You are on page 1of 11

14 Disciplinarity

Contemporary reviews of disciplinarity and interdisciplinarity tend to be


sympathetic to the aims of interdisciplinarity but end up affirming the value
Chapter 2 of disciplinarity on grounds that bear closer inspection (Krishnan 2009).
Chandler feels in retrospect that Foucault had been misinterpreted, and
points to his inaugural lecture, The Order of Discourse, as evidence of a more
Through Others’ Eyes: nuanced approach to disciplinary authority (op. cit. p. 742). This is indeed
The Fate of Disciplines the case. Foucault (1981) is there concerned to outline two approaches to the
analysis of ‘discourses’, one he calls critique – which analyses the moments
Johan Muller of ‘restraint’ of a discourse – ‘sanctioning, exclusion and scarcity’ (ibid. p. 73),
the other he calls genealogy – which analyses the moments of creativity,
transgression and ‘affirmation’ (ibid.). Akin to Freud’s ego and id, as Foucault
(1981: 49) points out in his introduction to the published lecture, these
two necessarily work in tandem: in Foucault’s words, ‘the critical and the
genealogical descriptions must alternate, and complement each other, each
What is Disciplinarity? supporting the other by turns’ (op. cit. p. 73). He continues, ‘Scarcity and
affirmation; ultimately scarcity of affirmation, and not the continuous generosity
‘Disciplinarity’ is a term with a spectral half-life. According to the 5th edition of of meaning . . .’ (ibid.). A little earlier, Kuhn (1970) was making a very similar
the OED it doesn’t exist, though there are adjectival cousins – ‘disciplinal’ distinction between the necessary complementarity of normal and revolutionary
(‘belonging to or of the nature of discipline’) and ‘discipular’ (‘of, belonging science, though a distinction with more far-reaching relativizing implications
to, or of the nature of a discipline’) (ibid. p. 693). Which doesn’t tell us very than Foucault’s. George Steiner (1971) in his commentary on The Order of
much. What is it then that the new nominalization ‘disciplinarity’ signifies? Things reproached Foucault for not citing Kuhn. Foucault (1971) replied icily
James Chandler (2009) suggests that the word entered the lexicon in the heady that he had instead cited Canguilhem, a thinker who had anticipated and
wake of Michel Foucault’s The Order of Things in 1965, not to name a quality of superseded Kuhn. As I will show below, this is of more than passing interest, and
discipline-being, but rather to open a semantic space for its opposite, to name provides a vital clue to the way that Bernstein, firmly in the French tradition on
‘the space of the interdisciplinary’1 (Chandler 2009: 738), duly so named in this, frames the regulation of symbolic forms.
the OED. With this new term, and for the first time in the modern Humanities In retrospect it is rather strange that the epigones of interdisciplinarity
and the social sciences, the boundedness and rigour of conventional disciplined could, in Foucault’s name, with such confidence split apart scarcity and
scholarly work were considered suspect, somehow limited and limiting, jejune. affirmation, disciplinarity and interdisciplinarity, and allocate restraint to
Freedom and innovativeness lay in border crossing: under the cobblestones of disciplinarity, affirmation to interdisciplinarity (Messer-Davidow 1993).
disciplinarity lay the beach of interdisciplinarity.2 A host of what Chandler calls Foucault’s way with technical terms may have had something to do with it.
‘shadow disciplines’ (op. cit. p. 737), like ‘cultural studies’, moved to occupy It is only towards the end of the Archaeology of Knowledge that it becomes
the space thus opened up by the negational label, and together with the rush of clear that ‘knowledge’ (‘savoir’) is defined in opposition to ‘science’ or scien-
‘studies’ there was a brief vogue for Humanities Institutes, interdisciplinary tific knowledge (‘connaissance’). ‘Only propositions that obey certain laws
spaces of supposed freedom and creative possibility. of construction belong to a domain of scientificity’ (Foucault 1972: 183).
The momentum of negational interdisciplinarity was always going to be hard ‘Knowledge’ for Foucault is thus everything that does not make it into
to sustain; as Chandler (2009: 739) comments, ‘[E]ven casual observers of connaissance, into the stock of knowledge of a discipline.3 Perhaps it is not
debates about the state of the Humanities and social sciences will be aware that so strange after all that the remissive traducing of the disciplines has so
in recent years some reaction had already been registered against the regime of frequently been done in his name.
post-1960s interdisciplinarity’. A new appreciation for the virtues of disciplinarity If the critical tide has turned somewhat against interdisciplinarity as an
has made its way into print (e.g. Hunt 1994). The reaction of philosophers like ideological opposite to disciplinarity, the general practical sense of needing
Boghossian (2006) and Norris (2000, 2006) to constructivist science studies, and being able to draw on more than one mode of inquiry or body of knowledge
the standard bearer of interdisciplinarity, helped to check the enthusiasm. has an enduring appeal. It is only appropriate, after all, not to lose sight of the
fact that the rationale for our common endeavour in this volume is to see how a
Through Others’ Eyes 15 16 Disciplinarity

