You are on page 1of 36

This is a fragment of the author’s manuscript with corresponding page numbers of the published

version. The publisher’s version may be available through the publisher’s web site or your
institution’s library.

Igor M. Arievitch

BEYOND THE BRAIN: AN AGENTIVE ACTIVITY PERSPECTIVE ON MIND,


DEVELOPMENT AND LEARNING

CHAPTER 2: THE MIND IS NOT IN THE BRAIN

Citation for the book: Arievitch, I. M. (2017). Beyond the Brain: An Agentive Activity
Perspective on Mind, Development, and Learning. Rotterdam/Boston: Sense Publishers.

Publisher’s link: https://www.sensepublishers.com/catalogs/bookseries/bold-visions-in-


educational-research/beyond-the-brain/

TABLE OF CONTENTS of the book

Acknowledgements………………………………………………………………………………vii
Chapter 1: Introduction…………………………………………………………………………..1
The Goals and Starting Points of the Book…………………………………………………1
The Structure and Main Topics of the Book………………………………………………..4
Chapter 2: The Mind Is Not in the Brain…………………………………....................................7
A New Wave of Brainism in Psychology and Education…………………………………...7
Recent Criticism of Brainism……………………………………………………………….9
Summary of Arguments Against Brainism and “Mindless Neuroscience”………………..20
Chapter 3: The Mind Is the Form of the Individual’s Activity: The Emergence of the Active
Agent……………………………………………………………………………………………..25
Historical Context of Research on Non-Automaticity…………………………………….28
James’s Concept of the “Efficacity of Consciousness”……………………………..30
Dewey’s Notion of Coordination of Self-Guided Activity………………………….31
An Activity-Based Approach to Mind…………………………………………………….33
Background of Galperin’s Work……………………………………………………33
The Concept of Orienting Activity………………………………………………….35
The New Type of Causality…………………………………………………………39
The Mind is the Embodied Agent’s Activity, not the Brain Functioning…………...40
Comparison to Other Recent Attempts to Introduce an Agentive Approach to Mind…….42
Chapter 4: The Developmental Trajectory of Cultural Mediation (I): From Joint Activity to
Semiotic Mediation………………………………………………………………………………55
Approaches to Semiotic Mediation………………………………………………………..57
Vygotsky on Semiotic Mediation………………………………………………………….60
Taking a Broader View on Mediation: Pre-history of Semiotic Mediation……………….64
From Earlier Forms of Cultural Mediation to Semiotic Mediation:The “Magic of Signs” 72
Chapter 5: The Developmental Trajectory of Cultural Mediation (II): From Semiotically
Mediated Activity to Psychological Process…………………………………………………….77
The Internalization Controversy…………………………………………………………..77
An Activity-based Approach to Internalization…………………………………………...81
Focusing on External Activity………………………………………………………81
Mental Processes as Activities………………………………………………………86
Mental Processes are the Agent’s External Actions………………………………...91
Demystifying the Process of Mediation by Cognitive Tools……………………………...95
Reframing the Mediation Research…………………………………………………95
Cognitive Tools are Directed toward External Objects, not “Inward”……………...99
Broadening the Non-Mentalist Framework………………………………………………103
Neo-Piagetian Theorizing of Mental Processes and Internalization……………….104
The Human Agent: Adapting Organism or Inherently Social Actor?......................106
“Internal” Processes as Acting with Social Meanings…………………………….109
Chapter 6: The Quality of Cognitive Tools and Development of the Mind…………………..115
Development and Learning: The Relevance of Culturally Evolved Cognitive Tools……116
The Role of Learning in Cognitive Development………………………………………..120
Types of Learning………………………………………………………………….120
Traditional learning………………………………………………………….121
Systemic-empirical learning…………………………………………………123
Systemic-theoretical learning………………………………………………..125
Types of Learning and Cognitive Development…………………………………...132
Implications for Developmental Studies…………………………………………………137
Developmental Teaching and Learning………………………………………………….140
An Illustration: Bloom’s Taxonomy from the DTL Perspective…………………..142
Chapter 7: Conclusion: Overcoming the Contemplative Fallacy by Adopting the Agentive
Activity Perspective…………………………………………………………………………….147

References……………………………………………………………………………………...153

*****
--- Page 7 ---

CHAPTER 2

THE MIND IS NOT IN THE BRAIN

A NEW WAVE OF BRAINISM IN PSYCHOLOGY AND EDUCATION

This book is not about the brain or the role of brain studies in psychology and education. Instead,
it is about understanding the mind as a property of the active agent and as a form in itself of the
agent’s external activity, as well as the critical educational implications of such an understanding.
So why start with a review of recent criticism of the “brain-based” approach that claims to provide
full and complete explanations of consciousness, behavior and learning exclusively in terms of
brain functioning? The first reason is my strong belief that the steadily rising wave of “brainism”
coming from the “neuromarketing” branch of neuroscience, by generating misguided expectations
while at the same time depleting valuable resources in these disciplines, poses a seriously
detrimental threat to psychology, and in particular to education. This “brainism” is promoted with
mind-boggling confidence by many authors in research and media who declare that there is
“overwhelming evidence” that the causes of behavior and mind can be traced to brain processes,
and announce the advent of neuro-explanations of all things human (e.g., Dennett, 1991; Kandell,
2007, 2016; Pinker, 2003, 2009). In education such claims divert attention and resources away
from explorations into the dynamics of teaching and learning as meaningful activities that require
far more than focus on the brain.
The second reason to start with such a review is my belief that the current pushback by
psychologists and educators who are skeptical about the surge of “brainist” neuro-explanations is
inadequate and needs to be more conceptually deep and far-reaching. The final reason – and the
most important one in the context of this book – is my hope that a more consistent, non-
reductionist, and at the same time non-mentalist understanding of mind, mental development, and
learning can emerge from deeper conceptual elaborations on and intensification of the growing
opposition to “mindless neuroscience.” In this chapter, I will review these recent critical advances
that oppose “brainism” and offer a number of points that can further strengthen and unify this
opposition.
A substantial criticism of brain reductionism has recently emerged in philosophy,
psychology and education, as well as within neuroscience itself. Notable skeptical voices coming
from neuroscience include, for example, the recent books by Lengrenzi and Umilta (2011) and
Satel and Lilienfeld (2013). These authors eloquently challenge overly enthusiastic claims from
pop-neuroscience and neuro-marketers, in actuality not supported by evidence, about the alleged
link between certain mental activities and specific brain areas and processes. Conversely, the

--- Page 8 ---


authors discuss ample evidence that various brain areas and processes in fact support multiple and
very different human activities, including different mental activities and problem solving, which
makes establishing such direct links difficult if not impossible. Unfortunately, most of these
sobering critiques developed within neuroscience do not articulate any philosophically viable
alternatives to such unfettered brain reductionism on ontological grounds. Moreover, they express
hope and even confidence that, with more effort and research, sometime in the future such a direct
mind-brain link will be discovered. In their conviction that neuroscientific discoveries are on their
way to this, many researchers call for patience, noting that contemporary neuroscience does not
yet know even the most elementary facts about how the brain actually works (e.g., how the brain
“recognizes” a straight line), let alone the relationships between the brain processes and the more
complex mental states (e.g., see Marcus, 2012; Mausfeld, 2012). Yet, as many authors observe
(Jarrett, 2015; Willis, 2015), so far these calls for caution and patience fall on the deaf ears of
aggressive neuro-marketers (and, unfortunately, some neuroscientists and psychologists) who
continue to spread, with great fanfare, numerous simplistic interpretations and outright neuro-
myths.
Other neuroscientists, as well as psychologists and philosophers, have raised more general
concerns about the explanatory value of the reductionist brain-based approaches for understanding
the mind and behavior (Bem, 2001; Bissell, 1998; Carmeli & Blass, 2013; De Vos & Pluth, 2016;
Harré, 2012; Hruby, 2012; Gazzaniga, 2011; Gold & Stoljar, 1999; Miller, 2008; Rose & Abi-
Rached, 2013; Tallis, 2011; Uttal, 2001). These authors argue that neuro and biological
reductionism misrepresents and simplifies human nature by claiming that it can be derived from
and attributed to brain physiology. They point out that such complex social constructs as free will
or responsibility, as well as presumably more “simple” meaningful actions and behaviors (such as
driving a car), have no meaning in the “materialistic” and ‘deterministic” context of the brain
processes.
Many critics point out that educational claims putatively derived from neuroscience are
largely oversold and not supported by rigorous evidence. Indeed, the actual educational
recommendations that can be derived from recent neuroscientific research are strikingly
disappointing and, moreover, merely translate into fashionable neuroscientific terminology what
has long already been known, thus producing an illusion of new discoveries (e.g., Bruer, 1997;
2006; Fischer, Goswami, & Geake, 2010; Varma, McCandliss & Schwartz, 2008). These
observations have been echoed by the findings that mere insertion of neuroscientific terms and
references to brain research has a powerful convincing effect on non-experts’ judgments about
factually flawed and even nonsensical claims and recommendations (including guidelines for
teaching and learning), masking otherwise obvious weakness of these statements and
recommendations (cf. McCabe & Castel, 2008; Weisberg, Keil, Goodstein, Rawson, & Gray,
2008).
In mass literature and media, “brain” is routinely inserted into recommendations which, upon
closer examination, at best repeat commonplace knowledge bearing

--- Page 9 ---


no relation to actual brain studies and findings. This exploitation of flippant neuro-references have
reached such egregious levels that one could suspect that the real reason behind is that it is a cheap
way to impress with “cutting-edge science.” Alternatively, it is often an outright commercial ploy,
since today “brain” is like “sex” – it sells. Take for example a recent book which in its title
announces nothing less than the “Education Revolution,” and in its subtitle claims to explain “how
to apply brain science to improve instruction” (Sanzes, 2017). Although educational
recommendations provided by the author are either stunningly trivial or nonsensical, the book is
full of bizarre yet confident statements about brain research “findings.” For example, the author
proclaims that “the amygdala, the part of the brain in charge of emotions, has three universal needs:
The need to feel safe, the need to feel wanted, and the need to be successful” (ibid, p. 99). The
educational recommendation that follows is that teachers have to test what they teach on the
criterion “that the amygdala must value it” (ibid., p. 152). Or consider the author’s “innovative”
explanation of higher order thinking, which presumably would not be possible without the cutting-
edge brain research: “Higher level thinking is simply defined as the brain making connections,
which allow students to link new information to old… based on their prior knowledge” (ibid, p.
54). Such pieces of “revolutionary” pop-science could be just shrugged off and forgotten were they
not polluting the public discourses with fake explanations and false promises in the critically
important area of education.

RECENT CRITICISM OF BRAINISM

An elaborate critical analysis of neuroscientific interpretations of psychological processes


has been offered by Bennett and Hacker (2003; 2007). These authors argue that psychological
attributes cannot be ascribed to the brain. Instead, processes such as remembering, thinking, and
decision-making are done by people, not brains. They point to the confusion between levels of
analysis in brain-related educational literature, such as in routine references to the “learning brain”
(for one of the recent examples, see Sousa, 2011). They identify this error as the mereological
fallacy, in which characteristics of the whole entity (in this case, the person) are mistakenly
attributed to a part of the whole (in this case, the brain). This is a very important line of
argumentation. However, its development by the authors, as well as an alternative that they offer,
are presented mostly from the perspective of linguistic philosophy, discourse analysis, references
to “psychological predicates,” and the “normative connections of logic” rather than from a position
that is concerned with the ontological legitimacy of mental processes and their distinct role in
behavior. The authors’ legitimate and valuable point is that neuroscience cannot in principle shed
any light on many non-empirical, epistemological aspects of mind as

an a priori enquiry into the web of epistemic concepts that is formed by the
connections, compatibilities and incompatibilities between the concepts of knowledge,
belief, conviction, suspicion, supposition, conjecture, doubt,

--- Page 10 ---


certainty, memory, evidence and self-evidence, truth and falsehood, probability,
reasons and reasoning, etc. (Bennett & Hacker, 2003, p. 406)

