present state of the art.
sciousness is "strictly identical" with brain (Feigl 1967), then Whatever the value of Panksepp's observations and the pre-
Panksepp's thesis is literally correct. sent phenomenological ones, it can be seen that the study of
The claim that phenomenology can contribute to brain sci- consciousness could aid in developing the theory of brain at its
ence is thus relative to a pre-existing philosophical position that most complex levels of functioning, a level about which brain
Panksepp does not indicate. When he talks of a conscious mind science is notoriously silent and - given the complexity of the
that is able to "see clearly" subcortical dynamics, brain circuits system under consideration - is likely to remain silent for some
which "mediate" emotions, and brain mechanisms that "elabo- time. Practically speaking, if we are to theorize at all about the
rate" consciousness, he owes us a viable account of the con- highest levels of brain functioning, we ought at least to consider
sciousness/brain relation which will specify the meanings of the what phenomenologists have to say about consciousness in
terms in quotation. devising our theories.
There are various attitudes brain scientists may adopt when In summary, Panksepp's thesis generalized to the claim that
faced with this philosophical puzzle. Probably the great majority phenomenology can contribute to brain science can only be
would recoil from the philosophical issues entailed by Pank- judged pragmatically, in the absence of a solution to the con-
sepp's thesis and continue to do the bench science they have sciousness/brain problems. With the impoverished knowledge
been (quite successfully) doing all along. Some intrepid pragma- that we presently have of brain functioning at the highest levels,
tists may choose to follow Panksepp's lead and actually do some it would be premature to rule out any phenomenological contri-
systematic study of their own consciousness, and then see if it bution on dogmatic grounds. In the context of a multifaceted
proves of heuristic value for their research. Others may even be brain science, it would seem instead salutary to admit a lively
motivated to work directly on the consciousness/brain problems interface between phenomenology and brain science, as Pank-
so as to give phenomenological contributions to brain science a sepp has demonstrated for the case of emotions.
firm foundation. Although these problems are traditionally
considered the province of philosophy, and empirical science is
thought to be irrelevant to their resolution, it is worth consider-
ing the possibility (since we seem no closer than ever to resolv-
ing these problems) that a clear understanding of some basic On the classification of the emotions
principles of brain functioning might move philosophical discus-
sion forward at certain sticking points (such as the notorious Jeffrey A. Gray
causal theory of perception). Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, Oxford 0X1
3UD, England
A comparison of the merits of these respective attitudes
would require considerable discussion, and would probably Panksepp has described a general approach to the construction
prove indecisive, since these attitudes run deep. On issues like of a psychobiological theory of emotion with which I am in
this, each of us tends to take the path which interests him most, substantial agreement. Details of the scheme for classifying the
which is probably salutary, since it maintains scientific plural- emotions that Panksepp proposes are also consonant in part with
ism. I want to adopt the pragmatic attitude here toward the a scheme put forward previously on different grounds (Gray
general thesis that the study of consciousness can contribute to 1972). However, Panksepp's scheme rests on too narrow an
brain science, and to supplement Panksepp's illustration of this evidential basis (largely that of experiments on self-stimulation
by another example. and experimenter-applied stimulation of the hypothalamus). In
I shall consider briefly a partial taxonomy of consciousness, consequence, his suggested set of four basic emotional states
and what value it might have for brain science. I claim (where runs into major difficulties when it is confronted with data
"claim" is understood phenomenologically as an invitation to obtained by other methods.
coreflect; Zaner 1970) that consciousness over time divides into These difficulties centre on Panksepp's distinction between
two incompatible phases. In the ordinary phase of intentional "fear" and "rage," a distinction based upon the experimental
action, consciousness is always a consciousness-of, whether difference between sites in the hypothalamus at which stimula-
conscious of emotions, wants, external objects, thoughts, etc. In tion elicits flight (= fear) and attack (= rage) respectively. But,
the extraordinary phase in which all intentionality ceases (which even within Panksepp's own terms of reference, the distinction
may require some special training in meditation to achieve), is weakly supported. For, as he states, "Hypothalamic sites that
there is no consciousness-of. There is no object of awareness. provoke flight surround the core systems from which rage
There are no distinctions whatsoever. There is only the distinc- (threat behavior) is elicited (de Molina & Hunsperger 1962), and
tionless case of an unbroken and unbounded whole. I claim also there appears to be substantial anatomical overlap and func-
that consciousness may vary continuously in "richness'; under tional interaction between these systems." And, as his discus-
different conditions, there is more or less of it, as when we are sion elsewhere in the article makes clear, given such overlap and
wide awake, drowsy, or in nondreaming sleep. Furthermore, interaction, it is an arbitrary decision (in the absence of other
the state of sleep periodically supports episodes of conscious- evidence) whether flight and attack are alternative expressions
ness (dreaming) that can be so vivid that they are indistinguisha- of the same emotional state (as suggested by Gray, 1972) or each
ble from waking consciousness.
an expression of a different emotional state (as believed by
If these phenomenological observations in fact do provide Panksepp). Fortunately, there is other evidence. But this evi-
"direct information," as Panksepp says, about the brain, then dence does not favour two of Panksepp's key assumptions: that

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 431


Com?nentan//Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

"fear" should be defined in terms of flight, and that flight and tioned aversive stimuli and manifested (among other ways) as
attack reflect different emotional states. passive avoidance behaviour. Second, a separate "fight-flight
How should one define fear? Defining fear in terms of flight system" mediates responses to unconditioned aversive stimuli,
behaviour leads to conclusions that are at variance with those and activity in this system may manifest itself as eitherflightor
that can be derived from most other relevant lines of argument. attack behaviour. I have set out the evidence for this theory
Two other behavioural measures have commonly been used in elsewhere (Gray 1972; 1982a; 1982b). Clearly, further experi-
studies of fear: defecation (especially in the open field test), as in mental work is needed to test the two models. The fact that they
studies of the genetics of fearfulness (Broadhurst 1960) or sex make such clearly different assumptons at these key points
differences in fearfulness (Gray 1979b); and the suppression of should facilitate the task of discriminating between them.
responding under threat of footshock, as in the use of Geller and
Seifter's (1960) schedule or passive avoidance paradigms to
quantify anxiety. Neither of these measures relates to flight
behaviour in the way that Panksepp's scheme would lead us to
expect. Thus, antianxiety drugs, which clearly alleviate be- Panksepp's psychobiological theory of
havioural suppression induced by the threat of shock, do not in emotions: Some substantiation
general affect escape (Gray 1977); septal lesions, which reduce
both passive avoidance behaviour and open field defecation, do Robert G. Heath
not affect skilled escape behaviour and they even improve Department of Psychiatry and Neurology, Tulane University School of
Medicine, New Orleans, La. 70112
escape during agonistic encounters with conspecifics (Gray
1982a); and female rats, who defecate less and show poorer Panksepp has tackled a subject of tremendous scope. The
passive avoidance than males (Gray 1979b), nonetheless run manner in which he undertakes the task is to be commended.
more than males when they are shocked (Beatty & Beatty 1970; He modestly labels his hypothesis as a start, which he hopes will
Wilcock 1968). It follows from such patterns of data (and others lead to sound experimental work for broadening the base under-
could be cited) that, ifflightis the correct criterion of fear, these lying his theory. I am in agreement with many of the ideas he
other measures are inappropriate. Yet the case for both defeca- advances.
tion and passive avoidance as measures of fear is strong, and A major premise of Panksepp's is the importance of introspec-
furthermore (although there are exceptions) the conclusions to tion by human beings, the only species capable of reporting its
which these two indices give rise are usually concordant with thoughts and feelings - essential information in providing leads
one another (Gray 1979b). It would seem more parsimonious, concerning the function of neural-emotive circuits. Although
therefore, to abandon the postulate thatflightis a good index of Panksepp is somewhat apologetic in discussing this point, I
fear, especially since Panksepp does not offer either evidence or consider it a primary strength of his article. It is apparent from
argument in favour of this postulate. human introspection that sensory perception is closely interre-
Do flight and attack reflect different emotional states? As lated with emotion. Panksepp cites a number of references, but
noted above, the hypothalamic sites at which stimulation elicits the data base he uses to substantiate his hypothesis of brain
flight and attack closely intermingle. Indeed, they are some- circuitry and emotion is, unfortunately, narrow. Whereas he
times the same sites. As Panksepp states, stimulation at some focuses principally on the effects of stimulation to and ablation of
points "typically elicits flight, [but] defensive attack often en- the lateral hypothalamus in the rat, the existing data base for this
sues, if no avenue of escape is available." Under these circum- neural-emotional behavioral relationship is much broader. It is
stances, one may reasonably assume that both these patterns of derived from the use of many additional divergent methods and
behaviour are expressions of the same emotional state, the thereby provides hard data to support some aspects of Pank-
nature of the environment then determining which pattern
sepp's hypothesis. Moreover, the available data base provides
prevails on a particular occasion. Such an assumption would lie
comfortably within Panksepp's general line of reasoning (though additional platforms for modified and expanded hypotheses for
he chooses not to make it). It is supported by the general the collection of still more data.
similarity between the experimental conditions which, in non- The most significant data are from extensive human studies in
physiological experiments, provoke flight and attack respec- which a wide variety of inspective findings have been correlated
tively. These two patterns of behaviour may each be elicited not with the subjective introspective data reported by patients
only (as is well known) by punishing stimuli (e.g., footshock), (Heath 1974; 1975; Heath, Cox, & Lustick 1974; Heath &
but also by frustrative nonreward (e.g., Adelman & Maatsch Gallant 1964). These investigations involved implantation of
1956; Gallup 1965). Furthermore, there appears to be a psycho- deep brain electrodes for long-term studies. Electrodes have
logically important distinction between unconditioned punish- been implanted not only into the hypothalamus and numerous
ment and nonreward, on the one hand, and conditioned stimuli, other sites in the conventional limbic system, but also into
which signal the imminent occurrence of these two events, on several sensory relay nuclei and deep sites involving other
the other. Both flight and attack are elicited by unconditioned functional systems, as well as over numerous surface brain
aversive events of either (whereas behavioural inhibition or areas. With these techniques, the effects of brain stimulation on
freezing are not); while conditioned aversive stimuli do not feelings have been recorded. Further, it has been possible to
typically elicit either flight or attack, but freezing and be- correlate changes in deep brain activity (electroen-
havioural inhibition instead (Gray 1975; Myer 1971). cephalographic recordings) with varied emotional states: spon-
taneous emotion, emotional states induced in association with
This distinction between conditioned and unconditioned mood-altering drugs, and, in a few cases, emotional states
aversive stimuli makes it possible to predict many of the effects induced with administration of transmitters directly into the
of drugs (Feldon, Guillamon, Gray, De Wit, & McNaughton brain parenchyma at sites within the "hard-wired" emotive
1979; Gray 1977); and it forms part of the evidence on which I circuits. Multiple brain recordings concomitant with patients'
have based the concept of a "behavioural inhibition system" introspective reporting have suggested that correlates with both
specialized to respond to signals of aversive events (whether pleasurable and aversive emotional states occur elsewhere than
punishing or frustrating) but not the aversive events themselves in the lateral hypothalamus. Both recording and stimulation
(Gray 1975; 1977). The resulting model differs from Panksepp's data indicate that the lateral hypothalamus may well be func-
in the following two principal ways. First, anxiety (which sub- tioning as a type of final common pathway in the emotional
sumes the concepts of fear and anticipatory frustration as used circuitry. This would suggest that one should use caution in
by Mowrer, 1960, and Amsel, 1962, respectively) is treated as extrapolating too extensively from rat data (self-stimulation,
activity in the behavioural inhibition system, elicited by condi- ablation). Let us hope that Panksepp has put to rest the long-

432 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Comm«ntart//Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

prevailing concept that brain stimulation, as observed in ani- behavior in any direction and relative to any object or event, but
mals, represents sham rage. The emotion generated in patients all the appetitive functions under the expectancy command
by means of brain stimulation has always been an integral part of system are highly specific with respect to object and consumma-
consciousness - never a sham response. tion, with the possible exception of exploration. Interest, in
Deep electrode studies in intractably ill patients have led to human beings, surely motivates all kinds of exploration - from
studies in animals in which it was possible to outline the extent environmental to epistemic - and it can in the course of such
of the emotional circuitry, as well as the functional relationships exploration interact with other emotions as well as with the
within the system more completely and precisely than cited by appetitive functions. So here we may have a common ground.
Pankscpp. "Although it is clear that lateral hypothalamic neu- But is it enough? Perhaps it is, for it certainly suggests a common
ropil contains widely ramifying, long-axoned systems, both thread across a wide span of species. And it seems reasonable
ascending and descending, with multiple interneuronal feed- that in human phylogeny something like Panksepp's expectancy
back loops, . . . our knowledge of functional circuits in such a command system could have differentiated into various rela-
reticular substance remains too imperfect to attempt filling in tively independent motivational systems, including such drives
the details of system connectivities." Numerous anatom- or affects as hunger and sex, as well as the emotion of interest.
ic-physiologic studies in animals (derived from the correlated I am suggesting that the human emotion of interest - which,
introspective-inspective studies in human subjects) provide a among other things, promotes attention to biologically as well as
base of hard data for Panksepp's speculation about interrelations socially important stimuli (Langsdorf, Izard, & Rayias 1981) -
of the neural systems for sensation and emotion (Heath 1976; may have had its origins in something like an expectancy
1977; Heath, Dempesy, Fontana & Fitzjarrel 1980; Heath, command system. Its evolution as a discrete system indepen-
Franklin, & Shraberg 1979; Heath, Llewellyn, & Rouchell dent of appetitive functions may have stemmed from mutant
1980). They have led to the demonstration of the important role behaviors that had no immediate consummatory goal, were not
of the vestibular proprioceptive cerebellum (midline vermis) in stimulus-bound, yet had longer range pay-off in the processes
modulating emotion, as well as the recent demonstration of of adaptation. For example, the distinct advantage of territorial
cerebellar pathology associated with disordered emotion. In exploration without the restrictions of appetitive drives is the
sensory deprivation experiments, the absence of proprioceptive greater flexibility of cognitive and motor activities.
input rapidly induces the severe disruptive emotion characteris- In similar fashion, something like the "panic" command
tic of psychosis. Auditory and visual stimuli can profoundly alter system could have given rise to the drive-free human emotions
one's emotional state, and, conversely, changes in emotional of sadness and anger. However, Panksepp's panic command
state alter sensory perception. Panksepp correctly relates appe- system would be much more appropriately labeled the distress
titive behaviors to emotional circuitry. Basic metabolic states command system. While panic connotes overwhelming terror
related to survival selectively alter both emotional and sensory (the extreme of fear), distress connects both semantically and
perception. historically with sorrow, sadness, or grief. Darwin (1872/1965)
In conclusion, I agree with most of the principles in Pank- argued that the human expression of sadness is a neuromuscular
sepp's well-outlined hypothesis. To avoid repetition, I have not pattern that regulates the emergency facial and vocal expression
focused on many of his major points with which I agree. I have of physical distress. The young infant's physical-distress facial
chosen instead to discuss only a few of the author's points that I pattern in the brow-eye region (brow drawn sharply down and
believe could have been better illustrated had he drawn on the together and eyes tightly closed) can be converted to a sadness
existing broader data base. Like Panksepp, I feel the need to signal (obliquely raised inner corners of the eyebrows and
emphasize that the subject under consideration is much broader slightly squinted eyes) by contraction of the medial frontalis
than can be reviewed in this relatively short commentary. Only muscle, which is antagonistic to the orbicularis oculi, corruga-
a few aspects of this very broad subject have therefore been tor, glabella, and eyebrow depressors that tightly close the eyes
considered. and lower the brows. Interestingly, the pattern in the mouth
region that completes the full-face sadness expression (mouth
corners pulled downward by action of the depressor anguli oris)
is occasionally seen in young infants immediately following
From stimulus-bound emotive command painful medical procedures (Izard, Dougherty, Coss, &
Hembree 1981). This latter pattern tends to reduce the size of
systems to drive-free emotions the mouth and is associated with (and may "cause") a dampening
C. E. Izard of the distress cry (vocalization). These changes in the facial and
Department of Psychology, University of Delaware, Newark, Del. 19711
vocal signals probably tend to elicit cuddling and other nur-
turant behaviors from the care-giver.
As a differential emotions theorist, concerned mainly with the In terms of observable display, the anger expression is even
role of discrete emotions and patterns of emotions in human closer to the infant's physical distress expression, and in young
development, I found myself avidly foraging through Pank- infants this expression is often followed by an anger expression.
sepp's article, swept along, at times seemingly uncontrollably, This suggests possible interconnections between pain or physi-
by my expectancy command system, or rather by its human cal distress, sadness, and anger, with the latter being the
homologue. In my theory (Izard 1977), the homologue would be emotional counterpart of the protest seen in mother-infant
the discrete emotion of interest-excitement and various other separation. Relevant to this point and to Panksepp's discussion
emotions in patterns or combinations with interest, patterns of separation as a stimulus that activates the panic command
that would modify the direction and intensity of behavior as system, Shiller and Izard (1981) have found that the most
required by ecological conditions and events. frequent emotion expression during brief separation of 13-
There is a serious though perhaps not fatal flaw in this month-old human infants from their mothers was anger; the
homology. The emotion of interest, although capable of amplify- second most frequent expression was sadness, with a small
ing or attenuating the appetitive behaviors under the control of minority showing this expression predominantly.
Panksepp's expectancy command system, is also capable of Much of what Panksepp describes under the rubric of the
operating quite independently of them. My foray through this panic command system parallels in some way what we see in
article was accomplished while my appetitive drives were well human distress and sadness. As just noted, however, we see
satisfied. Thus, the emotion of interest is neither an appetitive anger and sadness in mother-infant separations, but we have
affect nor one that is slave to consummatory behavior. Interest observed no parallel for the freezing-explosive behavior se-
has the utmost flexibility and generality, capable of motivating quence Panksepp describes.

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 433


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
In early infancy, certain emotion expressions sometimes ap- the vastly important one of recruiting and sustaining appropri-
pear to function as stimulus-bound behaviors. Pain immediate- ate cognitions and instrumental behaviors.
ly elicits the well-defined physical distress pattern, and a nod-
ding human face regularly evokes a smile. While these affective
expressions do not serve appetitive drives, they function as
powerful social signals that typically elicit nurturant and positive A two-tiered theory of emotions: Affect and
affective behavior on the part of the care-giver. With increasing
age, increasing cognitive and motor capacities, and the impact of feeling
life experiences, the emotion expressions appear less and less
Julian Jaynes
stimulus-bound; they become responsive to a virtually limitless
Department of Psychology, Princeton University, Princeton, N.J. 08544
array of stimuli. It is this great capacity of the human being to
respond with emotion and hence to be appropriately motivated No theory of emotion can make sense out of the psychological
in relation to highly diverse incentive events that make human data unless it is absolutely clear about what is conscious in
behavior so complex and so adaptive in so many different emotional experience and what is not.
situations. Let me state briefly my own point of view.
The rage and fear command systems have quite comparable All mammals, including ourselves, have a basic set of genet-
homologues in human emotions. It is conceivable that at an ically organized affects, specific aptitudes to respond to charac-
early stage in our evolution, the similarity was even greater. terizable classes of stimuli or events in certain characterizable
At the present time, of course, comparisons yield several ways. Back in evolutionary history, I believe, the core of most of
important differences between these command systems and the these aptitudes, their "aptic paradigms," were actual overt
emotions of anger-rage and fear—terror in human beings. In behaviors of reptiles. But in mammals these overt behaviors
human beings there are weaker connections between activation have become inhibited by more recently evolved parts of the
of the anger mechanisms and aggression than is the case in lower brain, leaving them more diffusely related to actual overt behav-
animals. Also in the case of human beings, anger and fear (as is ior in a more general energizing way (MacLean 1973). Most
true of other emotions) rarely occur in "pure" forms for very emotional behaviors of mammals are thus paleoreptilian behav-
long. They typically occur in patterns with other emotions that iors transformed on both the stimulus and the response side by
are caused by events in the situation and by the original emo- limbic and cortical selective inhibition. And just as the behav-
tion, anger or fear. These patterns of emotion elicit (or occur iors in the repertoire of any animal cannot be set out as similar
with) certain affective-cognitive structures that stem from things, with the same characteristics - being different in their
learning and life experiences. The other emotions in the pattern nature, timing, pervasiveness, situational dependence, interre-
and the affective-cognitive structures serve to inhibit, amplify, lations with other behaviors, and dependence or independence
or attenuate the "original" emotion and give human behavior its of them - so mammalian emotions also cannot be set out in a
great complexity and variable relationships with external linear array. A list of mammalian emotions or affects, although
events. nonlinear and often interlocking, could start off clearly enough
I have a few miscellaneous comments on the paper. (1) M. B. with the usual items like fear, anger, disgust, and the various
Arnold (1960a; 1960b) should be credited for the observation affectional systems (Harlow 1971) and then end up somewhat
that "phenomenological analysis of emotional experience can vaguely, but no less appropriately, with those behaviors that are
guide us in identifying the brain structures and pathways that less commonly called emotional because of their lesser inten-
mediate feelings and emotions" (1960a, p. iii). (2) The robust sity, such as drowsiness and curiosity. Since expectancy is
evidence for the innateness and universality of certain human common to all molar mammalian behavior, I would not include
emotion expressions (Ekman, Friesen, & Ellsworth 1972; Izard it in such a list.
1971) provides general support for Panksepp's view of emotions Are all behaviors emotions? It is not the behaviors themselves
as fundamental evolutionary-biological phenomena. (3) A that we denote by emotions, but their inferred organizations,
rapidly growing body of research on emotions in human devel- which usually include four characteristics: (1) emotions have a
opment is generally supportive of Panksepp's view on the clear variation in intensity, so that every emotion has a more or
fruitfulness of an ontogenetic approach in understanding less to it; (2) even if not immediately expressed, emotions are
brain-emotion relationships. (4) the emotional-behavioral pro- associated with a distinct class of behaviors; (3) emotions have
cesses described under the panic command system (at least the
bodily and often facial expressions, which are distinguishable
sadness/grief components) are more probably associated with
depressive disorders rather than those specified in Figure 5. (5) from more usual states; (4) there exist distinct classes of stimuli
The concept of "emotional disorders" as commonly used is a or situations that occasion emotions.
misnomer, from Panksepp's vantage point, as well as mine. In This list is to be compared with Panksepp's list under his
Panksepp's system and in differential emotions theory, the heading "A definition of emotions." What Panksepp has done is
emotions are basically adaptive. In cognitive and behavioral to suggest a theory of the brain circuitry involved that is
dysfunction, the problem is not with the emotions but with interesting in itself, but is so restricted in an ad hoc way as to
faulty or deficient connections between emotion, cognition, and eliminate many behavioral responses that most observers would
behavior. Panksepp's use of the term emotional disorder as include under the term emotion.
unbalanced activities among emotions (or "emotive systems") is But the real point of my commentary concerns consciousness
a reasonable one, but it does not reflect the problem of dishar- and how consciousness, once established in history, adds some-
mony between the emotion, cognition, and motor-behavior thing new to genetically programmed mammalian affects that
systems. we can call/eeftngs. I believe this to be an historical change that
occurred in the ancient Mediterranean and Near Eastern world
Despite my differences with Panksepp - some of which must sometime after 1000 B.C. which, as I have tried to show else-
come from differences in perspectives developed from immer- where, is the beginning of the period when human beings
sion in the study of different phyla - I think his article provides learned consciousness on the basis of metaphor (Jaynes 1976).
biopsychological support for the currently increasing accep- By consciousness I mean precisely what Panksepp does in his
tance of differential emotions theory, which postulates a limited few references to it, namely, all our introspective experience,
number of innate fundamental emotions, each with a unique set including retrospection and imagination. Once human beings
of neurophysiological substrates, expressions, and quality of have these capacities, they can think out consciously and pri-
consciousness (Izard 1977). The last is basically a feeling state vately what they are to do, in contrast to a more ancient
that has inherently motivational-adaptive functions, including mentality called the "bicameral mind," in which what we call

434 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentary/Vanksepp: Psychobinlogy of emotions

volition was a matter of hearing and obeying auditory hallucina- very definitely demonstrating that sexual feelings were a new
tions called gods. and profound concern in human development in these regions.
With this metaphor-generated consciousness, there comes We can perhaps appreciate this change in ourselves if we try to
the metaphor of time as a space, or spatialized time, in which imagine what our sexual lives would be like if we could not
human beings 'see' themselves as embedded in their own fantasize about sexual behavior.
histories. This human sense of a lifetime begins over the same By this two-tiered theory, I mean to imply that because of our
period as the development of the idea of historical time (for ability to fantasize, both by reminiscing about the past and
evidence for this, see Starr 1968), as well as the appearance of imagining the future, our present affectional experience consists
ideas of justice, retribution, doing wrong, remission of wrongs, of far more than the basic affects of mammals. I should like to
and forgiveness, all very curious behaviors when we think of point out here in passing how well this development fits in with
them against the background of the evolution of mammalian the James-Lange theory (with some slight shifts in terminology).
behavior, and all occurring in world history for the first time. We see a bear, which occasions the genetically organizaed affect
The result is a new set of social and political problems. Behind of fear, and we run away, which we are then conscious of,
these social changes are the changes in personal emotion that turning the fear into the feelings of extreme anxiety. So the
arisefromthe new human capacity to stretch out the affects over James-Cannon controversy may be resolved.
the spatialized time, or, in other words, to dwell on past Emotional terminology is a considerable problem. We have
behaviors or on possible future behaviors and respond to them an excessive vocabulary of emotional terms that arise from our
as if they were presently occurring, with copies of the affects own experience and the culture in which we live. In observing
themselves. These are our feelings. My language here is difficult animal behavior, when we see a behavior similar to our own in
and metaphoric, because these processes are not fully under- emotional circumstances, we usually label it with that emotion.
stood at present. But let us consider some examples. This is, of course, all we can do; otherwise the behavior of
Shame is one of the most powerful affects. (For the best animals is merely topological. But if we have not made a clear
discussion, see Tomkins 1963). It occurs in many mammals, distinction between the affects and conscious feelings, we are
such as canines, primates, and early man. Observation of pre- likely to make mistakes and project our own conscious feelings
sent-day children's development or reminiscences about our into the simple affects of lower animals. Panksepp is making the
own will demonstrate the tyrannous power of humiliation, of methodological point that we have to use our own consciousness
rejection from a social group, in shaping behavior to some norm of our own behavior to label the emotions of lower animals.
or other. In fact, we have all been so shaped by shame into our True. But it certainly needs the added caution I have just
customary behavior that, as adults, we rarely have this affect in outlined. The two-tiered theory also suggests that studies of
its pure state. But once human beings can reminisce about hypothalamic stimulation or other presently known neural sub-
shameful actions or imagine possible shameful actions, until strates of emotion in animals, although largely important for
they imagine real or possible humiliation and ostracization in a understanding basic mammalian affects, are limited in their
general way, we have guilt: Guilt is thus a conscious feeling that application to human emotional experience.
is generated from the biological affect of shame.
This is obvious, I think, in the development of consciousness
in the child (see Kohlberg 1976). It is also evident in the Parting's sweet sorrow: A pain pathway for
development of consciousness in ancient history. Consider, for
example, the story of Oedipus. In its earliest form (in two lines the social sentiments?
from the Iliad and two lines from the Odyssey - pretty meager Leonard D. Katz
evidence, I agree), it seems to be the story of a king who had
Department of Philosophy, Princeton University, Princeton, N.J. 08544
killed his father and married his mother and had two daughters-
sisters by her, and who (since the incest taboo is the reason the The general theoretical and methodological framework em-
story is mentioned at all) certainly felt some shame, but then ployed by Panksepp should be relatively uncontroversial within
apparently lived a long remorseless life with his somewhat the community of physiological psychologists, ethologists, and
strange family until he was buried with military honors at comparative neuroanatomists interested in the functional
Thebes. But just a few centuries later, in the fifth century B.C., neuroscience of emotion. There, at least, this way of proceeding
consciousness has transformed the story into the tragic sense of comes naturally, even when candor about the use of our own
guilt that savages its way through the great tragic trilogy of wired-in emotional categories in interpreting animal behavior
Sophocles, (on this point, see Dodds 1951). does not. On the other hand, those accustomed to the study of
Similarly with other genetically organized affects. Fear, when emotion at a more molar level - and especially social psychol-
consciously reminisced about and projected into the future, ogists, computational cognitivists, and holistic functionalists -
becomes the conscious feeling of anxiety. The affect of anger will be understandably disposed to doubt that physiology and
stretched out over spatialized time in consciousness becomes neurochemistry can speak to their subject at all. I shall first
hatred. Excitement becomes the conscious feeling of joy; dis- attempt to argue and cajole these skeptics out of their specialist
gust, contempt; affiliation, love. And so on. All of these changes prejudice. I then turn to the substantive question of Panksepp's
need to be carefully documented in historical data and in child limbic command system for a basic emotion of panic or sorrow,
development. in terms of which, for the sake of both convenience and con-
Perhaps most interesting are the sexual emotions, which were creteness, my entire discussion proceeds.
usually omitted from Victorian lists of the emotions (including Suppose something like Panksepp's proposed central circuit
Darwin's) because their bodily expression is primarily genital is involved in isolation distress as well as in the more elaborate
rather than facial. We do know that mating in the anthropoid social emotions. What follows, then? Not necessarily that the
apes, in contrast to ourselves, is casual and almost minimal, with attachment of a child for his mother is subcortically (or even
observations of mating in gibbons, chimpanzees, orangutans, subcutaneously) localized. We could still say that this is a
and gorillas in the wild being extremely rare. Paralleling these relation between persons (and that love for an imaginary person
facts, tomb and wall paintings, sculpture and the writings of is only sham love). Or, alternatively, that the child's attachment
bicameral civilizations rarely if ever have any sexual references. is a state of the whole person (or mind or brain), that its
All classicists will agree with this, that all Mycenean and Minoan intentional object (underdetermined by the subcortical circuit-
art, in particular before 1000 B.C. is what seems to us as severely ry) is essential to its being the state it is, and that it must have
chaste. But after the advent of consciousness, say, about 700 some such object to be that sort of social attachment at all. But
B.C., Greek and Etruscan art is rampant with sexual references, however we may answer such subtle questions about attach-