fruitful interdisciplinary intercourse can be maintained between a Bernsteinian- between the internal relations of disciplines, each drawn with a particular
inspired sociology of knowledge and a Halliday-inspired systemic-functional purpose in mind. These are:
linguistics (SFL). Such a mode of interdisciplinarity is to be distinguished from
the wholesale flattening of disciplinary boundaries as in the phase of ‘institute
z the distinction between disciplines of the inner, the Humanities, and those
interdisciplinarity’ and ‘-studies interdisciplinarity’ referred to above. It should
of the outer, the sciences;
also be distinguished from ‘trading zones’, the term historian of microphysics
z the distinction between ‘singulars’, which are traditional disciplines, and
Peter Galison (1997) borrowed from anthropology to account for how theoretical
‘regions’, disciplinary formations that face both inward toward the knowledge
physicists, experimental physicists and instrument makers evolved a common
base and outward toward a field of application. In this distinction, Bernstein
form of technical pidgin or creole in which to communicate in the development
is distinguishing between the sciences and the Humanities, on the one hand,
of radar and particle detectors. Here, a common problem drives the technical
and the professions on the other;
intercourse. This is the kind of interdisciplinarity found in advanced research
z the third distinction is probably most familiar to the SFL community,
laboratories where research problems require the resources of more than one
between ‘horizontal knowledge structures’, the social sciences and more
intellectual tradition (Shapin 2008).
problematically the Humanities, and ‘hierarchical knowledge structures’,
Ruqaiya Hasan (2005: 51) has usefully distinguished between endotropic
the natural sciences.
theories – those that are ‘centred on their own object of study, isolating it
from all else’, and exotropic theories, which are able to reflect on their object
of study in ‘interaction with other universes of experience’. Such ‘cosmoramic’ The third distinction is thus one among singulars, the first two in different
theories are ‘open’ and able to ‘dialogue with theories of (these) phenomena ways are about the disciplines and the professions, about which Bernstein
provided their mode of engaging with their problematic is not in contradic- clearly worried. I will discuss each in greater detail below before I go on to
tion to their own’ (ibid.). There are for Hasan two conditions for dialogical discuss the external social relations of disciplines, that is, disciplines and their
success. First, the conceptual language must be sufficiently ‘well developed’ communities.
(ibid.) to avert a ‘threat of chaos’ (ibid.); more crucially, ‘The necessary and
sufficient condition for an exotropic theory’s potential for metadialogism is
met when its conceptual syntax is so developed that not only does the theory Forms of Disciplinary Difference
distinguish the different orders of relevant phenomena but it is also able to
specify the nature of this relevance’ (ibid.). A quarrelsome Bernsteinian
The Trivium and the Quadrivium
may well object that the more developed a conceptual syntax, the stronger
the classification or boundary between that syntax and another syntax, making Bernstein deals with this in at least two treatments, one in a 1988 lecture in
dialogism less, not more, likely. But we will gag our quarrelsome colleague Santiago (Bernstein 1990: 133–164) the other in an undated lecture given
for the moment and admit that, quite evidently, Bernstein was dialogically at the University of the Aegean (Bernstein 1996: 82–88). In the first he deals
in tune with Halliday. But how could that have happened? Did it happen with the historical emergence of the disciplines following, he claims, the
in volumes like this one, in casual conversation over a drink in the pub, account given by Durkheim (1977). By Bernstein’s version, the medieval
or some other way, seeping somehow into the conceptual syntax in a more university was founded on a particular combination of abstract Greek thought
sub-conscious way? These are some of the questions that I will explore with Christianity. Christianity represented the tutelage of the inner by the
further below. word; the outer was to be studied on the basis of an orientation conditioned by
Fixing on a common object is to face only the first of many hurdles. I will take a prior moral shaping on the basis of the word. The word was God’s word. The
the object to be disciplinarity, although to my knowledge Bernstein never used account is never crystal clear, but that should not detain us here. The upshot
the word.4 What is meant by this nominalization? All nominalizations condense is that some kind of necessary link, responsible for humanizing knowledge,
constituent elements into an abstract noun, denoting quality. The original was ensured by the particular form taken by the medieval curriculum: first the
object, the discipline, is presumed and endowed with qualities, and the agents disciplines of the inner (the Trivium: grammar, logic and rhetoric) were to
are morphed into a process. Yet for sociologists, it is precisely the delimitation be studied, only then could the disciplines of the outer (the Quadrivium:
of disciplines and the relations between their agents that matter, as we will see. arithmetic (number), geometry (space), astronomy (motion) and music
I will start by recalling the three forays Bernstein makes into distinguishing (time)) be studied. Word before world. In this way was the study of the profane
world subordinated to a prior sacred or moral ordering.
Through Others’ Eyes 17 18 Disciplinarity

The religious foundation of official knowledge was gradually replaced by a One clue lies in the paragraph where Bernstein fast-forwards from the
‘humanizing secular principle’ (Bernstein 1996: 86) over the next 500 years, medieval curriculum and its two specializing discourses to the present. He first
until ‘the last decades of the twentieth century’ (Bernstein 1990: 155) when we repeats the point: ‘The construction of the inner was the guarantee for the
are seeing a progressive weakening of the Trivium’s control, says Bernstein. construction of the outer’ (Bernstein 1996: 86), going on to say, ‘In this
This epistemological-moral balancing act has been upset by the displacement we can find the origin of the professions’ (ibid.). What merits this late entry of
of the humanizing principle by a ‘dehumanizing’ principle, namely the market. the professions to the discussion? In the early medieval universities, alongside
The market severs the link between the inner and the outer, the knower the Trivium and Quadrivium which were exclusively undergraduate courses of
and the known and ‘a new concept of knowledge’ (Bernstein 1996: 87), a truly study, could be found faculties of law, medicine and theology, which alone were
secular and unleavenedly profane one, takes root and threatens the very basis entitled to offer higher degrees, after the preparatory Trivium and Quadrivium,
of our civilization. Bernstein has never sounded so apocalyptic: ‘Knowledge, or liberal arts, had been covered in the Arts Faculty (Lloyd 2009: 178). This
after nearly a thousand years, is divorced from inwardness and literally dehu- is depicted clearly in the frontispiece to Gregor Reisch’s (1503) Margarita
manized. Once knowledge is separated from inwardness, from commitments, Philosophia, which depicts Prudentia (or philosophy) and the seven liberal arts.
from personal dedication, from the deep structure of the self, then people See Figure 2.1.
may be moved about, substituted for each other and excluded from the
market’ (ibid.).
Bernstein in thunderous prophetic mode here sounds suspiciously like the
outraged epigones of the Trivium upon their displacement by the Quadrivium,
ranging from the old humanists, through the ‘mechanisation of the world’
critics after Heidegger, to the petulant constructivists of yesterday and today.
How can that be? What is he really worrying about?
It is as well to recognize that his account differs in certain essential respects
from that of Durkheim on whom he is drawing. Durkheim (1977) asserts that
the disciplines form when the sages of the Dark Ages in Europe begin to con-
struct rules for linguistic forms, which by way of trying to capture forms of
thought attempt at a second remove to capture the forms of things. It is natural
perhaps that the first sages were grammarians, with luminaries like Priscian,
Donatius and Virgil the Asiatic of Toulouse in the seventh century and other
cultish figures. The ‘true spirit of scholarship’ (ibid. p. 56) breaks free from
mysticism in the ninth century with the grammarian Alcuin, inaugurating
the ‘age of grammar’ and the Carolingian Renaissance. Attempts to capture the
rules of debate moved the focus from grammar to dialectical logic with the
Scholastics in the Middle Ages, and from logic to literary form with the Human-
ists not much later. Their triumph was short lived, and in the seventeenth century
the explosion of scientific knowledge moved the balance of power ever more
firmly to the Quadrivium and to the study of the form of things. This was the
moment when the idea of ‘knowledge progress’ was born, an idea Bernstein
will go on to characterize in terms of ‘verticality’ (Muller 2007).
However, Durkheim is far from lamenting this shift. He considers that
science has finally thrown off the shackles of the humanists, and that the sacred
has moved decisively into scientific discourse. Bernstein parts company with
Durkheim when he places the sacred solely with the inner, the profane solely
with the outer. Durkheim in fact celebrates the triumph of science, the
disciplines of the outer. Could there be something else Prophet Bernstein is Figure 2.1 Frontispiece to Gregor Reisch (1503) Margarita Philosophica. Freiburgi:
warning us against? Johann Schott
Through Others’ Eyes 19 20 Disciplinarity