The authors do argue that consciousness, as well as other psychological states and processes,
“are bound to behavioral grounds,” not the brain. Yet again, their point is that consciousness can
be legitimately ascribed to an individual exhibiting a particular behavior and not to the brain;
therefore the focus is on the rules of attributing mental states to the individual or to the brain (in
the context of linguistic and epistemological discourse) rather than on whether, how, and why
consciousness is distinct from brain processes in functional and developmental terms.
Particularly notable is the criticism of different aspects of brain reductionism recently put
forth by Bakhurst, Gergen, Noë, and Joldersma. These works offer many refreshing insights about
critically important differences between the brain and the mind, about the embodied mind, and
other related concepts. To clarify what these authors suggest, their ideas are discussed in more
detail below.
David Bakhurst (2008; 2011) criticizes what he calls “brainism” (reducing the mind to the
brain) and advocates “personalism” by drawing on the insights of Russian philosopher Evald
Ilyenkov and a number of contemporary Western thinkers, particularly John McDowell. Both
Ilyenkov and McDonnell develop an argument that the brain is “not a candidate” for explaining
the mind because mental processes belong not to the physiological realm of the brain but to the
individual’s activity in the world. In so doing, Bakhurst draws on Ilyenkov’s position according to
which looking into the brain for an explanation of the mind is a fallacy. As Ilyenkov put it,

[T]he substance of mind is always [the individual’s] external activity . . . and the brain
with its inborn structures is only its biological substrate. This is why studying the brain
tells you as little about the mind as analyzing the physical properties of gold, silver, or
banknote paper tells you about the nature of money. (Ilyenkov, 2002, p. 98; italics in
the original)

Along the same lines, personalists maintain that the brain creates the possibility for, but does
not determine, psychological processes – in other words, brain functioning enables “mindedness,”
but is not constitutive of it. Following McDowell (1994), Bakhurst explores an important
distinction between two different types of explanations, one of which is relevant to the brain
(physiological processes), and the other – the mind (psychological processes). That is, the brain
belongs to the realm of natural-scientific causal explanations, whereas the mind belongs to the
“realm of reasons.” According to Bakhurst,

Since there is no possibility of reducing the items that occupy the space of reasons to
those that populate the realm of law, it follows that psychological talk represents a
fundamentally different discourse from talk of the brain, and these discourses have
fundamentally different subjects. With this view of rationality in place, we can say that
the qualitative transformation in the child occurs when it becomes an inhabitant of the
space of reasons, a being whose life-activity

--- Page 11 ---


must be understood by appeal to rational, rather than merely causal-scientific,
considerations. For McDowell, what is crucial is the acquisition of conceptual
capacities...Such a creature is a rational agent, a person. This conception of development
consolidates the view that the person is the centerpiece of rational explanation, not her
brain.” (Bakhurst, 2008, p. 425)

One important conclusion from this line of reasoning is worth repeating, since several
misguided assumptions and misleading language have immensely polluted educational and popular
discourse: Brains do not think, perceive, believe, and do not make decisions (and, one could add,
neither do amygdalae “need” or “feel” anything). These and similar processes do not take place in
the brain and are inapplicable to brain processes. It is persons with brains who do all these activities
and therefore are responsible for the consequences of their decisions and actions. What Bakhurst
actually touches upon here (though does not elaborate in detail) is not just a matter of different types
of logic or different levels of incompatible “discourses” (causal vs. rational). Rather, it is a
fundamental question about ontologically different types of causality. One of these types is
mechanical (physical, physiological) causality, which is applicable to all brain processes. Another
type is qualitatively different non-mechanical causality (a sort of “non-deterministic determinism”)
which emerges in evolution with the advent of embodied active agents who (not their brains)
consider various “reasons” for action and act upon them. I will come back to this important point in
the next chapter where I discuss the emergence of a new level of activity regulation – the non-
automatic (psychological) regulation.
To reiterate, one issue with Bakhurst’s account is that although he appears to imply the active
agent (person) in his discussion, he does this in mostly general and indirect terms, and in the context
of different “discourses” rather than in relation to the agents’ meaningful activity. The second issue,
closely related to the first one, is that his perspective on agency and first-person perspective critical
to agency seems to have a traditional mentalist flavor. For example, in commenting on how brainism
struggles to make sense of the first-person perspective, Bakhurst writes that
[a] person does not typically stand to her own mental states as to objects of observation.
…The attitude we take to our own mental lives is one of agency: we are the authors of
our orientation to the world, responsible for what we think and do and our attitude to
our own beliefs is never one of passive observation. Indeed, even in cases where our
minds are passive recipients, as they are in perception, we are nevertheless under a
standing

--- Page 12 ---


obligation to evaluate the veracity of what we take ourselves to see, hear and so on.
(ibid. p. 423)

From this and later passages it is apparent that Bakhurst is still wavering between two
radically different positions: one which posits an active agent and mind, and another that is rooted
in the traditional mentalist paradigm about the mind. The latter position transpires in Bakhurst’s
claims that in perception “our minds are passive recipients...” and that only after perceiving
something “we are under a standing obligation to evaluate the veracity of what we take ourselves
to see, hear, and so on” (ibid., p. 423). Interpreting the mind as a recipient of external information
or experience is clearly an instance of the traditional mentalist and cognitivist (information-
processing) framework. Therefore, one can conclude that although Bakhurst raises important
concerns with regard to brainism and articulates some potentially promising points for a possible
“personalist” alternative, his overall account is contradictory, since it still operates with the
elements of the traditional mentalist paradigm, which assumes that the mind passively receives
information to process it “in the head.” Consequently, in his further elaborations Bakhurst ends up
claiming that there is “no reason to assume a priori that causal factors relevant to explaining a
person’s… ability” do not come from the brain and that “there are no a priori grounds to declare
brain science irrelevant to educational issues” (Bakhurst, 2008, pp. 427-428). This conclusion by
Bakhurst seems inconsistent given that he spends the larger part of his article arguing that from
the personalist perspective, which he seems to share, there are actually very serious theoretical
grounds to assume exactly that – namely, that the brain is irrelevant in terms of “causal factors” in
behavior and that the “brain is not a candidate” for explaining the mind and mental processes.
Several topics raised by Bakhurst in his discussion of brainism resonate with the critique
of cortical explanations of human behavior put forth by Kenneth Gergen (2010), who also adds
several important threads to critiquing and potentially debunking brainism. Gergen claims that
looking into the workings of the brain by using imaging technology, however sophisticated, can
actually tell us very little, if anything at all, about the human mind, behavior, and learning.
According to Gergen, the “causes” of behavior are not in the brain but in the outside world, which
for humans is their social and cultural world. The human brain (and more broadly the nervous
system) enables all forms of cultural activities and behaviors due to its enormous plasticity, but
the brain is not responsible for human behavior because it is not the cause of behavior.
Based on evidence from neuropsychological research, Gergen makes a compelling case that
human activity is unintelligible in terms of neural processes and that the brain’s primary function is
to serve as an enabling tool for achieving socially originated goals. Accordingly, Gergen articulates
the conceptual premise that the brain processes can be only viewed as a necessary organismic
precondition for mental processes and abilities, but in no way as their causes or determinants. He
points to the intractable conceptual problem with understanding the brain as the causal source of the
mind states:

The distinction is represented primarily in the assumption that the brain is a causal source
of both mental states and behavior. We thus commonly speak of the neural basis, source,
or grounds of cognition, emotion, altruism, aggression, and so on. Yet this assumption
of the brain as a causal source raises major difficulties. There is, at the outset, Descartes’
intractable problem of how

--- Page 13 ---


brain states affect mind states. If mind states are not material, then how are we to
conceptualize the causal link between material and non-material worlds? (Gergen, 2010,
p. 802)

Gergen further states that the brain should be viewed not as causing behavior (and therefore
not as being somehow “responsible” for specific behavior) but instead, as an “organ” that supports
all kinds of activities:

There are dramatically different social implications between the conclusion that “my
brain made me do it, and “my brain prevents my doing it.” In the latter case, there is
considerable utility in determining whether a given incapacity, for example, is cortically
determined. It would be useful to know if symptoms characterized as autism resulted
from neurological as opposed to social factors – or some combination. (ibid, p. 811)

Instead of deriving behavior from the “programs” contained in the brain, Gergen suggests
viewing the function of the brain as “preparatory” – that of preparing the individual for an infinite
variety of actions (in the form of what he terms “protean action”) which implies innovation and
continuous adjustment to ever-changing environmental conditions. In this context, Gergen points to
the brain’s enormous plasticity as its most important property for human life that requires the
individual to be prepared for an infinite variety of activities that cannot be predetermined from the
beginning. He further draws attention to these requirements being cultural in origin, and sums his
position as follows,

In this context, it seems far more reasonable to view the brain not as prophetic, but as
preparatory in function. That is, it is an organ specifically preparing the individual for
protean action, for continuously responding, innovating, and initiating, as the conditions
of life unfold over time. It is at just this point that an enormous body of evidence for
neural plasticity becomes relevant.” (ibid. p. 806)

Insisting that efforts to find explanations of behavior in the brain are misguided, Gergen makes
a point that is similar to Ilyenkov’s reasoning (as discussed by Bakhurst) – that these explanations
should be looked for not in the realm of physiology but in the realm of culture and human meanings.
He discusses what resonates with Ilyenkov’s example (quoted earlier in this chapter) about the
futility of trying to discover the nature of money by examining the physical composition of
banknotes, explaining why the concept of time cannot be found in the mechanism of the clock itself.
In Gergen’s words,

The physical mechanism of a clock may be fully understood; the functioning of its parts
wholly predictable… Yet, there is nothing about the physical functioning of the clock
that yields information about time. That a clock furnishes us the time of day is entirely
dependent upon shared agreements within the culture… To return to the earlier issue of
causality, it makes little

--- Page 14 ---


sense to say that the working of the clock as a physical instrument is the causal basis (a
“hard-wired origin”) of the time. We are dealing here not with cause and effect, but with
two functionally distinct discourses. (ibid. p. 809)

Gergen also convincingly argues that it makes no sense to view the brain in isolation from the
nervous system and the whole body, as well as from its behavior, and instead suggests the broader
“body-in-environment” system as a more viable alternative and core focus of analysis. This shift in
focus eliminates the traditional distinction between brain and behavior and, likewise, refutes the
view of the brain as a cause of behavior:

... [T]he brain is but a constituent part of the nervous system as a whole, and, separated
from the remainder of the system, bodily movement is severely attenuated. In effect, it
makes little sense to view the “brain as behavior” separated from the broader system of
which it is a part. It is also apparent that the neural system is scarcely independent of the
pulmonary system; each depends on the other for its functioning. And, too, neither of
these could function effectively without the digestive system, skeletal structure, and so
on. Remove any part of the system and “behavior” is essentially negated. Given that
what we commonly distinguish as the brain acquires its function within the bodily
system as a whole, it defies common meaning to assert that the movement of the body
represents behavior, for which the brain is a cause. It is the functioning of the full array
of interdependent bodily systems that is synonymous with behavior itself. Remove the
functioning of this systemic process and there is no behavior; remove behavior and there
is nothing remaining to be called the body. The traditional distinction between brain and
behavior is erased, and likewise the view that the brain is a cause or basis of behavior.
(ibid., p. 804)

In this passage, in addition to its main line of argument that the functioning of the brain cannot
be separated from the functioning of the body as a whole and that, therefore, claims about the brain
causing behavior are unsubstantiated and misleading, one can also identify at least an implicit hint
to what other authors (Joldersma, 2013; Noë, 2008, among others) refer to as the embodied agent
who acts in the world, including various cultural environments. However, this important concept has
not been further developed by Gergen, which leads to the following problems with his account.
From the very beginning of the discussion, Gergen considers two types of factors as possible
candidates for determinants of the individual’s behavior: the physiological factors (brain processes)
and cultural factors. Having established these two alternatives, Gergen clearly chooses “cultural
conditions” as more suitable:

It is not the brain that brings about problem solving, but the cultural conditions in which
the very idea of solving problems and the kind of behavior defined as problem solving
are nurtured. In this case the brain is simply a conduit that carries the cultural tradition.
(ibid., p. 803)