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 435


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

ment and love, Panksepp's point should remain unchanged. He what Panksepp regards the "command" responsibility of limbic
would have found a neural center to match his hunch that these centers and still more rostral areas of the brain. But the ques-
social emotions have a common core. The mammalian basic tion, "Who does it to whom?' should be left to politics and the
emotion of sorrow would then also figure at the center of our analysis of dominance behavior. Especially at these higher
thinking about what makes longing for an absent person what it levels of the vertebrate neuraxis (as in open societies), it is
is, as distinct from feeling toward that same person gruding misleading to cast questions about the division of labor among
respect, rage, or sympathetic pain. Moreover, we should have the components of functional integrations as questions of who
that much more reason to believe that the affective states are commands whom.
among those psychological states that have a clearly biological In the organization of the social sentiments, pleasure, as well
basis - rather than being mere figments of self- or social as pain, certainly plays an important role, and not one that an
attribution, or fallout from the holistic programming or global undifferentiated "expectancy" foraging system could explain.
activity of the corticalized human brain. We are not normally inclined to (spiderlike) eat spouses or
But whereas the general program is plausible, the particulars (lizardlike) children when we like them very much (although an
of localization and interpretation seem premature. And es- aunt used to tell me that she could). And that we do not normally
pecially in the case of panic-sorrow. The possibilities open are resort to the swiftest and surest ways of escaping (or perma-
legion; I shall discuss but a single simple hypothesis that must be nently terminating) the aversive distress cry of the infant shows
refuted before we have reason to believe in a discrete system for that undifferentiated distress no more than anger, fear, or panic
social distress and cohesion. It is that there is no such system explains adult behavior - without which it would never have
distinct from the central pathways for pain. For all we have been been adaptive for young mammals to cry out in distress (as
told, most of Panksepp's forebrain sites are best construed as lizards, for good reason, do not!). From similar observations, the
sites for central analgesia, and the distress vocalizations (along ancient Stoics drew a conclusion about the origins of the social
sentiments, reported by Cicero:
with agitated behavior) upon the offset of stimulation, as normal
Therefore, just as it is clearly our nature to abhor pain, so it is evident
responses to pain. (Obviously, an ethologist's eye for the to-
that from this same nature we receive the impulse toward those we
pography and significance of the species-typical behavioral ex-
have begotten. From this develops the general affinity of human
pressions of motivational states is called for here.) The same goes
beings for one another; which thus, likewise, finds its source in
all the more for the central gray, so far as we know from data
nature. (De flnibus bonorum et malorum, bk. 3, sects. 62-63)
cited here. We may have only central pain, and the rebound on
But benevolence is often too weak a force to hold the line against
stimulation offset of the opioid-inhibited affective dimension of
selfish pleasure and pain. We often need to be brought up short
pain (Melzack & Casey, 1970); and no special system for social
by the threat of isolation (whether moral or physical) from our
pain.1
As for the hypothalamic response that Panksepp suggests fellows, which we internalize as the self-exile of guilt or shame.
"may . . . indicate the hypothalamic location of the emotive (Contrition, confession, and absolution end the sorrow of social
command system that is attuned to social loss," (in "The 'Panic' isolation, not the sin.) Our moral and social nature like our
Command System") this seems to have been interpreted as brain, is a tangled skein of pleasure and pain.
stimulus-bound attack in the original publication (Panksepp NOTES
1971a).2 While the reinterpretation seems to fit better the 1. But is the difference between the pain which makes us shrink into
original description of behavior, an ethologist's eye, once more, ourselves, and the panic which impels us to seek comfort from others,
is needed to rule out alternatives.3 I should like to know, for only a matter of degree? More probably - and more likely than either of
example, the significance of the original denial of jumping and the overly simple hypotheses considered in this paragraph of the text -
the current mention of leaping. Is this like running or bounding, the integration of pain with sorrow-panic and the other negative affects
and is it compatible with reinterpretation as an escape response, is a matter of degree. Panksepp, Herman, Vilberg, Bishop, and DeEs-
a sexual approach, or perhaps along the lines of the normal way kinazi (1980) suggest that their social affect system is an evolutionary
an immature rat solicits play? The gaping, chattering, and development of a system originally regulating only pain. But in the
squealing described in the 1971 paper require similar careful present paper, based as it is on a discrete command system picture, this
phylogenetic insight into functional organization is obscured.
examination. Finally, Panksepp's doubts (in "A Definition of 2. I assume that the hypothalamic area in question is that called Area
Emotions") about the usefulness of the pleasure-distress dimen- 3 in Experiment 1 of the referenced original paper (Panksepp 1971a).
sion notwithstanding, approach and avoidance are among the Only this group of rats seems to offer a tolerablefitto the present report;
clearest of behavioral signs. Here, as happens quite frequently, the others seem really to manifest only stimulus-bound attack. But the
interpretation at the pleasure-pain level is almost all that re- original description as near the lateral border of the ventromedial
mains constant through change of hermeneutic view. And, after nucleus, as compared with the current description as merely anterior
all, Panksepp's typology sits well with a hedonic partition of basal, leaves some room for doubt.
emotion into positive emotions (lumped here under "expectan- 3. In this connection, see the specific recommendations of Adams, in
cy") and the negative emotions, which he calls by their specific response to the commentaries of the Brelands, Rodgers, and Waldbillig
names. (Adams 1979, p. 232).
Pleasure and pain are phylogenetically and ontogenetically
old. It seems only reasonable to suppose that the later and
specifically mammalian developments are outgrowths of the Panic, separation anxiety, and endorphins
earlier, and that the introspectively easy and theoretically natu-
ral partition of affect into positive and negative marks a biolog- Donald F. Klein
ically important functional distinction as well. These newer New York State Psychiatric Institute, New York, N.Y. 10032
components, and the older systems on which they are built,
work together. The hierarchically organized mammalian brain is Panksepp spends a good deal of time in proclaiming defensively
not an army or bureaucracy in which a command system is that introspection is a good source of testable hypotheses with
unconditionally obeyed by slavelike subalterns incapable of regard to emotional organization. He is beating a dead horse.
initiating action on their own (Gallistel 1980; 1981). Responsibil- The effective critique of introspectionism was not that it could
ity is distributed among systems and levels of integration, and not produce testable hypotheses, but rather that it claimed that
there is every reason to suppose that features of conscious it could produce truths that were irreducible and beyond
experience reflected in introspection are distributed in these testing.
ways too. The pleasure-pain dimension may be largely an affair We should focus on the validity of a hypothesis rather than its
of the caudal brainstem, while social cohesion, may also involve source. If Panksepp is affirming that we can produce more valid

436 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentory/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

hypotheses by introspection than by some dry empirical induc- macological approach to affective dissection was reaffirmed
tion, I tend to agree with him. However, this affirmation, which when it was shown that the benzodiazepines were of some value
we both support, remains yet another testable hypothesis. It is in lessening expectant anxiety but did not benefit the spon-
certainly not clear that any single approach to understanding taneous panic attack, thus doubly affirming the dissociation of
emotion has won the prize. these states.
Therefore, I think that Pankscpp should focus more firmly on Panksepp relates this basic emotional system to endogenous
the utility of his definitions and the validity of his distinctions opiates and, indeed, to the neurochemical dynamics of opiate
and forget the self-justification. addiction and social dependence, and he has reported that
In his definitional approach, he says, "On the assumption that guinea pig separation-distress vocalization increases upon
emotions arise from the activities of brain circuits, a general naloxone injection. As we were in the midst of a study of the
definition of emotion would consist of a list of attributes such provocation of panics in patients who have spontaneous panics
brain circuits possess . . . the list must first be constructed (panic disorder) by intravenous sodium lactate, we were able at
rationally." least partially to test this reasonable hypothesis by infusing four
This is just what Panksepp is not doing. What he has done is to patients with 20 mgs. of intravenous naloxone. Unfortunately
respond to a set of observations and introspections rather than for the hypothesis, none of these patients demonstrated the
construct a set of rational a priori definitions. In my view, the panic attacks typically manifested during sodium lactate
basic observation requiring the emotion construct is that there infusions.
are certain classes of behavior consisting of relatively stereo- To sum up, Ifindthe paper useful as a set of keen observations
typed patterns of activity that respond to life-challenging cir- and inferences, rather than a set of "rational" definitions. How-
cumstances in an innately adaptive fashion, promoting both ever, I think that is a positive event.
individual and species survival. This notion received its paradig-
matic expression in the work of Cannon and was pithily epito-
mized in the belief that anger and fear, respectively, subserved
fight or flight. Generality and specifics in psychobiological
Panksepp's assertion that emotions are genetically hard-
wired is not a "rational" assertion but simply a reasonable theory of emotions
inference derived from the observation that these species spe- Eric Klinger and Ernest D. Kemble
cific behaviors are both stereotyped and adaptive to threat. This
Department of Psychology, University of Minnesota, Morris, Minn. 56267
seems the major expository stylistic flaw of the paper. A set of
interesting propositions is presented in an assumptive form Panksepp's model represents an admirable synthesis of diverse
rather than in a form that closely relates them to the body of data and a laudable open-mindedness with regard to sources of
observation that they hope to explain. For instance, Panksepp information. The bold sweep of this theory brings together
uses his definitional statements to distinguish such states as widely diverse physiological approaches, neurochemical studies
"disgust" or "pleasure" from his construct of emotion. Since of transmitter substances, behavioral observations of nonhuman
definitions are a set of stipulations concerning the use of words, species, and ideas based on human instrospection.
he is certainly entitled to do this, but if he wishes to persuade us The overall theory is an impressive and quite plausible for-
to accept these definitions, he has to explain why making these mulation that is likely to stimulate exciting research. However,
distinctions results in a superior heuristic approach. It does not it suffers from two principal difficulties: It makes too few specific
seem intuitively obvious to me that disgust does not activate predictions and conceptualizes too loosely to provide unam-
diverse classes of species-typical behaviors, nor that pleasure biguous tests with nonhuman organisms; and it treats the avail-
does not generate unique behavioral manifestations. His Aristo- able empirical literature about humans in such broad gener-
telian belief that pleasure may be a state that accompanies alities that it fails to come to grips with some of the important
stimuli and tends to return organisms towards physiological issues this literature presents. Furthermore, one can argue
homeostasis contradicts his later proposal that "expectancy," a about the clinical predictions implicit in the theory. The re-
basic emotion that produces nonhomeostatic exploratory ac- mainder of this commentary details these problems in order.
tivities, is subjectively represented by joyful anticipation (which First, the means and criteria for unambiguously demonstrat-
I think most people would introspectively affirm to be a pleasur- ing the proposed executive circuits remain elusive. This is
able state). particularly important in view of the large amount of recent data
Panksepp's substantive hypotheses are that there are four showing high apparent specificity of functions that have been
basic emotions: (1) fear, elicited by pain and resulting in flight quite resistant to consolidation into broadly general behavioral
(with a poorly delineated functional neuroanatomy, although categories. How, for example, can we go about demonstrating
Panksepp leans toward the importance of anterior lateral hypo- the existence of the proposed expectancy circuit? Given the
thalamic sites); (2) expectancy (which Panksepp confusingly uses diversity of species-typical behaviors elicited by brain stimula-
as a term for positive expectation only), based on neural circuits tion, what common features are we to expect from stimulation of
mediating electrical self-stimulation of the lateral hypo- this circuit? If we are limited to increases in forward locomotion,
thalamus; (3) rage, primarily related to the ventro-medi- sniffing behavior, and the life, the model is not likely to be very
alhypothalamus but substantially overlapping with the field for useful. Should it not be possible to predict the effects of stimula-
expectancy self-stimulation; and finally (4) panic. tion in species with novel foraging strategies (e.g., ambush
As Panksepp asserts, this is controversial and innovative. In predators, insectivores, etc.)?
most systems, panic is considered to be simply the quantitative Since the theory presumes functional unity in the executive
extension of fear, whereas Panksepp affirms that it is a separate circuits that underlie diverse species-typical behaviors, heavy
basic motive system related to separation-induced distress. emphasis is placed on the plasticity of stimulus-bound behavior
In my own work with psychiatric patients who exhibit spon- demonstrated by Valenstein, Cox, and Kakolewski (1970) as
taneous panic attacks, we have noted a high incidence of exces- evidence for the presence of homogeneous psychobehavioral
sive childhood separation anxiety. We have also established the tendencies. Such plasticity, however, has not always been
peculiar fact that the so-called antianxiety agents do not block found, particularly with smaller electrodes. The theory fails to
these spontaneous panic attacks, but antidepressant agents do specify the common features we may expect to find if these
(although the patients had not been depressed). nonplastic stimulation sites are, in fact, part of a more homoge-
We also hypothesized that the spontaneous panic attack was neous system. It is, of course, possible that alternative species-
quite distinct from the ordinary fearful response. This phar- specific behaviors are nested within the broader "circuits," that

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 437


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
the selection among them normally depends on stimulus situa- fulfilling an expectancy. If we eliminate this possibility, then
tions, but that stimulation with small electrodes rigidly elicits just what is joy within Panksepp's system, and where does it
one of these particular lower-order behaviors. This possibility come from? In the case ofjoy and some other affects, the system
offers the theory a way out, but it needs to be specified. seems in need of elaboration and further specification.
The theory similarly needs to specify more clearly how one Finally, Panksepp's attempt to relate his model to psycho-
might distinguish among different circuits, such as between the pathology in Figure 5, while provocative, is highly questionable
proposed fear and panic circuits. The descriptions of these in a number of respects and in some details almost certainly
circuits and their underlying mechanisms certainly seem plausi- wrong. For instance, the classification of schizophrenia as aris-
ble, but the range of test conditions on which this distinction is ing from overactive expectancy or panic circuits rides roughshod
made is rather small. The theory would benefit from specifying over the web of data regarding these disorders. Similarly, the
test situations that would permit a fuller expression of these gathering consensus that psychopathy involves defective fear-
underlying emotional states. responding is not reflected in Figure 5, except in placing
One avowed strength of Panksepp's model is in applying sociopathy at the underactive end of the panic axis. Psychopathy
features of human emotional experience to animal behavior. (or sociopathy) probably does also involve some kind of attach-
However, the theory does not propose specific tests with non- ment disorder, but the fear defect has been found with electric
human species that show rather subtle patterns of emotional shocks as well as social deprivation.
expression or social organization, including several primate and In summary then, the Panksepp model summarizes a great
social carnivore species that have now been described in some deal of information and has the potential to generate some
detail. Furthermore, a much larger body of truly comparative exciting research. Its success or failure will depend on how well
data is needed to evaluate Panksepp's critical assumption of the author can elaborate the model further to accommodate
phylogenetic continuity in the underlying executive functions. existing behavioral and self-report data and to specify critical
There are a number of issues raised in human self-report data tests and predict outcomes.
that bear on Panksepp's theory in important ways. Nearly every
attempt to identify affective dimensions, whether interin-
dividual or intraindividual (Zevon & Tellegen, in press), has
found two or three dimensions that, between them, account for Psychobiology without psychosocial
an overwhelming proportion of variance. The most prominent
two have been variously labeled and interpreted, commonly as significance
"pleasantness" and "tension" or "activation." However they
Richard S. Lazarus
might be labeled or interpreted, such dimensions correspond
Psychology Department, University of California, Berkeley, Calif. 94720
poorly to the basic command circuits proposed by Panksepp.
The "pleasantness" dimension probably accords well affectively Those in the emotion business are bound to become curious on
with Panksepp's expectancy circuit but the "activation" dimen- seeing this ambitious title, "Toward a general psychobiological
sion taps elements of all the other three command circuits. theory of emotions." Yet, given their reductionist predilections,
Panksepp is no doubt right in deploring the interpretive psychobiological approaches usually have little to say of rele-
difficulties in dimensional approaches to emotion and in offering vance to those of us with cognitive and social science outlooks.
neurophysiological anchorages as an aid to resolving these Cognitivists like myself make a few central assumptions about
questions. However, a psychobiological theory that takes self- emotion. First, we view emotions as the result of evaluative
report data seriously must also deal with the existing data. One cognitions (e.g., cognitive appraisals) about the significance of a
possible implication of these data is that there may be higher- transaction for a person's well-being. That is, emotions reflect
order hedonic codes that transcend the proposed circuits. Alter- the outcomes of encounters with the world as cognized by the
natively, the "supercodes" may reflect the limitations of the individual, outcomes that may be real, imagined, or anticipated.
introspective perceptual process rather than the underlying Second, each emotional quality (e.g., fear, anger, guilt, sadness)
circuitry. expresses and includes a somewhat different appraisal of an
A different kind of problem arises out of Panksepp's treatment outcome; the appraisal involving anger is different from that
of sorrow as a low-amplitude "panic" response (a social re- involving fear, etc. Third, although primitive animals have
sponse), but depression as a disorder of the expectancy circuit, wired-in dispositions to make such evaluative perceptions of
and both of these as separate from the rage circuit. The difficulty specific environmental configurations, higher mammals gener-
resides in the relation of this treatment to the following findings: ally learn to interpret the significance of what is happening. This
(1) invigoration, anger, and some form of depression (disap- process is often highly symbolic, as when it is concerned with
pointment, sorrow, grief, etc.) follow the loss of an incentive, definitions of self.
whether social or nonsocial; (2) they follow as part of a usually Imagine, therefore, the sudden rush of enthusiasm of a
orderly sequence dubbed an "incentive-disengagement cycle"; dedicated cognitive theorist reading Panksepp's early state-
(3) amygdalectomy eliminates both the invigoration and depres- ments in defense of anthropomorphizing about emotions. These
sion components; and (4) depression is strongly correlated with statements suggest Panksepp's conviction that an understand-
irritability (see Barta, Kemble, & Klinger 1975; Klinger 1975; ing of emotions cannot be based on reduction of human emo-
1977; Klinger, Barta, & Kemble 1974). To parcel out this tions to the least common denominator of animal life, or to
seemingly coherent response sequence among three different lower- or midbrain circuits that organize phylogenetically uni-
command circuits does violence to these findings. At the very versal, primitive emotions. The psychobiological and phy-
least, they call for an explanation within the framework of the logenetic orientations traditionally decorticate the emotional
Panksepp theory. process, metaphorically speaking. Even neurophysiological re-
The treatment of joy in this theory seems unsatisfactory. search as high up as the limbic system omits or understates the
Panksepp suggests that "joy may be the fulfillment of expectan- cognitive processes through which the psychological and social
cies," but also that the expectancy and rage systems reciprocally significances of transactions are construed. Reading Panksepp's
inhibit each other. If joy fulfills expectancies, does this mean account, one's enthusiasm continues for a time with the brief
reduced activity in the expectancy circuit? And if so, would this historical overview of taxonomies of emotion that goes back to
not then disinhibit rage? On the other hand, if joy represents an the Greeks and touches on "passions" such as joy, desire,
increase in activity of the expectancy system, this should in- sorrow, gratitude, resentment, and the like. One thinks, as one
crease striving, which does not seem a likely consequence of reads on, "Surely here is a psychobiological approach that

438 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentory/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

disdains reduction and addresses emotions as they are experi- tion when what is badly needed is some way to bring them
enced by people in the course of their daily lives." together.
Alas, it could not be. The bold anthropomorphic beginning is
lost as soon as Panksepp gets to neural circuits, and one wonders
why he thought it fruitful in the first place. We are given a
system based on four basic emotions or "command systems,"
upon which all emotions are presumably built. Panksepp thus Introspection and cultural knowledge
retreats to the time-honored reductionism of research that systems
never gets beyond the limbic system and is based mainly on
relatively primitive animals. As in the case of other phy- Catherine Lutz
logenetically oriented systems such as Plutchik's (1980), subtle Department of Anthropology, State University of New York at Binghamton,
Binghamton, N.Y. 13901
and complex human emotions reflecting culturally based mean-
ings and the "feeling rules" of the social structure are treated as Panksepp's call to "approach the brain with realistic experiential
blends of the elemental emotions that are presumably shared by concepts" represents a potential meeting ground for social and
all animals. biological research on emotions. His proposal that introspection
And what an odd and idiosyncratic lot these basic emotions be used as a technique for garnering information on human
are on which the richness of human emotions must depend. emotions can, as he notes, balance previous emphases on facial
"Fear" and "rage" are, of course, traditional and ubiquitous in expression and physiological correlates of emotions. The issue
theory. "Expectancy" is difficult for me to view as an emotion, concerning which of the "experiential concepts" emerging from
because of its highly cognitive character and its limited arousal introspection should be accepted as "realistic" ones is more
potential, comparable at best to the "orienting response." Final- complex, however, than the author indicates. Introspection has
ly, it is not clear how "panic" differs from fear. In the typical in fact already been in extensive (though rarely acknowledged)
social scientist's position, panic depends on a person's sense that use in the study of emotions as evidenced, for example, in the
escape routes are closing, and is distinguished from fear through ubiquitous reliance on the concepts of emotion as represented
such a cognitive discrimination and its generation of frantic in the English language. Whether our everyday language and
escape behavior. intuitive sense of the nature of emotional experience should
What about Panksepp's treatment of the rich panoply of serve as the bases for inferences about brain organization can be
emotions in human experience? This central issue is treated so decided only on the basis of data, which Panksepp does not cite.
briefly (one page) that it is mostly begged. His solution consists The nature of the relation between brain activity and verbal
of interactions or blends among emotion systems, but they seem accounts of emotion concepts will not be discovered simply by
strange and difficult to fathom. For example, it is suggested that searching out those who are judged to be "thoughtful" observers
jealousy arises from some "admixture of panic, rage, and expec- of their own emotional states. Anthropologists and psychologists
tancy. " But we are not told how panic is involved in jealousy, or have for years investigated the question of the relationship
the nature of the expectancy; nor is it obvious what rage has to do between language and cognition, verbal report and internal
with jealousy, and why rage and not anger. Resentment in experience. They have accumulated several kinds of evidence
Panksepp's view may arise from "a blend of activities in the rage, that point to the diversity and complex origins of introspective
fear, and expectancy systems," a pattern of reasoning which also accounts of emotions and other phenomena. Each of the follow-
escapes me and which is not spelled out in sufficient detail to ing three areas of research indicates that individual and cultural
moderate my confusion. knowledge systems concerning internal experience are highly
I must say with regret that Panksepp offers little help in organized and pervasive, and have profound effects on the
bridging the chasm that seems to separate the psychobiological communication and perhaps the nature of that experience.
and the psychosocial sides of emotions. I found tremendously There has been a long-standing interest in and reliance on
obscure what was said about physiological circuitry, and after subjects' descriptions of the cognitive processing underlying
reading and rereading many of the arguments (for example, on their performance on experimental tasks. The relation between
emotive circuits in "Emotive circuits of the brain: The theory", I these accounts and actual introspective accessing of those pro-
felt keenly the need of a translator. I can't be sure whether my cesses is problematic, however. Nisbett and Wilson (1977)
confusion stemmed from my own modest grasp of neurophysiol- review experiments with American subjects that use verbal
ogy and its jargon, or from the obscurity of the writing. If reports of cognitive processes and conclude that such reports are
psychophysiologists are able to appreciate the treatment or based on the subjects' previously held notions about the relation
resonate with it, all well and good, but I am certain that social between events and responses, not on actual introspection.
scientists will cry for help, or, more likely, will simply be turned D'Andrade (1974) has shown that individuals' reports of their
off. long-term memory for the observed behavior of others are not
To return, then, to the theme with which I began, what related to that behavior as coded by an observer, but are
cognitively oriented psychologists and other social scientists will correlated with the judged semantic similarity of the behavioral
find missing from Panksepp's paper is their own prime concern terms involved. Personal knowledge structures about what
in emotion theory, namely, psychosocial significance or mean- behaviors, responses, and events should go together affect
ing. Not only do emotions engender the mobilization for adapta- verbal reports.
tion, which requires reconciling external demands with internal A second areas of psychological research has great potential
agendas, as well as the physiological mechanisms for such importance for the understanding of introspective accounts of
mobilization, but they also express and reveal how people emotion. Metacognitive studies are concerned with the way in
construe what is happening to them with respect to their which people introspect about, classify, and monitor their men-
individual well-being. If there is any truth in such a view, then tal activity (Brown 1978; Brown & Barclay 1976). Investigators
Panksepp's efforts to offer a general psychobiological theory of have also examined, in our own society, the development in
emotions fall fatally short, because they completely omit the children of knowledge concerning the nature of distinct mental
psychological and social significance of transactions between processes such as reasoning, memory, and imagery (Wellman,
people and their environments and the role of cognitive activity in press). The ontogenetic research strategy that Panksepp sees
in sensing this significance. Despite initial signals to the con- as necessary for examining the interaction between cognitive
trary, these efforts preserve the unfortunate dichotomy be- appraisal and emotive command circuits is also a key to under-
tween psychobiological and social science approaches to emo- standing the origins of metacognitive skills such as introspection

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 439


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
and of the concepts and theories of mind and emotion held by human behavior in such a way as to cope with emergencies; that
adults. is, emotions are designed to respond unconditionally to stimuli
Third, cultural knowledge structures concerning the mind arising from major life-challenging circumstances and so to
and emotion have been documented by anthropologists in the organize behavior . . . which has proved adaptive in just such
field of ethnopsychology. Conceptions of the nature of emotion, circumstances.
its role in the organization of the person and in social interaction, ii. There are four clearly delineated and distinct channels -
and typologies of the emotions have been found to vary (Geertz
or four distinct behavioral control systems or psychobehavioral
1959; Hallowell 1955; Levy 1973; Lutz 1981; 1982). The fact that
psychological knowledge systems are culturally variable means tendencies - which this process of coping with emergencies can
that introspection on brain activity will be mediated by the employ, namely expectancy, fear, rage, and panic.
categories provided by language and culture. Although the iii. Therefore, expectancy, fear, rage, and panic are the four
documentation of variation in emotion-word classification sys- basic emotions.
tems has barely begun, the description of theories and concepts 2. Have emotions been developed by evolution as responses
of emotion held in various societies can provide the basis for to life-challenging circumstances? Or, to put the question an-
understanding the role of culturally provided knowledge sys- other way, is the first premise of Panksepp's psychobiological
tems in a person's understanding and experience of emotional argument true?
processes. There is a large literature, chiefly in psychology, which claims
All this is not to say that introspection is either necessarily that emotions are coping processes or processes developed by
"wrong" about mental activity, or that the cultural mediation of evolution such that they organize behavior to cope with
introspection results in brain activity being hopelessly inaccessi- emergencies. The most famous exponent of this view is probably
ble to the conscious mind. Introspection is simultaneously about Alexander Shand (1914, especially bk. 2, chap. 1), but there
knowledge and process, as these two factors are inseparable. have been many others (more recently, e.g., Arnold & Gasson
The suggestion being posed here is that a combination of 1968; Leeper 1948; Young 1961.) Unfortunately, there seems to
developmental and cross-cultural studies can aid in sorting be an equal number who claim the opposite, that emotions are
through the processes which result in account-giving, including disorganising and disruptive (e.g., Munn 1961; Pradines 1958),
both those which may involve the use of cultural or personal and the truth seems to be that there are undeniable facts to
knowledge structures and those which may not. The brain support both views, even when the alleged basic emotions are
activity, which forms at least part of the basis for the initial considered. Panic, for example, might speed up responses and
construction of knowledge structures about emotions, may yet facilitate mass escape by communicating itself to others nearby,
be retrieved via the comparison of introspective accounts of but it might as likely lead to dangerous and unnecessary and
diverse individuals. blind flight (Lorenz 1970, vol. 1, pp. 149, 166, 225, 309). Fear
Panskepp's theory has the distinct advantage of allowing for may lead to the frightened animal's running away from the
this kind of comparison by going beyond the common focus on predator faster than it ever ran before, but it may also lead to
the physiological symptoms of emotions. Emotion, in his catatonic freezing - and so on. Thus E. J. Murray writes that
scheme, is characterized by the recognition of diverse environ- "the evidence so far suggests that both emotion and motivation
mental events as calling for one class of responses. Introspective can positively organize and facilitate behavior, at certain times,
accounts of emotional states and their environmental correlates
but they may also disorganize and disrupt behavior" (1964, p.
may both be more readily comparable. An example can illus-
trate the usefulness of a combined comparative and introspec- 64; see also Lyons 1980, pp. 41-44, 188-92).
tive perspective for evaluating scientific theories of emotion. Furthermore, the "emotion as coping with emergency" thesis
This particular example lends some support to Panksepp's has always seemed strained once one gets outside the speeded-
exclusion of "surprise" and "disgust" from the group of major up, adrenalin-pumping variety of emotions, and it has seemed
emotive circuits. Accounts given by residents of the island of equally strained to limit basic emotions to the class of speeded-
Ifaluk, in the Western Pacific, of the nature and taxonomy of up ones. At any rate, it would be hard to make out a convincing
emotions explicitly depict "disgust" (the parallel term for which, case that boredom and contentment in animals help cope with
in the Ifaluk language, refers exclusively to the response to fetid emergencies (and, in humans, that sadness, despondency, en-
or spoiled objects) as being different in kind from other words nui, depression, shame, or embarrassment are mechanisms for
descriptive of temporary internal states (Lutz 1982). Also ex- coping with emergencies). These emotions do not seem to be
cluded from this domain is the term for physical startle, which is on-the-qui-vive emotions; they (or some of them) are backward-
seen as a simple behavioral description. There is no separate looking responses to the past.
term like "surprise" that exclusively describes the reaction to But even within the list of "best candidates" from the class of
sudden events. Panksepp's other claims for the centrality of speeded-up, adrenalin-pumping emotions, it should be obvious
certain types of emotional circuits should also be compared with that such emotions as fear and rage can be positively disadvan-
the introspective accounts generated by individuals of other tageous where calmness and quietness are required. Although
theoretical and cultural persuasions. fear may lead an animal to hide, it will also occasion the animal's
loud breathing, increased odor, shaking and quivering, and,
maybe on that account, lead to the predator's discovering its
hiding place. An enraged animal or person will very often fight
less well than a cooler calmer individual. Rage - as well as fear
Concerning the alleged four basic emotions and panic - can very easily lead to misperceptions and bad
decisions. At the human level, an enraged boxer or street fighter
William Lyons may be easy game for a cool and calculating opponent.
Department of Moral Philosophy, University of Glasgow, Glasgow G12
At a more fundamental level again, why should we assume,
800, Scotland piously, that the process of evolution throws up only useful
behavioral tendencies or patterns of behavior? It may be claim-
1. The structure of Panksepp's psychoblologlcal argu- ed that, in the different conditions of long ago, the thesis was
ment. Panksepp's basic argument for choosing expectancy, fear, true; namely, that fear, panic, and rage were always or most
rage, and panic as the four fundamental emotions, though not as often useful, though, in both animals and humans, it may now be
explicit as it might be, seems to be the following: the case that these emotions are as much a hindrance as a help.
i. In the process of evolution, emotions, or at least basic But will this move save the thesis? For how do we know that long
emotions, have developed as systems for organizing animal and ago they were or even must have been useful? Is the answer,