It is plausible to infer from this that Bernstein was not in fact deploring the education (Bernstein 1990: 161–163). At times the description is studiedly
triumph of the sciences, but the triumph of an instrumental turn in the direc- neutral. At others, the anxiety seeps through: whatever the recontextualizing
tion of vocational and professional education – these are effectively Bernstein’s principle regulating the region, it represents a ‘technologization’ of knowledge.
‘outer’, which in market-driven capitalism have become ‘divorced from inward- Moreover, the advent of the outer is predatory: regionalization ‘necessarily
ness’ (Bernstein 1996: 87), not the sciences per se. Indeed pitting the sciences weakens both the autonomous discursive base and the political base of singulars’
against the Humanities would have been quite un-Durkheimian, for as we saw (Bernstein 1996: 66), drives towards ‘greater central administrative control’
above, Durkheim believed just the opposite: ‘Far from its being the case that (ibid.) and introduces greater ‘external regulation’ (ibid.). The primary
between the disciplines which deal with world of persons and those that deal instrument for doing this is the systematic weakening of the classification that
with the world of things there is gulf fixed, the fact is they mutually imply one constructs the coherence of its component singulars. Cuckoo-like it seeks a fun-
another and converge on the same end’ (Durkheim 1977: 337). And again: damental re-arrangement of the university. It is hard not to recognize described
‘As long as science is conceived of in this way, as directed exclusively towards here the zealotry of the more aggressive programmes for interdisciplinarity
the external world and to things which have nothing to do with us, it is imposs- characteristic of the seventies and eighties.
ible that the subject will be humanised and revitalised’ (ibid.). Presuming that The notion of regionalization is powerful yet over-inclusive. Where does it
Bernstein was staying true to Durkheim, it is not unreasonable to infer that he come from? There is no attribution but it is not without its precedents. Were
is thus worrying not about the sciences; he was worried about professional one to glance over at the formalist/rationalist tradition of history of science
and vocational education, which ran the risk, as he presciently saw, of cutting in France, one would see an analogous train of thought represented there.
off the necessary conceptual grounding, its necessary ‘inner’, in its scramble for Canguilhem and Bachelard, who Bernstein does not cite, are progenitors of the
relevance, usefulness, and direct applicability to a field of production. Which tradition celebrated by Althusser, Levi-Strauss, Foucault and Bourdieu who
was precisely Durkheim’s fear in his critique of the pragmatists in general, Bernstein does cite. It was Bachelard who made the distinction, in dissecting
and of Bergson and William James in particular (Durkheim 1983; Young and the disciplinary organization of knowledge, of ‘synthetic rationalisms’ and
Muller 2007). ‘regional rationalisms’ (cited by Canguilhem 1998: 18). It is not hard to recognize
these as cousins to singulars and regions. This is not at all to suggest some kind
of covert or illicit influence. On the contrary, it is an example of the phenomenon
of multiples, the simultaneous discovery of a concept or a theory by one or
Singulars and Regions
more scholars at more or less the same time in widely different places (Merton
A second support for this interpretation is to be found in the distinction 1992). This is not the only consilience Bernstein shares with his trans-channel
between ‘disciplines’ – later ‘singulars’ – and ‘regions’. Singulars refer to cousins, and I will have reason to return to the French connection at greater
the distinctive form that knowledge came to take in the nineteenth-century length below.
university, which became a model for the school subjects of mass schooling, It remains to point to a distinct limitation of the account of regionalization
thus creating a taproot from school to university for the first time. Singulars – given above. That is, all regions – let us say professions – are painted with the
examples given are physics, chemistry, English – establish themselves in the same brush. This cannot be the case, as Bernstein would have been the first to
field of the production of knowledge, they are only about knowledge and they admit. The older professions, like engineering and medicine, have a very well-
refer only to themselves. They control the criteria for the production of developed relation to strong singulars which are by no means de-classified into
privileged texts, the rules of field entry, standards for graduation, licence to regional promiscuity, but retain a strong sense of specialized and specializing
teach or practise and distribute rewards or honours. They are Bernstein’s identity. These professions are strong because they have strong – that is, reason-
paradigm case of strong classification. ably strongly classified – singulars which are however more beholden to the
Regionalization is a process of untethering singulars from their strongly outside than their professionally unaffiliated singular colleagues, but no less
classified mooring, weakening their classification and affiliating them into a accountable inwards to disciplinary good practice. This is in marked contrast
looser or tighter federation. Regions face both inward towards the field of to the newer professions, like tourism and management, that have not (yet),
knowledge production and outward towards a field of practice or production. though to differing degrees, managed to corral a compliant robust set of
Classic examples given are the traditional professions – engineering, medicine, singulars into a federation, instead depending upon de-classification of often
architecture – but Bernstein also mentions the newer generation of professions already weak boundaries to bring putatively relevant weak or non-existent
like tourism, business studies and media. He ends his first treatment of regions with knowledge bases to heel. The weakness of the knowledge bases becomes appar-
an appendix examining teacher education as an aberrant form of professional ent when the distributive rules are unable to select, with any stability, a coherent
Through Others’ Eyes 21 22 Disciplinarity