--- Page 15 ---


The problem with Gergen’s interpretation, however, is that it appears that cultural factors
somehow act directly and shape behavior by themselves. In other words, Gergen seems to view
cultural conditions themselves as determinants of behavior: “The brain does not determine the
contours of cultural life; cultural life determines what we take to be the nature and importance of
brain functioning” (p. 813). Therefore, the physiological causes of behavior are replaced by Gergen
with cultural causes. As a result, there is no clearly defined human agent in Gergen’s account. In
some parts of the discussion, such as the passage above, the agent is seemingly presumed but is
neither explicitly identified nor theorized in any detail as a potentially key concept to theorizing the
mind and the role of the brain. In turn, this leads to an implicit assumption about a direct relationship
between the brain and the outside world (which, in the case of humans, is the predominantly cultural
world). This assumption shows up right in the title of Gergen’s (2010) article – The Acculturated
Brain, which not so tacitly implies a position that the brain itself is directly connected to culture and
even “acculturated” by it. In addition, expressions like “brain as culture carrier” (p. 805) also point
to the same problematic assumption about the direct synergy and immediate connection between the
brain and culture.
Quite paradoxically, in such an account, assuming a direct connection between the brain and
culture means that there is no clear place for the mind as something distinctly different from the
brain. Consequently, one is bound to have a hard time explaining how cultural factors (Gergen’s
version of the causes of behavior) in synergy with the brain allow for the individual’s “protean”
(ever-changing) or any other type of meaningful actions in the dynamic cultural and social
environment. That is, omitting the human agent as the defining part of the relationship between the
brain and cultural factors makes a productive conceptualization of the role of the mind
(psychological processes) very difficult, if not impossible. As I discuss in the following chapters,
the concept of active agents and their meaningful goal-directed activities in the world is central to
understanding the mind’s function as irreducible to the brain processes and to resolving old dualistic
dichotomies between the brain and the mind, the mind and the body, the physiological and cultural
processes, and so on. My brief comment about Gergen’s view here is that while brains themselves
do not “carry” culture, neither do cultural conditions, nor cultural artifacts themselves carry culture.
Rather, real people (enabled by human brains and bodies) as they engage in their cultural practices
do.
A compelling case against ‘brainism’ has been recently made by Alva Noë. In his thought-
provoking book Out of Our Heads (2009), Noë criticizes mainstream neuroscience and cognitive
science for promoting the view that the brain is the seat of the mind and that the brain generates
consciousness. His charge is that these views are misguided, unsustainable and have no empirical
support:

Brains don’t think. The idea that a brain could represent the world on its own doesn’t
make any more sense than the idea that mere marks on paper could signify all on their
own (that is, independently of the larger social practice of

--- Page 16 ---


reading and writing). The world shows up for us thanks to our interaction with it. It is
not made in the brain or by the brain.” (Noë, 2009, p. 164)

Noë forcefully argues that consciousness (which for him in most cases is identical to the
mind) does not “take place” in the brain in the way digestion takes places in the stomach. The mind
is not what we have; it is what we do in the world when being engaged with the environment. The
mind is embodied and engaged with the world – there is no “Mission Control” somewhere in the
brain because the mind is not a “thing”; instead, it is relational. As Noë states, “[c]onsciousness of
the world around us is something that we do: we enact it, with the world’s help, in our dynamic
living activities. It is not something that happens in us” (ibid., p. 65).
Since Noë’s own research focus has been visual perception, his most convincing points come
from the studies of perception. For example, he draws on the experiments involving rewiring the
brains of newborn ferrets by wiring up their eyes to the parts of the brain normally used for hearing.
It turned out that the ferrets were able to see with their auditory brains, and Noë rightfully concludes
that “this teaches us that there isn’t anything special about the cells in the so-called visual cortex that
makes them visual. Cells in the auditory cortex can be visual just as well” (ibid., p. 54). Such findings
illustrate the brain’s plasticity, as well as an important proposition that there are no direct neural
correlates of mental cognitive functions that could by themselves generate these functions because
cognition does not “happen” inside the brain. In Noë’s words,

Seeing is … a bodily activity. Seeing is not something that happens in us. It is not
something that happens to us or in our brains. It is something we do. It is an activity of
exploring the world making use of our practical familiarity with the ways in which our
own movement drives and modulates our sensory encounter with the world. Seeing is a
kind of skillful activity.” (ibid., p. 60)

Noë criticizes the mechanistic model of visual perception, which holds that initially the
retinal image (which is “on its way” to the brain) is turned upside down due to optical laws, and
then the brain, in the process of “analyzing” that image, turns it back into the upright position. Noë
argues that this model is fundamentally misleading. The retinal “image” is not a picture that is
somehow scrutinized by the mind’s eye, or by the brain. The brain does not see the retinal image.
The claim that the brain “adjusts the inversion of the retinal image” (because the retinal image is
“upside down”) does not make sense; it is based on the misguided assumption that the retinal image
is a picture, that is, a representation that needs to be interpreted by some observer. From this
perspective,

Seeing is active. Vision is not an internal process in the sense like digestion. When we
give up the misguided assumption that the brain generates vision, we lose the feeling
of puzzlement about how the brain does it. (ibid., p. 145)

--- Page 17 ---


One of the most provocative arguments by Noë is directed towards the information-
processing view – the presumed “commonplace knowledge” that the brain, and its “visual areas”
in particular, is an organ for processing information about the environment. According to this
disputable though widely shared view, the visual system in the brain performs an information-
processing task – it extracts information about the environment from the retinal image, thus
constructing an internal representation of that environment. Noë contends that there are serious
reasons to question such a theory because the brain itself does not interpret information in any
way:

When a detective extracts information about an intruder from a footprint, or when an


oceanographer gathers information about a prehistoric climate by studying fossils of
unicellular organisms that she dredges up from today’s ocean floor – these are nice
examples of “extracting information” about one thing from another… Things are
different when it comes to the brain and the retinal image. No doubt the retinal image
is rich in information about the scene before the eyes…But the brain is no scientist or
detective; it doesn’t know anything and it has no eyes to examine the retinal image. It
has no capacity to make inferences about anything, let alone the remote environmental
causes of the observable state of the retina.” (ibid., p. 161)

To reiterate, in this sense the brain is not an information processing device, since the brain
does not “know” the operations it is performing, just as a clock knows nothing about time. This
argument sounds convincing, especially if one assumes that information processing includes
making sense of that information rather than just “processing” it for abstract algorithms, formulaic
consistencies, and combinatorial logistics and patterns.
Criticizing the mentalist model of cognition, Noë argues that it is a mistake to think that the
brain builds up an internal picture of the world. Rather, cognition can be construed in terms of
“access to the world”:

What I see is never the content of a mental snapshot; the world does not seem to be
reproduced inside me. Rather – and this is the key – the world seems to be available to
me. What guarantees its availability is, first of all, its actually being here, and second,
my possessing the skills needed to gain access to it. I gather the detail as I do it by
turning my head or shifting my attention… The world doesn’t show up for me as
present all at once in my mind. It shows up as within reach, as more or less nearby, as
more or less present.” (pp. 140-141, italics in the original)

The theme about “skillful access” to the world as a basis for perception, which resonates
with Gibson’s (1979) idea of affordances, is prominent is Noë’s account. However, the subsequent
important questions that follow from this position are never discussed or even raised – namely,
what exactly are those skills that are needed to gain access to the world, how do they develop and
what does this imply for understanding the mind? These questions and a whole set of related issues
lead

--- Page 18 ---


to the problem of defining and analyzing different types of the agent’s actions and to the notion of
internalization in its reconceptualized form as a major avenue of human mental development,
which is the main topic of Chapter 5 of this book.
In addition, although in contrast to the mentalist accounts Noë (2004) explains perception
as connected to external action, he seems to conceptualize action itself in a quite narrow, sensory-
motor way, as a merely physical movement of the biological organism adapting to the
environment. Along the same line of narrowly biological reasoning, Noë posits that human mind
and activity are biologically based, and claims that “the goal is to understand the biological basis
of consciousness” (Noë, 2009, p. 161). Such a biologically-driven view leads Noë to argue that
the mind is everywhere where there is life – even in bacteria: “The bacterium is not merely a
process; it is an agent, however simple; it has interests...Where we discern life, we have everything
we need to discern mind” (ibid., p. 41). Paradoxically, in such a radical form of a blanket
generalization, the call for a biological perspective turns out to be non-evolutionary at its core,
since there is no acknowledgement of any qualitative changes and developmental trajectories
across forms of life and mind (from snails to mammals), let alone of the unique features of human
mental development. These unique features will be discussed in Chapters 4 and 5 of this book.
To summarize, in Noë’s works there is an explicit and forceful rejection of brainism and, as
an alternative, an implicit move towards the notion of the active embodied agent. However, due to
Noë’s understanding of practically all living beings as agents, the specific properties of active
agents and the distinct and qualitative characteristics that differentiate them from non-agents are
not discussed. The analysis of such differences and their fundamental implications for action-based
conceptualization of the mind is the main topic of Chapter 3 of this book.
Another important line of arguments against brainism has been recently advanced by
Clarence Joldersma (2013) from the perspective of the radical embodiment model of mind. The
idea of embodied cognition has been advanced by a number of authors (e.g., Clark, 2008; Overton,
Müller & Newman, 2008; Varela, Thompson & Rosch, 1991), but Joldersma used it in the most
systematic way to challenge the brain reductionism. Not surprisingly, many themes in Joldersma’s
account are similar to those raised by the authors discussed above. For example, Joldersma argues
that mental process and behavior do not “supervene” on the brain – that is, they are not determined
by the brain; brain processes do not determine actions but rather “modulate” sensorimotor patterns
based on sensory feedback:

Localized sensory feedback adjusts and adapts general motor dynamic patterns while,
conversely, neural states participate as a bodily-subsystem in the entire bodily
subject’s action as informed by the network of affordances. That is, the relations
between neural activity and the sensorimotor elements of embodied environmental
interaction are modulating. (Joldersma, 2013, p. 266; italics in the original)

--- Page 19 ---


The radical embodiment model adopted by Joldersma seeks to conceptualize the mind as
“embodiedness,” including its embeddedness in the world: “The human mind is embodied in the
entire bodily subject and embedded in the world, and hence is not reducible to structures inside
the head” (ibid., p. 266; for similar arguments, see Marshall, 2009). This model is non-
representational (no internal pictures are assumed to exist under the skull), just as are the similar
views of Noë, and it also employs Gibson’s notion of affordances. Accordingly, this model also
holds that there is no one-to-one correspondence between neural processes and mental states.
An introduction of the active agent in this model leads to the potentially fundamental idea
that underlying all cognition is the agent’s activity, even when the active component of cognition
is not explicit:

Even in settings where action is not obvious, evidence indicates that certain sensory
and motor actions are simply bracketed while running on the same neural machinery.
Cognition remains subtended by the same neuronal dynamics that support general
patterns of sensorimotor skills. This means that cognition centrally involves something
that we do, aptly characterized by Noë as a “temporally extended process of skillful
probing” in which “the world makes itself available to our reach. (Joldersma, p. 267)

However, although Joldersma claims that the model is action-based, in reality he (as well as
other proponents of embodied cognition, e.g., Núñez, 2004) typically reduces actions to physical
movements (“moving around”). Consequently, he interprets the integration of action and
perception just as “sensorimotor” coordination. I would argue that such a narrow understanding of
action and activity (at least in Joldersma’s account) substantially inhibits the ability of the
embodied cognition perspective to elaborate a radically novel alternative to brainism.
As pointed out in the foregoing discussion in this chapter, the general non-mentalist and
non-reductionist thrust in the embodied cognition framework is indeed much needed and
productive. However, apart from the references to the “extension to the world” and statements that
we “experience ourselves as minds by being bodily oriented to the world,” there is no specific and
detailed explanation of the mind’s role in the life conduct and behavior which would be irreducible
to brain functioning. That is, the function of the mind as distinct from that of the brain is blurred
in Joldersma’s account. In my view, this is exactly because in discussing the role of both the brain
and the mind, Joldersma remains solely at the sensorimotor level of regulation, which in his
description looks as entirely physiological level. As a result, the need for a qualitatively different
level of regulation – psychological regulation (i.e., the mind, as will be elaborated in the next
chapter) – remains unspecified.
The reduction of all cognition to the sensorimotor level in Joldersma’s discussion of the
embodied view of cognitive functioning is evident when he states that

[i]n radical embodiment, cognition is understood not only as an active process, but also
as being dependent on being a body with certain patterns

--- Page 20 ---


of sensorimotor actions. At minimum, some argue that cognition simply is
sensorimotor coordination...This means that in its basic form cognition involves
coordinating the sensorimotor behavior of the organism by coupling sensory and motor
patterns and capacities. (Joldersma, 2013, p. 267; italics in the original)

Even human cognition, according to Joldersma, is no different because “human cognition


also centrally still involves patterns of sensorimotor coordination” (p. 267). For example, speaking
about thinking and mathematical concepts, Joldersma argues that the underlying mechanisms are
sensorimotor in their basis:

In abstract thinking, cognition remains geared for action, although with interesting and
marked modifications. Even, for example, in mathematical abstractions, cognition
remains enmeshed in sensorimotor dynamisms, even though there is no overt
sensorimotor activity. (ibid. p. 268)

With such a narrow focus on sensorimotor components, where even human action is
basically interpreted just as sensorimotor movement, it remains unclear which specific functions
of cognition (as a psychological level of regulation) cannot be reduced to brain processes. When
action is understood largely in a physiological way, the embodied cognition model, at least in
Joldersma’s elaboration, paradoxically misses the all-important part: the agent’s activity (as
different from “moving around” and using “sensors and effectors”), which is mediated by
meanings and goals and therefore necessitates a qualitatively new form of regulation –
psychological regulation.
In summary, with all the very important and well-reasoned arguments put forth against
brainism, Joldersma’s account of embodied cognition blurs the fundamental difference between
merely physiological regulation and cognitive (psychological) regulation, such as perception. It is
difficult to elaborate the critically important concept of the embodied agent in a consistent way
while remaining confined to essentially physiologically-based theorizing, level of analysis, and
language. Whatever is generally claimed about the irreducibility of the mind to the brain, the
physiological level of analysis inevitably leads to the conclusion that the only true reality is not
the intentional agent, but an organism (“body-in-environment”) with its dominating physiological
forms of regulation, into which brain processes fit perfectly. Consequently, it is difficult for this
account to discern the functional difference between brain processes and the mind, the latter
understood as the qualitatively new ability of embodied agents to regulate their activity in the
world.