440 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commenton//Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
"They would not have survived if they were not useful," a good the fear of losing weight! (Re emotions and behavior and behav-
answer? To simplify the picture, surviving species may have, ior tendencies, see Lyons, 1980, pp. 17-25, 41-44.)
say, behavioral tendencies X, Y, and Z. The species may have I have much to say of a similar nature about Panksepp's
survived because of X or Y, or both, but survived with, but not attempts to "home in on" supposedly typical and unique rage-
because of, tendency Z. Z may have no clear survival value, behavior and panic-behavior, but space and time will allow me
positive or negative; it may have been, so to speak, carried along only a few more brief comments. As regards rage, is it plausible
on the backs of the survival-valued tendencies X and Y. Emo- to suggest that one of its "major adaptive function[s] . . . is to
tions, or some of them (including some of the basic ones) may be invigorate behavior when activity in the expectancy circuit
Zs! diminishes rapidly"? Do animals in the wild fly into a rage when
3. Are there four distinct and basic "psychobehavloral sys- their "foraging-expectancy" explorations "diminish" for some
tems"? Or, to put this question also another way, is the second reason or another, or should I say when their "hopes and joyful
premise of Panksepp's psychobiological argument true? anticipations" wane? I would need a lot of ethological evidence
My first query is whether "foraging-expectancy" is an emo- to be convinced of this.
tion rather than, say, just an appetitive inclination derived from Finally, is it plausible to maintain that the "major adaptive
"homoeostatic imbalances in the body and their respective function" of panic is "to sustain social cohesion" when etholo-
environmental incentives," that is, an appetitive inclination gists such as Lorenz (1970) and Lorenz and Leyhausen (1973)
without any strong somatic or visceral speeding-up or slowing- write of "wild" and "blind" and "baseless" panic, of misdirected
down (we must not forget the "calm emotions," Lyons 1980, pp. and "extremely dangerous panic," and, finally, of "disastrous
9, 30, 116-17). In humans at any rate - and Panksepp urges us to panics" in animals? Thorpe (1963) refers to "fatal panic" in
take such introspective-cum-retrospective evidence seriously - animals, though, admittedly, the evidence was in connection
hunger and thirst do not characteristically give rise to emotions with animals in zoos. Could "social cohesion" coexist with such
of expectancy or exploration. When the search for food or drink blind, wild, disastrous flight?
is frustrated or proving fruitless, then emotions may begin to Though I have been critical of Panksepp's central psycho-
arise, such as, initially, frustration and irritation, then fear and biological argument, I nevertheless enjoyed the paper. It is
perhaps panic, and finally despair. Besides, it seems a farfetched good to see a return to attempts to define and model the
theoretical claim to suggest an emotion is needed to induce "an emotions.
animal to move from where it is to where it should be in order to
consume the substances needed for survival." The wants and
desires - or, in the preferred jargon, "incentives" leading to
"motor arousal" - arising from the body's needs in the states of Psychobiology needs cognitive psychology
hunger and thirst seem inducement enough.
Adam Morton
Panksepp is more plausible when he later glosses "forag-
Department of Philosophy, University of Bristol, Bristol BS8 1RJ, England
ing-expectancy" as "hope, desire - joyful anticipation." But
such a gloss reveals a dilemma. If the basic emotion is left Panksepp's real conclusion could be stated somewhat as follows:
labeled simply as "foraging-expectancy," and coupled with the There are four interacting but separable limbic neural complex-
basic behavior of sniffing, it does not seem to be an emotion but a es in mammals, each of which is associated with a definite range
homeostatically based drive (or instinct or, in general, impulse). of species-specific behavior, which have some pretty basic, but
Relabel this basic emotion "hope, desire — joyful anticipation" still not entirely clarified, relation to emotional states of all
and it becomes an emotion all right; it becomes a nonbasic mammals, including humans. To put it this way would make it
(because nonsimple) congeries of emotions as suitable to the all seem less interesting and original than it is, though, and so he
anticipation of non-survival-related objects or events as of those formulates a tentative stronger claim, which is more likely to
that have something to do with survival. make the reader read on. This version runs: Distinct limbic
Panksepp's descriptions and analysis of the function of his circuits in all mammals can be identified as expectancy, rage,
three strongest candidates for basic emotions - fear, rage, and fear, and panic; and when humans experience emotions, their
panic - also seem arbitrarily truncated and unfair to the facts. In experiences (or a large component of them) can be compounded
the case of fear, Panksepp proposes that we look to the "hard- out of these elements. My comments are addressed to the
wired circuit" in the hypothalamus from which "flight and relation between the stronger and the weaker version of Pank-
unconditional escape behaviors can be elicited." But Shand, sepp's thesis.
who long ago attempted a program similar to Panksepp's real- People not only experience emotions, they also have moods
ized that he had to admit that, even in animals, fear gives rise to and attitudes, and exhibit character and personality. All these
a daunting variety of behavior; namely, behavior expressive of are related, though it is not clear what the relations are. Some-
the "instincts of flight, of concealment, of silence, of clinging times it seems as if Panksepp is talking about this whole class of
and keeping close to something, of shrinking or starting back, of states and attributes, and sometimes he seems to be concerned
immobility or simulation of death, of crying for help " (Shand only with a subclass. That subclass would be not that of the
1914, bk. 2, chap. 2, p. 207 - and he had read the ethology of his emotions proper but that of moods and feelings. Attribute
day, notably Brehms and Hudson). Or is Panksepp's phrase number 4 of his command circuits ("A definition of emotions")
"unconditional escape behaviors" a catchall phrase that can is meant to make the states in question relatively independent of
accommodate anything? What seems fair to say is that few the environmental factors that occasion them; for the descrip-
ethologists would any longer accept a simple "fight and flight" tion of jealousy as an admixture of panic, rage, and expectancy,
view of anger and fear in animals, and so to base a strategy for or resentment as a mixture of rage, fear, and expectancy to have
discovering the emotion circuits in the brain upon such a view any plausibility, we must abstract away the typical cognitive
must produce a very precarious methodology. I do not think that content of jealousy or resentment and concentrate only on the
there is convincing evidence that one can differentiate the mood or feeling; and the definitions of sorrow as a diminutive
emotions by reference to neatly packaged behavior or, a for- form of panic and anxiety as a diminutive form of fear seem to
tiori, to the much more elusive "behavior tendencies." The involve a similar decision to ignore the nonfelt aspect of a state.
behavior that results from a single "behavior tendency" may be But, on the other hand, the allusions to the attempts of De-
multifarious, and depend very much on the context, as Shand scartes and others at a grand classification of states of mind, and
elaborated. Fear is always fear of something in particular, and - Panksepp's speculative extension of his theory to personality
to take an example relevant only to humans - the fear of getting disorders ("Diseases of emotive systems") suggest that he wants
fat will give rise to behavior very different from that arising from to include all affective states in his theory.

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 441


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
The main importance of the emotion/feeling contrast con- that there are only four emotion control circuits, those which
cerns cognitive content. Emotions typically have the causes and elaborate states of expectancy, rage, fear, and panic.
effects that they do, in part because of their associations with There are a number of arguments that can be presented
complex thoughts. That is why we express them with "that" against the last two assumptions. For one, although introspec-
clauses. James is afraid that his house may burn down. James's tions may sometimes be useful in revealing an individual's
fear (unlike his anxiety) cannot be identified without reference emotional states, they are far from infallible guides even to the
to its object, and cannot be accounted for except by reference to subjective aspects of emotion. For example, the psychoanalysts
whatever it is (surely essentially neocortical) that allows him to have made us aware of the fact that subjective reports of affects
have such thoughts as "my house may be on fire." Panksepp's cannot always be accepted at face value. Not only are some
theory tacitly acknowledges this. Fear, for example, is associ- emotions totally repressed, and thus unavailable to introspec-
ated with environmental stimuli of "threat of destruction" (Fig- tion, but others are frequently modified or distorted as a result
ure 1). But a stimulus isn't simply of "threat of destruction " of partial repressions. Even academic psychologists have ac-
(contrast it with the stimulus of "bodily irritation" cited for rage); cepted the idea that ego defense mechanisms can transform or
the stimulus must be conceptualized as representing such a modify the nature of introspective reports (Plutchik, Keller-
threat, and unless the mechanisms for such a conceptualization man, & Conte 1979).
are included in it, a neural circuit must produce something Other problems with introspection are the following: (a)
other than fear. A similar point could be made for rage, using the Repression may create false negatives; that is, an observer may
data Panksepp cites on the expression of rage in monkeys: the erroneously assume that no emotion exists because none has
effects of rage are not simple behavioral routines, but depend on been reported, (b) Verbal reports of emotions may be deliberate
cognitively complex representations of the animals' social attempts to deceive another person (as is often the case in so-
group. called deception experiments), (c) Reports of emotions depend
I would not conclude from this that Panksepp is confused. on individuals' particular conditioning history as well as their
Rather, the moral seems to be that the English terms he has facility with words, (d) Reports of inner emotional states are
chosen for the sake of exposition are not quite what he needs. He retrospective and depend on memory. Remembered events are
does not want to define his subject as feelings, because he wants notoriously subject to distortions, such as leveling and sharpen-
to exclude many feelings from primary consideration ("A defini- ing, (e) The inherent ambiguity of language creates the problem
tion of emotions") and because his ultimate aim is to cover much of the "true" meaning of emotion terms. The importance of
more than just feeling. But the cognitive associations of "emo- context in determining meaning implies that the same verbal
tion" and of English emotional terms aren't wanted either. report of an emotion may have a different referent in another
Moreover, the terms "expectancy, ' "fear," "rage,' and "panic" setting, (f) Emotions are rarely if ever experienced in a pure
are not quite the right labels for what he has in mind. "Expec- state. More typically, any given situation creates mixed emo-
tancy" is particularly ill-fitting; on reading what Panksepp has tions, which are difficult to describe in any simple or unequivo-
to say about it, one does acquire a feel for the state in question, cal way.
but it has no simple relation to expecting (or hoping) that For these and other reasons one can conclude that an intro-
something will happen. spective report of an inner emotional state is only a rough
What should Panksepp say, then? Just that there seem to be approximation to whatever that state is. It hardly seems likely
these four neural circuits, and that he hypothesizes that there that such crude reflections of emotional states are a royal road to
are four corresponding psychological states, which are felt the nature of underlying brain mechanisms associated with
throughout human affective life and are related to the following emotions. Emotions are complex chains of events whose proper-
states and behaviors in the following ways. . . . But then the ties can be inferred only through the use of a wide variety of
dots have to be filled in. And that's a problem, for one needs a sources of evidence.
theory of how the four states affect human behavior and the Incidentally, from an historical point of view, the use of
affective states we report with our rich, complicated vocabulary. introspection alone has led to the idea that there are different
A purely neuropsychological theory won't do the job, and numbers of basic emotions. Spinoza proposed three, Descartes,
neither will pure philosophical analysis. One is too hard and the six, Hobbes, seven, McDougall, twelve, Murray, sixteen, and
other too soft. Somewhere in the middle there will have to be a others have proposed various intermediate numbers. Introspec-
cognitive psychology of the emotions, which connects up at one tion alone is not an adequate guide to the number of basic
end with neural and behavioral data and at the other with what emotions we possess, just as factor analysis alone, or physiology
we humanly say and feel. It would be nice if one could get along alone, or brain anatomy alone, or stimulation studies alone are
just by mixing neuropsychology and philosophical analysis, but insufficient.
the points at which Panksepp's promising thesis bog down
provide some reason for believing that this combination is not My second set of objections to Panksepp's theory concerns his
going to be enough. assumption that there are only four basic emotions as defined by
transhypothalamic executive circuits. Panksepp prefers to be-
lieve that surprise, disgust, and joy are not basic emotions,
despite the fact that they have clear behavioral referents in
animals as well as humans, and may be controlled by limbic
circuits. He claims that these emotions are "largely time-locked
Only four command systems for all to the precipitating stimuli, with no sustained regenerative
emotions? feedback in the underlying brain systems." This statement
ignores the fact that all these emotions can occur in various kinds
Robert Plutchik of sustained derivative forms (e.g., revulsion or contempt as
Department of Psychiatry, Albert Einstein College of Medicine, Bronx, N. Y. derivatives of disgust, and cheerfulness and friendliness as
10461 derivatives of joy). Contrary to Panksepp's statement, these
The idea that emotions arise from hard-wired neural circuits and states do have unique behavioral manifestations (see, for exam-
ple, Bull 1951; Darwin 1872; MacLean 1975) and do operate
that they facilitate adaptive responses stems from the Darwinian through discrete neurochemical dopamine and endorphin sys-
evolutionary, ethological tradition and has been described by tems of the brain. Electrical stimulation of the brain produces
many others (e.g., Plutchik 1962; 1970; 1980). What is new and not only withdrawal reactions, destruction reactions, and food
most controversial about Panksepp's views is his claim that intake reactions, but sexual reactions, "disgust" reactions, star-
human introspection may provide direct information concern- tle reactions, and watchfulness reactions (Plutchik, McFarland,
ing operations of emotive circuits. Also debatable is the view

442 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentary'/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

& Robinson 1966). The only kind of reactions not produced by individual differences and it is weak in its treatment of the
direct brain stimulation are loneliness and grief reactions. It is subjective aspects. Unfortunately, instead of bringing us up to
highly unlikely that "panic" reactions are defined simul- date on the latter topic, he squanders the available space on a
taneously by distress vocalizations (how does Panksepp know review of pretwentieth-century philosophical treatments of this
the vocalizations reflect "distress"?) and by "explosive behavior, question. While this may be the most difficult of thefivefacets, I
during which the animal exhibits violent leaping about the test cannot see what Panksepp is trying to achieve by quoting from
chamber." seventeenth-century authors such as Willis and Descartes. We
One may also object to the label of "panic" for the emotional can surely do better than to make lists of emotions, and to talk
state described by Panksepp as "social loss", or "loneliness." In about "passions"! But Panksepp (see his Table 1) actually decid-
my own research, high-intensity fear is typically defined by es to take one of these early authors seriously, namely Cogan
subjects as panic, while high-intensity sadness (social loss) is (1802). The point is that contemporary treatments of the subjec-
defined as grief. tive aspect of the problem are of much greater scientific value
The form of the diagrams presented (e.g., target article, than he would have us believe. In fact, they constitute the
Figure 2) also has certain implications. Expectancy is placed widely accepted "cognitive basis of emotion" whose claims are
opposite rage, and fear is placed opposite panic. In contrast, a focused on two related ideas: cognitions as cue-attributions, and
number of empirical, multidimensional scaling studies (Plutchik cognitive appraisals as causes of emotional states. Thefirstview,
1980) indicate that grief is opposite joy, fear is opposite anger, which is primarily due to the research of Schachter (1964), sees
expectancy is opposite surprise, and disgust is opposite accep- the detection of the combined internal physiological cues and
tance. (Incidentally, the concept of expectancy as a basic emo- external situational cues as the basis for the attribution of an
tion, along with an evolutionary rationale, was first presented in emotional state. The second view, which is primarily due to the
detail in my 1962 book.) It is not the case that "rage and research of M. B. Arnold (1970) and Lazarus (1966), is ex-
expectancy circuits should strongly inhibit each other." From emplified by Lazarus, Averill, and Opton (1970, p. 219) when
both an introspective and observational point of view, sex and they say that "the situation is evaluated as relevant, threatening,
aggression are often found together, and factor analytic studies frustrating, . . . etc. . . . This appraisal also includes an eval-
have demonstrated that assertive children are often the most uation of the options for coping and their potential conse-
sociable as well. quences. Cognitive processes thus create the emotional re-
The idea that basic emotions may be related to psychiatric sponse out of the organism-environmental transaction and
disorders is a good one (Figure 5), but it has already been shape it into anger, fear, grief, etc." Thus, according to this
developed in detail by Schaefer and Plutchik (1966) and by view, a cognitive interpretation is not a passive correlate, it is a
Plutchik and Platman (1977). cause of the emotive state.
In conclusion, the general ideas presented by Panksepp are Although the exact role of cognitive processing in emotion is
important, but the specific details of the model are debatable, not clear, it is highly probable that cognition is involved, in at
and his assumptions about the role of introspection probably least the less violent emotive states. This means that the neural
wrong. Despite his claims for the importance of introspection, underpinnings of emotion probably include cortical areas of the
he presents no insights into brain mechanisms based on this brain in addition to Panksepp's four transdiencephalic emotive
source of information alone. circuits. There is also a significant body of evidence (e.g., see
Eysenck 1967; Lindsley 1950; Royce & Diamond 1980) implicat-
ing the reticular activating system, particularly in the case of the
less disruptive emotions.
On the complexity of emotion Of course, these are claims rather than solidly established
Joseph R. Royce facts. However, they are no less established than Panksepp's
biobehavioral emotive circuits, the neural details of which are
Center for Advanced Study in Theoretical Psychology, University of
Alberta, Edmonton, Alberta, Canada T6G 2E9
not known and, therefore, "can only be surmised." Further-
more, although Panksepp alludes to mixtures of his four emotive
The study of emotion has been refractory to scientific advance, command systems combining with learning in order to account
particularly to theoretical advance. The major deterrent is for the full range of emotive states, this is a very large promissory
complexity. The crux of this complexity is that emotion simul- note on a problem of central importance to a general theory of
taneously involves subjective thoughts and feelings, physiologi- emotions.
cal reactions, evolutionary adaptive significance, behavior, and Although one is hesitant to be critical of attempts to under-
individual differences. Furthermore, full understanding of a stand phenomena as complex as emotion, my remarks are
given emotion requires an alignment at all five levels - and the offered in the same heuristic spirit that comes through in
alignment includes temporal sequence in addition to consisten- Pankepp's paper. Thus, although I have pointed to some weak
cy of each of thefivefacets. An inconsistency in the alignment of spots, these criticisms are minor when placed in the context of
any one of thefivefacets would constitute a failure of the theory. what Panksepp is reaching for. In short, I am in agreement with
For example, a high rather than a low level of physiological Panksepp's central argument, namely, that his four emotive
arousal is the appropriate correlate for the emotive state of anger neural circuits are a good basis form which to move "toward a
or rage. general psychobiological theory of emotions."
The problem of complexity in this domain is exacerbated
further by the fact that there is ambiguity as to what the
emotional domain includes. Plutchik (1962), for example, lists
some 21 definitions, and Strongman (1978) concludes that
On the nature of specific hard-wired brain
"emotion defies definition." circuits
Given this degree of complexity and ambiguity, it is not
Allan Siegel
surprising that the typical theory tends to cover only one or two
of the five facets. Furthermore, since there is no adequate Department of Neurosciences, New Jersey Medical School, Newark, N.J.
07103
definition, it is also not surprising to find that the typical theory
fails to cover the full range of possible emotive states. Panksepp has made a potentially significant contribution to our
Panksepp's theory is no exception. Although his approach is research strategies by reminding us of what our priorities should
particularly strong in its specification of the biobehavioral and be in our attempts to discern the brain mechanisms underlying
evolutionary aspects of the problem, it says nothing about the various forms of emotional behavior. In particular, he has

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 443


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

argued effectively that "emotional" constructs achieve signifi- through the relevant hypothalamic field in a given cat, we have
cance when they are linked to specific circuitry in the brain. The observed that the region from which quiet biting attack can be
value of this approach rests in the fact that Panksepp would have obtained is quite limited (approximately 0.5-1.0 mm. across),
us attend to the details of the neuroanatomical substrates under- and that this observation supports the specificity hypothesis
lying the emotional expression of behavior. By pursuing this (Fuchs, Dalsass, Siegel, & Siegel 1981). In addition, in studies
course we can then design our experiments specifically to test a dealing with affective display behavior, we have routinely found
variety of hypotheses about such circuitry. In particular, if we that dorsomedial hypothalamic stimulation will evoke flight
focus on the anatomical pathways relevant to a given behavioral behavior and that, as the electrode is passed ventrally for a short
process, the data obtained from such experiments may provide distance into the region of the ventromedial nucleus, the behav-
meaningful clues to the sites of interaction at which sensorimo- ior evoked changes to affective display. Thus, in this instance,
tor integration as well as forebrain modulation are most likely to the passage of the electrode through the relevant hypothalamic
occur. field does, in fact, produce a change in the nature of the behavior
Panksepp appears to base his conclusions concerning the evoked. Our explanation is simply that stimulation at more
nature of thefixedcircuitry primarily on data from experiments dorsal sites activates a selective set of pathways that mediate
on rats. It is on this issue that I wish to comment. Panksepp flight responses (Fuchs, Siegel, & Edinger 1981), while stimula-
states that current evidence supports the notion of a "non- tion at the more ventral sites activates a somewhat different
specificity" explanation for a variety of stimulus-bound appe- group of fibers (Fuchs, Siegel, & Edinger 1980).
titive behaviors, such as feeding, drinking, gnawing, hoarding, Concerning the statement that the behavior is not changed
pup-retrieving, predatory aggression, and copulation. His con- after a lesion at the tip of the electrode, and that only its
clusions are based on the following lines of evidence: (1) that threshold is elevated: this is not, in itself, an argument for a
through experience one appetitive behavior (elicited by electri- nonspecificity hypothesis. Such an argument could just as well
cal stimulation) can be changed to another (Valenstein, Cox, & be used to support a specificity hypothesis. When a lesion is
Kakolewski 1970); (2) "that stimulus-bound appetitive behav- placed at the tip of the electrode in the cat, the attack response
iors do not change when an electrode is passed through the may be totally eliminated (Chi, Bandler, & Flynn 1976; Chi &
relevant lateral hypothalamic field (Wise 1971)"; (3) that "The Flynn 1971). In any event, such an observation has been in-
type of behavior elicited from an electrode does not change terpreted by these authors to mean simply that the pathways
when the tissue under the electrode is damaged (Bachus & mediating attack behavior are highly discrete and were
Valenstein 1979)"; and (4) that "the temperament of the test damaged by the lesion.
animal may be more important in determining the stim- The final statement made by Panksepp - that the tempera-
ulus-bound appetitive behavior observed than the exact loca- ment of the animal may be more important as a determinant of
tion of the stimulating electrode in the active zone within the the stimulus-bound behavior than the exact placement of the
dorsolateral hypothalamus (Panksepp 1971a)." electrode — is one for which I have not seen support in the
Over the past 15 years our own observations on the cat, as well behavior of th,e cat. In fact, some of our cats displaying the most
as data reported from the laboratory of the late Dr. John Flynn, ferocious attack responses upon stimulation turn out to be
clearly support a different point of view, which corresponds to markedly timid and placid in the absence of electrical stimula-
what Panksepp calls a "specificity" hypothesis concerning the tion. It seems that, in the cat, the most relevant variable is the
nature of the anatomical circuitry underlying various behavioral placement of the electrode rather than the "personality" of the
processes. This view is that for each behavioral process, there animal. Furthermore, our anatomical studies dealing with quiet
exists a distinct set of anatomical pathways, which become biting attack behavior have demonstrated that the pathways
activated during the behavioral sequence in question. We have mediating this response are quite specific. Our anatomical
considered the possibility of trying to replicate the Valenstein tracing procedures reveal a very consistent pattern of distribu-
experiment in the cat but have decided against it, because the tion offibersamong all cats displaying this behavior. In contrast,
length of hypothalamic stimulation per trial, the intertrial inter- when a different response such as affective display or flight
val, and length of experimental session would, in my opinion, behavior is obtained from a neighboring site, the pathways that
represent a regimen too stressful for application to the cat. Thus, we have traced, and which are associated with these responses,
in order to avoid any discomfort to the animals, data bearing on are clearly different.
this central issue of specificity versus nonspecificity have been Accordingly, on the basis of our observations in the cat, I have
obtained during the course of other experiments performed in drawn the following conclusions regarding the nature of hard-
our laboratories. Most notably, the related question of whether wired circuitry in the cat: (1) The sites and pathways underlying
the same site in the hypothalamus could elicit, upon stimula- each behavioral response are clearly distinct and discrete, with
tion, two different behavioral responses, was discussed by only some degree of overlap (or commonality offiberpathways).
Flynn, Vanegas, Foote, and Edwards (1970). They described an (2) The constellation of pathways mediating one response pat-
experiment in which horsemeat and an anesthetized rat were tern is not the same as that associated with other hypothala-
alternately made available to a cat. Following stimulation of the mically elicited responses (i.e., "specificity" hypothesis). (3)
hypothalamus, most cats displayed attack behavior only, while The "nonspecificity" hypothesis generated from data in the rat
both eating and attack were present in a small percentage of the cannot be generalized to the cat. The strategy of utilizing
remaining animals. When both horsemeat and an anesthetized anatomical tracing procedures is of heuristic value in identifying
rat were present in the cage (the horsemeat having been placed the neural substrates underlying various behavioral response
between the cat and the rat), electrical stimulation of the patterns as well as their sites of interaction for achieving sen-
hypothalamus reliably produced attack behavior in a similarly sorimotor integration.
high percentage of the animals. Other unpublished observa-
tions revealed that even 24-48 hour, food-deprived cats will
cease eating to attack a rat following electrical stimulation, and
stimulation in the continued presence of horsemeat alone did
not later cause the cat to select food instead of the rat. These
findings clearly point to the fact that most sites in the hypo- Emotional cookbooks
thalamus of the cat are ones from which quiet attack, but not
eating, can be evoked. Robert C. Solomon
Department of Philosophy, University of Texas, Austin, Texas 78712

Concerning the statement that a "stimulus-bound" appe- Panksepp's article seems to me to be a valuable research project
titive behavior does not change when an electrode is passed misconceived. The project is not just his, of course; it surveys a

444 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

campaign which dates back to the nineteenth, if not to the early Our paradigm of an emotional reaction has always been one of
seventeenth century, to explain emotions in terms of their those dramatic "outbursts," so easily characterized by rage or
neurophysiological substrata in the central nervous system. panic, which consists of an emergency reaction to a stimulus, a
Unlike many researchers in that tradition, Panksepp does not more or less stereotyped and perhaps even instinctual sequence
pretend to reduce emotions to such neurophysiological (and of behavior and the familiar sensations of the physiological
associated) disturbances and systems; indeed, his insistence on a disturbances we now know to identify with certain specific
dialogue between neurology and the "subjective awareness" of hormonal secretions. The traditional mistake, canonized by
our own emotions through "introspection" is an attempt to block James (and not uncanonized by Cannon) has been to think of
any such reductionist thesis. Panksepp's views, accordingly, these reactions as the very essence of emotion, thus ignoring
tend to be expressed as a kind of dualism - of method if not of what, on a moment's reflection, would appear to be the vastly
entities. This will properly arouse some of the philosophers and larger proportion of our emotional life - lifelong love of a brother
cognitive scientists, who would rightly argue that such talk can or shame about an adolescent crime, envy of the rich or resent-
and should be replaced by the newer language of functionalism, ment of the powerful. But even within the narrow confines of
in theories of emotion as in other more straightforwardly cogni- that paradigm, the analysis of emotion in terms of basic phys-
tive fields of study. This presupposes, of course, that emotions iological reactions is inadequate. There may indeed be specific
are cognitive phenomena, ways of conceiving and knowing neural systems to explain the reactions of rage and fear, but
rather than mere systems of organized behavior, triggered by those neural systems, and their products, are not yet rage or
neural systems and resulting in a readily identifiable "subjective fear. Rage and fear require a cognitive component to distinguish
experience." This is also what bothers me about Panksepp's them, for example, from mere surprise, which Panksepp right-
presentation - not just its dualism, but its continued treatment ly, but for the wrong reasons I am afraid, eliminates from the
of emotions as "primitive" ingredients in an emotional cook- usual list of emotions. "Rage,' if it means anything like what we
book, raw neurological-behavioral elements that are combined ordinarily mean by "rage," necessarily includes a component
in a variety of recipes to yield the more complex and subtle crudely characterized as "being offended" or at least frustrated;
emotions of adult human life. Jealousy is analyzed as a admixture without some reference to what the rage is "about," we don't
of panic, rage and expectancy, for example. have rage at all. (This raises the question whether dogs and rats
The idea that emotions are "primitive" or have primitive can be angry - there is little doubt that they can feel fear - but
"components," which are more or less instinctual, unlearned, that is not a question I want to raise here.) Panksepp may be
inherited, and form compounds of other emotions, gives rise to right about his neurological components, but he leaps to conclu-
an intellectual game, which can be traced back through the sions when he assumes that the component itself is rage, rather
middle ages to ancient times. Medieval physiologists conceived than, at most, a causal precondition for that dramatic but
of various lists of basic emotion-components, and then devel- narrowly conceived paradigm of rage which traditionally has
oped ingenious lists of recipes. Descartes listed his six primitive formed the focus of theories of emotion.
emotions in his treatise on "The passions of the soul," and John There may be distinctive neural systems which in some sense
Watson, more ontologically frugal as always, reduced his basic lie at the base of certain emotional reactions. But these systems
list to three. Robert Plutchik now argues eight, Panksepp four. are not themselves emotions, and are not required for the
But what has changed in the game in Panksepp's hands is that having of an emotion. What neurological stew can one cook up to
the classification no longer turns on the rather casual examina- explain David Hume's "calm passions," such as "a sense of
tion of our ordinary conceptions of emotions and their identifica- justice," for instance? Emotional phenomena are not easily
tion (not to be confused with "subjective awareness" or "intro- distinguished from our more general and less episodic views of
spection"); the identification of the primitive emotions turns on the world and ourselves. Neuroscience has an exciting realm of
neurological observations. This explains the oddness of his basic its own to investigate, a realm which does indeed explain in part
four components - expectancy, rage, fear, and panic. The some of the more dramatic scenes of our emotional life. But even
inclusion of expectancy, and thefirstjoint appearance of fear and then, to explain Othello's rage without reference to Desdernona
panic, suggest something more than an eccentric list of ingre- and Iago will not do, even if our neuroscience is,finally,down to
dients; it is a list of ingredients that, in terms of our ordinary the precision of a cookbook.
language of emotions (again, not "subjective awareness" or
"introspection") is simply unintelligible. This becomes obvious,
for example, when we see the ingenious but desperate attempt
Panksepp has to make in order to analyze virtually any human Softening the wires of human emotion
emotion; his analysis of jealousy, for instance, is not even
plausible, no matter how generous our interpretation. Spinoza Michael Stocker
had it better when he suggested that jealousy was a combination Philosophy Department, La Trobe University, Melbourne, Victoria 3083,
of hatred and envy, but then Spinoza was not saddled with the Australia
frugal neurological list of components Panksepp imposes on
himself. Panksepp wishes to conjoin introspectivist with behaviorist and
neurophysiological approaches to a psychological understand-
What is wrong about the cookbook model of emotions, in ing of emotions. Central to his attempt are first, his claim about
which certain emotions are basic ingredients and all of the the hardwiring of certain, supposedly basic emotions, and,
others combinations of these, is not the implausibility and second, his suggested understanding of emotions. From the
sometimes the absurdity of particular lists of ingredients. Pank- perspective of a philosopher investigating human emotions, I
sepp has it obviously wrong, no matter what the neurological found both the first and second themes unhelpful.
findings, but Watson and Descartes and Spinoza, too, are First, a process is hard-wired if, at least roughly, it is (at the
mistaken, and not because of the details of their lists. Emotions relevant time) invariant, automatic, not under conscious or
are not made out of basic components, and insofar as a neu- programmable control; if it is a matter of hardware, not software.
rological substratum of systems and disturbances can be identi- What goes on in a pocket calculator when the square-root button
fied (as Panksepp and his colleagues are attempting to do), there is pushed is, thus, a good example. And Panksepp writes "each
is no reason to identify those systems and disturbances with emotive circuit . . . may . . . be specific (hard-wired), in the
emotions. Emotions themselves have a structure, which they sense that each generates a single, homogeneous psycho-be-
may share with other (more primitive) emotions, but it does not havioral tendency. "
follow that they have components, or that the more primitive In both classical (e.g., Aristotle 1941) and contemporary (e.g.,
(unlearned) emotions are more fundamental. Rorty 1980)1 philosophy, emotions have been seen as involving