consensus curriculum to act for the weakly constituted professional field. becoming disconnected and re-aggregated, they might lose the conceptual-
Courses or diplomas at one site consequently display little resemblance to those formative core of the discipline, their inner, leaving the resultant segmental
at other sites, and the production field is as yet too weak to coordinate this into ensemble conceptually, which is to say morally, rudderless.
a stable licensing system (Muller 2009). Heritage and museum studies would be Grammaticality does not help elucidate the structure of other Humanities
an example here. singulars like logic and linguistics, which are disciplines whose object domain is
This makes visible another feature that differentiates professions from each constituted by definition, and whose internal language is not subject to discon-
other. Strong professions do not only have a strong knowledge base; they also firmation in the same way as it is in the empirical and experimental disciplines.
have a strong, that is, a well-organized professional base able to take over the As Fran Christie and Mary Macken-Horarik (2007; this volume) are beginning
functions of criteria-setting and licensing formerly performed by the singulars, to show, ‘verticality’ can indeed help to characterize, and signpost, the ‘systemic-
without any diminution of the power of the singulars, only of some of their functional verticality’ of subject English, but neither verticality nor grammati-
symbolic control functions. To put that another way, strong professions have cality will be much help when it comes to the stylistic and aesthetic dimensions
strong knowledge bases (disciplines) as well as strong professional commu- (see Moore 2010). As Christie and Macken-Horarik show, pressures for relev-
nities. It is rare to find one without the other. As I will argue further below, in ance in the English curriculum, be they for personal growth, cultural heritage
strong professional fields, the academic and professional communities are not and so on have the same flattening effect on the acquisition of the syntax that
only well integrated, but share epistemic norms that coordinate their judge- all but the smartest pupils get to master. As Bernstein showed, this kind of
ments to both academic and practical best practice without putting them at modularization of an incrementally more abstract system of meaning-making
odds with one another. into sets of generic skills is precisely the school curriculum equivalent of region-
So far then I have distinguished professions in terms of the strength, or alization in higher education (Bernstein 1996: 66), and, he might have added,
classification, of their knowledge bases and their external communities. Both of interdisciplinarity in its aggressive, de-classifying mode.
of these require further comment. In the third of his forays into knowledge All the neo-Durkheimians, including Merton (1992), Bourdieu (2004), Collins
types, Bernstein deals with the first. (1998) as well as Bernstein relate the form of organization of the symbolic
system of a discipline to its form of internal social organization, its insulation
from influence from outside and its consequent level of autonomy. The degree
of this form of control is regulated by what Bernstein called verticality,
Verticality and its Others
what Merton called ‘codification’6 and what Bourdieu called their degree of
Bernstein’s account of vertical and horizontal discourses is by now well enough ‘formalisation’ or ‘mathematisation’ (Bourdieu 2004: 58). These cognate con-
known in the SFL community not to require rehearsal here. In Muller (2007) cepts condition the internal division of labour of the discipline, the level of
I discussed the principal way that disciplines differ in terms of their internal interdependence of the members, their ability to achieve ‘closure’ (Bourdieu)
structure as ‘verticality’, that is, the way that the internal theoretical apparatus or strong insulation of their boundaries (Bernstein) and consequently the
of the discipline progresses. I also raised there the question as to whether degree of autonomy from external interference they are able to achieve.
verticality applied to all the disciplines of the inner, the Humanities, since fields It is at this point that our previously gagged Bernsteinian insists on having
like history or literature did not advance vertically,5 either strongly or weakly, in his say: ‘can we not see’, he asks, ‘that there is something of a non sequitur here
any meaningful sense, even though others clearly did – like logic or linguistics. in Bernstein’s accounts of knowledge insulation and hybridity?’ Let us take
Bernstein’s second criterion, grammaticality or the way that internal theories of discipline X, which has over time developed a reasonable degree of verticality
disciplines ‘read’ their domain of worldly objects, is only a help in some cases. or its equivalent, has developed a certain set of internal epistemic norms
History, for example, though possessing a discernible tradition of historio- adhered to by most disciplinary adepts and that has as a consequence developed
graphical dispute, does not have theories on any widespread scale of consensus. an effective degree of autonomy and self-rule built on strong disciplinary
Nevertheless, there are strong rules of grammaticality, in this case rules of evid- identities. Why then would it suddenly become vulnerable to weakening from
ence and grounds for demonstration, even though these might be periodically without? What in its make-up makes a once-impregnable disciplinary empire
challenged. These rules generate strong epistemic norms, which bestow a high vulnerable to either regional or interdisciplinary external weakening? What
measure of self-control upon the internal community of historians, and allow boundary-dissolving trumps can suddenly be deployed? What is the enemy
them to police their own protocols of truth, despite strong current pressures to without that Bernstein so fears? The market – mere material reward – seems too
regionalize the singular into coalitions of relevance like ‘museum’ or ‘heritage cynical an answer. Or is it?
studies’. This, as will be recalled, is the Bernsteinian apprehension, that in
Through Others’ Eyes 23 24 Disciplinarity

It seems clear that we must distinguish between two kinds of interdisciplinarity. differentiation, many levels of hierarchy which are explicated in normal schol-
The first is predatory or negational interdisciplinarity, that seeks to undermine arly commerce by citation rates and more eventfully by the award of honours
disciplinary boundaries as an end in itself, as a means to achieve some pre- and prizes, a high degree of complexity and consequently autonomy, policed by
sumed pedagogical good (‘generic skills’, ‘modularity’) or seeks to re-federate what Durkheim calls formalistic and restitutive regulations (Durkheim 1973).
them in the name of an external instrumental principle of relevance (‘relevant I will probe these regulations a little further below. This is contrasted with
to the workplace’, or ‘community engagement’; see Chen et al. this volume for mechanical solidarity, which has much less internal differentiation and emphas-
a discussion of such a programme). Bernstein seems to have worried about izes similarity and low autonomy. On the other hand, disciplinary sociality
both these predatory movements. Empirical studies here have been scanty, but is not only organic. It is also punctuated by rituals of mechanical solidarity –
both the theory and those studies we do have would indicate that predatory conferences, meetings of peers and so on – which generate a sense of renewal
interdisciplinarity would be resisted to the degree that the disciplines con- and effervescence. In other words, disciplines are marked by both rituals of
cerned are strong. Individual historians may have gone into ‘heritage studies’ similarity and rituals of differentiation. This translates into the peculiar ambi-
but this has not weakened history itself, which continues to flourish in part to guity of disciplinary membership, where everyone is a peer, but some peers are
train the future ‘heritage’ workers, but also because it is a strong discipline in more equal than others.
the sense of strong grammaticality, strong epistemic norms and strong internal Scholars are necessarily driven by what Bourdieu calls the illusio of disinterest:
self-regulation. Where interdisciplinary teaching programmes have been set ‘to be in a scientific field is to be placed in conditions in which one has an
up with such disciplines, and these strong disciplines feel threatened by the interest in disinterestedness’ (Bourdieu 2004: 52). This is not optional; to be
regionalizing thrust, it will either be resisted – the discipline may successfully a recognized scholar demands ‘unconstrained submission to the imperative of
refuse to participate – or the programme will become internally balkanized, disinterestedness’ (ibid. p. 51). As Bernstein would have said, this is the inner
with the disciplines retaining an identifiable shape and identity within the connection to serious scholarly work, which is its constitutive bulwark against
teaching activities of the programme7 (Ensor 2001). It is doubtful (though one external manipulation. Merton (2001) has shown how Puritanism in seven-
cannot be categorical) whether strong disciplines that still have vibrant research teenth-century England acted as a powerful spur to science, by making its inner
programmes at the cutting edge can be completely undermined by predatory explicit. A virtuous marriage between experimental empiricism and veneration
interdisciplinarity. of God meant that science could be presented as simply revealing the glory of
By the same token, creative or productive interdisciplinarity occurs when it is the works by His hand: as Robert Boyle said: ‘our utmost Science can but give us
driven by a bona fide intellectual problem which draws together a group of a juster veneration of his Omniscience’ (quoted in Merton 2001, p. 103), or as
creative scholars who pool their disciplinary energies in one way or another. John Ray put it, science is simply making visible ‘divine Reason, running like a
If this proves to be a stable basis for a new domain of problem solving, it will Golden Vein, through the whole Leaden Mine of Brutal Nature’ (ibid. p. 104).
morph into a new region, which if it proves stable and productive over time will In Puritan England, thus, there was no conflict between science and religion;
finally become a discipline in its own right. indeed, Puritanism both drove science, as an obligation to venerate His work,
All of which helps to make clear that disciplinarity and interdisciplinarity are and provided an ironclad justification for its disinterested pursuit.
not two different things. (See Moore this volume for related discussion.) This is Of course, the Puritan impulse has long since been secularized, but disinter-
probably why Bernstein never used the latter term. All knowledge formations, est has remained a constitutive norm. This does not mean that scholars are not
be they singular or regional, must have a certain quality of disciplinarity in competitive, or that they don’t vie for personal glory. They do. Its principal
order to qualify as a knowledge region. A next question then arises: what is form is the struggle for priority, to be first with a discovery or novelty. The norm
it that all their members have in common, and how did they get it? What of disinterest frequently leads scholars to disavow this thirst for priority, which
drives the common enterprise? What drives fertile disciplinarity and interdisci- somehow seems uncollegial, unscholarly, but the now-secularized obligation to
plinarity alike? be productive has led to many a tussle for priority, often quite bitter. Cavendish,
Watt and Lavoisier argued over who had first discovered that water was not an
element; Newton and Leibnitz argued over who invented the calculus; Janet
Social Life in Disciplines contested Freud’s claim to have invented psychoanalysis. These are but a few of
the disputes over priority that animate the histories of invention. The German
On the one hand, disciplinary sociality is an example of what Durkheim called language has a word for this commonplace phenomenon: Prioritätsstreit (Merton
organic solidarity, that is, it is characterized by a high degree of internal 1992: 289).
There is a specific reason why disputes over priority are so frequent. Merton
(1992) has distinguished between ‘singletons’ – individual discoveries that can
Through Others’ Eyes 25 26 Disciplinarity