SUMMARY OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST BRAINISM AND “MINDLESS


NEUROSCIENCE”

Wrapping up the discussion of recent criticism aimed at countering the new wave of
brainism, the most important points of this discussion could be summarized as follows.

--- Page 21 ---


1. The “neuromarketing” trend in contemporary neuroscience, as well as many “neuro-
minded” psychologists, make increasingly bold claims concerning the possibility of explaining
mind and behavior by looking exclusively into brain processes. Nevertheless, despite confident
statements about “overwhelming evidence” for neurological roots of all things human, a careful
scrutiny of these claims reveals that they are largely unfounded. On the contrary, analysis points
to very vague or even non-existent evidence for establishing the presumed connections between
mental activities and brain processes. But regardless of the cautioning of many scholars, including
in neuroscience itself, the inflated promises of neuro-explanations are being perpetuated with great
fanfare, especially by the media. This wave of “neuromania” is detrimental to research in
psychology – because it cannibalizes resources for studying anything else but the brain – and
especially to education, since it generates misguided expectations of the upcoming educational
“revolution” based on studies of the brain.
2. The practical recommendations from neuroscience to other areas and disciplines,
especially for education, are shallow at best, as compared to its spectacular promises and claims.
Moreover, although these recommendations are typically presented as being based on “cutting
edge” research and scientific discoveries, a careful look reveals that many of them merely
parasitize on already- existing bodies of knowledge in other areas, and often just on common sense.
These “brain-based” recommendations actually add very little to what is already well known about
behavior, development and learning – they just rephrase that knowledge, framing it in neurological
terms and adding the “magical” particle neuro- to every interpretation, accompanied by fancy brain
images, thus creating an illusion of new compelling findings. In reality, the original contribution
of neuroscience to education is extremely limited, except for specialized cases when learning
difficulties are indeed partly caused by deficiencies in brain processes.
3. Neuroscientific and educational discourses take place at dramatically different levels that
are philosophically and ontologically incompatible. The language of neuroscience is too “atomic”
to support useful generalizations for education. Education researchers would gain practically
nothing from translating their concepts into the terminology of neuroscience.
4. Connecting different aspects of cognition to different brain areas and functions
(questionable as it is in itself) does not and cannot inform educational practice, contrary to
expectations and the hype of recent years. Even if such localization is ultimately established, which
is highly improbable, knowing the “location” of cognitive processes, such as memory and
attention, tells us practically nothing about how to organize, support, and design teaching and
learning in order to develop these processes. For example, when we learn to drive a car, we
obviously learn not how to fire one group of neurons and inhibit another group of neurons, but
how to switch gears or how to detect

--- Page 22 ---


dangerous conditions on the road. Similarly, when a teacher needs to teach a new concept, knowing
or explaining to students which parts of the brain get activated when someone thinks about this
concept is not going to improve the students’ understanding of the concept. This is not a matter of
just two different “lingos” spoken by different sciences about the same thing (with the language
of neuroscience putatively being “more precise”). Rather, the phenomena themselves that these
disciplines (neuroscience on the one hand, and psychology and education on the other) describe
are at incompatibly different levels. As another illustration, it is possible to describe what is going
on in the brain when an individual buys something, or when an individual decides whether
someone is guilty of some wrongdoing, but it is impossible on this basis to explain the concepts
of exchange value or criminal justice.
5. Brain functions and psychological processes belong to ontologically different realms also
in terms of radically different types of causality – the realm of mechanical “causes,” in the case of
the brain functions, versus the realm of affordances and “reasons” in the case of psychological
processes (as will be discussed in Chapter 3). Although brain functions create the necessary
physiological support for the mind, these functions can neither determine nor “explain” the mind.
There is no and cannot be one-to-one correspondence between mental states and neural processes.
6. Psychological processes do not occur in the depths of the brain. Rather, they belong to the
embodied agent’s intentional and meaningful interaction with and activity in the external world.
The cutting-edge research in embodied cognition and philosophy of neuroscience explains that we
cannot expect to find representations (little pictures) of external objects under the skull.
7. Brains do not think, perceive, memorize, or learn. It is whole persons as active agents, not
brains, who think, interpret information, decide, and act. And it is persons, not brains, who are
responsible for their actions. The brain does not “care” about what we do and how we do it and
about the outcomes of these actions.

To reiterate, all the works discussed in this chapter make significant contributions to
developing a much-needed alternative to brainism in psychology and education. At the same time,
substantial aspects and considerations seem to be still missing in their criticism of brainism. In
particular, there is a lack of more consistent philosophical and conceptual lines of argumentation
that are needed to expose the inadequacy of neuro-explanations of the mind and human behavior.
Even in the most advanced attempts to overcome brainism, the implicit reduction of psychological
processes to sensory components, and of human actions to physical movements makes it difficult
to arrive at a consistent non-reductionist account of mind and cognition. This leaves the
fundamental task of debunking this misleading wave of brain reductionism

--- Page 23 ---


and of the ambitions of “brain-based” education incomplete. It appears that all the discussed
accounts, while making many important points, stop short of articulating the necessary ontological
and methodological conclusions from these points which would make the assumptions of brainism
irrelevant. As discussed in more detail in the following chapters, the key component that seems to
be missing in these accounts is the question about what the mind really is – beyond the important
arguments that it cannot be reduced to brain functions. A more elaborate and consistent theorizing
is needed in order to conceptualize the mind and its irreducible role in a non-mentalist and, at the
same time, non-reductionist way.
As will be argued throughout the rest of the book, the key argument that needs to be advanced
is that the essential role of the mind is to extend the flexibility of behavior far beyond the limits of
what entirely physiological regulation is able to provide. With the increasing complexity of the
environment, merely physiological regulation (based as it is on previous experience encoded in
the organism’s physiological processes) becomes inadequate for survival and successful acting. In
other words, a line of theorizing is needed to reveal how and why an evolutionary need emerges
for a qualitatively different kind of behavior regulation – the non-automatic (psychological)
regulation employed by an active agent. Without considering this new kind of behavior regulation,
the critically important concept of the active embodied agent itself remains theoretically flawed
and ultimately gets reduced to just “body-in-environment,” while its most defining agentive
characteristic – the agent’s activity in the world – is overlooked.
More generally, one of the main recurring themes in the rest of this book has to do with
addressing the cause of conceptual difficulties in overcoming brainism in order to develop a
consistent non-reductionist and non-mentalist account of the mind and psychological processes, as
well as individual psychological development and meaningful learning. As already mentioned in
the introduction, I see the root cause for these difficulties in the implicit but powerful
contemplative fallacy associated with the contemplative stance (spectator perspective) which still
dominates major theoretical frameworks dealing with mind, development, and learning. This
contemplative fallacy leads to a misguided “objectification” of psychological phenomena – that is,
to viewing psychological phenomena as separate “objects” and processes which in self-observation
seem to exist independently within a special realm that is different from the outside world. It is
exactly the fallacious objectification of psychological processes in our self-observation that creates
an illusion that these processes are something separate from external activity and take place “in
the head” or in the brain. This fallacious placement of psychological processes “under the skull”
was the main topic of this chapter.
In the following chapters, I discuss other aspects of the same contemplative fallacy as they
underlie the fundamental issues in conceptualizing phylogeny (evolutionary development) of the
active agent, human ontogeny (individual development),

--- Page 25 ---


microgenetic development (the development of new ways of acting within a limited time of
structured learning), and the role of learning in cognitive development. I also outline the steps
needed for overcoming the contemplative fallacy by adopting a radically different perspective –
the agentive activity perspective. By doing this, I hope to contribute to developing a consistent
non-mentalist and non-reductionist account of the mind, which requires going far beyond the brain.