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 445


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

affect, desire, ratiocination, and action. So Aristotle ("Rhet- important pain is to anger, or what being pleased or amused by
oric," II, 2) holds that to be angry I must be pained by a wrong, having one's foot stepped on shows about one's emotion. Sec-
seen as such; and I must have a desire to retaliate. Thus, to claim ond, in Panksepp's own characterizations, these concepts figure
that human emotions are hard-wired is to hold that the affective, importantly: for expectancy, joy; for fear, pain; for rage, irrita-
desiderative, ratiocinative, and action "elements" are hard- tion or discomfort; and for panic, distress.
wired - perhaps triggered by some stimulus. Or it is to claim Had Panksepp paid more attention to these factors, he would
that these elements, especially the first three, are unimportant have been able to offer us a better understanding of human
or epiphenomenal. I shall here simply ignore the latter; Pank- emotions. So, for example, he would not have had to speculate
sepp, by his appeal to introspectivism, surely joins me and other that supposedly incompatible emotions such as positive expec-
philosophers in rejecting it. I wish here to show why we should tancy and anger (at the same time and/or about the same thing)
also reject the former. involve reciprocally inhibiting "hypothalamic cells." Rather, he
We at least seem to have some control, for example, through could have considered whether the seeming conflict is due to a
reflection, over whether we have the beliefs (or thoughts) that conflict of ideas - note the problems in believing something
are necessary for an emotion - for example, that we have been both, say, good and bad (in the same respects); or a conflict of
wronged. At least over time, we have some control over our desires - note the problems in both desiring and not desiring
desires: Education and other forms of socialization depend on something (in the same respects); or a conflict of affect - note the
this. Further, whether desire and ratiocination are under our problems in being, say, pleased and pained by something (in the
(present) control, they are often enough not "activated" by an same respects). And, more generally, Panksepp might have
independently identifiable stimulus. So, someone's stepping on been able to further our understanding of the central and
my foot may arouse my anger and thus the appropriate affects, difficult topic of ambivalence in emotions (on which, see Green-
desires, and beliefs. But it may not if I do not believe the person span 1980).
was at fault, or if I do not wish to engage in hostile affrays, or if To draw my comments on the two point together: It must,
my level of affect is too low, or if I was amused, not pained, by however, be recognized that to have pursued affect, desire, and
what happened. Further, even if the emotion is aroused, I may ratiocination would have been to show even more clearly just
hold my temper and not retaliate. And if I do retaliate, I may do how nonhard-wired, just how soft-wired, human emotions are.
so in any number of different ways: hit, kick, swear, belittle, call NOTE
for help. . . . 1. Rorty (1980), is an especially useful anthology. It includes essays
There are indications throughout that Panksepp recognizes by both philosophers and social scientists, and it has an extensive
these facts (e.g., in "A definition of emotions" at (5) and in bibliography on emotions under the following headings: general and
"Learning, reinforcement, and transhypothalamic emotive sys- historical, physiological, biological, psychological, psychoanalytic, an-
tems," last paragraphs) as being true not only of humans, but thropological, and philosophical.
also of lower animals. But then, what remains of the hard-wiring
claim? Very little, I suggest, except perhaps that there is some
neurophysiological "pathway" or complex which may be hard-
wired, which may inhibit or enhance affect, desire, and
ratiocination, and which may mediate between those elements
The rat as hedonist - A systems approach
and either or both of, for example, visceral or hormonal goings- Frederick M. Toates
on, and also (just possibly) physical actions, such as hitting,
Biology Department, The Open University, Milton Keynes MK7 6AA,
unless the latter are inhibited. However true this may be, it is England
not an especially powerful or novel claim. Indeed, it seems true
if neurophysiology plays any role at all in emotions. It might be First, let's accept that behaviour and subjective experience are
suggested that at least Panksepp has elucidated the nature of functions of the nervous system. Then, it is reasonable to
that neurophysiological role. This is outside my competence. attempt a simplified taxonomy of neural circuits and associated
As for the second central point, Panksepp's characterization of affective states, for example, anxiety. However, I don't like to
emotions is both unclear and unclearly motivated. Are we really think of this as a return to introspection. Surely, verbal reports,
told why there are just those four emotions? Is it just that they as made to an interested party (e.g., "I feel afraid"), should be
are the ones so far found? We are not told why the six attributes the subject of the taxonomy. Such reports reflect a common
in "A definition of emotions" are offered as characterizations of language and cultural heritage involving behaviour patterns and
emotional circuits. We are not told what "life-challenging cir- associated verbal labeling.
cumstances" means or applies to. If "challenging" tends towards My primary interest is in animal behaviour, and here Pank-
what is threatening, many emotions - for example, curiosity, sepp considers only one aspect (albeit a vital one) of a complex
amusement, joy - are not captured. If it tends toward what is system. I am concerned with how the mechanisms governing
simply engaging or what is important to or for life, then what is behaviour work. Let me start from a perspective somewhat
not life-challenging? One way to bring this out is to note that in different from Panksepp's. I see the main task to be the design-
this second understanding of "life-challenging," the six condi- ing of a "model rat," which, in its commerce with the simulated
tions would fit (at least various) desires and beliefs. Perhaps this environment, exhibits some performance characteristics of real
is as it should be. Perhaps they, too, are or involve emotions. rats (Deutsch 1960; Gallistel 1980; Toates 1980). Even if one
But this is not discussed, although it may be hinted at in were to attempt a neurophysiologically viable model, the kind of
"Learning reinforcement, and transhypothalamic emotive technique in which Panksepp has faith (lesions, chemical stim-
systems." ulation, etc.) might be of limited use. Given that so many
Panksepp does not deal with beliefs and desires, perhaps out millions of neurons are available, we might need to implicate
of deference to the view that "questions of animal awareness processes and emergent properties for which no obvious identi-
were [to be] shelved." But without beliefs and desires, how fication technique is available, though we would be constantly
could one explain or distinguish among (at least various) human aware of what neurophysiology had to offer. In contrast to
emotions? considering whole, behaving rats, looking at only bits of rats can
Panksepp writes that "the concepts of pleasure/relief and appear, on close examination, to have left the rat immobile,
displeasure/distress are not included in the present analysis." buried in "hope, desire - joyful anticipation," fear, or pleasure.
This might be thought fair enough. Not everything can be How then might we approach the problem of designing a rat?
covered at once. But, first, how can one characterize (at least Consider what Panksepp calls "expectancy." He writes: "A
various) emotions without those concepts? Just consider how fundamental requirement for survival is that an animal move

446 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

from where it is to where life-sustaining objects are located." physiology and behavior, as well as for measuring introspective
This is the crux of the matter, but what kind of process does it elements in the participating subjects. This is no longer any
implicate? First, it means putting a servomechanism in the major source of controversy. However, problems arise when we
head. It is not enough to have a system that "invigorates motor try to use introspective terms in our work with animals. Pank-
behavior" or "modifies sensory acuity." Foraging is not a ran- sepp's remedy is to insist that the terms derived from intro-
dom energization of activity but is purposive and goal-directed. spection should be linked to specific behaviors and specific brain
One might propose a goal-seeking model, in which the rat is structures. This sounds good, but experience with this approach
driven in such a way as to "hunt" for maximum activity at a is not encouraging. I agree with Panksepp that I should use my
hypothalamic site. Choice of goal would be dictated by incentive introspection. What worries me is that all you other people may
objects and physiological states (cf. Bindra 1978). A slight worry do the same. Even if my introspection helps me in my work,
with this model is the discontinuity between consummatory and does it really help us to communicate and develop a "nonperso-
appetitive states as found by Hamburg (1971). Stein (1964) nal" science?
designed a theoretical rat that would run a maze or bar-press for One important source of variance produced by introspection
food by ascending a series of predictive cues. Energy depletion is the attribution mechanisms humans use for the experience of
accentuages the incentive value of the cues, in other words, the emotional arousal. Panksepp treats this lightly, frowns upon the
hypothalamus would be activated by the cue. Compatible with James-Lange aspects of emotional experience, and mentions
Panksepp's argument, a variety of behaviours may maximize Schachter and Singer (1962) en passant. Maybe we should not
such activity, for example, moving towards incentives or self- ignore the attribution mechanisms in psychologists. They may
stimulation. In the latter case, the rat isn't left buried in have even stronger and more varied attribution mechanisms
pleasure, provided that each shock accentuates (reinstates) the than the ordinary person. Hence, we may end up with an even
incentive value of the lever, making it the goal for the next press. worse variance in terminology and a confusion that introspec-
Priming may be needed when the rat is "cold." tion alone cannot solve.
In the natural environment, things get more complex. Forag- One possible bridge to avoid dangerous phylogenetic jumps is
ing demands a cognitive map; the rat goes to distant sites. to compare the instrumental effects of a particular behavior.
Consider the Amakihi, a species of bird which, in its nervous There are, after all, a limited number of logical options open to a
system, can label distant food sites as replenished (Kamil 1978). logical machine like the brain when it is faced with, say, a danger
The map has to be activated by energy depletion, and a given or a frustration. When such logical functions have been identi-
aspect of it forms the goal of behaviour (Deutsch 1960; Gallistel fied across species, and found to depend on homologous struc-
1980). If the animal is blown off course, a control system realigns tures, it then remains only to put a name on the function in
it (cf. Powers 1978). Similarly, out of fear, animals move from a question. The main criterion for a good name is that it communi-
source of danger to one of safety (Bolles 1970; Toates & Birke cate. Flight, freezing, defense and offense are such terms, and
1982). no introspection is required. This is a possible contribution from
Tantalizingly, Panksepp simply notes that his ideas can "easi- comparative psychology that might reduce the confusing and
ly handle many of the striking characteristics of animal learn- terminological mess human introspection has left us with.
ing, " such as autoshaping. But surely the circuits that he reviews To some extent this has already happened. The psycho-
are of very limited usefulness in such an explanation. What kind analytical data base, to the extent that it exists, is based on
of model is relevant to explaining autoshaping? The animal introspection and reports of introspection. The Freudian drive
needs an internal spatial representation of its environment and or "instinct" concept of aggression is not supported by neuro-
superimposed upon this a representation of the causal texture of psychological or neuroethological research in animals. Aggres-
that environment, as, for example, light (E,) predicts food (£2). sion does not appear as a unity. Animal studies show three or
The system must work by E} evoking a memory of E2 (cf. four separate categories (offense, defense, prey-killing, and
Dickinson 1980; Lewis 1979; Toates 1982). It is as if E2 has male sexual behavior; see Adams 1979). Animal research in this
occurred; the animal makes an anticipatory response. In the field has had no benefit from the introspective tradition. Quite
special case of the pigeon, this involves attempting to eat the the contrary, this influence brought confusion and erroneous
key. This is an enormous amount of information processing, assumptions about an aggressive "drive." However, due to an
presumably involving a large part of the brain. active interface between animal and human research, this drive
and instinct concept now seems to be eliminated, both from the
animal and the human literature. The introspective tradition
may therefore benefit from close contact with behavioral sci-
Introspection and science: The problem of ence, but does it really work the other way?
standardizing emotional nomenclature This is not a critisism of Panksepp's own work, which is well
within the behavioral science tradition. As a matter of fact, I fail
Holger Ursin to see where he has really used introspection in anything but
Institute of Physiological Psychology, University of Bergen, 5000 Bergen, naming the phenomena he is studying. Also, I fail to see why his
Norway data or his introspection make it necessary to postulate "panic"
Panksepp's conviction is that the study of emotions is im- (= fear) as a separate emotion. His "expectancy" dimension is an
poverished by our failure to blend human introspection with approach contingency. It seems closely related to response
objective studies of the physiology and behavioral characteris- outcome expectancy (Bolles 1972), but is only a part of the many
tics of emotions in animals. This is, of course, a rather shocking expectancy functions described in contemporary learning theo-
statement, but I think Panksepp deserves credit for bringing ry, at least in its most cognitive formulations. His concept also
this issue into the open. There is little doubt that all of us use has a very interesting and challenging relation to the particular
introspection to some extent when we formulate our problems positive response outcome expectancy, which has been referred
and discuss the validity of our measurements. to as coping (Ursin 1980).
The shock effect may vary among disciplines. In human Finding a name for operationally defined behaviors is very
psychophysiology and psychoendocrinology, there may be only important, and it may be fair to use introspection to select names
mild surprise about his enthusiasm. The most obvious way to as long as we are aware that these remain labels for operational
bridge the gap between human introspection and physiological concepts. Failure to realize this may be the most important
and behavioral characteristics of emotion is, of course, to study source of confusion in our literature. Panksepp has probably put
behavioral and physiological changes in man. There are numer- hisfingeron a very sore and neglected area, but it is difficult to
ous studies where objective methods have been used, both for agree with his prescription for a cure. Our inability to standard-

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 447


Commentary/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

ize and communicate when it comes to our labels is overwhelm- mind, which, in turn, is assumed to be intimately associated
ing. It is remarkable that we still have difficulties with the with the brain. According to Panksepp, the brain contains
taxonomy of aggressive and fear behaviors. This is particularly so circuits corresponding to these subdivisions, and the overt
in the fields of animal neuropsychology and neuroethology. behaviors comprising emotional expression are assumed to be
Perhaps an international convention could help us agree on a initiated or mediated in some way by these primary emotional
nomenclature? This may be necessary to save ourselves, our networks. That is, it is assumed that brain organization is
students, and our future grants. Anatomists, zoologists, and subdivided in ways that correspond to major psychological
psychiatrists have established nomenclature agreements. These concepts.
systems do not eliminate all problems, but they identify the Is such an assumption justified? We think not. In a recent
problems and eliminate the unnecessary ones. At least we will paper, Vanderwolf and Robinson (1981) summarized a good deal
have to show much more determination and will in using each of evidence showing that cerebral slow wave activity is, to a large
other's terms and relating our own definitions to definitions extent, organized in terms of the performance of overt behaviors
available in the literature. We will also have to rid ourselves of such as immobility, head movement, walking, postural changes,
some of the easy paths to fame. One phenomenon will have to licking, face-washing, etc. This organization appears to be inde-
have one name - and not a reference to the smoothest salesman pendent of emotional state.
and best writer of the pack. Anatomists rid themselves of the A similar lack of correspondence between psychological expe-
person-names decades ago, at least for most structures. It may rience and neural organization of behavior has been demon-
be time we did the same. strated in a very different area of research. Despite the fact that
the unity of our visual perceptions is extremely compelling,
there is increasing evidence that this perceptual organization is
Does introspection have a role in not reflected in any simple way in the organization of our visual
pathways. Instead of a single visual system, there appear to be
brain-behavior research? five or more independent (albeit interactive) sensorimotor net-
works, each mediating very different visuomotor behaviors
C. H. Vanderwolf and M. A. Goodale
(Goodale, in press; Goodale & Milner 1982). None of this
Department of Psychology, University of Western Ontario, London, Ontario,
organization would have been discovered by introspection.
Canada N6A 5C2
In the same way, it is also possible that brain activity and
Panksepp's approach to brain-behavior research is based on the neural circuitry are organized, at some level, in terms of feeding
assumption that introspection provides a relatively direct means behavior, sexual behavior, parental behavior, thermoregulatory
of obtaining information about the functional organization of the behavior, grooming behavior, eliminative behavior, territorial
brain. Although this assumption is probably false, Panksepp behavior, predatory behavior, and so on. This organization need
should be commended for making explicit a tacit assumption not correspond with or conform to any of the neural substrates
underlying a good deal of physiological psychology and behav- underlying human emotional experience. In fact, we would
ioral neuroscience. For years, many researchers have routinely argue that there are no unitary representations of emotions as
labeled the behaviors they observe in animals as examples of such. Whatever the neural circuits are that permit comment
fear, pleasure, rage, or anxiety. Whereas we would criticize upon and cognitive processing of our sensory input and motor
them for using a terminology that is derived largely from output during the performance of behaviors we have come to
introspective experience, Panksepp chides them for not using label "emotional" or "affective," it is unlikely that such circuits
introspection enough. Indeed, he asserts that a "single-minded are related in a one-to-one fashion to the circuits mediating
focus on emotional expression without concurrent consideration different kinds of "emotional expression." That is, the brain
of underlying emotional process has outlived its usefulness in mechanisms that generate "emotional" behavior, such as run-
psychobiology and may be currently hindering progress in ning away when one sees a bear, may be quite distinct from the
understanding the neural organization of emotion." mechanisms that enable one to say, at a later time, "I was really
The explicit taxonomy that Panksepp proposes for investigat- frightened, so I ran away as soon as I saw the bear."
ing the neural organization of emotion is derived from an earlier Suggestions of this type are highly speculative. At present, we
introspective scheme developed by Cogan (1802). But however simply do not know how the brain is organized. It seems to us,
consistent this scheme may be with human self-report, we however, that an essential part of the analysis of the brain
contend that introspective systems such as his can tell us mechanisms that control behavior must consist of careful de-
nothing about the neural substrates of behavior. "Mental" scription and study of behavior. Behavior is the end result of the
processes cannot be directly examined. We "know our own activity of most of the nervous system and, as in any complex
minds" largely or entirely as an inference from our own behavior system, a study of output might reveal something of the internal
and not as a result of direct inspection (Hebb 1980). Similarly, organization. Psychological approaches such as Panksepp's,
Skinner (1974) concludes that the internal mechanisms that which consider "mind" to be of primary interest, tend to
cause behavior are, in general, not open to direct examination discourage systematic study of behavior (Vanderwolf, in press).
by introspection. A recent paper by Nisbett and Wilson (1977) For example, Panksepp makes no serious attempt to relate the
summarizes a body of experiments in the fields of social and effects of localized hypothalamic stimulation to the normal
cognitive psychology that supports these views of Hebb and behavior of the species studied, even though it is widely recog-
Skinner. Thus, it is quite unlikely that introspection can provide nized that a good knowledge of normal behavior is an essential
decisive information on the functional organization of the inter- prerequisite for work in this field. Further, Panksepp gives no
nal processes that give rise to behavior. In fact, it would be detailed discussion of possible rules by which an "emotional"
remarkable if introspection were of any assistance in this re- behavior might be distinguished from a "nonemotional" behav-
spect. In this century we have come to believe that neural ior, or of how one might identify the presence of any particular
activity is the immediate cause of all behavior. However, it is emotion in a normal animal.
apparent that introspection reveals nothing of the structure or In conclusion, we suggest that introspection, in the sense of
function of the brain. If it did, it would not be necessary to direct examination of the mechanisms that control behavior,
experiment on the brains of animals. An investigator could study probably does not exist and, therefore, cannot be a useful way of
the anatomy and physiology of his own brain by introspection! studying the brain. We suggest further that a preoccupation
A psychological approach of the type advocated by Panksepp with psychological concepts actually impedes research, since it
makes further assumptions. In his scheme, emotion and its diverts investigators from a thorough study of brain-behavior
components are conceived of as subdivisions or states of the relations.

448 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

Can arousal be pleasurable? rotransmitter, along with dopamine, mediates reward systems.
Evidence is conflicting on all of these hypotheses, but it should
Marvin Zuckerman be noted that there is the possibility of more than one arousal
Department of Psychology, University of Delaware, Newark, Del. 19711 system. Routtenberg (1968) suggested that the limbic reward
Like Gray's (1982a) The Neurophysiology of Anxiety [see BBS system has its own arousal pathways to the forebrain and that
multiple book review, this issue], Panksepp's article represents these constitute a second arousal system, the reticular activating
a laudable attempt to link emotions with specific neural circuits system being the first. Since his paper, these pathways have
in the limbic brain. Panksepp's work is more ambitious, dealing been discovered, lending support to the idea of a type of arousal
with four primary emotional states instead of one, and less generated by, and linked to, reward mechanisms.
insistently behavioral in admitting the value of introspective Certainly the high levels of arousal associated with sexual
data from humans as a source of knowledge, even though such activity are experienced as pleasurable before the drive- reduc-
data are hard to come by in the psychopharmacology and brain tion or orgasm. Male sexual behavior is enhanced by brain
stimulation literature. I am in agreement with these general dopamine and suppressed by serotonin (Gessa & Tagliamonte
approaches to the understanding of emotional states and traits, 1974). Norepinephrine may also play an excitatory role in sexual
and my criticism (as with Gray's work) is addressed at specifics arousal. The question is whether the monoamines simply exert a
rather than the comparative approach. My commentary will be nonspecific arousal effect or are specifically effective in sensitiz-
focused on the system of greatest interest to me, "expectancy," ing reward systems. Is the release of dopamine or nor-
because of its resemblance to the trait of "sensation seeking" epinephrine associated with the experience of pleasure,
(Zuckerman 1979). whether from intrinsic reward mechanisms or reduction of
Although Gray uses the term "anxiety," a term with phe- activity in a punishment-anxiety system? Many of these ques-
nomenological surplus meaning in the human sphere, to de- tions could be resolved by work with humans, in which intro-
scribe one of his three major emotional systems, he uses the spective data are obtainable.
more behavioral term "impulsivity" to describe the adient
system. Similarly, Panksepp uses "fear' to label the avoidant
mechanisms and "expectancy" to describe a system for the
mediation of "exploration-approach-investigation." Why are
these theorists reluctant to use terms like "desire, ' "pleasure,"
or "joy" when describing the emotional system related to the Author's Response
expectancy or reward, yet willing to use terms like "anxiety" or
"fear" to describe the system related to the expectancy of
punishment?
In the case of Panksepp, his avoidance of the term "pleasure," Archaeology of mind
despite his acceptance of human introspective data, is a function
Jaak Panksepp
of his drive-reduction view of motivation. Pleasure is conceived
Department of Psychology, Bowling Green State University, Bowling
as a state that accompanies stimuli "that tend to return organ- Green, Ohio 43403
isms toward physiological homeostasis and emotional equi-
librium." He further claims that such states do not appear to It is difficult to imagine science without words, but quite
"generate unique behavioral manifestations." But the system he easy to imagine feelings without words. This is under-
describes as "expectancy' (meaning limited to positive expec- standable, for functional neuroanatomy has affirmed that
tancy) is one that has been mapped through self-stimulation the brain's ability to elaborate affective representations of
studies of the brain as well as externally controlled stimulation.
Self-stimulation or exploration (which may occur in the absence reality evolved much earlier than its ability to generate
of specific searches for substances needed to redress "homeosta- scientific-linguistic representations of reality. Further-
tic imbalances") are activities that create arousal, not reduce it. more, granted that a major force behind the evolution of
In strict drive-reduction terms only the reduction of arousal can complex human linguistic abilities was the adaptive util-
be reinforcing. But tell that to well-fed rats sniffing around a new ity of communicating interrelations among environmen-
environment, or to humans spending large sums of money to tal events (such as would be needed, for example, in
travel and to look at or listen to complex and novel stimuli, or to complex forms of group-hunting, defense, foraging, co-
sniff or smoke stimulants like cocaine. While drug users may habitation, and migration), the linguistic and scientific
find pleasure in the effects of depressant and stimulant drugs, an analysis of internal processes such as emotion appears
experimental study of drugs given blind showed that the stim-
ulant D-amphetamine both maintained high levels of arousal compromised at the outset. Our imprecision in conveying
and produced positive affect more consistently than a depres- emotions verbally (as well as the importance of emotions
sant, diazepam (Carrol & Zuckerman, in press). The latter was in controlling behavior) is captured in the aphorism, "It's
more likely to produce states of anxiety, depression, or hostility, not what you say - it's the way you say it."
accompanying decreased arousal. The semantic controversies that routinely arise in the
Are there specific behavioral indicators associated with the discussion of emotion have long hindered the progress of
state of "pleasure" other than the tendency to approach the research in this area, and understandably, most biolog-
stimulus? Emotional expressions such as the human smile and ically oriented investigators have restricted their study of
the dog's tail wag seem to provide a behavioral supplement to emotion to behavioral expressions, with little considera-
the approach-behavior definition. Although I am not sure about tion of the underlying internal processes. At least we can
the expression of positive emotion in our more favored subject, agree verbally on what we have seen, while internal
the rat, I believe if we spent as much time studying positive
emotions as we do fear and anger, we wouldfindsuch indicators. processes can only be observed through a distorted intro-
Is there only one arousal system, as Panksepp seems to spective or theoretical lens.
suggest? Do norepinephrine and serotonin act equally on all However, I daresay most people would agree that "the
emotive systems (see Panksepp's Figure 4)? In contrast, Gray affective faculties have their origin from within, and are
(1982b) and Stein (1978) suggest that serotonin mediates an not acquired by any external circumstances. They cannot
anxiety system. Gray also feels that norepinephrine is involved be taught and must be felt to be understood; in them-
in part of this system, while Stein believes that this neu- selves they are blind and act without understanding;

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 449


Response/Fanksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
finally they are partly common to man and animals, partly Put simply, the emotive circuits I described may be
proper to man" (Spurzheim 1846, p. 136). My own necessary though not sufficient substrates for the genesis
position was premised on such seemingly self-evident of emotion in the mammalian brain. Brain software (i.e.,
truths. Accordingly, my aim was to interrelate the psy- learning) no doubt operates on the genetically provided
chology and neurology of emotional processes at a level emotive circuits (Averill, Stocker), but such software may
primitive enough to permit rather strict empirical evalua- not be possible without the hard-ware I have outlined.
tion of theoretical propositions. As there is only limited The schizm between the "two cultures" was most
biological knowledge on the topic, this is a narrow path, poignantly expressed by Lazarus, whose reaction to my
bordered on one side by ungrounded philosophy and art, proposal cascaded from the high hope that something
and on the other by a radical empiricism which recognizes new and psychosocially significant would be said about
only human observation (largely visual) as a credible the human condition to the despair of having to deal with
source of scientific inference and understanding. I would alien neurological facts. I regret that the bridge between
argue that to be tempted to one of these sides may be as these distant shores of understanding remains to be
detrimental to understanding as to be tempted to the completed, but it will require both sides to prepare
other. If there is a "royal road," it is one by which common and firm ground. Those with psychosocial and
psychobiology and psychophenomenology are interre- psychophenomenological interests must appreciate the
lated at a level that does no severe injustice to either. As nature, importance and limitations of psychobiological
summarized in the commentaries on my target article, inquiries, and neuroscientists must seek ever more com-
there is little agreement that this can be done. However, plex functional principles for the brain. Some commenta-
I was encouraged that the arrows of criticism were dis- tors steeped in the behaviorist tradition already thought I
tributed rather evenly around the target I provided, had gone too far toward the other side; the despair that
suggesting that I may have struck a realistic, if not a Lazarus felt on reading some facts about the brain was
happy, medium. Who has come closest to the mark matched by the concern Ursin and Vanderwolf & Good-
remains to be seen, of course, for the penetration of ale felt at the apparent capitulation of an empirically
future research into the underlying brain mechanisms of oriented colleague.
emotion is the metric by which the accuracy of our aim Still, there is a bridge to be built between the cogni-
will be measured. tive/clinical and the neurobehavioral cultures, and sever-
al commentators agreed that the needed materials may be
Two cultures. Two attitudes polarize the debate over at hand (Fonberg, Heath, Izard); and some attempts at
emotions. Commentators commited to understanding constructing it have already been made (see Willis, 1683,
affective experiences in human life are disturbed by and see Arnold, 1960, for a more recent admirable
attempts to view emotion in reductionist, neurological attempt).
terms. They recommend more conceptual complexity in
discussing emotions than can presently be incorporated Introspection! Why not? Among cognitively oriented
into the psychobiological enterprise (Averill, Jaynes, commentators, introspection was generally deemed es-
Lazarus, Plutchik, Royce, Solomon, Stocker). At the sential for understanding emotion (Arnold, Averill,
other pole, several investigators committed to charac- Clynes, de Rivera, Globus, Lazarus, Royce, Stocker,
terizing behavior accurately are skeptical of attempts to Zuckerman). On the other hand, Lutz, Plutchik, Ursin,
use concepts suggesting that animals experience emo- and Vanderwolf & Goodale were especially cautious
tions (Anisman & Zacharko, Ursin, Vanderwolf & Good- concerning the utility of introspective information in
ale) - a stance with which I do not agree because it generating hypotheses about brain function. Everyone
arbitrarily closes doors to potential knowledge (also see would certainly agree that many mechanisms that con-
Griffin 1976). There is also another road, perhaps most trol behavior operate subconsciously, and that introspec-
difficult of all, which I would take with those who suppose tion may be directly useful in deciphering only certain
that a realistic account of brain activity underlying emo- facets of brain organization.
tions will require a compromise between such polar Still, it seems evident that human consciousness ex-
viewpoints (Fonberg, Globus, Gray, Heath, Izard, ists, whether it started in 4004 B.C. as the seventeenth-
Katz). century Irish divine, James Ussher, would have had our
What appears too often forgotten by aesthetically, God-fearing ancestors believe, around 1000 B.C. as
philosophically, and cognitively oriented contemplators Jaynes suggests, before 10,000 B.C. as the paleolithic
of emotions is the basic nature of scientific inquiry. In wall painting at Lescaux may indicate, or around the
attempting to simplify complex systems, one necessarily time transhypothalamic emotive circuits evolved into
does some injustice to the manifestations of those systems basal ganglia in the premammalian brain, as I would
in the real world. For instance, in considering the lattice argue. Regardless of when it came about, the concept of
properties of crystallized water, science provides a cogent consciousness is as sound as that of gravity, even though
explanation for the six points of a snowflake, but it has not different species are probably endowed with different
explained the exact form each snowflake assumes in life. degrees of this brain function. Introspection emerges
As emphasized by Katz, even if the rules of nature I from this faculty in the human species. Although it will
propose are correct, the full emotional richness of human not help directly to solve all psychobiological questions
life will not have been denied, compromised, or deni- (Nisbett & Wilson 1977), I trust that, if carefully used in
grated: The emotive circuits I outlined may initiate emo- the study of emotion, it will deceive us no more than any
tions in all mammals, while also interacting with higher other adaptive mechanism evolution has bestowed on
brain functions and cultural processes that distinguish our bodies.
humans from other animals (as emphasized by Delgado). By way of reply to Globus: My perspective on the