unambiguously be ascribed to one person, and ‘multiples’ – discoveries that by ‘interaction ritual chains’ into networks of connections. Collins’ definition
are either discovered at the same time, or are periodically discovered and of an interaction ritual is that it depends on face-to-face interaction. Consensus
‘re-discovered’ by different people at different times and places. Some of these depends on it: ‘Intellectual life hinges on face-to-face situations because inter-
are poignant in the extreme, none more so than the case of Darwin and action ritual can only take place on this level’ (ibid. p. 26). Nevertheless, Collins
Wallace. It is well known that Darwin, though a humble man, prized what he elsewhere is less emphatic, and by the end of his introductory chapter he is
calls in his autobiography ‘the bauble of fame’, and says in a letter to Lyell referring to ‘interaction rituals inside their head’ and ‘imaginary rituals’ (ibid.
that ‘I shall certainly be vexed if anyone were to publish my doctrines before p. 52), and to the ‘vicarious community of the mind’ (ibid. p. 34), hence the
me’. Lyell tried unsuccessfully to hurry him up. In June 1858, Wallace sent coalitions ‘in’ the mind. By the end of the book, the ‘community’ has become
Darwin a manuscript which he recognized would pip him to the post. Darwin ‘invisible’ (ibid. p. 790).
felt crushed. The scientific community in the form of Lyell and Hooker then The same ambivalence can be seen in the literature around the more com-
arranged for a joint presentation to the Linnean Society, prefacing the publica- monly used term in the sociology of science, the ‘invisible college’. This term
tion of a joint paper by ‘Messrs. C. Darwin and A. Wallace’. Subsequently each was originally coined in the seventeenth century by members of the newly
of them tried to outdo the other in attributing the greater credit to the other formed Royal Society to refer to their loosely affiliated status outside the formal
(Merton 1992: 289). educational establishment. It was taken up by Price (1971) to denote elite
The recurrence of multiples leads Merton to a bold hypothesis: ‘the hypo- mutually interacting groups, what Collins and Evans (2002) refer to as the
thesis states that all scientific discoveries are in principle multiples, including discipline’s ‘core set’, who combine to exchange information. The upper limit
those that on the surface appear to be singletons’ (ibid. p. 356). We can glibly for such an invisible college for Price was 100 members. Other writers have
say that this is the product of disciplinarity, that it is because all peers in a dis- taken up the concept, and the definition of the invisible college has become
cipline share a disciplinary identity, that they ‘face the same way’, and ‘cover the rather loose (Zuccala 2006). Nevertheless, the central question remains:
same cognitive ground’. But that hardly explains it. After all, we are talking what produces the meeting of minds, from the consensus in the core, to the
about radical novelty here, where the step into the unknown, or the next known, tighter consensus at the frontier, to the recurrent and steady appearance of
has still to be taken. Cole (1983, 1994) distinguishes between the core of a dis- multiples?
cipline, the repository of knowledge accepted by all disciplinary members, and It is instructive to return to Kuhn. He may well be remembered best for the
the frontier, where researchers labour to produce something that will make it epic meeting at Bedford Hall at the University of London in July 1965 where he
into the core. Very little of it ever will. Cole (1983) goes on to say that when matched wits with Popper, Lakatos and Feyerabend. Did Bernstein attend?
people refer to disciplinary consensus they are referring to consensus in the Certainly he never refers to Kuhn. The reason may become clearer below.
core; and that here, there is larger consensus in what we would call the hier- Perhaps Kuhn’s most controversial claim was that paradigms were incommen-
archical disciplines than in the horizontal ones. However, Cole’s research also surable, which means that there is no rational way for choosing between rival
shows that at the frontier, the social sciences display as much consensus as do paradigms. This means in turn that choice of paradigm is a subjective decision.
the natural sciences (ibid. p. 136), and that ‘consensus at the research frontier If there is no rational way to choose between paradigms, disciplinary consensus
is created by social processes which tend to be similar in the various scientific is just a collective subjective decision, what Lakatos (1970: 78) derisively called
fields’ (ibid.). Cole’s example was sociology. My own investigations have shown ‘mob psychology’. Why the best epistemic judgement cannot be decided simply
that peer judgements about the relative contributions of others in the fields of by consensual aggregation can be illustrated by the old philosophical problem
psychology, law and history are remarkably stable (Muller forthcoming). of Socrates and the Athenians: just because the Athenians voted against Socrates
How is this possible? What is it that produces this common cast of creative does not make Socrates wrong and the Athenians right. As Gutting (2003: 63)
thought such that different investigators arrive independently at the same says, this is like making truth dependent on ‘the majority vote at the next
intellectual terminus? To answer this brings us to one of the deepest theoretical epistemic town meeting’.
fissures in the sociology of knowledge. Foucault’s teacher Canguilhem was similarly dismissive about Kuhn’s position
which he too said was ‘social psychology’ rather than ‘epistemology’. A social
psychological account (e.g. consensual choice of paradigm) is unable to
explain ‘how the truth of a theory is to be understood’ (Canguilhem 1998: 13)
Consensus or Epistemic Norms? The French Connection
or to account for scientific advance. Kuhn’s social psychological solution is
Karl Maton and Rob Moore (2010) sub-title their recent collection ‘coalitions mimicked in the micro-sociology of knowledge through the insistence that
of the mind’, after Randall Collins’ (1998) slightly different ‘coalitions in the
mind’. Collins develops a theory of intellectual centres that are linked together
Through Others’ Eyes 27 28 Disciplinarity