--- Page 153 ---

REFERENCES

Aaronfreed, J. (1968). Conduct and conscience: The socialization of internalized behavior. New York: Academic
Press.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2009). Why the mind is still in the head. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The
Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp.78-95). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2010). Defending the bounds of cognition. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp.
67-80). Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
Aidarova, L. I. (1978). Psikhologicheskie problemy obucheniia mladshsikh shkolnikov russkomu iazyku
[Psychological issues in teaching Russian language in elementary school]. Moscow: Pedagogika.
Aidarova, L. I. (1982). Child development and education. Moscow: Progress.
Allen, J. W. P., & Bickhard, M. H. (2013a). Stepping off the pendulum: Why only an action-based approach can
transcend the nativist–empiricist debate. Cognitive Development, 28(2), 96-133.
Allen, W. P., & Bickhard, M. H. (2013b). The pendulum still swings. Cognitive Development, 28(2), 164-174.
Anderson, L. W., & Krathwohl, D. R. (Eds.) (2000). A taxonomy for learning, teaching, and assessing: A revision of
Bloom's taxonomy of educational objectives. New York: Pearson.
Anokhin, P. K. (1974). Biology and neurophysiology of the conditioned reflex and its role in adaptive behavior.
New York: Pergamon Press.
Arievitch, I. M. (2003). A potential for an integrated view of development and learning: Galperin’s contribution to
sociocultural psychology. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 10, 278–288.
Arievitch, I. M. (2007). An activity theory perspective on educational technology and learning. In D. Kritt & L. T.
Winegar (Eds.), Educational technology: Critical perspectives and possible futures (pp. 49-72). Lanham,
MD: Lexington Books.
Arievitch, I. M. (2008). Exploring the links between external and internal activity from the cultural-historical
perspective. In B. van Oers, W. Wardekker, E. Elbers, & R. van der Veer (Eds.), The Transformation of
learning: Advances in cultural-historical activity theory (pp. 38-58). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Arievitch, I. M., & Haenen, J. P. P. (2005). Connecting sociocultural theory and educational practice: Galperin’s
approach. Educational Psychologist, 40 (3), 155-165.
Arievitch, I. M., & Nechaev, N. N. (1975). Psikhologicheskii analiz vizualnikh sposobov resheniya zadach
[Analysis of visual problem solving]. Novie issledovaniya v psikhologii [New Studies in Psychology], 1, 81–
88.
Arievitch, I. M., & Stetsenko, A. (2000). The quality of cultural tools and cognitive development: Galperin’s
perspective and its implications. Human Development, 43, 69-92.
Arievitch, I. M., & van der Veer, R. (1995). Furthering the internalization debate: Galperin’s contribution. Human
Development, 38, 113–126.
Arievitch, I. M. & van der Veer, R. (2004). The role of non-automatic processes in activity regulation: From Lipps to
Galperin. History of Psychology, 7 (2), 154-182.
Armstrong, D. & van Schooneveld, C. H. (Eds.) (1977). Roman Jakobson: Echoes of his scholarship. Lisse, NL:
Peter de Ridder Press.
Baldwin, J. M. (1911). Thought and things. A study of the development and meaning of thought, or genetic logic.
Vol. 3. Interest and art. London: George Allen.
Bakhtin, M. M. (1981). The dialogic imagination: Four essays by M.M. Bakhtin. Austin, TX: University of Texas
Press.
Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. L. (1999). The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist, 54, 462–479.
Baumeister, R. F., & Sommer, K. L. (1997). Consciousness, free choice, and automaticity. In R. S. Wyer Jr. (Ed.),
The automaticity of everyday life: Advances in social cognition (Vol. 10, pp. 75–81). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Bernstein, N. (1967). The coordination and regulation of movements. New York: Pergamon Press.
Bickhard, M. H. (2007). Learning is scaffolded construction. In D. W. Kritt and L. T. Winegar (Eds.), Education and
technology: Critical perspectives, possible futures (pp. 73-88).
Bickhard, M. H. (2009). The interactivist model. Syntheses, 166, 547-591.
Bickhard, M. H. (2016). The anticipatory brain: Two approaches. In Vincent C. Müller (Ed.), Fundamental issues of
artificial intelligence (pp.259-281). Switzerland: Springer International Publishing AG.
Bissell, R. E. (2015). Where there's a will, there's a “why”: A Critique of the objectivist theory of volition. The Journal
of Ayn Rand Studies, 15(1), 67-96.
Bakhurst, D. (2008). Minds, brains, and education. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 42 (3-4), 415-432.
Bakhurst, D. (2011). The formation of reason. Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.
Bandura, A. (1986). Social foundations of thought and action: A social cognitive theory. Engelwood Cliffs NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Bassok, M., & Holyoak, K. J. (1993). Pragmatic knowledge and conceptual structure: Determinants of transfer
between quantitative domains. In D.K. Dettermann & R.J. Sternberg (Eds.), Transfer on trial: Intelligence,
cognition, and instruction (pp. 68–98). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Bem, S. (2001). The Explanatory autonomy of psychology: Why a mind is not a brain. Theory & Psychology, 11 (6),
785-795.
Bennett, M. R. & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Bennett, M. R. & Hacker, P. M. S. (2007). The conceptual presuppostions of cognitive neuroscience: A reply to
critics. In M. R. Bennett, D. Dennett, P. M. S. Hacker, & J. Searle, (2007). Neuroscience and philosophy:
Mind, brain and language (127-162). New York: Columbia University Press.
Bissell, R. E. (1998). How Steven Pinker’s mind works. Reason Papers, 23(1), 18-39.
Bloom, B. S. (Ed.) (1984). Taxonomy of educational objectives: The classification of educational goals. Handbook
I: Cognitive domain. New York: Longman. (First published 1956)
Brown, A. L. (1997). Transforming schools into communities of thinking and learning about serious matters.
American Psychologist, 52, 399–413.
Brown, A. L., & Campione, J. C. (1996). Psychological learning theory and the design of innovative learning
environments: On procedures, principles, and systems. In L. Schauble & R. Glaser (Eds.), Contributions of
instructional innovation to understanding learning (pp. 289–325). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Brown, A. L., & Palincsar, A. S. (1989). Guided, cooperative learning and individual knowledge acquisition. In L.B.
Resnick (Ed.), Knowing, learning, and instruction: Essays in honor of Robert Glaser (pp. 393–451). Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Bruer, J. T. (1997). Education and the brain: A bridge too far. Educational Researcher, 26, 4-16.
Bruer, J. T. (2006). On the implications of neuroscience research for science teaching and learning: Are there any?
A Skeptical theme and variations: The primacy of psychology in the science of learning. CBE Life Sciences
Education, 5(2), 104–110.
Bruner, J. (1975). The ontogenesis of speech acts. Journal of Child Language, 2, 1-19.
Bruner, J. (1978). Foreword. In A. Lock (Ed.), Action, gesture, and symbol: The emergence of language. London:
Academic Press.
Bruner, J. S. (1985). Vygotsky: A historical and conceptual perspective. In J. V. Wertsch (Ed.), Culture,
communication and cognition: Vygotskian perspectives (pp. 21-34). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bruner, J. S. (2004), Introduction to "Thinking and Speech." In R. Rieber & D. Robinson (Eds.), The Essential
Vygotsky (pp. 9-25). New York: Plenum Press.
Bruner, J. S. (2008). Culture and mind: Their fruitful incommensurability. Ethos, 36(1), 29-45. DOI: 10.1111/j.1548-
1352.2008.00002
Burkhardt, F. H. (Ed.). (1983). The works of William James: Vol. 13. Essays in psychology. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Burmenskaya, G. V. (1976). Ponyatie invariantnosti i problema psikhicheskogo razvitija rebenka [The concept of
invariance and mental development of the child]. Voprosy psikhologii [Psychological Issues], 4, 104–113.
Butkin, G. A. (1968). Formirovanie umenii lezhaschikh v osnove geometricheskogo dokazatelstva [Formation of
skills underlying geometrical reasoning]. In P. Ia. Galperin & N.F. Talyzina (Eds.), Zavisimost obucheniya ot
tipa orientirovochnoi deyatelnosti [Dependence of teaching on the type of orienting activity] (187–237).
Moscow: MGU.
Bühler, K. (1930). The mental development of the child. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Carmeli, Z., & Blass, R. (2013). The case against neuroplastic analysis: A further illustration of the irrelevance of
neuroscience to psychoanalysis through a critique of Doidge's The brain that changes itself. The International
Journal of Psychoanalysis, 94(2), 391–410.
Carpay, J., & van Oers, B. (1999). Didactic models and the problem of intertextuality and polyphony. In Y.
Engestroem, R. Miettinen, & R.-L. Punamaki (Eds.), Perspectives on activity theory (pp. 298–313). New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Carpendale, J. I., Atwood, S., & Kettner, V. (2013). Meaning and mind from the perspective of dualist versus
relational worldviews: Implications for the development of pointing gestures. Human Development, 56(6), 381-
400.
Carpendale, J. I. M. & Lewis, C. (2004). Constructing an understanding of mind: The development of children’s
social understanding within social interaction. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 79-96.
Carpendale, J. I. M., Lewis, C., Susswein, N., & Lunn, J. (2009). Talking and thinking: The role of speech in social
understanding. In A. Winsler, C. Fernyhough, & I. Montero (Eds.), Private speech, Executive functioning,
and the development of verbal self-regulation (pp. 83-94). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Carpenter, M., Nagell, K., & Tomasello, M. (1998). Social cognition, joint attention, and communicative
competence from 9 to 15 months of age. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 63
(4), 1-143.
Ceci, S. (1991). How much does schooling influence general intelligence and its cognitive components? A
reassessment of the evidence. Developmental Psychology, 27, 703–722.
Chapman, M. (1991). The epistemic triangle: Operative and communicative components of cognitive development.
In M. Chandler, & M. Chapman (Eds.), Criteria for competence: Controversies in the conceptualization and
assessment of children's abilities (pp. 209-228). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Charney, E. (2012). Behavior genetics and post genomics. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 331–410.
Christopher, J. C., & Bickhard, M. H. (2007). Culture, self and identity: Interactivist contributions to a metatheory
for cultural psychology Culture & Psychology, 13(3), 259-295.
Claparède, E. (1931). L'éducation fonctionelle [Functional education]. Neuchatel: Delachaux & Niestlé.
Clark, R. A. (1978). The transition from action to gesture. In A. Lock (Ed.), Action, gesture, and symbol: The
emergence of language (pp. 231-257). London: Academic Press.
Clark, A. (1998). Magic words: How language augments human computation. In P. Carruther & J. Boucher (Eds.),
Language and thought: Interdisciplinary themes (pp. 162-183). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Clark, A. (2002). That special something: Dennett on the making of minds and selves. In Andrew Brook & Don
Ross (Eds.), Daniel Dennett (pp. 187-203). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Clark, A. (2004). Putting concepts to work: Some thoughts for the twenty first century. Mind and Language, 19, 57-
69.
Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active memory and the extended mind. Analysis, 65(1), 1-11.
Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Cobb, P. (1994). Where is the mind? Constructivist and sociocultural perspectives on mathematical development.
Educational Researcher, 23, 13-20.
Cobb, P. (1998). Learning from distributed theories of intelligence. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 5, 187–204.
Cobb, P. (2000). The importance of a situated view of learning to the design of research and instruction. In J. Boaler
(Ed.), Multiple perspectives on mathematics teaching and learning (pp.45-82). Westport, CT: Ablex
Publishing.
Cobb, P. (2006). Mathematics learning as a social practice. In J. Maasz and W. Schloeglmann (Eds.), New
mathematics education research and practice (pp.147-152). Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.
Cole, M. (1980). Introduction: The Khar’kov school of developmental psychology. Soviet Psychology, 18 (2), 3-8.
Cole, M. (1990). Cognitive development and formal schooling: The evidence from cross-cultural research. In L. Moll
(Ed.), Vygotsky and Education (pp. 89–110). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Cole, M. (1996a). Cultural psychology: A once and future discipline. Cambridge, MA: Harward University Press.
Cole, M. (1996b). Culture in mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Cole, M. (2009).The perils of translation: A first step in reconsidering Vygotsky’s theory of development in relation to
formal education. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 16, 291-295.
Cole, M. & Engeström, Y. (1993). A cultural historical approach to distributed cognitions. In G. Salomon, (Ed.).
Distributed cognitions: psychological and educational considerations. (pp. 1-46). New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Cole, M., & Engeström, Y. (2007). Cultural-historical approaches to designing for development. In J. Valsiner & A.
Rosa (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology (pp. 484-507).. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Cole, M., & Scribner, S. (1974). Culture and thought. A psychological introduction. New York: John Wiley.
Cole, M. & Wertsch, J. V. (1996). Beyond the individual-social antinomy in discussions of Piaget and Vygotsky.
Human Development, 39, 250–256.