450 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
utility of introspection in the study of emotions is a cesses. (Thus, de Sousa, Lutz, and Vanderwolf & Good-
natural outgrowth of my conception of how conscious- ale's citation of Nisbett & Wilson's (1977) critical analysis
ness evolved in the mammalian brain. I assume that the for higher order cognitive processes should not be over-
most primitive function of consciousness is to facilitate generalized to basic emotive processes.)
adaptive response selection from alternative courses of As Klein indicates, the classical introspective tradition
action: It allows organisms to cope with complex en- in psychology waned because it led to untestable propo-
vironmental situations in which several behavioral alter- sitions. When no agreement can be reached with words,
natives are competing, with comparable urgency, for a there can be no scientific reward. When mental pro-
common output channel in the brain. Such a crisis of cesses are not linked to brain mechanisms, avenues for
choice (if one can imagine a crisis on an evolutionary arbitrary disagreement will always remain open. Thus,
time scale) may have become most urgent to species that my point is that introspection (especially as applied to
possessed executive brain mechanisms that could con- cross-species analyses of internal brain functions) is best
currently promote several adaptive behavior patterns to restricted to brain processes that appear to have a sub-
a single type of environmental challenge. As I have stantive basis (i.e., which are genetically established
discussed more fully elsewhere (Panksepp 1981a), emo- rather than merely experientially derived). Such a re-
tive command circuits may have such a characteristic. striction could have several beneficial effects on the
This flexibility could promote adaptive response-mold- study of internal events. It may help curb over-imagina-
ing, perhaps by a "reinforcement" mechanism linked to tive concepts that hinder scientific progress, and it may
fluctuating activities in the underlying executive cir- encourage cognitively oriented investigators to under-
cuits. In simple animals, such response selection (or take reliable, convergent introspective studies rather
habit formation) might operate at a preconscious level, than open-ended ones.
but as the trajectory of evolution took species to ever I assume that interobserver reliability across different
more complex environments (reinforcing sophisticated cultures, in children as well as adults, would be very
spatial representation abilities), more sophisticated deci- high for identifying real-life as well as simulated por-
sion-making processes evolved from the earlier solu- trayals of the four emotional processes I discussed.1 I
tions; and today I think we call these processes con- also suspect that most observers could, with little hin-
sciousness. If human consciousness is rooted in the drance or assistance from culturally conditioned imag-
primitive response selection, response-molding mecha- ination, correctly decipher similar emotional signals in
nisms that emotive circuits elaborate, introspection other mammals. If such experiments yield stable results,
should still have some access to the dynamics of the we should accept the reality of the underlying brain
underlying command circuitry. This is not to deny that states as readily as if numbers had been read off meters.
the introspective view, through the layers of other brain The extent to which information derived from human
functions, can be hazy, as suggested by Freud, Lutz, and introspection is pertinent to related species, and the
Plutchik. extent to which information derived from animal brain
Although my approach could easily be mistaken for research is relevant for understanding human brain pro-
dualism (Solomon), Clobus correctly argues that my the- cesses is not known with precision at the present time
sis is not credible from that perspective. True dualism (Anisman & Zacharko). Ultimately, the validity of such
entails rejecting introspection as a source of scientific generalizations will depend on (1) whether brain net-
hypotheses about certain brain processes. The implicit works from which human emotions arise are class-typical
dualism of behaviorism has in fact long been disguised as or species-typical circuits, and, if the former is true (as it
monism and should be revealed for what it is - "sham" seems to be), (2) the degree of evolutionary modification
monism. If we believe in the continuity of the natural these circuits have undergone. There will surely be
world, we must acknowledge and use all available major species differences, but considering the impor-
sources of information in order to understand our brains. tance of the adaptive solutions encoded in the executive
Since the human brain must extract external informa- functions of such circuits, I suspect that the differences
tion from sensory transduction systems, it seems evident will be matters of detail rather than of kind. Evolution-
that all scientific knowledge is ultimately based on intro- ary molding of these circuits no doubt contributed to
spection (as decoded through language). Accordingly, all species-characteristic (i) variations in the vigor of the
aspects of brain function should be accepted as potential individual executive circuits, (ii) changes in the degree of
sources of psychobiological hypotheses. Although in- interaction among the circuits, (iii) channeling of differ-
terobserver reliabilities may be higher for visual and ent sensory and perceptual inputs to these circuits, and
auditory information than for other sensory systems, that (iv) modification of species-typical expressions that arise
is not a rationale for rejecting the other sources of infor- from the activation of these circuits. Of course, our use
mation. The subjective experiences generated by taste, of introspective insights to study these processes in other
touch, and smell provided fundamental information on species need not imply that other animals also have
which the physiological analysis of those sensory systems introspective capacities - only (as so frankly expressed
was based. Why should it be any different with in- by Fonberg) that they have emotions.
teroreceptive senses or internal brain processes? There Introspective analysis of internal processes has ob-
are no good objections; only unverified assumptions that vious limitations. As emphasized by Vanderwolf &
those sources of information either do not exist or have Coodale, it will not provide any information about the
little interobserver reliability. I think both skeptical localization of function in the nervous system (except
viewpoints are demonstrably incorrect regarding the perhaps in brain-damaged individuals). The mapping of
four emotive processes I have discussed, although they brain circuits can only be achieved through direct analy-
may well be correct regarding certain cognitive pro- sis of the nervous system, and for my purposes, well-

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 451


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
organized behavior patterns evoked by localized brain ple will stop analyzing the underlying control mecha-
stimulation are especially informative. Thus, the major nisms. I disagree. One could just as easily claim that
use of introspection will be in generating credible tax- such terms as "defense" and "flight" (Ursin) imply that
onomies that can be related to brain processes, leading, animals are voluntarily doing something, and hence that
one hopes, to incisive behavioral studies using tradi- those labels are unacceptably mentalistic. Affective
tional psychobiological tools. With luck, it may also pro- terms can promote the subtlety of our empirical studies
vide usable information about the attributes of those - increasing rather than decreasing our focus on behav-
processes, including interrelations among the various ior. And surely, if we insist that psychobiology can be
circuits. constituted only of constructs we see with the eye, we
shall have failed to confront nature on her own terms.
The semantics of emotions. Practically all words used to Can a consensus be forged? Perhaps - by selecting our
discuss affective processes are imprecise. Some are free terms according to some overall criterion of utility.
of undesirable connotations, while others are so heavily There are two principal reasons, and many subsidiary
laden with divergent meanings that their communicative ones, for studying emotion in the animal brain. First, it
value is compromised. Operational definitions are desir- may provide lasting insights into the common roots of
able, but the methodological advantage gained is often human and animal nature. Second, it may yield informa-
offset by the failure of rigid definitions to promote our tion through which human and animal suffering can be
thinking about the underlying issues. In defining emo- reduced. Thus, it would be most useful if we selected
tional processes simultaneously with respect to anatom- labels for our emotive circuits that are also applicable to
ically defined circuits and their many properties, I was existential experiences, psychiatry, brain research, and
seeking a compromise that might prove useful for the animal behavior. This was the compromise I was seek-
diverse disciplines that study emotions. ing. Perhaps hyphenated designations would be more
There was substantial disagreement with my selection acceptable to more disciplines -
of terms. Morton homes in on the problem of undesir- exploration-curiosity-foraging-expectation-desire;
able semantic connotations. As he notes, I may have flight-caution-anxiety-fear-horror;
identified four unconditional emotive circuits, which are offense-irritability-anger-rage-fury;
necessary for the elaboration of four affective qualities, crying-sadness-sorrow-grief-panic.
with no single word sufficing to label any of these states. The connotative crosstalk between the terms fear and
Zuckerman, on the other hand, expressed concern with panic was deemed especially troublesome (Fonberg,
the reluctance of psychobiologists to use terms such as Izard, Plutchik, Solomon). Through cultural condition-
"desire," "pleasure," or "joy." Ursin would retain only ing, we have learned to use the word "panic" in such a
visually descriptive words, which summarize what we general way as to convey practically any form of trepida-
think the animal is doing, such as "flight," "freezing," tion. Sorrow, sadness, and grief (or perhaps distress, as
"defense," and "offense." As he suggests, we are in suggested by Izard) would have been more understand-
desperate need of an international congress to standard- able. However, my choice was aimed at building a
ize terminology, but agreement would seem unlikely. bridge to the relevant data base in psychiatry. As dis-
The problem runs deeper than linguistics - to the cussed by Klein, those sudden crises of existential terror
very nature of the emotive neural circuits mammals are known as "panic attacks" that characterize agoraphobia
endowed with. Each emotive command system can ap- seem to be elaborated by brain mechanisms distinct
parently be activated by diverse stimuli and can control from those which mediate chronic anxiety neuroses (for
multiple responses at various levels of the neuraxis (tar- further discussion, see Panksepp on Gray, this issue).
get article, Figure 3). Since these systems do many There is reason to believe that "panic attacks" are con-
things simultaneously, it is not surprising that there are trolled by brain circuits that mediate separation distress.
multiple semantic representations for the patterns of Thus, so long as we recognize that the referent here is
neural activity that can be orchestrated by each system. sorrow rather than fear, panic may be a useful and
My prescription is simple: We should not label the appropriate term.
system with respect to its inputs or outputs; rather, we The label expectancy also caused concern (Fonberg,
should seek a label that will do justice to the most Lyons, Morton, Solomon), for it could be taken to apply
important existential attributes of these circuits, namely, either to positive or negative anticipatory states - desire
affective states. By this maneuver, we not only acknowl- or foreboding. It could also be taken to be affectively
edge our primary source of information about these cir- neutral (Lazarus). I did indicate that the term was ap-
cuits, but most people will understand us without having plied only in the positive affective sense, but perhaps
to learn alien and, at times, content-free vocabularies terms such as desire and pleasure advocated by Zucker-
(e.g., Type 1 and Type 2 behaviors: Vanderwolf & man, would have been clearer. Unfortunately, those
Robinson 1981). Also, since the most incisive informa- terms do not relate well to the major emotional disorder
tion in this area is bound to come from the study of presumed to arise from overactivity of this system
children (Izard), diverse cultures (Clynes, Lutz), the (schizophrenia). Perhaps expectancy does not accom-
emotionally ailing (Heath, Klein), and the brains of ani- plish this either,2 but the term does promise to be useful
mals, we should probably select a set of terms that can in animal research. Briefly (since this is discussed more
be shared across all these disciplines. extensively elsewhere: Panksepp 1981a; 1982a; 1982b),
Animal behaviorists may shudder and say that the the idea that lateral hypothalamic self-stimulation cir-
application of mental-state labels to animals will be disas- cuits mediate "foraging-expectancy" as opposed to
trous - that they will be used as explanations, and peo- "pleasure" suggests that we should begin analyzing how

452 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
these systems govern an animal's search for food and with little more than opinion, and that won't do in the
knowledge - lines of investigation that remain poorly laboratory.
developed. I am not wedded to the conclusion that there are only
It is unlikely that we can resolve disagreements con- four emotive command circuits in the brain (Stocker),
cerning the meanings of terms such as emotions and but each addition to the list should be related to empiri-
feelings (Fonberg). Fortunately, where animal brain re- cal evidence derived, in part, from an analysis of brain
search is concerned, such distinctions are not very systems. I have considered including executive circuits
urgent. In suggesting neurally based definitions for for courting and sexually directed behaviors (lust), since
these concepts, I attempted to provide a new perspec- brain stimulation can evoke genital engorgement and
tive on this old issue. In my scheme, emotive command copulation but, just as with eating and drinking (discrete
circuits are activated by various sensory inputs whose behaviors though they are), the common underlying
influence is at least bimodally distributed. The stimuli emotive impulse may arise from a shared executive influ-
that have strong and sustained interactions with these ence (one which promotes forward locomotion with in-
circuits may be considered life challenging (in answer to vestigation). Indeed, hypothalamic stimulation that
Stocker), and evoke bona fide emotions. Those stimuli yields sexual behavior in rats can, with time, come to
that have weak interactions with these circuits are con- evoke other consummatory behaviors (Caggiula 1969). I
sidered to have evoked feelings. Accordingly, the num- do not wish to deny by this the existence of distinct
ber of emotions is limited to the number of emotive sexual "feelings," but merely to suggest that seeking a
command systems that exist in the brain, while the sexual partner is not governed by a separate emotive
variety of feelings, like that of snowflakes, is infinite. circuit (although the aroused appetitive behavior may
In summary, the selection of terms for a psychobiol- well be channeled to an appropriate subject by feelings
ogy of emotions is indeed problematic (Ursin). Many arising from genitalia and hormonal interoreceptors). I
difficulties arise from the old fear that animal behavior- am also hesitant to include "defense" and "submission"
ists will begin using mentalistic terms as explanatory as primary systems (see Panksepp 1979). It seems more
principles (Vanderwolf & Coodale). If such terms are to likely to me that there exists a distinct emotive circuit for
be used, they have to be tied to objective mechanisms. dominance displays (MacLean 1981), which may elabo-
The brain contains convergence pathways that collect rate a primitive "will to power" from which assertive
diverse forms of information from the external and inter- play, human courage, and the so-called "aggression" in
nal worlds; through intrinsic circuit transformations, sex (Plutchik) may arise; but the neurological evidence is
these circuits generate coherent psychobehavioral ten- presently too sparse to support the cross-species gener-
dencies that are only indirectly measurable as outputs. ality of such a conclusion.
Fortunately, many primitive central processes of this Although more complex models can be generated, it is
type may have been captured reasonably well by our to be hoped that such elaborations will not be based
introspective abilities as well as in the affective terms simply on introspective hunches. Plutchik has put for-
that came to be used during the early evolution of our ward a geometric model consisting of eight rather unam-
human languages. Although the psychobiology of some biguous affective processes; but to give surprise, disgust,
future time may find the continued use of such terms to and acceptance equal status with fear, rage, panic, and
be counterproductive (Anisman & Zacharko), I think desire does not seem justified either by subjective expe-
they serve well for now. Indeed, if such terms do ap- rience or our knowledge of brain mechanisms. Similarly,
proximate some essential neurological truths, they will the list of primary emotions proposed by Izard (1971) -
surely be retained in the future (the way the Newtonian surprise, enjoyment, disgust, shame, distress, interest,
concepts of "mass" and "force" endure). If, however, we fear, contempt, and anger - is longer than animal brain
begin using the human mental states represented by research can justifiably support at the present time.
these words as explanations of animal behavior, (dis- Although we can easily get startle/orienting-responses
regarding, for the moment, that evolution appears to (surprise?) from a vast number of electrodes in the re-
have provided such paths of causality to humans through ticular core of the brainstem, I interpret that to reflect
the emergence and refinement of brain fantasy mecha- precipitous brain activity evoked by sudden arousal of
nisms), then they will be psychobiology's "phlogistons" the reticular activating system (target article, Figure 4).
and "ethers." Thus, if we ever choose to use plain lan- Furthermore, surprise is a transient psychological state
guage again to discuss emotions in psychobiology, we without the sustained affect that characterizes the major
shall also have to pass down to our students the recogni- emotions. Disgust has even greater problems. It is diffi-
tion that words are just words - they help us think about cult to evoke retching via brain stimulation, and subjec-
problems. That done, our job is to unravel the neural tively, nausea is about as affect-laden as stomach cramps
mechanisms subserving those processes (Toates). (they both feel bad), but the aversive feeling wanes
rapidly after the precipitating stimulus is gone. With
major emotions, the eliciting stimuli can disappear, but
On taxonomies of emotions. As Solomon noted, I did the emotions boil on. Further, there are no major psy-
indeed saddle myself with a rather frugal, neurologically chiatric disorders characterized by imbalances of sur-
based list of emotions, which does require one to go prise, disgust, and stomach cramps. This suggests that
through some mental gymnastics to generate the more the neural circuitry differs in kind from that mediating
subtle human feelings; Solomon concludes that I must bona fide emotions. Along similar lines, Lutz indicates
obviously have it wrong, no matter what the neurological that cross-cultural studies have not found surprise and
findings (a rather antiscientific opinion). Unless we an- disgust to be perceived as emotional states. Solomon also
chor our emotional concepts empirically, we will end up

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 453


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
argues against their being emotions, but does not indi- of telling us something about pleasure. In our laborato-
cate his reasons (though he deems mine incorrect). ry, we have become very conversant with this appen-
Several commentators disagreed with my suggestion dage, but we have reached the conclusion that the tail
that exectancy should be considered an emotion (Fon- wags not as a generalized indicator of desire or pleasure,
berg, Lazarus, Lyons), while others did find it compati- but as a social, contact-soliciting gesture. As demon-
ble with their thinking (Izard, Plutchik). As already strated in a recent dissertation by Davis (1980), the dog's
discussed, this disagreement may merely reflect the se- tail does not wag vigorously when it is simply expecting
mantic biases that encumber the field. Considering my food or when it is pleasantly surprised, but it wags
definition of emotion with reference to circuit charac- frenziedly at the appearance of a desirable social com-
teristics, which no commentator seriously criticized, it panion (who, in real life, is all too often carrying a bowl of
should have been clear that the brain system I was food, leading to potential ambiguity regarding what the
discussing did have properties essential for an emotive tail is responding to). It is noteworthy that opioid recep-
system, regardless of the label used. tor blockade is very effective in increasing tail wagging.
My taxonomy of emotions has much in common with Perhaps this is because the animal's internal state has
the models of Fonberg and Gray. However, diverging been shifted toward loneliness (i.e., the "panic" system
from Grays conclusion that flight and attack may repre- has become more active). The failure of the same experi-
sent activity in a single emotive system, Fonberg (in ment to produce panic attacks in humans (Klein) is in-
agreement with my own observations in rats) reports teresting, but not inconsistent with our work in the
that distinct fear and rage systems are activated by hypo- area.3 Although I would agree that pleasure is a concept
thalamic stimulation in dogs. Basing his conclusion we should continue struggling with in the animal labora-
largely on behavioral studies using electrical foot shock, tory, until it can be measured in a convincing fashion, it
contributes little to our understanding of animal behav-
Gray suggests that there are separate anxiety-fear and
ior. However, if we do reach a stage where such pro-
flight-flight systems. The problem with such experi- cesses can be analyzed in animals, I suspect that plea-
ments is that the convergence of pain inputs onto several sure will be best understood in the context of
emotive command systems - perhaps all three of the homeostatic principles that help sustain the integrity of
affectively negative ones in my list - makes it impossible the body as well as the species.
to distinguish among distinct neural systems. Contrary
to Gray's conclusion, my suggestion that hypothala- A number of commentators were concerned about my
mically elicited flight is a reasonable index of fear is brevity in describing how complex human emotions may
supported by pharmacological evidence that escape from arise from the more basic ones (Averill, de Sousa,
such brain stimulation can be reduced by antianxiety Lazarus, Solomon). I suggested only that they may be
agents (Panksepp, Gandelman, & Trowill 1970). blended from the activities of the fundamental systems.
At a more general level, several commentators were This, of course, is the traditional statement of ignorance
concerned about the absence of a pleasure/aversion di- about the matter, and no commentator suggested an
mension in my analysis (Katz, Zuckerman). Although I alternative view. Still, at a rational level (if Klein will
may well appreciate the pleasure/aversion dimension at again permit me to use the term loosely), I would argue
a personal level, I do not know of any empirical evidence that (contrary to Solomon's opinion) it is reasonable to
to indicate that it is elaborated in the brain by distinct consider jealousy (at least from love's perspective) as an
emotive circuits (i.e., ones that bring diverse behavioral admixture of panic, rage, and expectancy: As one feels
and physiological responses under a common executive abandoned (panic), and somewhat angry (rage) toward
influence). Accordingly, I suggested that pleasure/aver- the person whose behavior threatens the existing bond,
sion might be understood as fluctuating activities of the there may still be a longing that things will change
individual emotive systems. For instance, such affects (expectancy). Similarly, shame is a very important
may be elaborated by more generalized neural systems human feeling (Izard, Katz, Jaynes); however, I do not
within which the discrete emotive systems are embed- think it is a fundamental process, but one engendered by
ded (Katz). The issue of pleasure/aversion is of obvious diminished self-esteem (will-to-power), coupled with the
importance (and I have considered it elsewhere as a implicit threat of retribution, be it physical punishment
protopathic background activity in the brain; see Pank- (i.e., fear) or withdrawal of social support (i.e., panic).
sepp 1981a), but, except for taking sides on the need for Whether my introspective distillation of experience has
such concepts, no commentator proposed a cogent em- any generality can be evaluated empirically, and if it
pirical way to address the issue in animal research. We does, my major point would be that such results may tell
could indeed use simple approach and avoidance as mea- us something about interactions that can exist among the
sures (Katz); but with four systems already in place, one underlying primary emotive circuits. Presumably the
of which yields approach and the other three avoidance, mysterious glue that will render these mixtures a single
the utility of the more general dimension is compro- compound (de Sousa) resides in the semantic attribution
mised, save as a class identifier. Thus, in animal re- faculties of the human brain.
search, the concept of pleasure daunts us like the smile In attempting to simplify matters, my target article
of the Cheshire cat. Of course, in humans we can obtain may have portrayed emotive circuits too much as mono-
the needed verbal reports (Zuckerman), and pleasure lithic entities responding to major life emergencies
has in fact been evoked by stimulating the human brain (Lyons); to understand their role in behavior, we also
(Heath); many of us believe such feelings may be medi-
need to imagine their role in the organization of every-
ated by brain dopamine and endorphin systems
day affairs. I suspect that these circuits help control
(Plutchik).
behavior throughout the day, and modestfluctuationsin
Zuckerman suggests that the dog's tail may be capable them may evoke diverse affective states with distinct

454 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
names. Indeed, some remarkable phenomena could "Tiina, can you tell me something? [She looks up
emerge from the waxing and waning of activity in these agreeably.] How many emotions are there?"
circuits. For instance, Clynes describes the positive af- "What's an emotion?" she queries.
fect that can be experienced during music expressing "Mm . . . it's the way we feel. How many different
grief. This may seem paradoxical, but it is quite reason- ways can we feel?"
able from the viewpoint that music capable of activating She places a finger to her lips and looks briefly
the sorrow-panic system should yield successive in- puzzled, and then rattles off, "Happy, mad, sad. . . . Is
creases and decreases in the activity of the underlying that right, Daddy?"
circuit. Thisfluxshould repeatedly evoke opponent neu- "I'm not sure - you tell me. Are there any more?"
ral processes, and hence may be moving indeed. Al- "Mm, yes, yes, scared! Is that right?"
though our cognitive appraisal may add to its beauty, I "You tell me."
suspect that it would all sound rather flat if our limbic "Mm . . . mm . . . mm . . . frowned? Are there any
circuits did not resonate with the music. more?" [She is beginning to look exasperated.]
If one attempts to visualize the activities of the under- "Hey, that's really good. Can you show me all those in
lying neural mechanisms on a realistic time scale, the faces?"
behavioral and psychological possibilities within these As I say "happy," she smiles and jumps up and down
systems are vast. For instance, perhaps I can allay clapping her hands; as I say "mad," she frowns, clenches
Klein's and Klinger & Kemble's concern about positive her jaw, and more or less growls at me; as I say "sad,"
affective states existing during both increases and de- she pantomimes the mask of tragedy; as I say "scared,"
creases in the activity of the expectancy circuit, by spec- she retracts her torso, balloons her eyes, and shows a
ulating how this and related systems operate in real life. frightened mouth; as I say "frowned," she looks puzzled,
When a hungry animal is confronted by an enticing odor scratches her head a little, and finally crunches her face
(i.e., one that unconditionally evokes activity in the up in a way that communicates little to me.
expectancy system), the aroused dopamine circuits (es- Granted that "happiness" is the positive affective rep-
pecially the mesolimbic ones) would induce the animal resentation of desire (expectancies) fulfilled, and that the
to move forward (by activating appropriate motor sub- labels "mad," "sad," and "scared," can be translated as
routines), and there would be sequential decreases and "anger-rage," "sorrow-panic," and "anxiety-fear" re-
increases of activity in the system as the animal repeat- spectively, a little girl, on the threshold of her age of
edly tracked and mistracked the odor trail (perhaps reason, with little hesitation has spilled forth some simple
yielding minijoys and mini-engagements of an associa- truths about basic human emotions. They were also clear
tive reinforcement network). When the animal has been to Cogan (and I still believe - contrary to the opinion of
brought infinitesimally close to the object that provoked Royce - that he deserves as close a reading as modern
the foraging, the close interaction with the object would writers on the topic). It is also gratifying that this simple
provide adequate stimulation for consummatory reflexes scheme is compatible with some current empirical work
to be activated. During the consummatory act, there being done with humans (Clynes, Heath, Izard, Klein),
would be active inhibition of all emotive systems, includ- and that it can also be related to metaphysical conceptions
ing rage. Thus, there would be plenty of opportunity for of human emotionality (de Rivera).
the generation of "pleasure, " "joy," what have you,
during both the appetitive and the consummatory Cognitive mechanisms in emotions. Many commenta-
phases of behavior, although they may well differ in tors with philosophical and cognitive orientations took
kind. issue with the simplicity of my scheme, and pointed to the
Although this may sound like a simplistic approach to many ways in which affective processes are governed by
one of the most important aspects of mental life (Sol- human thoughts, belief systems, and perceived relation-
omon), the existing alternatives are closer to art than to ships among events (Arnold, Averill, Delgado, de Sousa,
science. In any case, the analytical view I advocated Jaynes, Lazarus, Lutz, Morton, Solomon, Royce, Stock-
should not be considered slighting to the spectrum of er). I do not disagree, but most of this criticism is
affects. Consider the beautiful paintings created from a misplaced, arising from a misconstrual of my position on
few colors, the music that arises from the vibrations of a the utility of introspection in psychobiology or a failure to
few strings and the diversity of life controlled by the appraise realistically the limits inherent in a "general"
sequences of four nucleotides. The claim that subcortical (i.e., cross-species) theory of emotions. While on the one
circuits are not essential for having emotions (Solomon) hand I was being congratulated (de Sousa) and, on the
is contradicted by the vast neuropsychological literature other, criticized (Arnold, Averill) for not having used
in humans (Heath; Kelly 1980) and is similar to a belief introspection adequately myself, a critical point of my
that the aesthetic riches of our world can be experienced analysis was being overlooked - that introspection has to
without the media in which they are expressed. be coupled with neuroscience to be scientifically useful.
There was abundant disagreement among the com- This self-imposed constraint limited my introspection
mentators as to the number of primary emotions that largely to matters of taxonomy; but for strict empiricists,
exist - similar to the disagreements I portrayed in the even that was too liberal (Anisman & Zacharko, Ursin,
historical section of my article and contrary to the in- Vanderwolf & Goodale). However, I regard the higher
ferences of Averill and Royce, my mention of Willis was order introspective insights provided by some of the less
not favorable, but an illustration of nonempirical, tax- empirically constrained commentators, whether or not
onomic nitpicking). So, to shed more light on the issue, I they correspond to my own personal insights, as scien-
turn from my desk to my six-year-old daughter playing at tifically premature until they are accompanied by testable
my feet. neurological hypotheses.