scholarly agreement must depend on consensus, and that this consensus must Hanging Together
be produced in face-to-face interaction. This is well exemplified by Michelle
Lamont’s (2009) recent account of the generation of scholarly agreement Where does this leave interdisciplinarity? Let us go back to SFL and the
in peer review panels reviewing interdisciplinary grant applications. Her Bernsteinians. I wondered idly at the beginning of the chapter whether
explanation of consensus reached is that this can only happen if peers are Bernstein and Halliday had talked themselves onto the same wavelength over
given opportunity to forge a consensus in face-to-face argument. This is coffee or something more convivial. If the answer provided in this chapter has
‘epistemic townhallism’. any merit, the answer would be no; they ‘got’ it at a deeper level of intellectual
What then is the alternative? Bachelard and Canguilhem make their point of consilience. In the idiom of the paper, they shared certain epistemic norms,
departure the need to re-capture rationality from the strictures of mere shared which meant that they worked with concepts that had an elective affinity, even
opinion. Their recourse is to social norms, not consensus, as the ultimate epi- if these did different work in their respective explanatory frameworks. What
stemological category (Canguilhem 1998, 1991). But what is a norm? A norm might these be?
is a regulative principle that produces continuity for grounds of judgement. I assume a background normative consilience – call it critical rationalism
All disciplines operate by virtue of a set of internal norms. These render a for want of a better term – which produces a mutual intellectual sympathy, but
framework that provides grounds for judging veracity. Veracity is embedded I will discuss the consilience here mainly at the level of concepts. Let us take
in concepts which must be distinguished from theories. ‘Organization’ and Bernstein’s concept of ‘code’, which models social contexts as semiotic clusters
‘adaptation’ are concepts; ‘evolution’ is a theory. ‘Code’ is a concept: ‘systemic- that evoke and require interactional recognition and realization practices
functional linguistics’ is a theory. The same concepts can function in different across a cline of less specialized and more specialized. The concept of ‘code’ was
theories, and they can embed improvements on knowledge independently of probably adapted from the Hallidayan concept of ‘text in context’ (Bernstein
theories: ‘Concepts bridge the discontinuity between successive paradigms and 1996: 57). The ‘Sydney School’ concept of ‘genre types’ is in turn a schematic
allow us to speak of truths persisting from theory to theory and of progress in structure of recognition/realization practices elaborating and modeling the
the sense of the increase of persisting truths over time’ (Gutting 2003: 57). Bernsteinian code cline (Martin and Rose 2008: 16). Each genre type, there-
Norms thus regulate progressive refinement for a particular community. It is, as fore, in terms of a ‘generalised structure of abstractions’ it evokes (ibid. p. 228)
Collins said, literally like having a conversation not only with an ‘imaginary varies from less to more abstract.
audience’ (Collins 1998: 52), but indeed an imaginary conversation with friends So far so good. There are points of incongruence, though. The Bernstein
and comrades, no matter how competitive you may be with them. concept of code sketched a single cline from commonsense to uncommon-
A consequence follows from this view. Disciplinary members do not have to sense. ‘Sydney School’ genre adapts this by describing the cline within both
meet face-to-face in order to judge from the same norm set: the reality of mul- time-structured genres (from personal recounts to narratives and histories and
tiples in far-flung times and places illustrates this clearly enough. With access non-time-structured genres (such as reports and explanations, ibid. p. 167)).
to the same concept set, it should not be surprising that Darwin and Wallace This means that there are degrees of abstraction within each macrogenre, in
converged on the theory of evolution at almost exactly the same time. The both history and science, for example. But where does that leave Bernsteinian
luckless Kuhn (1970) tried belatedly in his Postscript to change the term knowledge structure? It would not add to the SFL description to label the one
paradigm to ‘disciplinary matrix’, a term closer to norms, but it never stuck.8 ‘vertical’ and the other ‘horizontal’, as Bernstein would do. Why not? Because
Pace the micro-sociological tradition in science studies, the intellectual home knowledge structure is describing variations of theoretical subsumptability
of aspirational interdisciplinarity, patterns of rational construction depend within the context of knowledge production, not variations of context specific-
on impersonal norms that are the regulative basis of organic, not mechanical ity requiring variations of code/genre modality in the field of knowledge repro-
solidarity. Which is not to say that the effervescent rituals of mechanical duction and acquisition. In other words, codes and genres are designed to
solidarity aren’t refreshing and inspiring; they are just not where the norms elucidate the acquisition of the core of a knowledge field; knowledge structures
come from. In a study of academic judgement in anonymous peer panels in are designed to elucidate the addition of new knowledge to the knowledge
law, psychology and history, I have shown that local and international peers field at its periphery (Cole 1983, 1994). They are both about disciplinarity, just
rate in substantially similar ways within the ‘disciplinary matrix’ (Muller, different levels of it.
forthcoming). They had never had the opportunity to get together to forge The two different starting points become wonderfully blurred in work in
the basis for this common judgement. It is a prior institution of regularity both traditions describing qualification ladders. Let me briefly take my own
constitutive of their disciplinary identity. work and that of Jim Martin and David Rose. Consider my Table 2.1 below
(Muller 2009: 218) compared to Figure 2.2, from the work of Martin and
Rose (2008: 227).
Through Others’ Eyes 29 30 Disciplinarity