Cooper, R. (2005). Race and IQ: Molecular genetics as Deus ex machine. American Psychologist, 60 (1), 71-76.
Costall, A. (2007). The windowless room: Mediationism and how to get over it. In J. Valsiner, & A. Rosa (Eds.),
Cambridge handbook of socio-cultural psychology (pp. 109-123). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Cowley, S. J., Moodley, S., & Fiori-Cowley, A. (2004). Grounding signs of culture: Primary intersubjectivity in social
semiosis. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 11, 109-132.
Cox, B. D. & Lightfoot, C. (Eds.) (1997). Sociogenetic perspectives on internalization. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Danilova, V. L. (1978). Vospitanie sistematicheskogo myshleniya v reshenii zadach na soobrazhenie [Formation of
systematic thinking in non-standard problem solving]. Unpublished Doctoral dissertation, Moscow State
University.
Davydov, V. V. (1990). Types of generalization in instruction: Logical and psychological problems in the structuring
of school curricula. Reston, VA: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics. (Original work published
1972)
Davydov, V. V. (1998). Poslednie vystupleniia [Last talks]. Moscow: Tsentr Eksperiment.
Davydov, V. V. (2008). Problems of developmental instruction: A theoretical and experimental psychological study.
New York: Nova Science. (Original work published 1986)
Davydov, V. V., Pushkin, V. N., & Pushkina, A. G. (1973). Zavisimost razvitiya myshleniya mladshikh shkolnikov
ot haraktera obucheniya [The character of teaching-learning and the development of thinking in primary
school children]. Voprosy Psikhologii, 2, 124–132.
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown, & Co.
Dennett, D. C. (1996). Kinds of minds. New York: Basic Books.
Dennett, D. C. (2001). Are we explaining consciousness yet? Cognition, 79, 221–237.
De Vos, J. & Pluth, E. (Eds.) (2016). Neuroscience and critique: Exploring the limits of the neurological turn.
Routledge.
Dewey, J. (1896). Reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review, 3, 357–370.
Dewey, J. (1910). The influence of Darwin on philosophy and other essays. New York:
Henry Holt.
Dewey, J. (1916). Essays in experimental logic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Dewey, J. (1925). Experience and nature. Chicago: Open Court.
Dewey, J. (1981). Experience and nature. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), Collected works of John Dewey: Later works, v.1.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. (First published 1925)
Dettermann, D. K. (1993). The case for the prosecution: Transfer as epiphenomenon. In D. K. Dettermann, & R. J.
Sternberg (Eds.), Transfer on trial: Intelligence, cognition, and instruction (pp. 1-24). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Donaldson, M. (1978). Children’s minds. London: Fontana/Collins.
Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Dougherty, B. J. (2008) Measure up: A quantitative view of early algebra. In J. J. Kaput, D. W. Carraher, & M. L.
Blanton (Eds.), Algebra in the early grades (pp. 389-412). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Durkheim, E. (2014). The division of labor in society. New York: Free Press. (Original work published 1893)
Dusavitskii, A. K., & Repkin, V. V. (1975). Issledovanie razvitiya poznavatelnikh interesov mladshikh shkolnikov v
razlichnikh usloviyakh obucheniya [Study of the development of primary schooler’s cognitive motives in
different teaching-learning conditions]. Voprosy Psikhologii, 3, 92–102.
Durkheim, E. (1985). Les formes élémentaires de la vie religieuse. Le système totémique en Australie. Paris:
Quadrige/PUF. (First published 1912)
Egan, K. (1998). The educated mind: How cognitive tools shape our understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Elkonin, D. B. (1974). Development of speech. In A.V. Zhaporozhets & D.B. Elkonin (Eds.), The psychology of
preschool children (pp. 111–185). Cambridge: MIT. (Original work published 1964)
Elkonin, D. B. (1988). How to teach children to read. In J.A. Dowing (Ed.), Cognitive psychology and reading in the
USSR (pp. 387–326). Amsterdam: North Holland (Original work published 1976)
Elkonin, D. B. (1989). Izbrannye prsikhologicheskie trudy [Selected psychological works]. Moscow: Pedagogika.
Elkonin D. B. (1999a). On the structure of learning activity. Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 37,
84-92.
Elkonin, D. B. (1999b). On the theory of primary education. Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 37,
71-83.
Elkonin, D. B., & Davydov, V. V. (1966). Vozrastnie vozmoshnosti usvojenija znanij [Age-related potential of
knowledge acquisition]. Moscow: Prosveschenie.
Engeström, Y., Hakkarainen, P., & Hedegaard, M. (1984). On the methodological basis of research in teaching and
learning. In M. Hedegaard, P. Hakkarainen, & Y. Engeström (Eds.), Learning and teaching on a scientific
basis: Methodological and epistemological aspects of the activity theory of learning and teaching (pp. 119–
190). Aarhus, DK: Aarhus Universitet.
Eriksson, I., & Lindberg, V. (2016). Enriching ‘learning activity’ with ‘epistemic practices’ – enhancing students’
epistemic agency and authority. NordSTEP: Nordic Journal of Studies in Educational Policy, 2.
http://dx.doi.org/10.3402/nstep.v2.32432.
Farnell, B. (1999). Moving bodies, acting selves. Annual Review of Anthropology, 28, 341-73.
Fischer, K. W., Goswami, U., & Geake, J. (2010). The future of educational neuroscience. Mind, Brain, and
Education, 4, 68–80.
Flannery, M. C. (2007). Observations in biology. The American Biology Teacher, 69(9), 561–564.
Fogel, A. (1996). Relational narratives of the pre-linguistic self. In P. Rochat (Ed.), The self in early infancy: Theory
and research (pp. 117-139). North Holland: Elsevier.
Forman, E. A., & Cazden, C.B. (1995). Exploring Vygotskian perspectives in education: The value of peer
interaction. In J.V. Wertsch (Ed.), Culture, communication, and cognition: Vygotskian perspectives (pp. 323–
347). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Galperin, P. Ia. (1966). Psikhologija mishlenija i uchenie o poetapnom formirovanii umstvennikh dejstvij
[Psychology of thinking and the theory of stage-by-stage formation of mental actions]. In E.V. Shorokhova
(Ed.), Issledovanija mishlenija v sovetskoj psikhologii [Studies of thinking in Soviet psychology] (pp. 236–
277). Moscow: Nauka.
Galperin, P. Ia. (1967). On the notion of internalization. Soviet Psychology, 5 (3), 28–33. (Original work published
1966)
Galperin, P. I. (1976). Vvedenie v psikhologiiu [Introduction to psychology]. Moscow: MGU.
Galperin, P. Ia. (1981). Kurs lektsii po obschei psikhologii [Lectures on general psychology]. Unpublished
manuscript.
Galperin, P. Ia. (1985). Metody obuchenija i umstvennoe razvitie rebenka [Methods of instruction and mental
development of the child]. Moscow: MGU.
Galperin, P. Ia. (1989a). Mental actions as basis for the formation of thoughts and images. Soviet Psychology, 27 (3),
45–65. (Original work published 1957)
Galperin, P. Ia (1989b). Organization of mental activity and the effectiveness of learning. Soviet Psychology, 27 (3),
65–82. (Original work published 1974)
Galperin, P. Ia (1989c). The problem of attention. Soviet Psychology, 27 (3), 83–92. (Original work published 1976)
Galperin, P. Ia. (1989d). Study of the intellectual development of the child. Soviet Psychology, 27, 26–44 (Original
work published 1969)
Galperin, P. I. (1992a). Otvety na voprosy zhurnala Estudios de Psichologia [An interview to the journal Estudios de
Psichologia]. Vestnik Moskovskogo Universiteta, 4, 3–10.
Galperin, P. Ia. (1992b). The problem of activity in Soviet psychology. Journal of Russian and East European
Psychology, 30 (4) 37-59. (Original work published 1977)
Galperin, P. Ia. (1998). Psikhologiia kak obiektivnaia nauika [Psychology as an objective science]. Moscow: Institut
Prakticheskoi Psikhologii.
Galperin, P. Ia., & Elkonin, D. B. (1967). K analizy teorii Zhana Piazhe o razviti detskogo myshlenija [Piaget’s
theory of development of children’s thinking]. Afterword in J. H. Flavell, Geneticheskaja psikhologija Zh.
Piazhe [Developmental psychology of J. Piaget] (pp. 596–621). Moscow: Prosveschenie.
Galperin, P. Ia., & Georgiev, L. S. (1960). Psikhologicheskij analiz sovremennoj metodiki obuchenija nachalnim
matematicheskim ponjatijam [Psychological analysis of methods of teaching concepts in elementary
mathematics]. Moscow: Doklady APN RSFSR, 1, 3, 4, 5, 6.
Galperin, P. Ia., & Kabylnitskaya, S. L. (1974). Eksperimentalnoe formirovanie vnimaniya [Experimental formation
of attention]. Moscow: MGU.
Galperin, P. Ia., & Talyzina, N. F. (1961). Formation of elementary geometrical concepts and their dependance on
directed participation of the pupils. In E. O’Conner (Ed.), Recent Soviet psychology (pp. 247–272). Oxford:
Pergamon Press. (Original work published 1957)
Gazzaniga, M. S. (2011). Who is in charge? Free will and the science of the brain. New York: Ecco/HarperCollins
Publishers.
Gergely, G., & Watson, J. S. (1999). Early socio-emotional development: contingency perception and the social-
biofeedback model. In P. Rochat (Ed.), Early social cognition: Understanding others in the first months of
life (pp. 101-136). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Gergen, K. J. (2010). The acculturated brain. Theory & Psychology, 20 (6), 795-816.
Glick, J. (2013). Recovering the organismic: Werner and Kaplan’s “symbol formation” 50 years later. Culture and
Psychology, 19(4), 441-452.
Greenfield, P.M. (1984). A theory of the teacher in the learning activities of everyday life. In B. Rogoff & J. Lave
(Eds.), Everyday cognition: Its development in social contexts (pp. 117–138). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Gilbert, S. F. (1994). Dobzhansky, Waddington, and Schmalhausen: Embryology and the modern synthesis. In M.
B. Adams (Ed.), The evolution of Theodosius Dobzhansky (pp. 143-154). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Gold, I. & Stoljar, D. (1999). A neuron doctrine in the philosophy of neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
22(5), 809-830.
Gottlieb, G. (1992). Individual development and evolution: The genesis of novel behavior. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Gottlieb, G. (2002). Developmental-behavioral initiation of evolutionary change. Psychological Review, 109, 211-
218.
Haenen, J. (1996). Piotr Galperin: Psychologist in Vygotsky’s footsteps. Commack, NY: Nova Science Publishers.
Halpern, D. F. (1998). Teaching critical thinking for transfer across domains. American Psychologist, 53, 449–455.
Harré, R. (1992). Introduction: The second cognitive revolution. American Behavioral Scientist, 36, 5-7.
Harré, R. (1999). The rediscovery of the human mind: The discursive approach. Asian Journal of Social Psychology,
2, 43-62.
Harré, R. (2012). The brain can be thought of as a tool. Integrative Physiological and Behavioral Science, 46(3),
387-394.
Hollan, J., Hutchins, E., & Kirsh, D. (2000). Distributed cognition: Toward a new foundation for human-computer
interaction research. Transactions on Computer-Human Interaction, 7, 174-196.
Hruby, G. G. (2012). Three requirements for justifying an educational neuroscience. British Journal of Educational
Psychology, 82(1), 1-23.
Hedegaard, M. (1990). The ZPD as basis for instruction. L.C. Moll (Ed.), Vygotsky and education: Instructional
implications and applications of sociohistorical psychology. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hedegaard, M. (1995). The qualitative analysis of the development of a child’s theoretical knowledge and thinking.
In L. M. W. Martin, K. Nelson, & E. Tobach (Eds.), Sociocultural psychology: Theory and practice of doing
and knowing (pp. 293–325). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hedegaard, M. (1999). Activity theory and history teaching. In Y. Engestroem, R. Miettinen, & R. L. Punamaeki
(Eds), Perspectives on activity theory. (282-297). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Hedegaard, M. (2002). Learning and child development: A Cultural-historical study. Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.
Hedegaard , M. , & Fleer , M. ( 2013). Play, learning, and children’s development. Cambridge MA: Cambridge
University Press.
Humboldt, W. von (1999). On the diversity of human language construction and its influence on the mental
development of human species. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published
1836)
Humphrey, N. (2000). How to solve the mind–body problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7, 5–20.
Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Huttenlocher, P. R. (2002). Neural plasticity: The effect of environment on the development of cerebral cortex.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jablonka, E. (2001). The systems of inheritance. In S. Oyama, P. E. Griffiths, & R. D. Gray (Eds.), Cycles of
contingency: Developmental systems and evolution (pp. 99-116). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jakobson, R. (1990). On language. Edited by L. R. Waugh & M. Monville-Burston. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology, Vol. 1. New York: Holt.
Jaynes, J. (1976). The origin of consciousness in the breakdown of the bicameral mind. Reading, MA: Addison-
Wesley.
Jarrett, C. (2015). Great myths of the brain. Chichester, UK: Willey/Blackwell.
Joldersma, C. W. (2013). Neuroscience, education, and a radical embodiment model of mind and cognition. In C.
Mayo (Ed.), Philosophy of education 2013 (p.263-272). Urbana, IL: Philosophy of Education Society.
Ilyenkov, E. (2002). Shkola dolzhna uchit myslit [Schools must teach thinking]. Moscow/Voronezh: Moskovskii
Psikhologo-Sotsialnyi Institut.
Janet, P. (1935). Les débuts de l'intelligence. Paris: Flammarion.
Kabanova, O. Ia. (1976). Osnovnye voprosy metodiki obuchenya inostrannomu yaziku na osnove kontseptsii
upravleniya usvoeniem [Methodology of teaching foreign language based on the concept of guided knowledge
acquisition]. Moscow: MGU.