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 455


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

Many of the cognitive issues raised may also be irrele- development of psychiatric disorders. It is here, at the
vant to a "general" theory of emotions. They are more juncture of visceral-emotional and cognitive-somatic
pertinent to "special," nonbiological theories of human processes of the brain that a hard-core reinforcement
emotion (e.g., the Class II passions of Cogan), which principle, so uncongenial to humanists, may be essential
may be of limited relevance to understanding the behav- for understanding the sources of behavioral control.
ior of other species. Still, I believe that to understand It is noteworthy that another brainstem-cortical pro-
those higher emotions, we will have to clarify how the cess has been demonstrated to function by a causal di-
basic ones are generated. The human brain's ability to alogue similar to the one described above. While the
elaborate higher feelings is probably still integrally executive mechanism for rapid eye movement (REM)
linked to basic brainstem mechanisms we share with less sleep resides in primitive, autonomic areas of the lower
complex creatures, although we may, of course, encoun- brain stem (Jouvet 1972), it is capable of inducing hallu-
ter totally new organizational principles at higher levels cinatory dreaming activity (typically affect-laden) in fore-
in various species. For instance, the massive develop- brain areas of higher animals. Humans who have lost
ment of the human fontal lobe and a paramedian lobe in their frontal lobes still exhibit normal physiological man-
cetacean species (Morgane, Jacobs, & McFarland 1980) ifestations of REM, but the hallucinatory dream content
may indicate unique principles of organization involved has been eliminated by the surgery (Jus, Villeneuve,
in human expectancy and in dolphin social-emotional Pires, Rachance, Fortier, & Villeneuve 1973). In intact
systems. individuals, these cortical consequences of REM sleep
There is a major empirical issue embedded in the presumably exert a reciprocal organizing effect on the
perspective that cognitive processes have to be consid- behavior of the waking organism.
ered in explaining the genesis of emotions. At the level In the same way, executive systems for the various
of neural organization, the question reduces to: Do emo- emotions may arouse certain types of thoughts and feel-
tions arise primarily from brain areas that mediate cogni- ing states, elaborated in specific zones of cortex and
tive processes, or elsewhere? The evidence seems rea- related basal ganglia, and reciprocal controls from these
sonably clear. Cognitive processes appear to be higher areas may exert feedback control over subsequent
mediated primarily by neocortex, tissue which is largely expression of emotions. Expectancy circuitry may in-
an outgrowth of rapidly-firing neural systems specialized teract in a primary sense with frontal neocortex and basal
for processing exteroceptive information (i.e., they arise forebrain nuclei (e.g., substantia innominata and nucleus
from the "somatic" nervous system comprising the accumbens), fear and rage with temporal cortex and
thalamic-neocortical axis). Emotional processes, on the amygdaloid nuclei, and panic with cingulate cortex, sep-
other hand, appear to be largely an outgrowth of slowly- tal nuclei, and bed nuclei of the stria terminalis. Nearby
firing neural systems designed to collect interoreceptive basal ganglia (globus pallidus and corpus striatum) may
information (i.e., they are part of the "visceral" nervous contain higher order motor subroutines that are acti-
system comprising the hypothalamic-limbic axis). Al- vated by the emotive command systems. By such re-
though these distinct nervous systems interact at all ciprocal interactions, emotive command circuits may
levels of the neuraxis, anatomical evidence suggests that help precipitate much richer internal states in humans
visceral-limbic control of thalamic-neocortical activity than might have been apparent in my simple taxonomic
is much greater than the reverse. This is congruent with analysis.
common subjective experience, for, as noted by many If, after all this, one is still inclined to believe that
observers from the Greeks on, emotions appear to be emotions are basically cognitive, one need but consider
more influential in controlling thought than vice versa the phylogenetic and ontogenetic evidence. As evolution
(and, hence, this may be a fine example of how intro- provided ever-increasing ability for the brain to think (as
spective experience tells us something concrete about indexed by species-typical expansions of multimodal as-
brain organization). sociation cortices), the basic affective expressions of or-
This is not to deny that cognitive processes can also ganisms remained relatively stable. To rephrase my re-
influence emotive circuits. People can consciously exert sponse's opening remarks, this suggests that affective
some control over their emotions. Similarly, the con- representations of reality were built into brain tissue
templation of a trying situation can arouse one emo- before complex cognitive representations of reality. Sim-
tionally even after the precipitating events. Although ilarly, during ontogenetic development of all mammals
these corticofugal controls are much less powerful than (at both neural and behavioral levels), the basic affective
the corticopedal ones, there is room for an updated faculties mature earlier than cognitive abilities, indicat-
James-Lange perspective on the genesis of emotions. ing their primacy in the evolution of brain organization.
We must remember that, at the turn of the century, Although many contemporary thinkers may prefer not to
there was no substantive evidence that a visceral ner- dichotomize these processes (since they are so thor-
vous system existed in the brain, and James's suggestion oughly blended in adult subjective experiences), the
that somatic actions precipitated peripheral visceral neurological data confirm that a dichotomy exists, and
changes which were then perceived as emotions, could indicate the primacy of the affective rather than the
be recast with an eye to current knowledge of brain cognitive faculties.
organization. Thus, a modern form of the theory could Yes, psychobiology does need more input from cogni-
assert that somatic-thinking processes evoke activity tive psychology (Morton), but that discipline has yet to
within visceral-limbic areas of the brain, and this then take up the challenge of dealing effectively with basic
leads to affect-laden perceptions in neocortical areas. subcortically organized brain processes. It has generally
Such recurrent controls no doubt exist and probably chosen to focus more on those complexities of human
contribute to the growth of personality traits and the mind that distinguish us from other animals. Psycho-

456 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
biologists might benefit from simple and clear human more tantalizing behavioral options are offered. Similar-
experiments focusing on those basic passions we still ly, rats are more likely to exhibit their own characteristic
share with other animals; and, I suspect, cognitive psy- foraging behaviors - investigation and object carrying -
chology would also profit from such endeavors. rather than specific consummatory responses when this
circuit is activated. I suspect that the consummatory
Facts, fantasies, and predictions. Anisman & Zacharko behaviors evoked by such brain stimulation have long
suggest that my system contains too few equations to misled us about the nature of the underlying circuitry.
solve for too many variables. It is understandable that Thus, I am suggesting that a common denominator may
the simplicity of my proposal might lead to that conclu- underlie the diverse behavioral effects that have been
sion, but such a conclusion overlooks the key element of observed from stimulating homologous neural tissue in
the system — a reinforcement process (in the associative different animals. (As discussed elsewhere, in Panksepp,
rather than the reward sense) that is linked to consum- 1981a, this position does not imply that there are no
matory responses and hence to a rapid lowering of ac- drive-specific homeostatic detector circuits in nearby
tivity in an emotive system. Considering that each emo- areas of the hypothalamus.)
tive system can simultaneously bias a number of flexible The fact that one can get distinct types of behavior
behavioral options, such a reinforcement principle could from different zones of the hypothalamus is not an argu-
mold many behavioral habits from a limited number of ment against my perspective; rather, it is congruent with
command circuits. Behavioral variation under similar it. Transitions from stalking to flight to affective displays
conditions may also be due to differences in species- that Siegel describes are the very evidence on which my
typical behaviors that are sensitized by emotive circuits proposal was based. But these distinct classes of behav-
as well as by variations in the degree and types of in- ior are taken as evidence for general control circuits, as
teraction among the circuits. In addition, as noted be- opposed to rigidly coded neural pathways governing
fore, pain evoked by shock may activate several emotive unitary behavioral acts. Indeed, the experientially in-
systems, yielding confused patterns of activity within duced interchangeability of stimulus-bound behaviors
complexly interrelated circuits. Of course, these logical that Valenstein, Cox, and Kakolewski (1970) originally
alternatives are difficult to evaluate with existing described appears to have been based on the study of a
techniques. single system, the one that is in the present context
Many examples of animal behavior patterns that are labeled the expectancy circuit. My modified non-
difficult for the theory to explain can be derived from specificity hypothesis does not predict that stimulus-
laboratory experiments that constitute ecologically inval- bound flight or rage could be changed to any other type
id experimental paradigms - catch-22's that fail to clearly of emotive behavior, even though considerable response
differentiate underlying control systems. Has an animal molding may transpire within an individual system.
in nature ever been confronted by anything resembling I have previously observed that the specific consum-
lengthy sessions of signaled and unsignaled shock? matory behavior evoked by activation of the expectancy
Moreover, the tradition in experimental psychology of circuit is influenced by the personality of a rat (Panksepp
studying animals socially isolated from conspecifics for 1971); Siegel claims that is not the case in cats. I suspect
prolonged periods in extremely monotonous surround- it is, however, for Hutchinson and Renfrew (1966) re-
ings may be a poor basis for drawing meaningful conclu- ported stimulus-bound feeding from the LH of many of
sions about normal animal behavior. Challenging the their animals exhibiting stalking attack, while Flynn
nervous system with high doses of psychoactive drugs, (1967) and Siegel have noted that it is a rare occurrence.
which drive neurochemical systems beyond levels ever Indeed, Siegel's observation that the most ferocious
experienced in real life, likewise seems a dubious ap- stimulus- bound attack is often obtained from the most
proach for deriving credible conclusions about the oper- placid cats may reflect the operation of a personality
ations of the brain. Perhaps the same could be said about factor (paradoxical though it may seem if one does not
brain stimulation, but as noted by Heath, artificial consider adaptation-level factors). Jouvet (1979) has also
arousal of these subcortical circuits in humans yields noted that rage is an especially striking characteristic of
subjective feelings that are perceived as integral parts of dream-related activity in some normally placid cats.
consciousness rather than as sham responses. Katz questions the interpretation of several stimulus-
Siegel raises several key issues over which there is bound behaviors described in my 1971 paper, specifical-
considerable confusion concerning stimulus-bound be- ly asking why leaping behavior is now taken to indicate
haviors evoked from the hypothalamus. For instance, he the location of a "panic" system, when it was originally
argues that a cat's disregard of food in favor of stalking used to characterize "rage" placements. The confusion
behavior during lateral hypothalamic (LH) stimulation here is simple: I have not changed any interpretations,
argues against the nonspecificity hypothesis I espoused. but merely expanded on observations deemed secondary
This, I believe, reflects a misunderstanding of my defini- to the aim of the original study. That paper described
tion of nonspecificity. It is not that there is unlimited several hypothalamic zones from which aggression could
plasticity to the behaviors evoked by hypothalamic stim- be elicited in rats; at some sites the attack was accom-
ulation, but merely that the stimulus-bound consumma- panied by flight (leaping), probably due to emotive sys-
tory responses typically reported represent epi- tem overlap. However, there was no theoretical discus-
phenomena of more generalized behavioral tendencies. sion of a series of electrode sites above the optic chiasma
Thus, I view the stalking behavior of the cat as a species- that yielded explosive behaviors. I wrote, "At current
typical foraging behavior, arising from the arousal of the onset, these animals would freeze, and after a variable
expectancy command circuit; it is gratifying that cats are period of time that could last for several minutes, they
rarely fooled into exhibiting consummatory acts when would explode (i.e., run around wildly bounding off the

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 457


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
sides of the test chamber). Suddenly, they would again and in neural storms of REM sleep) probably refining
stop all activity and sit quietly, breathing deeply. These the intrinsic competence of these systems.
animals never exhibited any aggression" (1971, p. 323; Because I related activity in the expectancy command
sites indicated by crosses in histology of Figure 1). The circuit to homeostatic detector systems of the body,
evoked behavior did not resemble the well-directed several commentators (Izard, Lyons, Zuckerman) con-
flight obtained from more dorsal sites, and I now enter- cluded that I was espousing a drive-reduction approach
tain the idea that such explosive episodes are the rat to understanding emotional circuitry. This interpreta-
homologue of "panic attacks." Still, I acknowledge that tion is wrong. Although homeostatic detectors probably
the anatomical designation of panic is more speculative modulate activity in these circuits, each system is under
than that of the other emotive circuits; and perhaps the influence of a variety of incoming stimuli. For exam-
distress vocalization sites found in diverse brain areas ple, any novel stimulus should be capable of provoking
may constitute a better estimate of the trajectory of the activity in the expectancy system, thereby precipitating
panic system (Herman & Panksepp 1981). investigatory activity. The more pertinent the stimulus
Katz also questioned whether existing evidence ne- is for the animal's survival, the more likely it is to sustain
cessitated a social cohesion (i.e., panic) system indepen- activity in the emotive system. Also, I believe that the
dent of pain systems. I have discussed the possible evo- expectancy system has a resting level of activity (yielding
lutionary links between pain and separation distress a baseline level of exploration, curiosity, and interest in
previously (Panksepp, Herman, Conner, Bishop, & the world), which is increased not only by biologically
Scott 1978; Panksepp, Herman, Vilberg, Bishop, & important events but also by reafferents from higher
DeEskinazi 1980; Panksepp 1981b), but would re- areas of the brain. Invigorated foraging activity could be
emphasize that the induction of separation-distress vo- reduced in the short term by various consummatory
calizations does not require any noxious stimulation, activities, and quelled for a longer term by complete
merely the removal of a young animal from its social satisfaction of the organism's needs. Such home-
environment. The reflexlike nature of this response sug- ostatically induced circuit stabilization may permit hu-
gests an intrinsic brain system designed to perceive and mans to pursue their cerebral interests. This is not a
respond to social separation. The fact that this separation simple drive-reduction view, even though implicit in my
response is exquisitely sensitive to opiates - indeed, argument is a foraging-reduction hypothesis of appe-
considerably more sensitive than traditional laboratory titive reinforcement.
measures of analgesia - further suggests that the brain Toates need not worry that the approach I have taken
systems for the mediation of social affect can be dis- will stagnate at some sterile mentalistic level instead of
tinguished from pain systems (at least as traditionally proceeding to the analysis of mechanisms of action. The
understood). In fact, brain sites from which distress aim of the target article was to describe the types of
vocalizations can be elicited do overlap with opioid sys- emotive processes that exist in the brain, so as to under-
tems, but not with classical pain pathways - except in stand ultimately how the systems operate. I have gone
the lower brain stem. Of course, other emotional sys- into more detail on possible mechanisms elsewhere
tems also participate in social relationships (de Rivera), (Panksepp 1981a; 1982b), but to further extend one tan-
but the evidence suggests that one in particular ("panic") talizing promissory note, I would resketch what the key
has evolved specifically for the establishment and main- mechanism underlying autoshaping may look like: if
tenance of social bonds. Although the affect conveyed by there is a foraging-expectancy system, which activates
arousal of this system is aversive, the return journey is forward directed motor sequences interspersed with
presumably pleasurable. Perhaps the waxing and waning various species-typical investigatory activities, then au-
of activity in this and closely related circuits contribute toshaping is likely to be mediated by that circuit. Al-
to the feeling called love. though the rat will need various other psysiological sys-
I do not claim that emotive systems start in the hypo- tems to express itself (including legs and spatial
thalamus, as suggested by Delgado; only that the hypo- representation abilities), I would suggest that the essen-
thalamus is presently an ideal brain area in which to tial process underlying autoshaping is the capacity of
conduct systematic analysis of most of these systems. previously neutral stimuli to conditionally evoke activity
Indeed, the panic circuit may primarily flow through in the expectancy command circuit. Thereby foraging
dorsomedial reticular areas of thalamus that are linked will come to be directed at reward-related stimuli. In
with the bed nuclei of the stria terminalis and cingulate line with that hypothesis, Phillips, McDonald, and
gyms (i.e., areas where distress vocalizations can be Wilkie (1981) recently reported that DA receptor block-
elicited). Surely, the ramification of emotive command ade inhibits autoshaping. Although a computer-rat may
circuits through the neuraxis will yield many surprises. help us refine and sharpen our thinking about a prob-
For instance, while Averill is amused by the introspec- lem, that, I trust Toates agrees, is no substitute for
tively misguided notion of Willis that emotions may be physiological research (Panksepp 1979b).
elaborated by the cerebellum, Heath as well as Bernt- Averill and Plutchik question my introspectively de-
son, Potolicchio, and Miller (1973) are demonstrating rived hypothesis that the "rage" and "expectancy" cir-
the participation of deep cerebellar nuclei in the organi- cuits inhibit each other. Plutchik bases his skepticism on
zation of emotive behaviors. It is unfortunate that the the supposition that aggression and sex are often found
anatomy and properties of these important brain systems together. In fact, sexually related "aggression" is proba-
are still not well understood.4 Although emotive circuits bly an expression of dominance (will-to-power) rather
may not be as hard wired as a radio (Averill, Stocker), than anger ("rage"). Averill's observation that the "expec-
the basic plan appears to be laid down genetically, with tation" of revenge must be attended by a certain pleasure
life experiences (especially as manifested in juvenile play highlights once more the connotative difficulties of terms

458 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Response/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
such as expectation and pleasure, and may indicate how organization), the emotional world can be seen as one of
the fantasy-creating mechanism of the human mind inter- contradiction and confusion, but I would doubt that
mittently projects itself forward toward the hope of what evolution has constructed animal behavior on so shaky a
could be, even during the worst of circumstances. Still, at foundation.
the moment of pure rage, I believe the feeling of positive As Royce argues, the complexity of emotions seems to
anticipation dwindles toward the vanishing point. Only as defy comprehensive coverage. As he notes, my paper
the consuming passion of anger wanes, will opponent had little to say about individual differences and did not
neural processes (Solomon 1980) come into play (e.g., delve into subjective attributes of emotions. Although
target article, Figure 2). In any case, the facts of the the former could be easily incorporated into the theory
matter strongly suggest that lateral hypothalamic self- by assuming that the vigor of the various emotive sys-
stimulation (i.e., expectancy) and rage circuits mutually tems can be inherited and modified by various life cir-
inhibit each other (e.g., Hutchinson & Renfrew 1978). cumstances, there is little of substance to be said about
Klinger & Kemble raise enough issues to fill another those matters at the present time. Similarly, I was hesi-
Response. One of their major concerns was the paucity tant to undertake anything more than a taxonomic analy-
of specific predictions in the target article. A series of sis at the subjective level, especially since practically
predictions for the expectancy system are spelled out everything I would have to say on the matter would be
elsewhere (Panksepp 1981a; 1982b), so I shall only ad- opinion and, at that, largely repetitive of Cogan's in-
dress the key issue of how we might go about determin- sightful analysis. A seemingly endless series of books has
ing whether a neural system constitutes a command discussed subjective aspects of emotions during the last
circuit. Although the lesion approach has many short- several hundred years without promoting major scien-
comings, it can tell us whether a neural system is neces- tific understanding in this field; and, due to the growth
sary for a certain class of behaviors. For instance, Fon- of behaviorism, as well as the impropriety of evoking
berg (1972) has demonstrated how corticomedial and strong emotions in the human laboratory, the systematic
basolateral amygdalectomy in the dog can have opposite experimental analysis of subjective emotional experience
effects on appetitive and friendly behaviors, while a remains in its infancy. Quite independent of what intro-
combined lesion leads to reestablishment of normal be- spection may have had to say about emotion, brain phys-
havioral balance. This suggests that a modulatory rather iologists at the turn of the last century started to unearth
than a command influence was disrupted by those le- some fundamental mechanisms in ancient areas of the
sions. If a complete rebalancing of appropriate target brain that seemed to be essential substrates for emotion.
behaviors can be achieved in animals whose hypothala- I believe that this branch of brain physiology has reached
mic emotive circuits are damaged, the command circuit a stage of development where further progress could be
idea I have espoused would be seriously compromised. promoted by modest doses of introspective data, es-
Such data would constitute an especially compelling re- pecially the kind derived from sound empirical analysis.
futation of my position if destruction of the putative If there is good alignment between demonstrable phys-
command circuits is accomplished in young animals so iological systems and introspective categories at a basic
that little prelesion translocation of function could have taxonomic level, we may be in a position to proceed to a
occurred. And what might the appropriate target behav- deeper analysis.
iors be? For the foraging-expectancy circuit, I assume
that any of a multitude of tasks that required an animal to Summary. We are far from realizing an empirically
search out goods from its environment would suffice. grounded understanding of emotional processes in the
For the rage circuit, a variety of frustration- and irrita- brain. The scheme I have presented is incomplete in
tion-induced aggression tasks could be used. For the fear many ways, and many of the controversies, which have
circuit, I would think unconditional flight behaviors or paralyzed this field of inquiry, are well summarized in
many avoidance tasks, where the aversive stimulus is not the foregoing debate. Because of the remarkable diffi-
present during the test, such as conditioned emotional culty in achieving any consensus in this area, modern
response paradigms, would be appropriate. For the pan- neuroscience has failed to develop a coherent framework
ic circuit, natural separation-induced distress and social for the study of emotions. The dilemma of human and
contact maintenance behaviors seem to be reasonable animal emotions remains an embarassing skeleton in the
target behaviors. Furthermore, temporal analysis of cel- vast cathedral of knowledge being constructed by scien-
lular activities in appropriate brain sites in relation to the tists working on the brain. Some hope that an under-
initiation of natural emotive behaviors (e.g., Adams standing of emotions will be achieved by creeping up-
1979; Rolls 1980) will be essential for assessing the pri- ward, synapse by synapse, from autonomic, brainstem
macy of these systems in the genesis of emotions. reflex circuits toward those higher order brain systems
Lyons raises enough issues for yet another Response, that dictate the coherent organismic response. Perhaps
but his central theme - that emotions can generate that "bottom-up" enterprise will work. However, the
maladaptive behavior patterns - can be handled briefly. complexity of the reticular neuropil may provide an
Certainly, every physiological system of the body is insurmountable barrier to the progress of a systematic
susceptible to deranged functioning - to being over- empirical march up the neuraxis, and the science of the
stressed and to becoming ill. As sketched in Figure 5 of brain may be confronted with the need to make some
the target article, imbalances of emotional systems can hard decisions on how intrinsic higher order brain func-
lead to short- and long-term psychological disorders. If tions are to be categorized and studied.
we wish to look at it simply from the "dis-ease" perspec- It is unlikely that traditional animal psychology, in
tive (represented, perhaps, by the descending limb of which the operational referents for terms are based on
the inverted-U function relating arousal and behavioral external events, will provide concepts adequate for the

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 459


Re/erences/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
task. When diverse external and internal stimuli funnel behavior. Such environmentally inappropriate "solutions" may
onto integrative-convergence pathways that elaborate crystallize into core delusional systems and henceforth exert
complex psychobehavioral tendencies in the brain, our overriding influences on thinking patterns. On the basis of this
sources of knowledge other than sensory observation kind of reasoning, the widely discussed relationship between
may prove useful. To the degree that those integrative schizophrenia and a form of creativity can be linked to a
circuits are class typical and reflected with some degree common physiological substrate. If the normal function of the
system is to promote exploration and meaning-extraction from
of accuracy in human consciousness, we have few rea- the environment, the pathological expressions of the system
sonable alternatives but to begin systematically applying may be solutions that are not restrained by brain reality-testing
our subjective insights to our scientific enterprise. How- principles (reinforcement?), which, under normal circum-
ever, perhaps there are no such convergence pathways, stances, are closely coupled to environmental events. Of
and emotions are elaborated by a loosely organized al- course, a person who has lost touch with consensual reality will
gebraic flow of diverse and dynamic influence through a receive diverse forms of social punishment, which will sec-
behaviorally unarticulated reticular net to functionally ondarily bring many other emotional systems into play.
fragmented final common pathways, as suggested by From such a perspective, it is noteworthy that self-stimula-
Delgado. If that is the case, the specific outlook I have tion along the trajectory of ascending brain dopamine systems
recommended is not promising. Still, the fact that we is our best current animal model for schizophrenia. Not only do
can evoke a number of distinct, well-organized (not frag- animals appear crazed while self-activating this system, but
practically every drug treatment known to worsen schizo-
mented) emotive behaviors from discrete zones of the phrenic symptoms increases self-stimulation, while those
visceral brain by the mere application of electrical noise, which ameliorate schizophrenic symptoms, reduce self-stim-
suggests that we mammals possess neural systems, pre- ulation. Thus, keeping in mind some reasonable qualifications,
pared through evolution, for achieving behavioral co- I do not think it implausible that far lateral hypothalamic self-
herence at a moment's notice. To understand the func- stimulation and certain forms of schizophrenia reflect the un-
tional organization of psychobehavioral processes in the bridled activity of a brain system whose normal function is to
brain, we must determine how such executive circuits mediate expectancies - as expressed in foraging at lower levels
govern the diverse neurophysiological subroutines that of the neuraxis and as a search for meaning at higher levels of
lead to the objective organismic changes we can see. The brain organization.
major emotions appear to be elaborated by executive 3. We have not been able to provoke panic attacks (as
circuits such as these, and they provide the raw material measured by the induction of separation-induced crying) in
young socially housed dogs, guinea pigs, and chicks with nalox-
from which a lasting understanding of key aspects of one. We can only facilitate the crying process once it has
mammalian behavior and the human psyche can be already been precipitated, and of the species tested, this works
constructed. only for guinea pigs and chicks. In dogs, the naloxone increases
another care- or contact-soliciting response - tail wagging. This
NOTES suggests that brain opioid systems provide a modulatory rather
1. Izard (1971) summarizes a substantial amount of cross- than a triggering influence over the relevant circuitry; accord-
cultural data indicating that the identification of affective facial ingly, a better test of opioid participation in human panic
expressions is quite accurate (for a larger number of emotions attacks would be to determine whether chronic opiate receptor
than the four basic ones I discussed). This is remarkable, since blockade increases the frequency and intensity of panic attacks
a considerable amount of emotional behavior is contained in or whether opiate receptor agonists can quell panic attacks in
postures and body movements (Clynes) that were not captured the same way separation distress is reduced (Panksepp et al.
in the still photographs used in those studies. Also, it is impor- 1980).
tant to remember that the sounds of emotions are as charac- 4. There is much more evidence concerning trans-
teristic as the faces (see Davitz 1964). Thus, I think it is safe to hypothalamic neural systems than I summarized in my target
assume that, if all these dimensions were combined in a emo- article. Unfortunately, no anatomically identified circuit has
tional recognition task, the "hit" rate for the four emotions I been firmly related to an emotional process. For instance,
have discussed would be very high indeed, even for young although it is reasonable to hypothesize that one emotive com-
children. mand system (perhaps fear) is partially isomorphic with long-
2. Klinger & Kemble correctly emphasize that my attempt axoned amygdalo-tegmental (Hopkins & Holstege 1978) and
to attribute psychiatric disorders to individual emotive systems hypothalamo-tegmental systems (Swanson & Kuypers 1980),
(target article, Figure 5) is a great simplification, most notably and their ascending reciprocal circuits, critical functional data
in the case of schizophrenia. This is especially true in light of remain unavailable. Although such circuits have anatomical
recent trends to develop substantive subclassifications within characteristics that could coordinate diverse physiological and
the global diagnosis of this brain disorder. Still, there may be behavioral processes, only recently has it become feasible to
some utility in the conceptual simplifications I suggest, since apply neural and behavioral mapping approaches in the same
animal (Siegel). Only after concurrent behavioral, neuro-
they may be helpful in promoting and guiding further re-
anatomical and neurochemical mapping has been successfully
search, especially with animal models. At a general semantic conducted at brain sites that yield stimulus-bound emotive
level, a connection between schizophrenia and overactivity in behaviors will it be possible to ask precise questions concern-
an expectancy system suggests that something may have gone ing synaptic interactions between circuits (Figure 2).
awry in a primitive "reality-creating" mechanism of the brain.
If a fundamental function of the expectancy system is to gener-
ate various search behaviors when an organism is confronted
by environmental stressors or homeostatic imbalances, the
vivid psychological changes that accompany the florid phase of
schizophrenia may become more understandable. When this References
system is overactive, heightening of perceptual awareness and
Adams, D. B. (1979) Brain mechanisms for offense, defense, and
sense of potential meaning in the world, a solution may arise
submission. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2:201-42. [EF, LDK,
rather automatically from fluctuating activities of the underly-
tarJP, HU]
ing neural substrate, which is promoting the invigorated search Adelman, H. M. & Maatsch, J. L. (1956). Learning and extinction based

460 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Re/erences/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

upon frustration, food reward, and exploratory tendency. Journal of Baxter, B. L. (1968) Elicitation of emotional behavior by electrical
Experimental Psychology 52:311-15. [JAG] stimulation applied at the same loci in cat mesencephalon.
Ahorn, G. L., Landin, M. L., & Wolf, G. (1978) Escape from deficits in Experimental Neurology 21:1-20. [taJP]
sodium intake after thalamic lesions as a function of preoperative Beagley, W. K. & Holley, T. L. (1977) Hypothalamic stimulation facilitates
experience. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology contralateral visual control of a learned response. Science
92:544-54. [taJP] 196:321-22. [taJP]
Alexander, M. & Perachio, A. A. (1973) The influence of target sex and Beatty, W. W. & Beatty, P. A. (1970). Hormonal determinants of sex
dominance on evoked attack in rhesus monkeys. American Journal of differences in avoidance behaviour and reactivity to electric shock in the
Physical Anthropology 38:543-47. [taJP] rat. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology
Amsel, A. (1962) Frustrative nonreward in partial reinforcement and 73:446-55. [JAG]
discrimination learning: Some recent history and a theoretical Bell, C. (1806) The anatomy and philosophy of expression as connected with
extension. Psychological Review 69:306-28. [JAG] the fine arts. London: H. G. Bohn.- [taJP]
Anisman, H. (1975) Task complexity as a factor in eliciting heterosis in Bernstein, I. S. (1981) Dominance: The baby and the bathwater.
mice: Aversively motivated behaviors. Journal of Comparative and Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4:419-57. [JMRD]
Physiological Psychology 89:976-84. [HA] Berntson, G. G. (1972) Blockade and release of hypothalamically and
Anisman, H., Grimmer, L., Irwin, J., Remington, G., & Sklar, L. S. naturally elicited aggressive behaviors in cats following midbrain
(1979) Escape performance after inescapable shock in selectively bred lesions. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology
lines of mice. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology 81:541-54. [taJP]
93:229-41. [HA] Bernston, G. G. & Micco, D. J. (1976) Organization of brainstem
Anisman, H., Kokkinidis, L., & Sklar, L. S. (1981) Contribution of behavioral systems. Brain Research Bulletin 1:471-83. [taJP]
neurochemical change to stress-induced behavioral deficits. In: Theory Berntson, G. G., Potolicchio, S. J., & Miller, N. E. (1973) Evidence for
in psychopharmacology vol I, ed. S. J. Cooper. London: Academic higher functions of the cerebellum: Eating and grooming elicited by
Press. [HA] cerebellar stimulation in cats. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Aristotle (1941) The basic works of Aristotle, ed. R. McKeon. New York: Sciences of the United States of America 70:2497-499. [rJP]
Random House. [JRA, MS] Bindra, D. (1978) How adaptive behavior is produced: A
Arnold, M. B. (1960a) Emotion and personality, vol. 1, Psychological aspects. perceptual-motivational alternative to response-reinforcement.
New York: Columbia University Press. [MBA, CEI] Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 1:41-92. [taJP, FMT]
(1960b) Emotion and personality, vol. 2, Neurological and physiological Bolles, R. C. (1970) Species-specific defense reactions and avoidance learning.
aspects. New York: Columbia University Press. [MBA, CEI, rJP] Psychological Review 77:32-48. [HA, FMT]
Arnold, M. B. & Gasson, J. (1968) Feelings and emotions as dynamic (1971) Species-specific defense reactions. In: Aversive conditioning and
factors in personality integration. In: The nature of emotion, ed. M. learning., ed. F. R. Brush, pp. 183-233. New York: Academic
B. Arnold, pp. 203-21. Middlesex: Penguin. [WL] Press. [HA]
(1970) Perennial problems in the field of emotion. In: Feelings and (1972) Reinforcement, expectancy and learning. Psychological Review
emotions: The Loyala symposium, ed. M. B. Arnold. New York: 79:394-409. [HU]
Academic Press. [JRR] Bolles, R. C. & Fanselow, M. S. (1980) A perceptual-defensive-
Averill, J. R. (1974) An analysis of psychophysiological symbolism and its recuperative model of fear and pain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences
influence on theories of emotion. Journal for the Theory of Social 3:291-323. [EF]
Behavior 4:147-90. [JRA] Bower, G. H. (1981) Mood and memory. American Psychologist
(1979) Anger. In: Nebraska symposium on motivation, ed. H. Howe & 36:129-48. [taJP]
R. Dienstbier, pp, 1-80. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Bower, G. H. & Miller, N. E. (1958) Rewarding and punishing effects
Press. [JRA] from stimulating the same place in the rat's brain. Journal of
(1980a) A constructivist view of emotion. In: Theories of emotion, ed. Comparative and Physiological Psychology 51:669-78. [taJP]
R. Plutchik & H. Kellerman, pp. 305-39. New York: Academic Bowlby, John (1980) Loss. vol. 3 of Attachment and loss. New York: Basic
Press. [JRA] Books. [RdeS]
(1980b) On the paucity of positive emotions. In: Assessment and Braestrup, C. & Squires, R. F. (1977) Specific benzodiazepine receptors
modification of emotional behaviors, ed. K. R. Blankstein, P. Pliner, in rat brain characterized by high-affinity 3 H-diazepam binding.
& J. Pliner, pp. 7-45. New York: Plenum Press. [JRA] Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, United States of
Ax, A. F. (1953) The physiological differentiation of fear and anger in America 74:3805-9. [taJP]
humans. Psychosomatic Medicine 15:433-42. [taJP] Broadhurst, P. L. (1960). Applications of biometrical genetics to the
Baecelli, G., Albertini, R., Mancia, G., & Zanchetti, A. (1976) inheritance of behaviour. In: Experiments in personality, vol. 1,
Interactions between sino-aortic reflexes and cardiovascular effects on Psychogenetics and psychopharmacology, ed. H. J. Eysenck, pp.
sleep and emotional behavior in cat. Circulation Research 38, Suppl. 3-102. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. [JAG]
2:30-34. [taJP] Brodie, B. B. & Shore, P. A. (1957) A concept for a role of serotonin
Baeeelli, G., Guazzi, M., Libretti, A., & Zanchetti, A. (1965) and norepinephrine as chemical mediators in the brain. Annals of the
Pressoceptive and ehemoceptive aortic reflexes in decorticate and in New York Academy of Sciences 66:631-42. [taJP]
decerebrate cats. American Journal of Physiology 208:708-14. [taJP] Brown, A. (1978) Knowing when, where and how to remember: A
Bachus, S. E. & Valenstein, E. S. (1979) Individual behavioral responses problem of metacognition. In: Advances in instructional psychology,
to hypothalamic stimulation persist despite destruction of tissue vol. 1, ed. R. Glaser, pp. 77-165. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum
surrounding electrode tip. Physiology and Behavior 23:421-26. Associates. [CL]
[taJP] Brown, A. & Barclay, C. (1976) The effects of training specific mnemonics
Balagura, S., Wilcox, R. H., & Coscina, D. V. (1969) The effect of on the meta-mnemonic efficiency of retarded children. Child
diencephalic lesions on food intake and motor activity. Physiology and Development 47:70-80. [CL]
Behavior 4:629-33. [taJP] Bull, N. (1951) The attitude theory of emotions. New York: Nervous and
Bard, P. (1928) A diencephalic mechanism for expression of rage with mental diseases Monograph no. 81. [RP]
specific reference to the sympathetic nervous system. American Cabanac, M. (1971) Physiological role of pleasure. Science
Journal of Physiology 34:490. [taJP] 173:1103-7. [taJP]
(1934) On emotional expression after decortication with some remarks on Caggiula, A. R. (1969) Stability of behavior produced by electrical stimulation
certain theoretical views. Psychological Reviews 41:309. [taJP] of the rat hypothalamus. Brain, Behavior and Evolution 2:343-58. |rJP]
Bard, P. & Macht, M. B. (1958) The behaviour of chronically Campbell, B. A. & Baez, L. A. (1974) Dissociation of arousal and
decerebrated cats. In: Neurological basis of behaviour. Ciba regulatory behaviors following lesions of the lateral hypothalamus.
Foundation Symposium, pp. 55-75. London: Churchill. [taJP] Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology
Bard, P. & Mountcastel, V. B. (1948) Some forebrain mechanisms 87:142-49. [taJP]
involved in expression of rage with special reference to suppression of Cannon, W. B. (1927) The James-Lange theory of emotions. American
angry behavior. Research Publications: Association for Research in Journal of Psychology 39:106. [taJP]
Nervous and Mental Disease 27:362-404. [taJP] (1929) Bodily changes in pain, hunger, fear and rage. London:
Barta, S. G., Kemble, E. D., & Klinger, E. (1975) Abolution of cyclic Brandford. [taJP]
activity changes following amygdaloid lesions in rats. Bulletin of the (1931) Again the James-Lange and the thalamic theories of emotion.
Psychonomic Society 5:236-38. [EK| Psychological Review 38:281-95. [taJP]