Table 2.1 Occupational fields and knowledge, adapted from Muller, 2009: 218. Rose and Martin are extrapolating their abstraction cline into respectively a
Particular General Professions Research-based knowledge hierarchy, a school and university curriculum hierarchy, linked
occupations occupations work in turn to a hierarchy of the division of labour. Mine, extrapolating from an
analysis of knowledge structures, carves the knowledge domain up into four
Labour E.g. Travel agents, E.g. Engineering E.g. Engineers, Academics,
market hospitality workers trades (fitters, lawyers, architects, researchers, new different kinds of common/uncommonsense combinations which translate
boilermakers), HR managers, white collar welfare into four different curriculum and qualification pathways. The important thing
HR operators doctors, teachers, and service workers about this variant is that the pathways are only partly articulable (see also
social workers Gamble 2009). As curriculum, they do not form a single continuum of
Knowledge Largely practical Practical Applied theory Largely theoretical variation. It seems that Martin and Rose’s does.
Knowledge knowledge plus plus practical progression of These extrapolations are clearly affiliated to one another, and we will
some applied experience the discipline undoubtedly be able to bring them into alignment with some work. Putting
theory
them up here is not to emphasize their differences. Rather, it is to illustrate
Induction On-the-job- Apprenticeship External Internal internship some features of interdisciplinarity. The first is that we are clearly extrapolating
training, some internship (e.g. (e.g. postdoctoral off a common parent stem, namely Bernstein. But while Martin and Rose
apprenticeship pupilage, work, tenure)
interleave their adaptation with SFL and discourse semantics, for example,
housemanship)
I am extrapolating from a later version of the conceptual family. No wonder
Regulation Moderate to weak Moderate Strong sectoral Moderate to strong we end up in slightly different places. The second is that the more sophist-
sectoral regulation sectoral regulation (e.g. disciplinary
icated the concept, the more it has to be worked on – adapted, extrapolated
(e.g. hairdresser’s regulation (e.g. board exams) regulation (peer
practical test) trade test) review) and recontextualized – to become fecund in a different disciplinary context.
Most usually it can’t just be borrowed across ‘as is’. A direct borrowing can
have helpful resonances, as in Christie and Macken-Horarik’s (2007) use
EDUCATION ECONOMIC PRODUCTION of systemic-functional ‘verticality’, used, it seems to me, in the sense of a
translating science ‘generalised structure of abstraction’ (Rose and Martin 2008: 228). Without
translating experience into industrial
of reality into science production
careful recontextualization, I suspect borrowing will mostly be explanatorily
Post-graduate barren.
research
I would speculate that, in the end, conceptual consilience goes only so
supply of research
far, and that their embedding theories must also eventually be properly
leading to the production
of new knowledge Undergraduate professional scientists understood for continued fruitful intercourse. The SFL community is
training training
developing new
probably far better versed in Bernsteinian sociology than vice versa. I speak
leading to matriculation supply of applied
scientific now mainly for the sociologists: without dedicated reading groups to master
processes
into ternary science Senior secondary science
scientists & engineers the rich canopy of SFL, we are not going to go much further with SFL
faculties (& TAFE subjects
certificate) designing &
in future beyond the occasional reporting on conceptual consiliences as
leading to senior supply of qualified
managing they arise, as they surely will. It will require dedicated tilling to make them
Years 9--10 technology
science subjects:
(elite) themes of
technicians &
paraprofessionals
productive.
biology, chemistry,
physics, geology
science
constructing &
Interdisciplinarity by this account is premised on the prior consilience of
supply of skilled
maintaining epistemological approach between the two traditions, one sociological the
Years 7--8 technology
leading to
(general)
operators other systemic-functional linguistic. It is also premised on a prior epistemic
acquisition of learning to
basic scientific do science understanding about how the social world, its institutions and agents are
knowledge operating
supply of de-skilled technology regulated and ordered. In other words, though some of the methods
process workers will differ, as will the theories, there are several concepts which quilt the
leading from two disciplines together. After that, it will take some dedicated recontextual-
commonsense
translating science izing work to make them explanatorily productive in their adoptive dis-
learnt in the home
into curriculum
& primary school ciplinary home. This is the labour of interdisciplinarity. I have no doubt

Figure 2.2 Stages in science education and levels in industry, from J. R. Martin
and D. Rose (2008) Genre Relations. Mapping Culture. Equinox, p. 227
Through Others’ Eyes 31 32 Disciplinarity

whatever that there is much to be gained from cultivating this enduring Fleck in the continental rationalist manner called ‘thought collectives’. Kuhn calls
consilience. these rather disparagingly ‘hypostatised fictions’.

References
Notes
Abbott, A. (2001), Chaos of Disciplines. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
1
Much the same happened in the domain of pedagogy: education, hitherto the
Bernstein, B. (1990), The Structuring of Pedagogic Discourse, vol 4, Class, Codes &
‘one best system’ (Tyack 1974), was only named ‘traditional’ in the early twentieth
Control. London: Routledge.
century with Dewey in order to open the discursive space for ‘progressive’ ped-
— (1996), Pedagogy, Symbolic Control and Identity. London: Taylor & Francis.
agogy, another spectral construct living more in dreams and wishes than in their
— (2000), Pedagogy, Symbolic Control and Identity (revised edn). Oxford: Rowman &
realization (Muller 2001).
Littlefield.
2
This refers to the revolutionary slogan of the radical students in Paris in 1968. It is
Bloom, B., Engelhart, M., Furst, E., Hill, W. and Krathwohl, D. (1956), Taxonomy of
meant to denote that under the thin veneer of civilization lies untrammelled nature.
Educational Objectives, vol 1, The Cognitive Domain. New York: McKay Publishers.
3
This odd way with knowledge is to be found also in another milestone text, that of
Boghossian, P. (2006), Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism. Oxford:
Bloom et al. (1956). Here, in Bloom’s taxonomy, ‘knowledge’ refers to rote facts,
Clarendon Press.
and sits at the lowest rung of Bloom’s cognitive hierarchy, below ‘comprehension’,
Bourdieu, P. (2004), Science of Science and Reflexivity (trans. R. Nice). Cambridge:
‘application’, ‘analysis’, ‘synthesis’ and ‘evaluation’.
Polity Press.
4
In the only reference to ‘discipline’ in his last book, Bernstein revealingly says: ‘It
Canguilhem, G. (1991), The Normal and the Pathological (intro. M. Foucault). New
may be of interest here to contrast Durkheim and Foucault’s concept of discipline.
York: Zone Books.
In Foucault discipline equals the death of the subject through the annihilation of
— (1998), Ideology and Rationality in the History of the Life Sciences. Cambridge, MA:
transgression in whose act the subject lives. In Durkheim discipline equals life
The MIT Press.
for without it there is no social, no coordination of time, space and purpose.
Chandler, J. (2009), Introduction: Doctrines, disciplines, discourse, departments.
Transgression through its punishment revivifies the social . . . My work follows this
Critical Inquiry 35: 729–746.
approach’ (Bernstein 2000: 206).
Christie, F. and Macken-Horarik (2007), Building verticality in subject English, in
5
A strong ‘disciplinary’ lobby in history teaching has mounted a challenge to this
F. Christie and J. R. Martin (eds), Language, Knowledge and Pedagogy: Functional
assumption: ‘People often assume that history is a “common-sense” subject that
Linguistic and Sociological Perspectives. London: Continuum.
lacks the “progression” of ideas to be found in science or maths. This may be
Cole, S. (1983), The hierarchy of the sciences? American Journal of Sociology 89(1):
a mistake. Research over the past 30 years suggests both that history may be
111–139.
counterintuitive, and that we may be able to talk seriously about progression in key
— (1994), Why sociology doesn’t make progress like the natural sciences.
ideas about the discipline’ (Lee and Howson 2009: 219). They are pointing here
Sociological Forum 9(2): 133–154.
neither to facts nor skills, but to something they call ‘historical consciousness’.
Collins, H. and Evans, R. (2002), The third wave of science studies: Studies of
They might do well to refer to genre theory (Martin and Rose 2008).
expertise and experience. Social Studies of Science 32(2): 235–296.
6
‘Codification refers to the consolidation of empirical knowledge into succinct and
Collins, R. (1998), The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change.
interdependent theoretical formulations. The different sciences and the various
Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press.
specialities within them differ in the extent to which they are codified’ (Merton
Durkheim, E. (1973), On Morality and Society: Selected Writings. Chicago: The
1992: 507).
University of Chicago Press.
7
‘We have an example in my university of the kind of thing that can result from
— (1977), The Evolution of Educational Thought: Lectures on the Formation and
top-down interdisciplinary pressures from the administration, a course in “poetry
Development of Secondary Education in France. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
and math”. It is the darling of the deans et al., who love to cite it when the topic of
— (1983; 1955), Pragmatism and Sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University
interdisciplinarity comes up. What goes on in this course? One half of each class is
Press.
taken up by an English prof discussing a poem and the other half by a math prof
Ensor, P. (2001), Education programme planning in South Africa: Three institu-
discussing a mathematical concept; despite the possibilities one can think of, no
tional case studies, in M. Breier (ed.), Curriculum Restructuring in Higher Education
interchange between the two halves takes place’. From a weblog on ‘Disciplinarity’,
in Post-apartheid South Africa. Pretoria: Centre for Science Development.
posted by Mel Wiebe, wiebm@qsilver.quensu.ca, posted 7 August 2001.
Fleck, L. (1979), Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact (trans. T. Trenn and
8
In his Foreword to Ludwig Fleck’s (1979) late published classic, Kuhn draws
R. Merton, foreword T. Kuhn). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
attention to the difference between what he called ‘scientific networks’ and what
Foucault, M. (1971), Foucault responds/ 2. Diacritics 1(2): 60.
— (1972), The Archaeology of Knowledge. London: Tavistock Publications.
Through Others’ Eyes 33 34 Disciplinarity