Kandell, E. R. (2007). In search of memory: The emergence of a new science of mind. New York: W. W. Norton &
Co.
Kandell, E. R. (2016). Reductionism in art and brain science: Bridging the two cultures. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Kaptelinin, V., & Nardi, B. A. (2006). Acting with technology: Activity theory and interaction design. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Karpov, Yu. V. (2005). The Neo-Vygotskian approach to child development. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Karpov, Y. V., & Haywood, H.C. (1998). Two ways to elaborate Vygotsky’s concept of mediation: Implications for
instruction. American Psychologist, 53, 27–36.
Karpova, S. N. (1967). Osoznanie slovesnogo sostava rechi doshkolnikami [Preschoolers’ awareness of the lexical
structure of speech]. Moscow: MGU.
Karpova, S. N. (1977a). The realization of the verbal composition of speech by preschool children. The Hague:
Mouton. (Original work published 1967)
Karpova, S. N. (1977b). Kharakter orientirovki doshkolnikov na slovo pri raznykh tipakh ucheniia [Preschoolers’
orientation toward words in different types of learing]. In P. Ia. Galperin (Ed.), Upravliaemoe formirovanie
psikhicheskikh protsessov [Guided formation of mental processes] (120-136). Moscow: MGU.
Keller, H. (2011). Culture and cognition: Developmental perspective. Journal of Cognitive Education &
Psychology, 10(1), 3-8. http://dx.doi.org/10.1891/19458959.10.1.3
Kozulin, A. (1990). Vygotsky’s psychology: A biography of ideas. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Kozulin, A. (1995). The learning process: Vygotsky’s theory in the mirror of its interpretations. School Psychology
International, 16, 117–129.
Kozulin, A. (1998). Psychological tools: A sociocultural approach to education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Köhler, W. (1971). Methods of psychological research with apes. In The selected papers of Wolfgang Köhler (197-
233). New York: Liveright Publishing. (Original work published 1927)
Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition (1983). Culture and cognitive development. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.),
Handbook of child psychology (Vol. 1): History, theory, and methods (pp. 295–356). New York: Wiley.
Lantolf, J., Thorne, S. L., & Poehner, M. (2015). Sociocultural theory and second language development. In B. van
Patten & J. Williams (Eds.), Theories in second language acquisition (pp. 207-226). New York: Routledge.
Latash, M. L. (2015). Bernstein’s “desired future” and the physics of human movement. In M. Nadin (Ed.),
Anticipation: The Russian/Soviet contributions to the science of anticipation (pp. 287-300). New
York/London: Springer Publishing.
Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning: Legitimate peripheral participation. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Lawrence, J., & Valsiner, J. (1993). Conceptual roots of internalization: From transition to transformation. Human
Development, 36 (3); 150-167.
Lawrence, J., & Valsiner, J. (2003). Making personal sense: An account of basic internalization and externalization
processes. Theory and Psychology, 13 (6), 723-752.
Lemke, J. L. (1990). Talking science: Language, learning and values. Norwood NJ: Ablex Publishing.
Lemke, J. (2001). Articulating communities: Sociocultural perspectives on science education. Journal of Research in
Science Teaching, 38(3), 296-316.
Lengrenzi, P. & Umilta, C. (2011). Neuromania: On the limits of brain science. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lebesgue, H. (1958). Notice d’histoire des mathématiques [Notes on the history of mathematics]. Geneva:
L’Enseignement mathematique.
Lerman, S. (2000). The social turn in mathematics education research. In J. Boaler (Ed.), Multiple perspectives on
mathematics teaching and learning (pp.19-44). Westport, CT: Ablex Publishing.
Lerner, G. I. (1980). Psikhologiya vospriyatiya prostranstvennikh form [Psychology of the perception of spatial
forms]. Moscow: MGU.
Leiman, M. (1999). The concept of sign in the work of Vygotsky, Winnicott, and Bakhtin: Further integration of object
relations theory and activity theory. In J. Engeström, R. Miettinen, & R. Punamäki (Eds.) (1999), Perspectives
on activity theory (pp. 419-434). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Leontiev, A. A. (2001). Deiatelnyi um [The active mind]. Moscow: Smysl.
Leontiev, A. N. (1981). Problems of the development of mind. Moscow: Progress. (Original work published 1959)
Leontiev, A. N. (1983). Deiatelnost, soznanie, lichnost [Activity, consciousness, personality]. In V. Davydov, V.
Zinchenko, A. A. Leontiev & A. Petrovskij (Eds.), A. N. Leontiev. Izbrannie psihologicheskie proizvedenija
[A. N. Leontiev. Selected psychological works] Vol. 2, pp. 94–231. Moscow: Pedagogika.
Lévy-Bruhl, L. (1966). Primitive mentality. Boston: Beacon Press. (Original work published 1922).
Lickliter, R., & Honeycutt, H. (2013). A developmental evolutionary framework for psychology. Review of General
Psychology, 17, 184–189.
Lickliter, R., & Honeycutt, H. (2015). Biology, development, and human systems. In R. M.
Lerner (Ed.), Handbook of child psychology and developmental science (pp. 162–207). New
York: Wiley.
Lickliter, R. & Schneider, S. M. (2006). The role of development in evolutionary change: A view from comparative
psychology. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 19, 151-169.
Lisina, M. I. (1986). Potrebnost v obschenii [The need for communication]. In Lisina M. I. (Ed.), Problemy
ontogeneza obschenia (pp. 31-57). Moscow: Pedagogika.
Litowitz, B. (2000). Commentary on A. Perinat and M. Sadurni “The ontogenesis of meaning: An interactional
approach.” Mind, Culture, and Activity, 7, 243-248.
Lyra, M. C. D. P. (2007). On abbreviation: Dialogue in early life. International Journal for Dialogical Science, 2,
15-44.
Lompscher, J. (1984). Problems and results of experimental research on the formation of theoretical thinking
through instruction. In M. Hedegaard, P. Hakkarainen, & Y. Engeström (Eds.), Learning and teaching on a
scientific basis: Methodological and epistemological aspects of the activity theory of learning and teaching
(pp. 293–358). Aarhus, DK: Aarhus Universitet.
Lompscher, J. (1999). Motivation and activity. European Journal of Psychology of Education, 14, 11–22.
Lompscher , J. ( 2004). Lernkultur und Kompetenzentwicklung aus kulturhistoricher Sicht: Lernen Erwachsener im
Arbeitsprozess [Learning culture and competence development in a cultural– historical perspective: Adult
learning in the process of work]. Berlin: Lehmanns Media.
Maksimov, L. K. (1979). Zavisimost razvitya matematicheskogo mishleniya shkolnikov ot haraktera obucheniya
[The character of teaching-learning and the development of mathematical thinking in schoolchildren].
Voprosy Psikhologii, 2, 57–65.
Malov, S. L. (1976). Usloviya obrazovaniya visshikh edinits dvigatelnogo navyka [Development of high-order motor
skills]. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Moscow State University.
Mandler, J. (1992). How to build a baby: II. Conceptual primitives. Psychological Review, 99, 587-604.
Markus, G. (2012). Neuroscience fiction. The New Yorker, November 30, 2012.
Marshall, P. J. (2009). Relating psychology and neuroscience: Taking up challenges. Perspectives on psychological
science, 4(2), 113-125.
Marshall, S. P. (1995). Schemas in problem solving. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Marx, C. (2000). The German Ideology. In D. McLellan (Ed.), Selected writings of Carl Marx (pp. 175-208).
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1932)
Mashburn, A. J., Pianta, R., Hamre, B. K., Downer, J. T., Barbarin, O., Bryant, D., Burchinal, M., Clifford, R.,
Early, D., Howes, C. (2008). Measures of classroom quality in pre-kindergarten and children’s development
of academic, language and social skills. Child Development, 79, 732-749.
Mausfeld, R. (2012). On some unwarranted tacit assumptions in cognitive neuroscience. Frontiers in Psychology,
v.3, article 67. http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00067
Maynard, A. E. (2008). What we thought we knew and how we came to know it: Four decades of cross-cultural
research from a Piagetian point of view. Human Development, 51, 56-65.
McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McTighe, J., & Lyman, F. T. (1988). Cueing thinking in the classroom: The promise of theory embedded tools.
Educational Leadership, 45, 18–24.
Matusov, E. (2001). The theory of developmental learning activity in education: Dialectics of the learning
content. Culture and Psychology, 7(2), 231–240.
McCabe, D. P., & Castel, A. D. (2008). Seeing is believing: The effect of brain images as judgments of scientific
reasoning. Cognition, 107, 343–352.
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self and society. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Miller, G. (2008). Growing pains for fMRI. Science Magazine, 320, 1412-1414.
Minick, N. (1987). The development of Vygotsky’s thought: An introduction. In R. W. Rieber & A. S. Carton
(Eds.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky: Vol. 3. Problems of general psychology (pp. 17–38). New
York: Plenum.
Minskaya, G. I. (1966). Formirovanie ponyatiya chisla na osnove izucheniya otnosheniya velichin [Formation of the
concept of number on the basis of comparison of quantities]. In D. B. Elkonin, & V. V. Davydov (Eds.),
Vozrastnye vozmozhnosti usvoyeniy znanii [Age-related potential for knowledge acquisition] (pp. 190–235).
Moscow: Prosveschenie.
Morrison, A. B., Conway, A. R. A., & Chain, J. M. (2014). Primacy and recency effects as indices of the focus of
attention. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8(6), http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00006.
Moll, I. (1994). Reclaiming the natural line in Vygotsky's theory of cognitive development. Human Development, 37,
333-342.
Morse, S. J. (2005). Brain overclaim syndrome and criminal responsibility: A diagnostic note. Ohio State Journal of
Criminal Law, 3, 397-413.
Mozes, E. (2010). The dogmatic determinism of Daniel Dennett. http://atlassociety.org/objectivism/atlas-
university/deeper-dive-blog/3712-the-dogmatic-determinism-of-daniel-dennett
Müller, U. & Carpendale, J. I. M. (2000). The role of social interaction in Piaget’s theory: Language for social
cooperation and social cooperation for language. New Ideas in Psychology, 18, 139-156.
Müller, U., & Newman, J. L. (2008). The body in action: Perspective on embodiment and development. In W. F.
Overton, U. Müller, & J. L. Newman (Eds.), Developmental perspectives on embodiment and consciousness
(pp. 313-342). New York: Erlbaum.
Müller, U., & Overton, W. (1998). How to grow a baby: A reevaluation of image-schema and Piagetian action
approaches to representation. Human Development, 41, 71-111.
Müller, U., Sokol, B., & Overton, W. (1998). Reframing a constructivist model of the development of mental
representation: The role of higher-order operations. Developmental Review, 18, 155–201.
Müller, U., Yeung, E. & Hutchison, S. M. (2013). The role of distancing in Werner and Kaplan’s account of symbol
formation and beyond. Culture and Psychology, 19(4), 463–483.
Nelson, K. (1974). Concept, word, and sentence: Interrelations in acquisition and development. Psychological
Review, 81, 267-285.
Nelson, K. (1996). Language in cognitive development: The emergence of the mediated mind. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Nelson, K. (2007). Young minds in social worlds: Experience, meaning, and memory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Newman, D., Griffin, P., & Cole, M. The construction zone. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Noë, A. (2009). Out of our heads: Why you are not your brain, and other lessons from the biology of consciousness.
New York: Hill & Wang.
Núñez, R. (2004). Do real numbers really move? Language, thought, and gesture: The embodied cognitive
foundations of mathematics. In F. Iida, F., R. Pfeifer, L. Steels, & Y. Kunyoshi, (Eds.), Embodied artificial
intelligence. New York: Springer.
Obukhova, L. F. (1968). Formirovanie sistemy fizicheskikh ponjatii v primenenii k resheniyu zadach [Formation of
physical concepts in the process of problem solving]. In P. Ia. Galperin & N. F. Talyzina (Eds.), Zavisimost
obucheniya ot tipa orientirovochnoi deyatelnosti [Dependence of teaching on the type of orienting activity]
(pp. 153–186). Moscow: MGU.
Obukhova, L. F. (1972). Etapy razvitija detskogo myshlenija [Stages of development of the child’s thinking].
Moscow: MGU.
Obukhova (1981). Kontsepsiia Jean Piaget: Za i protiv [The theory of Jean Piaget: Pros and cons]. Moscow: MGU
Obukhova, L. F. (2001). P. Ia. Galperin i J. Piaget: dva podhoda k probleme psikhologicheskogo razvitiia rebenka
[P. Ia. Galperin and J. Piaget: Two approaches to child mental development]. In L. F. Obukhova & G. V.
Burmenskaya (Eds.), Jean Piaget: Teoriia, eksperimenty, diskussii [Jean Piaget: Theory, experiments,
discussions] (352-366). Moscow: Gardariki. (First published 1998)
Olson, D. (2005). Technology and intelligence in a literate society. In R. Sternberg & D. Preiss (Eds.), Intelligence and
technology: The impact of tools on the nature and development of human abilities (pp.55-67). Mahwah, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Orestov, R.O. (1989). Formirovanie professionalnoi orientirovki visokokvalifitsirovannikh rabotchikh [Formation of
professional orientation in industrial workers]. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Moscow State University.
Osipova, N. R. (1977). Formation of attention in mentally retarded schoolchildren. In P. Ia. Galperin (Ed.),
Upravlyayemoe formirovanie psikhicheskikh protsessov [Guided formation of psychological processes] (pp.
71–79). Moscow: MGU.
Overton, W. F. (1998). Developmental psychology: Philosophy, concepts, and methodology. In W. Damon & R. M.
Lerner (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology, Vol. 1: Theoretical models of human development (pp. 107-188).
New York: Wiley.