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 461


fie/erences/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions
Carlsson, A. (1965) Morphologic and dynamic aspects of dopamine in the measured with the potentiated startle paradigm. Psychophannacology
nervous system. In: Biochemistry and pharmacology of basal ganglia, 62:1-7. [taJP]
ed. E. Casta, J. Cote, & M. D. Yahr, pp. 107-13. New York: Raven Davitz, J. R. (1964) The communication of emotional meaning. New York:
Press. [taJP] McCraw-Hill. [rJP]
Carrol, E. N. & Zuckerman, M. (in press) A test of the optimal level of Delgado, J. M. R. (1964) Free behavior and brain stimulation. In:
arousal theory of sensation seeking. Journal of Personality and Social International review of neurobiology, vol. 6, ed. C. C. Pfeiffcr & J.
Psychology. [MZ] R. Smythies, pp. 349-449. New York: Academic Press. [JMRD]
Chapman, W. P. (1958) Studies of the periamygdaloid area in relation to (1969) Physical control of the mind: Toward a psychocivilized society.
human behavior. Research Publications of the Association for Research New York: Harper & Row. [JMRD, taJP]
in Nervous and Mental Disease 36:258-77. [taJP] (1979) Inhibitory functions in the neostriatum. In: The neostriatum, ed.
Chi, C. C , Bandler, R., & Flynn, J. P. (1976). Neuroanatomic I. Divac, R. Gunilla, & E. Oberg, pp. 241-61. New York: Pergamon
projections related to biting attack elicited from the ventral midbrain Press. [JMRD]
in cats. Brain, Behavior and Evolution 13:91-110. [AS] (1980) Neuronal constellations in aggressive behavior. In: Procedural
Chi, C. C. & Flynn, J. P. (1971). Neuroanatomic projections related to conference on psychobiology of aggression and violence (Saint Vincent,
biting attack elicited from hypothaiamus in cats. Brain Research Italy), ed. L. Valzelli. [JMRD]
35:51-65. [AS] Delgado, J. M. R., Roberts, W. W., & Miller, N. E. (1954) Learning
Christopher, M. & Butter, C. M. (1968) Consummatory behaviors and motivated by electrical stimulation of the brain. American Journal of
locomotor exploration evoked from self-stimulation sites in rats. Physiology 179:587-93. [taJP]
Journal of Cotnparative and Physiological Psychology de Molina, A. F. & Hunsperger, R. W. (1962) Organization of the
66:335-39. [taJP] subcortical system governing defence and flight reactions in the cat.
Clarke, S. (1971) Sniffing and fixed-ratio behavior in sucrose and brain Journal of Physiology 160:200-13. [taJP]
stimulation reward in the rat. Physiology and Behavior Dennett, D. C. (1978) Requisition for a Pexgo. Behavioral and Brain
7:695-99. [taJP] Sciences 1:57 [RdeS]
Clarke, S., Panksepp, J., & Trowill, J. A. (1970) A method of recording de Rivera, J. (1977) A structural theory of the emotions. New York:
sniffing in the free-moving rat. Physiology and Behavior International Universities Press. [JdeR]
5:125-26. [taJP] (1981) Conceptual encounter. Washington, D.C.: Universities Press of
Clarke, S. & Trowill, J. A. (1971) Sniffing and motivated behavior in the America. [JdeR]
rat. Physiology and Behavior 6:49-52. [taJP] Descartes, R. (1650) Treatise on the passions of the soul. [RdeS]
Clavier, R. M., Fibiger, H. C , & Phillips, A. C. (1976) Evidence that de Sousa, R. (1980) The rationality of emotions. In: Explaining emotions, ed.
self-stimulation of the region of the locus coeruleus in rats does not A. O. Rorty, pp. 127-52. Berkeley: University of California
depend upon noradrenergic projections to telencephalon: Brain Press. [RdeS]
Research 113:71-81. [taJP] Deutsch, J. A. (1960) Structural basis of behavior. Chicago: University of
Clynes, M. (1969) Toward a theory of man: Precision of essentic form in Chicago Press. [FMT]
living communication. In: Information processing in the nervous Dickinson, A. (1980) Contemporary animal learning theory. Cambridge:
system, ed. K. N. Leibovie & J. C. Eccles. New York: Cambridge University Press. [FMT]
Springer. [MC] Dodds, E. R. (1951) The Creeks and the irrational. Berkeley: University
(1973) Sentics - Biocybemetics of emotion communication. Annals of of California Press. [JJ]
the New York Academy of Sciences 220:55-131. [MC] Duffy, E. (1941) The concept of energy mobilization. Psychological Review
(1975) Communication and generation of emotion through essentic form. 58:30-40. [taJP]
In: Emotions — Their parameters and measurement, ed. L. Levi, pp. Eccles, J. C. (1976) Brain and free will. In: Consciousness and the brain:
561-602. New York: Raven Press. [MC] A scientifw and philosophical inquiry, ed. G. Globus, C. Maxwell, &
(1980) The communication of emotion: Theory of sentics. In: Theories of I. Savodnik. New York: Plenum Press. [GGG]
emotion, ed. R. Plutchik & H. Kellerman, pp. 271-301. New York: Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1979) Human ethology: Concepts and implications for
Academic Press. [MC] the sciences of man. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2:1-59. [taJP]
Clynes, M. & Nettheim, N. (1982) The living qualities of music: Eichelman, B., Thoa, N. B., & Ng, K. Y. (1972) Facilitated aggression in
Neurobiologic basis of communicating qualities of feeling. In: Music, the rat following 6-hydroxydopamine administration. Physiology and
mind, and brain: The neuropsychology of music, ed. M. Clynes, pp. Behavior 8:1-3. [taJP]
47-82. New York: Plenum Press. [MC] Ekman, P., ed. (1973) Darwin and facial expression. New York: Academic
Clynes, M. & Walker, J. (1980) Recognition by aboriginals of expressive Press. [taJP]
sounds derived from expressive touch of urban subjects. 10th Edman, P., Friesen, W. V., & Ellsworth, P. (1972) Emotion in the
International Congress on Acoustics. Abstract K-12.4. [MC] human face: Guidelines for research and an integration of findings.
Clynes, M., Walker, J., & Nettheim, N. (1981) Touch and sound have a New York: Pergamon Press. [CEI]
common brain program for the production and recognition of emotion Ellison, G. D. & Flynn, J. P. (1968) Organized aggressive behavior in
expression. Society for Neurosdence, 11th Annual Meeting. Abstract cats after surgical isolation of the hypothaiamus. Archives of Italian
7:883. [MC] Biology 106:1-20. [taJP]
Cogan, T. (1802) A philosphical treatise on the passions. 2nd ed. London: Enloe, L. J. (1975) Extralimbic mediation of emotionality and social
S. Hazard. [tarJP, JRR, CHV] cohesiveness effects. Physiology and Behavior 15:271-76. [taJP]
Corbett, D. & Wise, R. A. (1979) Intracranial self-stimulation in relation Eysenck, H. (1967) The biological basis of personality. Springfield, III.:
to the ascending noradrenergic fiber systems of the pontine Charles C. Thomas [JRR]
tegmentum and caudal midbrain: A moveable electrode mapping Fass, B., Jordan, H., Rubman, A., Seibel, S., & Stein, D. (1975)
study. Brain Research 177:423-36. [taJP] Recovery of function after serial or one-stage lesions of the lateral
Coscina, D. V., Seggie, J., Godse, D. D., & Stancer, H. C. (1973) hypothalamic area. Behavioral Biology 14:283-94. [JdeR]
Induction of rage in rats by central injection of 6-hydroxydopamine. Feigl, H. (1967) The 'mental' and the physical' Minneapolis: University
Pharmacology Biochemistry and Behavior 1:1-6. [taJP] of Minnesota Press. [GGG]
Crosby, E. C. & Showers, M. J. C. (1969) Comparative anatomy of the Feldon, J., Guillamon, A., Gray, J. A., De Wit, H., & McNaughton, N.
preoptic and hypothalamic areas. In: The hypothaiamus, ed. W. (1979). Sodium amylobarbitone and responses to nonreward. Quarterly
Haymaker, E. Anderson, & W. J. H. Nauta, pp. 61-135. Springfield, Journal of Experimental Psychology 31:19-50. [JAG]
111.: Charles C. Thomas. [taJP] Flynn, J. P. (1967) The neural basis of aggression in cats. In:
D'Andrade, R. (1974) Memory and the assessment of behavior. In: Neurophysiology and emotion, ed. D. C. Class. New York:
Measurement in the social sciences, ed. T. Blalock, pp. 159-86. Rockefeller University Press. [rJP]
Chicago: Aldine. [CL] (1976) Neural basis of threat and attack. In: Biological foundations of
Darwin, C. (1872/1965) The expression of the enwtions in man and animals. psychiatry, ed. R. G. Grenell & S. Gabay, pp. 273-95. New York:
Reprint ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Orig. ed. London: Raven Press. [taJP]
John Murray. [CE1, taJP, RP] Flynn, J. P., Edwards, S. B., & Bandler, R. J. (1971) Changes in sensory
Davis, K. (1980) Opioid control of canine social behavior. Doctoral and motor systems during centrally elicited attack. Behavioral Science
dissertation, Bowling Green State University, Ohio. [rJP] 6:1-19. [taJP]
Davis, M. (1979) Diazepam and flurazepam: Effects on conditioned fear as Flynn, J. P., Vanegas, H., Foote, W., & Edwards, S. (1970). Neural

462 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Re/erences/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

mechanisms involved in a cat's attack on a rat. In: The neural control Goltz, F. (1892) Der Hund ohne Grosshirn. Pflugers Archiv— European
of behavior, ed. R. E. Whalen, R. F. Thompson, M. Verzeano, & Journal of Physiology 51:570-614. [taJP]
N. M. Weinberger, pp. 135-73. New York: Academic Press. [AS] Goodale, M. A. (1981) Vision as a sensorimotor system. In: Behavioral
Fonberg, E. (1958) The manifestation of the defensive reactions in contributions to brain research, ed. T. E. Robinson. New York:
neurotic states. Ada Biologiae Experimentalis 18:89-116. [EF] Oxford University Press. [CHV]
(1961) On the transfer of two different defensive conditioned reflexes Goodale, M. A. (1981) Vision as a sensorimotor system. In: Behavioral
type 11. Bulletin de L'Acadbnie Polonaise des Sciences-SGrie des contributions to brain research, ed. T. E. Robinson. New York: Oxford
Sciences Biologiques 9:47-49. [EF] University Press. [CHV]
(1963) The inhibitory role of amygdala stimulation. Ada Biologiae Gray, J. A. (1972) The structure of the emotions and the limbic system.
Experimentalis 23:171-80. [EF] In: Physiology, emotion and psychosomatic illness, ed. R. Porter & J.
(1966) Emotional reactions evoked by electrical stimulation of subeortical Knight, pp. 87—130. Amsterdam: Associated Scientific
structures and their role in the conditioning of alimentary and Publishers. [JAG]
defensive reactions. 18th International Congress of Psychology, (1975) Elements of a two-process theory of learning. London: Academic
Moscow, pp. 125-29. [EF] Press. [JAG]
(1967) The motivational role of the hypothalamus in animal behaviour. (1977). Drug effects on fear and frustration: Possible limbic site of
Ada Biologiae Experinmitalis 27:303-18. [EFJ action of minor tranquilisers. In: Handbook of psychophannacology,
(1968) The role of the amygdaloid nucleus in animal behaviour. Progress ed. L. L. Iversen, S. D. Iversen, & S. H. Snyder, vol. 8, pp.
in Brain Research 22:273-81. [EF] 433-529. New York: Plenum Press. [JAG]
(1972). Control of emotional behaviour through the hypothalamus and Gray, J. A. (1979a) A neuropsychological theory of anxiety. In: Emotions
amygdaloid complex. In: Physiology, emotion and psychosomatic in personality and psychopathology, ed. C. E. Izard, pp. 303-35.
illness, ed. J. Knight & R. Porter, pp. 131-61. Amsterdam: Elsevier New York: Plenum Press. [taJP]
Excerpta Medica, North-Holland. [EF, rJP] (1979b). Emotionality in male and female rodents: A reply to Archer.
(1979a) Emotions and neuroses [in Polish]. "Ossolineum." PWN, Wroclaw, British Journal of Psychology 70:425-40. [JAG]
pp. 1-231. [EF] (1982a). The neuropsychology of anxiety: An enquiry into the functions
(1979b) Physiological mechanisms of emotional and instrumental aggression. of the septo-hippocampal system. Oxford: Oxford University
In: Aggression and behavior change, ed. S. Feshbaeh & A. Fraczek, pp. Press. [JAG, MZ]
6-53. New York: Praeger Publisher. [EF] (1982b) Precis of Gray's The neuropsychology of anxiety: An enquiry
(1980) Pain and fear are different motivations. Behavioral and Brain into the functions of the septo-hippbeampal system. Behavioral and
Sciences 3:308-10. [EF] Brain Sdences 5:469-534. [JAG, MZ]
(1981). Amygdala and emotions. In: The body weight regulatory system: Greenspan, P. S. (1980) A case of mixed feelings: Ambivalence and the
Normal and disturbed mechanisms, ed L. A. Cioffi, W. P. T. James, & logic of emotion. In: Explaining emotions, ed. A. O. Rorty. Berkeley:
T. B. Van Itallie, pp. 25-32. New York: Raven Press. [EF] University of California Press. [MS]
Fonberg, E. & Kostarczyk, E. (1980) Motivational role of social Griffin, D. R. (1976) The question of animal awareness. New York:
reinforcement in dog-man relations. Ada Neurobiologiae Rockefeller University Press. [rJP]
Experimentalis 40:117-36. [EF] Grill, H. J. & Norgren, R. (1978) The taste reactivity test. 2. Mimetic
Fowler, C. A. & Turvey, M. T. (1978) The concept of "command responses to gustatory stimuli in chronic thalamic and chronic
neurons" in explanations of behavior. Behavioral and Brain Sciences decerebrate rats. Brain Research 143:281-97. [taJP]
7:20-21. [RdeS] Grings, W. W. & Dawson, M. E. (1978) Emotions and bodily responses:
Frigyesi, T. L., Ige, A., Iulo, A., & Schwartz, R. (1971) Denigration and A psychophysiological approach. New York: Academic Press. [taJP]
sensorimotor disability induced by ventral tegmental injections of 6 Grinker, R. & Serota, H. (1938) Studies on cortico-hypothalamic relations
hydroxydopamine in cats. Experimental Neurology 33:78—87. [taJP] in the cat and man. Journal of neurophysiology 1:573. [taJP]
Fuchs, S., Dalsass, M., Siegel, H. E., & Siegel, A. (1981). The neural Groves, P. M., Wilson, C. J., Young, S. J., & Rebec, G. V. (1975) Self-
pathways mediating quiet biting attack behavior from the inhibition by dopaminergic neurons. Science 190:522-29. [taJP]
hypothalamus in the cat: A functional autoradiographic study. Hallowell, A. I. (1955) Culture and experience. Philadelphia: University of
Aggressive Behavior 7:51-67. [AS] Pennsylvania Press. [CL]
Fuchs, S., Siegel, A., & Edinger, H. (1980). Functional mapping of Hamburg, M. D. (1971) Hypothalamic unit activity and eating behavior.
hypothalamic pathways eliciting aggression and escape behavior in the American Journal of Physiology 220:980-85. [taJP, FMT]
cat: A radioautographic study. Society for Neuroscience Abstracts Harlow, H. (1971) Learning to love. San Francisco: Albion. [JJ]
7:420. [AS] Heath, R. G. (1964) Pleasure response of human subjects to direct
(1981). The neural basis of escape behavior elicited from the feline stimulation of the brain: Physiologic and psychodynamic
hypothalamus. Society for Neuroscience Abstracts 8:755. [AS] considerations. In: The role of pleasure in behavior, ed. R. G.
Gall, F. J. (1835) On the functions of the brain and each of its parts. 6 Heath, pp. 219-43. New York: Harper & Row. [RGH]
vols., trans. W. Lewis. Boston: Marsh, Capen & Lyon. [taJP] (1975) Brain function and behavior: 1. Emotion and sensory phenomena
Gallistel, C. R. (1980) The organization of action: A new synthesis. in psychotic patients and in experimental animals. Journal of Nervous
Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. [LDK, FMT] and Mental Disease 160:159-75. [RGH]
(1981) Precis of The organization of action: A new synthesis. Behavioral (1976) Correlation of brain (unction with emotional behavior. Biological
and Brain Sdences 4:609-19. [LDK] Psychiatry 11:463-80. [RGH]
Gallistel, C. R., Karreman, G. A., & Reivich, M. (1977) (14C) 2-deoxy- (1977) Modulation of emotion with a brain pacemaker: Treatment for
glucose uptake marks systems activated by rewarding brain intractable psychiatric illness. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease
stimulation. Brain Research Bulletin 2:149-52. [taJP] 165:300-17. [RGH]
Gallup, G. G. (1965). Aggression in rats as a function of frustrative Heath, R. G., Cox, A. W. & Lustick, L. S. (1974) Brain activity during
nonreward in a straight alley. Psychonomic Science 3:99-100. [JAG] emotional states. American Journal of Psychiatry 131:858-62. [RGH]
Geertz, H. (1959) The vocabulary of emotion: A study of Javanese Heath, R. G., Dempsey, C. W., Fontana, C. J. & Fitzjarrell, A. T.
socialization processes. Psychiatry 22:225-37. [CL] (1980) Feedback loop between cerebellum and septal-hippocampal
Geller, I. & Seifter, J. (1960). The effects of meprobamate, barbiturates, sites: Its role in emotion and epilepsy. Biological Psychiatry
D-amphetamine and promazine on experimentally induced conflict in 15:541-56. [RGH]
the rat. Psychopharmacologia 1:482-92. [JAG] Heath, R. G., Franklin, D. E. & Shraberg, D. (1979) Gross pathology of
Gellhorn, E., Koella, W. P., & Ballin, H. M. (1955) The influence of the cerebellum in patients diagnosed and treated as functional
hypothalamic stimulation on evoked cortical potentials. Journal of psychiatric disorders. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease
Psychology 39:77-78. [taJP] 167:585-92. [RGH]
German, D. C. & Bowden, D. M. (1974) Catecholamine systems as the Heath, R. G. & Gallant, D. M. (1964) Activity of the human brain
neural substrate for intracranial self-stimulation: A hypothesis. Brain during emotional thought. In: The role of pleasure in behavior, ed.
Research 73:381-419. [taJP] R. G. Heath, pp. 83-106. New York: Harper & Row. [RGH]
Gessa, G. L. & Tagliamonte, A. (1974) Role of brain monoamines in male Heath, R. G., Llewellyn, R. C , & Rouchell, A. M. (1980) The cerebellar
sexual behavior. Life Sciences 14:425-36. [MZ] pacemaker for intractable behavioral disorders and epilsepsy: Follow-up
Glickman, S. E. & Schiff, B. B. (1967) A biological theory of report. Biological Psychiatry 15:254-56. [RGH]
reinforcement. Psychological Review 74:81-109. [taJP] Heath, R. G. & Mickle, W. A. (1960) Evaluation of seven years

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 463


References/Fanksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

experience with depth electrode studies in human patients. In: midbrain: The resultant alterations in respiration. Journal of
Electrical studies on the unanesthetized brain, ed. E. R. Ramey & Comparative Neurology 64:187-208. [taJP]
D. S. O'Doherty, pp. 214-42. New York: Hoeber. [EF] Kamil, A. C. (1978) Systematic foraging by a nectar-feeding bird, the
Heath, R. C , Monroe, R. R., & Mickle, W. A. (1955) Stimulation of the Amakihi (Loxops cirens). Journal of Comparative and Physiological
amygdaloid nucleus in a schizophrenic patient. American Journal of Psychology 92:388-96. [FMT]
Psychiatry 3:862-63. [RGH, taJP] Karli, P. & Vergnes, M. (1964) Nouvellcs donnees sur les bases
Hcbb, D. O. (1980) Essay on mind. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum neurophysiologiques du comportement d'aggression intersp<5cifi(|ue
Associates. [CHV] rat-souris. Journal de Physiologie 56:384. [taJP]
Herberg, L. J., Stephens, D. N., & Franklin, K. B. J. (1976) Karplus, J. P. & Kreidl, A. (1909) Cehirn und Sympathicus. 1.
Catecholamines and self-stimulation: Evidence suggesting a reinforcing Zwischenhirnbasis und Halssympathicus. Pflugers Archiv-European
role for noradrenaline and a motivating role for dopamine. Journal of Physiology 129:138-44. [taJP]
Pharmacology Biochemistry and Behavior 4:575-82. [taJP] (1927) Gehim und Sympathieus. F. Ober Beziehunger der
Herman, B. H. (1979) An exploration of brain social attachment substrates Hypothalamuszentren %\\ Blutdruck und innerer Sekretion. Pflugers
in guinea pigs. Ph.D. dissertation, Bowling Green State University, Archiv—European Journal of Physiology 215:667—70. [taJP]
Ohio. [taJP] Kelly, D. (1980) Anxiety and emotions. Springfield, III.: Charles C.
Herman, B. H. & Panksepp, J. (1981) Ascending endorphin inhibition of Thomas. [rJP]
distress vocalization. Science 211:1060-62. [tarJP] King,. H. E. (1961) Psychological effects of excitation in the limbic system.
Hess, W. R. (1957) The functional organization of the diencephalon. New In: Electrical stimulation of the brain, ed. D. E. Sheer, pp. 477-86.
York: Grune & Stratton. [taJP] Austin: University of Texas Press. [EF, taJP]
Hetherington, A. W. & Ranson, S. W. (1942) The spontaneous activity Klein, D. F. (1981) Anxiety reconceptualized. In: Anxiety: New research
and food intake of rats with hypothalamic lesions. American Journal and changing concepts, ed. D. F. Klein & J. Rabkin, pp. 235-63.
of Physiology 136:609-17. [taJP] New York: Raven Press. [taJP]
Hopkins, D. A. and Holstege, G. (1978) Amygdaloid projections to the Klinger, E. (1975) Consequences of commitment to and disengagement
mesencephalon, pons and medulla oblongata in the rat. Experimental from incentives. Psychological Review 82:1-25. [EK]
Brain Research 32:529-47. [rJP] (1977) Meaning and void: Inner experience and the incentives in people's
Hunsperger, R. W., Brown, J. L., & Rosvold, H. E. (1964) Combined lives. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [EK]
stimulation in areas governing threat and flight behaviour in the brain Klinger, E., Barta, S. G., & Kemble, E. D. (1974) Cyclic activity
stem of the cat. In: Topics in basic neurology, vol. 6, Progress in changes during extinction in rats: A potential model of depression.
brain research, ed. W. Bargmann & J. P. Schade. pp. 191-97. Animal Learning and Behavior 2:313-16. [EK)
Amsterdam: Elsevier. [taJP] Kluver, H. & Bucy, P. C. (1937) "Psychic blindness" and other symptoms
Huston, J. P. & Borbely, A. A. (1974) The thalamic rat: General following bilateral temporal lobectomy in rhesus monkeys. American
behavior, operant learning with rewarding hypothalamie stimulation, Journal of Physiology 119:352-53. [taJP]
and effects of amphetamine. Physiology and Behavior (1939) Preliminary analysis of functions of the temporal lobes in
12:433-48. [taJP] monkeys. Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 42:979-1000. [taJP]
Hutchinson, R. R. & Renfrew, J. W. (1966) Stalking attack and eating Kohlberg, L. (1981) Moral stages and moralization: The cognitive-
behavior elicited from the same sites in the hypothalamus. Journal of developmental approach. In: Moral development and behavior, ed. T.
Comparative and Physiological Psychology 61:360-67. [rJP] Liekona. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston. [JJ]
(1978) Functional parallels between the neural and environmental Kupfermann, I. & Weiss, K. R. (1978) The command neuron concept.
antecedents of aggression. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Review Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1:3-40. [taJP]
2:33-58. [taJP] Langer, S. K. (1973) Mind: an essay on human feeling, vols. 1 & 2.
Iversen, L. L. (1978) Biochemical psychopharmacology of GABA. In: Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. [MC]
Psychopharmacology, a generation of progress, ed. M. A. Lipton, A. Langsdorf, P., Izard, C. E., & Rayias, M. (1981) Interest expression,
DiMascio & K. F. Killam, pp. 25-38. New York: Raven attention, and heart rate changes in two- to eight-month-old infants.
Press. [taJP] Unpublished paper, University of Delaware. [CEI]
Izard, C. E. (1971) The face of emotion. New York: Appleton-Century- Lavater, J. C. (1789-1798) Essays on physiognomy: Designed to promote
Crofts. [CEI, rJP] the knowledge and love of mankind. 3 vols., trans. H. Hunter.
(1972) Patterns of emotions: A new analysis of anxiety and depression. London: J. Murray. [taJP]
New York: Academic Press. [taJP] Lazarus, R. S. (1966) Psychological stress and the coping process. New
(1979) Human emotions. New York: Plenum Press. [CEI] York: McGraw-Hill. [JRR]
Izard, C. E. & Buechler, S. (1979) Emotion expressions and personality Lazarus, R. S., Averill, J. R., & Opton, E. M. (1970) Towards a
integration in infancy. In: Emotions in personality and cognitive theory of emotion. In: Feelings and emotions: The Loyala
psychopathology, ed. C. E. Izard, pp. 447-72. New York: Plenum symposium, ed. M. B. Arnold. New York: Academic Press. [JRR]
Press. [taJP] Leeper, R. W. (1948) A motivational theory of emotion to replace emotion
Izard, C. E., Dougherty, L. M., Coss, C. L., & Hembree, E. A. (1981) as disorganized response. Psychological Review 55. Reprinted in: The
Age-related and individual differences in infants' facial expressions nature of emotion, ed. M. B. Arnold. Penguin. [WL]
following acute pain. Unpublished paper, University of Levy, R. (1973) Tahitians: Mind and experience in the Society Islands.
Delaware. [CEI] Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [CL]
James, W. (1884) What is emotion? Mind 19:188-205. [taJP] Lewis, D. J. (1979) Psychobiology of active and inactive memory.
(1892) Psychology: The briefer course. New York: Harper & Psychological Bulletin 86:1054-83. [FMT]
Row. [taJP] Lindsay-Hartz, J. (1981) Joy, elation, and gladness. In: Conceptual
Jasper, H. H. & Rasmussen, T. (1958) Studies of clinical and electrical encounter, ed. J. de Rivera. Washington, D.C.: Universities Press of
responses to deep temporal stimulation in man with some America. [JdeR]
consideration of functional anatomy. Research Publications: Association Lindsley, D. B. (1950) Emotions and the electroencephalogram. In:
for Research in Nervous and Mental Disease 36:316-34. [taJP] Feelings and emotions: The Mooseheart symposium, ed. M. L.
Jaynes, J. (1976) The origin of consciousness in the breakdown of the Reymert, pp. 238-46. New York: McCraw-Hill. [taJP, JRR]
bicameral mind. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. [JJ] Lorenz, K. (1970) Studies in animal and human behaviour. London:
Jouvet, M. (1972) The role of monoamines and acetylcholine-containing Methuen, vol. 1. [WL]
neurons in the regulation of the sleep-waking cycle. Ergebnisse der Lorenz, K. & Leyhausen, P. (1973) Motivation of human and animal
Physiologie 64:166-307. [rJP] behavior: An ethological view. Princeton, N.J.: Van Nostrand, chap.
(1979) What does a cat dream about? Trends in Neurosciences 10. [WL]
2:280-82. [rJP] Luria, A. R. (1973) The working brain. New York: Basic Books. [JRA]
Jiirgens, U. & Ploog, D. (1970) Cerebral representation of vocalization in Lutz, C. (1981) Situation based emotion frames and the cultural
the squirrel monkey. Experimental Brain Research 10:532-54. [taJP] construction of emotions. In: Proceedings of the third annual
Jus, A., Jus, K., Villeneuve, A., Pires, A., Rachance, R., Fortier, J., & conference of the Cognitive Science Society, pp. 84-89. Berkeley,
Villeneuve, R. (1973) Studies on dream recall in chronic schizophrenic Calif. [CL]
patients after prefrontal lobotomy. Biological Psychiatry (1982) The domain of emotion words on Ifaluk. American Ethnologist
6:275-93. [rJP] 9:113-28. [CL]
Kabat, H. (1936) Electrical stimulation of points in the forebrain and Lyons, W. (1980) Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [WL]