— (1981), The order of discourse, in R. Young (ed.), Untying the Text: A Post- Muller, J. (2001), Progressivism redux: Ethos, policy, pathos, in A. Kraak and
structuralist Reader. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. M. Young (eds), Education in Retrospect: Policy and Implementation since 1990.
Galison, P. (1997), Image and Logic: A Material Culture of Microphysics. Chicago: The Pretoria: HSRC Press.
Chicago University Press. — (2007), On splitting hairs: Hierarchy, knowledge and the school curriculum, in
Gamble, J. (2009), Knowledge and practice in curriculum and assessment, Pretoria: F. Christie and J. Martin (eds), Language, Knowledge and Pedagogy: Functional
UMALUSI. Linguistic and Sociological Perspectives. London: Continuum.
Gutting, G. (2003), Thomas Kuhn and French philosophy of science, in T. Nickles — (2008), La tension essentielle: essai sur la sociology du savoir, in D. Frandji and
(ed.), Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. P. Vitale (eds), Actualité de Basil Bernstein: Savoir, Pédagogie et Société. Rennes:
Halliday, M. and Martin, J. (1993), Writing Science: Literacy and Discursive Power. University of Rennes Press, 182–191.
London: The Falmer Press. — (2009), Forms of knowledge and curriculum coherence. Journal of Education and
Hasan, R. (2005), Language, Society and Consciousness: The Collected Works of Ruqaiya Work, 22(3): 203–224.
Hasan. London: Equinox. — (forthcoming), Social life in disciplines.
Hunt, L. (1994), The virtues of disciplinarity. Eighteenth Century Studies 28(1): Norris, C. (2000), Minding the Gap: Epistemology & Philosophy of Science in the Two
1–7. Traditions. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.
Krishnan, A. (2009), What are academic disciplines? Some observations on the — (2006), On Truth & Meaning: Language, Logic & the Grounds of Belief. London:
disciplinarity versus interdisciplinarity debate. National Centre for Research Continuum.
Methods Working Paper, University of Southampton. Price, D. de Solla (1971), Some remarks on elitism in information and the invisible
Kuhn, T. S. (1970; 1962), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (revised edn). Chicago: college phenomenon in science. Journal of the American Society for Information
The University of Chicago Press. Science 22: 74–75.
Lakatos, I. (1970), The methodology of scientific research programmes, in — (1986), Little Science, Big Science and Beyond. New York: Columbia University
I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Press.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Shapin, S. (2008), The Scientific Life: A Moral History of a Late Modern Vocation.
Lamont, M. (2009), How Professors Think: Inside the Curious World of Academic Chicago: The Chicago University Press.
Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Steiner, G. (1971), Steiner responds to Foucault. Diacritics 1(2): 59.
Lee, P. and Howson, J. (2009), ‘Two out of five did not know that Henry V111 had Tyack, D. (1974), The One Best System. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
five wives’: History education, historical literacy and historical consciousness, in Young, M. and Muller, J. (2007), Truth and truthfulness in the sociology of
L. Symcox and A. Wilschut (eds), History Standards: The Problem of the Canon and educational knowledge. Theory & Research in Education 5(2): 173–201.
the Future of Teaching History. Charlotte: Information Age Publishers, Inc. Zuccala, A. (2006), Modeling the invisible college. Journal of the American Society for
Lloyd, G. (2009), Disciplines in the Making: Cross-cultural Perspectives on Elites, Learning Information Science and Technology 57(2): 152–168.
and Innovation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Martin, J. (2007), Construing knowledge, in F. Christie and J. Martin (eds),
Language, Knowledge and Pedagogy: Functional Linguistic and Sociological
Perspectives. London: Continuum.
Martin, J. and Rose, D. (2008), Genre Relations: The Mapping of Culture. London:
Equinox.
Maton, K. and Moore, R. (2010) (eds), Social Realism, Knowledge and the Sociology of
Education: Coalitions of the Mind. London: Continuum.
Merton, R. K. (1992), The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations.
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
— (2001; 1970), Science, Technology and Society in Seventeenth-Century England (revised
edn). New York: Howard Fertig.
Messer-Davidow, E., Shumway, D. and Sylvan, D. (1993) (eds), Knowledges:
Historical and Critical Studies in Disciplinarity. Charlottesville: University Press
of Virginia.
Moore, R. (2010), Knowledge structures and the canon; a preference for judgments,
in K. Maton and R. Moore (eds), Social Realism, Knowledge and the Sociology of
Education: Coalitions of the Mind. London: Continuum.
Moran, T. (2001), Interdisciplinarity: The New Critical Idiom. London: Routledge.

You might also like