464 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Re/erences/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

MacLean, P. D. (1949) Psychosomatic disease and the "visceral brain": hypothalamie chemical stimulation. Canadian Journal of Psychology
Recent developments bearing on the Papez theory of emotion. 18:6-14. [taJP]
Psychosomatic Medicine 11:338-53. [taJP] Nakamura, K. & Thoenen, H. (1972) Increased irritability: A permanent
(1973) A triune concept of the brain and behavior. In: The Mncks behavior change induced in the rat by intraventricular administration
memorial lectures, cd. T. Boag & D. Campbell, pp. 6-66. Toronto: of 6-hydroxydopamine. Psychopharmacologia 24:359-72. [taJP]
University of Toronto Press. [JJ, taJP] Nakao, H. (1958) Emotional behavior produced by hypothalamie
(1975) Sensory and perceptive factors in emotional functions of the stimulation. American Journal of Physiology 194:411-18. [taJP]
triune brain. In: Emotions: their parameters and measurement, ed. L. Nauta, W. J. H. (1946) Hypothalamie regulation of sleep in rats. Journal
Levi. New York: Raven Press. [RP] of Neurophysiology 9:285-316. [taJP]
(1981) Role of transhypothalamic pathways in social communication. In: Nisbett, R. E. & Wilson, T. D. (1977) Telling more than we can know:
Handbook of the hypothalamus. vol. 3, pt. B, Behavioral studies of Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review
the hypothalamus, ed. P. J. Morgane & J. Panksepp. pp. 259-87. 84:231-59. [RdeS, CL, rJP, CHV]
New York: Marcel Dekker. [tarJP] Olds, J. (1975) Unit recordings during Pavlovian conditioning. In: Brain
MacPhail, E. M. & Miller, N. E. (1968) Cholinergic stimulation in cats: mechanisms in mental retardation. UCLA Forum in Medical Sciences,
Failure to obtain sleep. Journal of Comparative and Physiological No. 18, ed. N. A. Buchwald & M. A. B. Brazier, pp. 343-71. New
Psychology 65:499-503. [taJP] York: Academic Press. [taJP]
Maier, S. F. & Seligman, M. E. P. (1976) Learned helplessness: Theory Oomura, Y. (1980) Input-output organization in the hypothalamus relating
and evidence. Journal of Experimental Psychology 105:3-46. [HA] to food intake behavior, in: Handbook of the hypothalamus. vol. 2,
Mancia, B. & Zanchetti, A. (1981) Hypothalamie control of autonomic Physiology of the hypothalamus, ed. P. J. Morgane & J. Panksepp,
function. In: Handbook of the hypothalamus. vol. 3, pt. B, New pp. 557-620. New York: Marcel Dekker. [taJP]
Behavioral studies of the hypothalamus, ed. P. J. Morgane & J. Palkovits, M. & ZSborszky, L. (1979) Neural connections of the hypothalamus.
Panksepp, pp. 47-202. New York: Marcel Dekker. [taJP] In: Handbook of the hypothalamus. vol. 2, Anatomy of the
Mark, V. H. & Erwin, R. F. (1979) Violence and the brain. New York: hypothalamus, pp. 379-509. New York: Marcel Dekker. [taJP]
Harper & Row, pp. 1-190. [EF] Panksepp, J. (1971a) Aggression elicited by electrical stimulation of the
Marshall, J. F. (1979) Somatosensory inattention after dopamine depleting hypothalamus in albino rats. Physiology and Behavior 6:321-29. [LDK,
intracerebral 6-OH-DA injections: Spontaneous recovery and tarJP]
pharmacological control. Brain Research 177:311-24. [JP] (1971b) Drugs and stimulus-bound attack. Physiology and Behavior
Marshall, J. F., Berrios, N., & Sawyer, S. (1980) Neostriatal dopamine 6:317-20. [taJP]
and sensory inattention. Journal of Comparative and Physiological (1971c) Effects of hypothalamie lesions on mouse-killing and shock-
Psychology 94:833-46. [taJPJ induced fighting in rats. Physiology and Behavior 6:321-29. [taJP]
.Marshall, J. F. & Teitelbaum, P. (1974) Further analysis of sensory (1979a) Offense and defense vs. rage and fear: A matter of semantics?
inattention following lateral hypothalamie damage in rats. Journal of Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2:225-26. [tarJP]
Comparative and Physiological Psychology 86:375-95. [taJP] (1979b) Cost-benefits of computer modelling. Behavioral and Brain Sciences
Martm-Ramfrez, J., Blanco, J. J., Alonso, A., & Delgado, J. M. R. (1982) 2:114. [rJP]
Hissing in the cat evoked by brain stimulation. Poster presented at (1981a) Hypothalamie integration of behavior: Rewards, punishments,
First World Congress of IBRO. Lausanne March 31-April 6, and related psychological processes. In: Handbook of the
1982. [JMRD] hypothalamus. vol. 3, pt. B, Behavioral studies of the hypothalamus,
Masserman, J. H. (1941) Is the hypothalamus a center of emotion? ed. P. J. Morgane & J. Panksepp, pp. 289-431. New York: Marcel
Psychosomatic Medicine 3:3-25. [taJP] Dekker. [tarJP]
Mnsuoka, D. T. & Alcaraz, A. F. (1975) An autoradiographic method of (1981b) Brain opioids - A neurochemical substrate for narcotic and
mapping the distribution and density of monoamine neurons in mouse social dependence. In: Theory in psychophannacology. vol. 1., ed. S.
brain. European Journal of Pharmacology 33:125-30. [taJP] Cooper. London: Academic Press. [tarJP]
McCinty, D. J. & Sterman, M. B. (1968) Sleep suppression after basal (1982a) The pleasure in brain substrates of foraging. Behavioral and
forebrain lesions in the cat. Science 160:1253-55. [taJP] Brain Sciences 5:71-72. [rJP]
Mclntyre, M. & Stein, D. G. (1973) Differential effects of one- vs. two- (1982b) Foraging-expectancy command circuitry of the brain: A
stage amygdaloid lesions on activity, exploratory, and avoidance functional theory of lateral hypothalamie self-stimulation,
behavior in the albino rat. Behavioral Biology 9:451-65. [JdeR] submitted. [rJP]
Melzaek, R. & Casey, K. L. (1970) The affective dimension of pain. In: Panksepp, J. & Bishop, P. (1981) An autoradiographic map of (3H)
Feelings and emotions, ed. M. B. Arnold, pp. 55-68. New York: diprenorphine binding in rat brain: Effects of social interaction. Brain
Academic Press. |LDK] Research Bulletin 7:405-10. [taJP]
Millhouse, O. E. (1979) A golgi anatomy of the rodent hypothalamus. In: Panksepp, J., Candelman, R., & Trowill, J. (1970) Modulation of
Handbook of the hypothalamus. vol. 1, Anatomy of the hypothalamus, hypothalamie self-stimulation and escape behavior by chlordiazepoxide.
ed. P. J. Mogane & J. Panksepp. pp. 221-65. New York: Marcel Physiology and Behavior 5:965-69. [rJP]
Dekker. [taJP] Panksepp, J., Herman, B., Conner, R., Bishop, P., & Scott, J. P. (1978)
Monroe, R. R. & Heath, R. C. (1954) Psychiatric observations on the The biology of social attachments: Opiates alleviate separation distress.
patient group. In: Studies in schizophrenia: A multidisciplinary Biological Psychiatry 13:607-18. [rJP]
approach to mind brain relationships, ed. R. C. Heath, pp. 345-83. Panksepp, J., Herman, B. H., Vilberg, T., Bishop, T., & DcEskinazi, F.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [taJP] G. (1980) Endogenous opioids and social behavior. Neuroscience and
Morgane, P. J., Jacobs, M. S., & McFarland, W. L. (1980) The anatomy Biobehavioral Reviews 4:473-87. [LDK, tarJP]
of the brain of the bottlenose dolphins (Titrsiops tntneatus): Surface Papez, J. W. (1937) A proposed mechanism of emotion. Archives of
configurations of the telencephalon of the bottlenose dolphin with Neurology and Psychiatry 38:725-44. [taJP]
comparative anatomical observations in four other cetacean species. Parent, A. (1979) Anatomical organization of monoamine- and
Brain Research Bulletin, vol. 5, supplement 3. [rJP] acetylcholinesterase-containing neuronal systems in the vertebrate
Mowrer, O. H. (1960) Learning theory and behavior. New York: hypothalamus. In: Handbook of the hypothalamus. vol. 1, Anatomy of
Wiley. [JAC] the hypothalamus, ed. P. J. Morgane & J. Panksepp, pp. 511-54.
Moycr, K. E. (1976) The psychobiology of aggression. New York: Harper New York: Marcel Dekker. [taJP]
& Row. [taJP] Perochio, A. A. & Alexander, M. (1974) Neurophysiologieal approaches to
Miinn, N. L. (1961) Psychology: The fundamentals of human adjustment. the study of aggression. In: The neuropsychology of aggression, ed.
New York: Harrap. [WL] R. E. Whalen, pp. 65-83. Advances in Behavioral Biology 12. New
Murphy, M. R., MacLean, P. D., & Hamilton, S. C. (1981) Species- York: Plenum Press. [EF]
typical behavior of hamsters deprived from birth of the neocortex. Phillips, A. G. (1975) Object-carrying by rats: Disruption by ventral
Science 213:429-61. [taJP] mesencephalic lesions. Canadian Journal of Psychology
Murray, E. J. (1964) Motivation and emotion. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: 29:250-62. [taJP]
Prentice-Hall. [WL] Phillips, A. G. & Fibiger, H. C. (1973) Dopaminergic and noradrenergic
Myer, J. S. (1971) Some effects of noncontingent aversive stimulation. In: substrates of positive reinforcement: Differential effects of d- and I-
Avcrsive conditioning and learning, ed. F. R. Brush, pp. 469-536. amphetamine. Science 179:575-77. [taJP]
New York: Academic Press. [JAC] Phillips, A. G., McDonald, A. C , & Wilkie, D. M. (1981) Disruption of
Myers, R. D. (1964) Emotional and autonomic responses following autoshaped responding to a signal of brain-stimulation reward by

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 465


Re/erences/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

neuroleptic drugs. Pharmacology Biochemistry and Behavior Rorty, A. O., ed. (1980) Explaining emotions. Berkeley: University of
14:543-48. [rJP] California Press. [MS]
Piechowski, M. (1981) The logical and empirical form of feeling. Journal Routtenberg, A. (1968) The two-arousal hypothesis: Reticular formation and
of Aesthetic Education 15:31-53. [MC] limbic system. Psychological Review 75:51-81. [MZ]
Pinel, J. P. J. & Treit, D. (1978) Burying as a defensive response in rats. Routtenberg, A. & Malsbury, C. (1969) Brainstem pathways of reward.
Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology 68:22-30. [taJP]
92:708-12. [HA] Royce, J. R. & Diamond, S. R. (1980) A multifactor-system dynamics
Plotnik, R., Mir, D., & Delgado, J. M. R. (1971) Aggression noxiousness theory of emotion: Cognitive affective interaction. Motivation and
and brain stimulation in unrestrained rhesus monkeys. In: The Emotion 4:263-98. [JRR]
physiology of aggression and defeat, ed. B. E. Eleftheriou & J. P. Ruckmick, C. A. (1936) The psychology of feeling and emotion. New York:
Scott, pp. 143-222. New York: Plenum. [taJP] McGraw-Hill. [taJP]
Plutchik, R. (1962) The emotions: Facts, theories and a new model. New Ruger, J. & Schulkin, J. (1980) Preoperative sodium appetite experience
York: Random House. [RP, JRR] and hypothalamic lesions in rats. Journal of Comparative and
(1970) Emotions, evolution and adaptive processes. In: Feelings and Physiological Psychology 94:914-20. [taJP]
emotions, ed. M. Arnold. New York: Academic Press. [RP] Schacter, S. (1964) The interaction of cognitive and physiological
(1980) Emotion: A psychoevolutionary synthesis. New York: Harper & determinants of emotional states. In: Psychological and biological
Row. [JdeR, RSL, taJP, RP] approaches to social behavior, ed. P. Leederman & D. Shapiro.
Plutchik, R., Kellerman, H., & Conte, H. R. (1979) A structural theory Stanford: Stanford University Press. [JRR]
of ego defenses. In: Emotions, personality and psychopathology, ed. Schachter, S. & Singer, J. E. (1962) Cognitive, social and physiological
C. E. Izard. New York: Plenum. [RP] determinants of emotional state. Psychological Review
Plutchik, R., McFarland, W. L., & Robinson, B. W., (1966) Relationships 69:379-99. [taJP, HU]
between current intensity, self-stimulation rates, escape latencies and Schaefer, E. & Plutchik, R. (1966) Interrelationships of emotions, traits
evoked behavior in rhesus monkeys. Journal of Comparative and and diagnostic constructs. Psychological Reports 18:399-410. [RP]
Physiological Psychology 61:181-88. [RP] Schreiner, L. & Kling, A. (1953) Behavioral changes following
Plutchik, R. & Platman, S. R. (1977) Personality connotations of rhinencephalic injury in cat. Journal of Neurophysiology
psychiatric diagnoses. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 16:643-59. [taJP]
165:418-22. [RP] Schwartz, M. & Teitelbaum, P. (1974) Dissociation between learning and
Powers, W. T. (1978) Quantitative analysis of purposive systems: Some remembering in rats with lesions in the lateral hypothalamus. Journal
spadework at the foundations of scientific psychology. Psychological of Comparative and Physiological Psychology 87:384-98. [taJP]
Review 85:417-35. [FMT] Sem-Jacobsen, C. W. & Torkildsen, A. (1969) Depth recording and electrical
Pradhan, S. N. & Bose, S. (1978) Interactions among central stimulation in the human brain. In: Electrical studies on the
neurotransmitters. In: Psychopharmacology: A generation of progress, unanesthetized brain, ed. E. R. Ramey & D. S. O'Doherty, pp. 275-87.
ed. M. A. Lipton, A. DiMascio, & K. F. Killam, pp. 271-81. New New York: Hoeber. [EF]
York: Raven Press. [taJP] Shand, A. (1914) The foundations of character. London: Macmillan. [WL]
Pradhan, S. N. & Kamat, K. A. (1973) Effects of anticholinergic agents on Sherrington, C. S. (1900) Experiments on the value of vascular and
self-stimulation. Archives Internationales de Pharmacodynamie et de visceral factors for the genesis of emotion. Proceedings of the Royal
Therapie 201:16-24. [taJP] Society (London), Series B 66:390-403. [taJP]
Pradines, M. (1958) Traitd de psychologie generale. vol. 1, 6th ed., Paris: Shiller, V. M. & Izard, C. E. (1981) Patterns of emotion expressions
Presses Universitaires de France. [WL] during separation. Unpublished paper, University of Delaware. [CEI]
Pribram, K. & Melges, F. (1969) Psychophysiological basis of emotion. In: Siegel, A. & Edinger, H. (1981) Neural control of aggression and rage
Handbook of clinical neurology, ed. P. J. Vinken & G. W. Brunyn. behavior. In: Handbook of the hypothalamus. vol. 3, pt. B, Behavioral
Amsterdam: North-Holland. [JdeR] studies of the hypothalamus, ed. P. J. Morgane & J. Panksepp, pp.
Ranson, S. W. (1934) Autonomic reactions induced by electrical stimuation 203-40. New York: Marcel Dekker. [tarJP]
of the hypothalamus. American Journal of Physiology 109:85. [taJP] Skinner, B. F. (1974) About behaviorism. New York: Alfred A.
(1939) Somnolence caused by hypothalamic lesions in the monkey. Knopf. [CHV]
Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 41:1-23. [taJP] Smith, D. A. (1972) Increased perioral responsiveness: A possible explanation
Ranson, S. W. & Magoun, H. W. (1939) The hypothalamus. Ergebnisse for the switching of behavior observed during lateral hypothalamic
der Physiologie 41:56-163. [taJP] stimulation. Physiology and Behavior 8:617-21. [taJP]
Redmond, D. E., Jr. & Hunag, Y. H. (1979) Current Concepts. 2. New Solomon, R. C. (1976) The passions. Garden City, N. Y.: Doubleday
evidence for a locus coeruleus-norepinephrine connection with Anchor. [JRA]
anxiety. Life Sciences 25:2149-62. [taJP] Solomon, R. L. (1980) The opponent-process theory of acquired
Reeves, A. G. & Plum, F. (1969) Hyperphagia, rage, and dementia motivation. American Psychologist 35:691-712. [rJP]
accompanying a ventromedial hypothalamic neoplasam. Archives of Sperry, R. W. (1969) A modified concept of consciousness. Psychological
Neurology 20:616-24. [taJP] Review 76:532-36. [GGG]
Rescorla, R. A. & Solomon, R. L. (1967) Two process learning theory: Spurzheim, J. G. (1832) Phrenology or the doctrine of the mental phenomena.
Relationships between Pavlovian and instrumental learning. vol. 1, Physiological part. New York: Harper & Row. [taJP]
Psychological Review 74:151-82. [HA] (1846) Phrenology, or the doctrine of the mental phenomena. New York:
Roberts, W. W. (1958) Rapid escape learning without avoidance learning Harper & Brothers. [rJP]
motivated by hypothalamic electrical stimulation. Journal of Stark, P. & Boyd, E. S. (1963) Effects of cholinergic drugs on
Comparative and Physiological Psychology 51:391-99. [taJP] hypothalamic self-stimulation rates of dogs. American Journal of
(1980) ('4C) deoxyglucose mapping of first order projections activated by Physiology 205:745-48. [JP]
stimulation of lateral hypothalamic sites eliciting gnawing, eating and Starr, C. (1968) The awakening of the Greek historical spirit. New York:
drinking in rats. Journal of Comparative Neurology Knopf. [JJ]
194:617-38. [taJP] Stein, L. (1964) Reciprocal action of reward and punishment mechanisms.
Roberts, W. W. & Berquist, E. (1968) Attack elicited by hypothalamic In: The role of pleasure in behavior, ed. R. G. Heath, pp. 113-39.
stimulation in cats raised in social isolation. Journal of Comparative New York: Harper & Row. (FMT]
and Physiological Psychology 66:590-96. [taJP] (1978) Reward transmitters: Catecholamines and opioid peptides. In:
Robinson, B. W., Alexander, M., & Browne, G. (1969) Dominance Psychopharmacology: A generation of progress, ed. M. A. Lipton, A.
reversal resulting from aggressive responses evoked by brain DiMascio, & K. F. Killam, pp. 569-81. New York: Raven
telestimulation. Physiology and Behavior 4:749-52. [taJP] Press. [taJP, MZ]
Rolls, E. T. (1980) Activity of hypothalamic and related neurons in the Stein, L. & Belluzzi, J. D. (1978) Brain endorphins and the sense of
alert animal. In: Handbook of the hypothalamus. vol. 3, pt. A, well-being: A psychobiological hypothesis. In: The endorjihins, ed. E.
Behavioral studies of the hypothalamus, ed. P. J. Morgane & J. Costa & M. Trabucchi, pp. 299-311. New York: Raven Press. [taJP]
Panksepp, pp. 439-66. New York: Marcel Dekker. [tarJP] Straus, E. (1963) The primary world of senses. London: Free Press of
Rolls, E. T. & Kelly, P. H. (1972) Neural basis of stimulus-bound Glencoe. [JdeR]
locomotor activity in the rat. Journal of Comparative and Strieker, E. M. & Zigmond, M. J. (1976) Recovery of function after damage
Physiological Psychology 81:173-82. [taJP] to central catecholamine-containing neurons: A neurocheinical model for

466 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3


Re/erences/Panksepp: Psychobiology of emotions

the lateral hypothalamic syndrome. In: Progress in psychobiology and Wada, J. A., Matsuda, M., Jung, E., & Hamm, A. (1970) Mesencephalically
physiological psychology, vol. 6, ed. J. M. Sprague & A. N. Epstein, pp. induced escape behavior and avoidance performance. Experimental
121-88. Academic Press: New York. [taJP] Neurology 29:215-20. [taJP]
Strongman, K. T. (1973) The psychology of emotion. London: John Wahlsten, D. (1972) Phenotypic and genetic relations between initial
Wiley. [taJP] response to electric shock and rate of avoidance learning in mice.
(1978) The psychology of emotion, 2nd ed. New York: Wiley & Behavior Cenetics 2:211-40. [HA]
Sons. IJRR] Watson, J. B. (1924) Psychology from the standpoint of a behaviorist.
Swanson, L. W. & Kuypers, H. G. J. M. (1980) The paraventricular Philadelphia: Lippincott. [taJP]
nucleus of the hypothalamns: Cytoarchitectonic subdivisions and Wayner, M. J., Barone, F. C , & Loullis, C. C. (1981) The lateral
organization of projections to the pituitary, dorsal vagal complex, and hypothalamus and adjunctive behavior. In: Handbook of the
spinal cord as demonstrated by retrograde fluorescence double-labeling hypothalamus. vol. 3, pt. B, Behavioral studies of the hypothalamus,
methods. Journal of Comparative Neurology 194:555-70. [rJP] ed. P. J. Morgane & J. Panksepp, pp. 107-46. New York: Marcel
Thorpe, W. H. (1963) Learning and instinct in animals. London: Dekker. [taJP]
Methucn, chap. 4. [WL] Weiss, J. M., Glazer, H. I., Pohorecky, L. A., Bailey, W. H., &
Toatcs, F. M. (1980) Animal behaviour - A systems approach. Chichester: Schneider, L. H. (1979) Coping behavior and stress-induced
Wiley. [FMT] behavioral depression: Studies of the role of brain catecholamines. In:
(1982) Exploration as a motivational and learning system. A (tentative) The psychobiology of the depressive disorders: Implications for the
cognitive-incentive model. In: Exploration in animals and man, ed. J. effects of stress, ed. R. A. Depue, pp. 125-60. New York: Academic
Archer & L. I. A. Birke. Wokingham: Van Nostrand. [FMT] Press. [HA]
Toates, F. M. & Birke, L. I. A. (1982) Motivation - A new perspective on Wellman, H. (in press) A child's theory of mind: The development of
some old ideas. In: Perspectives in ethology, vol 5, ed. P. Bateson & P. conceptions of cognition. In: The growth of insight in the child, ed.
H. Klopfer. New York: Plenum Press. [FMT] S. R. Yussen. New York: Academic Press. [CL]
Tomkins, S. (1962) Affect, imagery, consciousness, vol. 1, The positive Wheatley, M. C. (1944) The hypothalamus and affective behavior in cats.
affects. New York: Springer. [JdeR] Archives Neurology and Psychiatry (Chicago) 52:296-316. [taJP]
(1963) Affect, imagery, consciousness, vol. 2, The negative affects. New Wilcock, J. (1968). Strain differences in response to shock in rats
York: Springer. [JJ] selectively bred for emotional elimination. Animal Behaviour
Treit, D., Pinel, J. P. J., & Fibiger, H. C. (1981) Conditioned defensive 16:294-97. [JAG]
burying: A new paradigm for the study of anxiolytic agents. Willis, T. (1683) Two discourses concerning the soul of brutes.
Pharmacology Biochemistry and Behavior 15:619-26. [HA] London. [tarJP]
Trowill, J. A., Panksepp, J., & Candclman, R. (1969) An incentive model (1664/1965) The anatomy of the brain and nerves. Tercentenary ed.
of rewarding brain stimulation. Psychological Review Montreal: McGill University Press. [JRA]
76:264-81. [taJP] Wise, R. A. (1971) Individual differences in effects of hypothalamic
Ursin, H. (1965) The effect of amygdaloid lesions on flight and defence stimulation: The role of stimulation locus. Physiology and Behavior
behavior in cats. Experimental Neurology 11:61-79. [taJP] 6:569-72. [taJP]
(1980) Personality, activation, and somatic health: A new psychosomatic (1978) Catecholamine theories of reward: A critical review. Brain
theory. In: Coping and health, ed. S. Levine & H. Ursin, pp. Research 152:215-47. [taJP]
259-79. New York: Plenum Press. [HU] (1982) Neuroleptics and operant behavior: The anhedonia hypothesis.
Ursin, H. & Kaada, B. R. (1960) Functional localization within the Brain and Behavioral Sciences. 5:39-87. [taJP]
amygdaloid complex in the cat. Electroencephalography and Clinical Wishart, T. B. & Walls, E. K. (1974) Reduction of stimulus-bound food
Neurophysiology 12:1-20. [taJP] consumption in the rat following amphetamine administration. Journal
Valenstein, E. S., Cox, V. C , & Kakolewski, J. W. (1970) Reexamination of Comparative and Physiological Psychology 87:741-45. [HA]
of the role of the hypothalamus in motivation behavior. Psychological Young, P. T. (1961) Motivation and emotion. New York: Wiley. [WL]
Review 77:16-31. [HA, EK, tarJP] Zaner, R. (1970) The way of phenomenology: Criticism as a philosophical
Vanderwolf, C. H. (in press) The influence of psychological concepts on discipline. New York: Pegasus. [GGG]
brain-behavior research. In: Behavioral contributions to brain Zevon, M. A., & Tellegen, A. (in press) The structure of mood change:
research, ed. T. E. Robinson. New York: Oxford University An idiographic/nomothetic analysis. Journal of Personality and Social
Press. [CHV] Psychology. [EK]
Vanderwolf, C. H. & Robinson, T. E. (1981) Reticulo-cortical activity and Zolovick, A. J., Rossi, J. Ill, Davies, R. F., & Panksepp, J. (1982) An
behavior: A critique of the arousal theory and a new synthesis. improved pharmacological procedure for depletion of noradrenaline:
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4:459-514. [rJP, CHV] Pharmacology and assessment of noradrenaline-associated behaviors.
von Economo, C. (1930) Sleep as a problem of localization. Journal of European Journal of Pharmacology: [taJP]
Nervous and Mental Disease 71:249-59. [taJP] Zuckerman, M. (1979) Sensation seeking: Beyond the optimal level of
Wada, J. A. & Matsuda, M. (1970) Can hypothalamically induced escape arousal. Hillsadale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. [MZ]
be conditioned? Experimental Neurology 28:507-12. [taJP]

BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1982)3 467


Call for Papers

Investigators in " . . . superbly presented . . . the result Is


practically a vade mecum or Who's Who in

Psychology, each subject. [Articles are] followed by pithy


and often (believe it or not) witty comments
questioning, illuminating, endorsing or just
plain arguing... I urge anyone with an Inter-

Neuroscience, est In psychology, neuroscience, and behav-


ioural biology to get access to this jour-
nal."—New Scientist

Behavioral Biology, and "Care is taken to ensure that the commentaries


represent a sampling of opinion from scientists
throughout the world Through open peer com-
mentary, the knowledge imparted by the target

Cognitive Science article becomes more fully integrated into the


entire field of the behavioral and brain sciences.
This contrasts with the provincialism of special-
ized journals . .."—Eugene Garfield Current
Contents
Do you want to: "The field covered by BBS has often suf-
• draw wide attention to a particularly fered In the past from the drawing of battle
important or controversial piece of work? lines between prematurely hardened posi-
tions: nature v. nurture, cognitive v. behav-
iourist, biological v. cultural causation....
• solicit reactions, criticism, and feedback [BBS] has often produced important articles
from a large sample of your peers? and, of course, fascinating Interchanges
the points of dispute are highlighted if not
• place your ideas in an interdisciplinary, always resolved, the styles and positions of
the participants are exposed, hobbyhorses
international context? are sometimes ridden with great vigour, and
mutual incomprehension is occasionally
made very conspicuous.... commentaries
are often Incisive, integratlve or bring highly
relevant new information to bear on the sub-
ject."—Nature
" . . . a high standard of contributions and dis-
cussion, it should serve as one of the major

and
an extraordinary journal now in its fifth year, provides a
stimulants of growth in the cognitive sciences
over the next decade."—Howard Gardner
(Education) Harvard
special service called Open Peer Commentary to re- " . . . keep on like this and you will be not
merely good, but essential..."—D.O. Hebb
searchers in any area of psychology, neuroscience, (Psychology) Dalhousle
behavioral biology or cognitive science. " . . . a unique format from which to gain some
Papers judged appropriate for Commentary are circulated appreciation for current topics in the brain sci-
ences . . . [and] by which original hypotheses
to a large number of specialists who provide substantive may be argued openly and constructively."—
criticism, interpretation, elaboration, and pertinent com- Allen R. Wyler (Neurological Surgery)
Washington
plementary and supplementary material from a full cross-
disciplinary perspective. " . . . one of the most distinguished and use-
ful of scientific Journals. It is, Indeed, that
Article and commentaries then appear simultaneously with rarity among scientific periodicals: a crea-
tive forum . . ."—Ashley Montagu (Anthro-
the author's formal response. This BBS "treatment" pology) Princeton
provides in print the exciting give and take of an interna- "I think the idea is excellent."—Noam Chomsky
tional seminar. (Linguistics) M.l.f.
The editor of BBS is calling for papers that offer a clear " . . . open peer commentary . . . allows the
reader to assess the 'state of the art' quickly
rationale for Commentary, and also meet high standards of in a particular field. The commentaries pro-
conceptual rigor, empirical grounding, and clarity of style. vide a 'who's who' as well as the content of
Contributions may be (1) reports and discussions of empiri- recent research."—Journal of Social and Bi-
ological Structures
cal research of broader scope and implications than might
"... presents an imaginative approach to learn-
be reported in a specialty journal; (2) unusually significant ing which might be adopted by other jour-
theoretical articles that formally model or systematize a nals."—Library Journal
body of research; and (3) novel interpretations, syntheses or "Neurobiologists are acutely aware that
critiques of existing theoretical work. their subject is in an explosive phase of de-
velopment . . . we frequently wish for a fo-
Although the BBS Commentary service is primarily devoted rum for the exchange of ideas and Interpre-
to original unpublished manuscripts, at times it will be ex- tations . . . plenty of journals gladly carry the
facts, very few are willing to even consider
tended to precis of recent books or previously published promoting ideas. Perhaps even more impor-
articles. tant is the need for opportunities publicly to
criticize traditional and developing concepts
Published quarterly by Cambridge University Press. Edi- and interpretations. [BBS] is helping to fill
torial correspondence to: Stevan Hamad, Editor, BBS, these needs."—Graham Hoyle (Biology)
Oregon
Suite 240, 20 Nassau Street, Princeton, NJ 08540.

You might also like