Overton, W. F., Müller, U., & Newman, J. L. (Eds.) (2008). Developmental perspectives on embodiment and
consciousness. New York, NY: Erlbaum.
Palincsar, A. S., & Brown, A. L. (1984). Reciprocal teaching of comprehension-fostering and comprehension-
monitoring activities. Cognition and Instruction, 1, 117–175.
Pantina, N. S. (1957). Formirovanie dvigatelnogo navika pisma v zavisimosti ot tipa orientirovki v zadanii
[Formation of writing skills in relation to the type of orientation in the task]. Voprosy Psikhologii, 4, 117–
132.
Penrose, R. (1989). The emperor’s new mind: Concerning computers, minds, and the laws of physics. Oxford,
England: Oxford University Press.
Perinat, A., & Sadurni, M. (1999). The ontogenesis of meaning: An interactional approach. Mind, Culture, and
Activity, 6, 53-76.
Perkins, D. N. (1995a). Outsmarting IQ: The emerging science of learnable intelligence. New York: Free Press.
Perkins, David N. (1995b). Smart schools: Better thinking and learning for every child. New York: Free Press.
Perkins, D. N., & Grotzner, T. A. (1997). Teaching intelligence. American Psychologist, 52, 1125–1133.
Piaget (1950). The psychology of intelligence. New York: Harcourt, Brace. (Original work published 1947)
Piaget, J. (1952a). The origins of intelligence in children. New York: International University Press. (Original work
published 1936)
Piaget, J. (1952b). The child’s conception of number. London: Routledge. (Original work published 1946)
Piaget, J. (1955). Les stades du développement intellectuel de l’enfant et de l’adolescent [Stages of intellectual
development of the child and adolescent]. In P. Osterrieth (Ed.), Le problème des stades en psychologie de
l’enfant [The problem of developmental stages in child psychology] (pp. 33–113). Paris: Presses Univer.
Piaget, J. (1974). The child and reality: Problems of genetic psychology. London: Frederick Muller. (Original work
published 1972)
Pinker, S. (2003). Blank Slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York: Penguin Books.
Pinker, S. (2009). How the mind works. New York: Norton & Company. (First published 1997)
Podolskij, A. I. (1978). Formirovanie simultannogo opoznaniya [Formation of simultaneous identification].
Moscow: MGU.
Podolskij, A. P. (1987). Stanovlenie poznavatelnogo deistviia: Nauchnaia abstraktsiia i realnost [The development
of cognitive action: Scientific abstraction and reality]. Moscow: MGU.
Podolskij, A. I. (2008). Bridging a gap between psychology and instructional practice. In D. Ifethaler, P. Pirnay-
Dummer, & M. Spector (Eds.), Understanding models for learning and instruction (pp. 211-224). New York:
Springer.
Poluyanov, Y. A. (1982). Voobrazhenie i sposobnosti [Imagination and abilities]. Moscow: Pedagogika.
Racine, T. P. (2004). Wittgenstein’s internalistic logic and children’s theories of mind. In J. I. M. Carpendale & U.
Müller (Eds.), Social interaction and the development of knowledge. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Racine, T. P. & Carpendale, J. I. M. (2007). The role of shared practice in joint attention. British Journal of
Developmental Psychology, 25, 3–25.
Ratner, C. (1991). Vygotsky's sociohistorical psychology and its contemporary applications. New York: Plenum
Press.
Reed, E. S. (1997). From soul to mind: The emergence of psychology from Erasmus Darwin to William James. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Rees, T. (2010) Being neurologically human today. Life and science and adult cerebral plasticity. American
Ethnologist, 37, 150–166.
Repkina, N. V. (1983). Pamyat i osobennosti tselepolaganiya v uchebnoi deyatelnosti mladshikh shkolnikov
[Memory and goal-setting in learning activity of primary schoolchildren]. Voprosy Psikhologii, 1, 56–57.
Reshetova, Z.A. (1985). Psikhologicheskie osnovi professionalnogo obucheniya [Psychological foundations of
professional training]. Moscow: MGU.
Rochat, P. (2009). Others in mind: Social origins of self-consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Rogoff, B. (1990). Apprenticeship in thinking: Cognitive development in social context. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Rogoff, B. (1994). Developing understanding of the idea of communities of learners. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 1,
209–229.
Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development. New York: Oxford University Press.
Rogoff, B., & Chavajay, P. (1995). What’s become of research on the cultural basis of cognitive development?
American Psychologist, 50, 859–877.
Rogoff, B., Radziszewska, B., & Masiello, T. (1995). Analysis of developmental processes in sociocultural activity.
In L. M. Martin, K. Nelson, & E. Tobach (Eds.), Sociocultural psychology: Theory and practice of knowing
and doing (pp. 125–149). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rose, N. & Abi-Rached, J. M. (2013). Neuro: The brain sciences and the management of the mind. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Ryle, G. (1984). The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press (First published 1949)
Salmina, N. G. (1988). Znak i simvol v obuchenii [Signs and symbols in teaching and learning]. Moscow: MGU
Salomon, G. (Ed.). (1993). Distributed cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Salomon, G., & Perkins, D.N. (1989). Rocky roads to transfer: Rethinking mechanisms of a neglected phenomenon.
Educational Psychologist, 24, 113–142.
Salmina, N. G., & Sokhina, V. P. (1975). Obuchenie matematike v nachalnoi shkole [Teaching mathematics in
elementary school]. Moscow: Pedagogika.
Satel, S. & Lilienfeld, S. (2013). Brainwashed: The seductive appeal of mindless neuroscience. New York: Basic
Books.
Sanchez, H. (2017). The education revolution: How to apply brain science to improve instruction and school
climate. Thousand Oaks, CA: Corwin/Sage.
Scardamalia, M., & Bereiter, C. (1985). Fostering the development of self-regulation in children’s knowledge
processing. In S. F. Chipman, J. W. Segal, & R. Glaser (Eds.), Thinking and learning skills, Vol. 2: Research
and open questions (pp. 563–577).
Schmittau, J. (2004). Vygotskian theory and mathematics education: Resolving the conceptual-procedural
dichotomy. European Journal of Psychology of Education, 19 (1) 19-43.
Schmittau, J. (2005). The development of algebraic thinking: A Vygotskian perspective. ZMD [Zentralblatt für
Didaktik der Mathematik], 37 (1), 16-22, http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF02655893.
Schulz, L. E., Goodman, N. D., Tenenbaum, J. B., & Jenkins, A. (2008). Going beyond the evidence: Abstract
laws and preschoolers responses to anomalous data. Cognition, 109, 211-223.
Semenyuk, L. A. (1970). Formirovanie umstvennikh deistvii v protsesse izucheniya istorii [Formation of mental
actions in the process of teaching history]. In N.F. Talyzina (Ed.), K probleme upravleniya obucheniem i
vospitaniem [Guided learning in education] (pp. 44–64). Moscow: MGU.
Shotter, J. (1993). Vygotsky: The social negotiation of semiotic mediation. New Ideas in Psychology, 11, 61-75.
Sinha, C. (2000). Culture, language and the emergence of subjectivity. Culture & Psychology, 6, 197-207.
Smith, L. B. (2005). Cognition as a dynamic system: Principles from embodiment. Developmental Review, 25, 278-
298.
Sokolov E. N. (1960). Neuronal models and the orienting reflex. In M. Brazier (Ed.), The central nervous system
and behavior (pp. 187–276). New York: Josiah Macy Jr. Foundation.
Sokolov E. N., Spinks J. A, Naatanen R., & Lyytinen H. (2002). The orienting response in information processing.
Mahwah, NJ/London, UK: Erlbaum.
Sousa, D. A. (2011). How the brain learns (4th ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: Corwin Press.
Srull, T. (1997). The vicissitudes of social behavior and mental life. In R. S. Wyer Jr. (Ed.), The automaticity of
everyday life: Advances in social cognition (Vol. 10, pp. 203–215). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Sternberg, R. J. (1997). Intelligence and lifelong learning: What’s new and how can we use it? American
Psychologist, 52, 1134–1139.
Stetsenko, A. (1981). Vygotskii i problema znachenija [Vygotsky and the concept of meaning]. In V. V. Davydov
(Ed.), Nauchnoe tvorchestvo L. S. Vygotskogo i sovremennaia psihologiia [Scientific works of L. S. Vygotsky
and contemporary psychology] (pp. 148-151). Moscow: Academy of Pedagogical Sciences Press.
Stetsenko, A. (1989). The concept of an “image of the world” and some problems in the ontogeny of consciousness.
Soviet Psychology, 27, 6-24. (Original work published 1987)
Stetsenko, A. P. (1995). The role of the principle of object-relatedness in activity theory. Journal of Russian & East
European Psychology, 33(6), 54-69. (Original work published 1990)
Stetsenko, A. (2004). Introduction to Vygotsky "Tool and Sign in the Development of the Child". In R. Rieber & D.
Robinson (Eds.), The Essential Vygotsky (pp. 499-510). New York: Plenum Press.
Stetsenko, A. (2005a). Razvitie znachenii v ontogeneze [Development of meanings in ontogeny]. In A. Stetsenko,
Rozhdenie soznaniia [The birth of consciousness] (pp. 11-137). Moscow: CheRo Press. (First published
1984)
Stetsenko, A. (2005b). Activity as object-related: Resolving the dichotomy of individual and collective types of
activity. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 12, 70-88.
Stetsenko , A. (2010). Teaching- learning and development as activist projects of historical becoming: Expanding
Vygotsky’s approach to pedagogy. Pedagogies: An International Journal, 5, 6–16.
Stetsenko, A. (2016). The transformative mind: Expanding Vygotsky’s approach to development and education.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Stetsenko, A. (2017, in press). Putting the radical notion of equality in the service of disrupting inequality in
education: Research findings and conceptual advances on the infinity of human potential. Review of Research
in Education.
Stetsenko, A., & Arievitch, I. M. (1996). The zone of proximal development: Resolving the contradiction between
idea and method in post-Vygotskyan psychology. In J. Lompscher (Ed.), Entwicklung und Lernen aus
kulturhistorischer Sicht [Development and learning form a cultural-historical point of view] (pp. 81–93).
Marburg: BdWi-Verlag.
Stetsenko, A., & Arievitch, I. M. (1997). Constructing and deconstructing the self: Comparing post-Vygotskian and
discourse-based versions of social constructivism. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 4, 160–173.
Stetsenko A., & Arievitch, I. M. (2002). Teaching, learning, and development: A post-Vygotskian perspective. In G.
Wells & G. Claxton (Eds.), Learning for life in the 21st century: Sociocultural perspectives on the future of
education (pp. 84-96). London: Blackwell.
Stetsenko, A. & Arievitch, I. M. (2004). The self in cultural-historical activity theory: Reclaiming the unity of social
and individual dimensions of human development. Theory and Psychology, 14 (4), 475-503.
Stetsenko, A. & Arievitch, I. M. (2010). Cultural-historical activity theory: Foundational worldview, major principles,
and the relevance of sociocultural context. In J. Martin and S. Kirschner (Eds.), The sociocultural turn in
psychology: The contextual emergence of mind and self (pp. 231-252). New York: Columbia University Press.
Still, A., & Costall, A. (1991). The mutual elimination of dualism in Vygotsky and Gibson. In A. Still & A. Costall
(Eds.), Against cognitivism. Alternative foundations for cognitive psychology (pp. 225-236). Hemel
Heampstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Sudakov, K. V. (2015). Theory of functional systems: A keystone of integrative biology. In M. Nadin (Ed.),
Anticipation: The Russian/Soviet contributions to the science of anticipation (pp. 153-174). New
York/London: Springer Publishing.
Susswein, N., Bibok, M. B. & Carpendale, J. I. M. (2007). Reconcepualizing internalization. International Journal
of Dialogical Science, 2(1), 183-205.
Sutton, A. (1980). Backward children in the USSR: An unfamiliar approach to a familiar problem. In M. Brine, M.
Perrie, & A. Sutton (Eds.), Home, school, and leisure in the Soviet Union (pp. 160–191). London: George
Allen & Unwin.
Tallis, R. (2011). Aping mankind: Neuromania, Darwinitis and the misrepresentation of humanity. Durham, UK:
Acumen Publishing.
Talyzina, N. F. (1981). The psychology of learning. Moscow: Progress. (Original work published 1975)
Talyzina, N. F. (1998). Pedagogicheskaya psikhologiya [Educational psychology]. Moscow: Academia.
Terlouw, C. (1993). A model for instructional development: Integration of theory and practice. In C. Terlouw (Ed.),
Instructional development in higher education: Theory and practice (pp. 11–33). Amsterdam: Thesis
Publishers.
Tharp, R. G., & Gallimore, R. (1988). Rousing minds to life: Teaching, learning, and schooling in social context.
Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Tobias, J. W., & Andreasen, J. B. (2013). Developing multiplicative thinking from additive reasoning. Teaching
Children Mathematics, 20(2), 102-109.
Todes, D. (2000). Ivan Pavlov: Exploring the animal machine. New York: Oxford University Press.
Tolman, C. W. (1992). Neopositivism and perception theory. In C. W. Tolman (Ed.), Positivism in psychology. New
York: Springer.
Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Tomasello, M., & Carpenter, M. (2013). Dueling dualists, Human Development, 56(6), 401-405.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity.
In M. M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before speech: The beginning of human communication (pp. 99-136). London:
Cambridge University Press.
Tsatskovskaja, M. (1978). Formirovanie obstchikh priemov mishleniya uchaschikhsja pri reshenii zadach
[Formation of general problem solving skills in mathematics]. In P. Ia. Galperin (Ed.), Upravlyayemoe
formirovanie psikhicheskikh protsessov [Guided formation of psychological processes] (pp. 80–100).
Moscow: MGU.
Tutdge, J. R. H., & Scrimsher, S. (2003). Lev Vygotsky on education: A cultural-historical, interpersonal, and
individual approach to education. In Barry J. Zimmerman and Dale H. Schunk (Eds.), Educational
psychology: A century of contributions (pp. 207-228). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Tudge, J. R. H., & Winterhoff, P. A. (1993). Vygotsky, Piaget, Bandura: Perspectives on the relations between the
social world and cognitive development. Human Development, 36, 61-81.
Uttal, W. R. (2001). The new phrenology: The limits of localizing cognitive processes in the brain. Cambridge, MA:
The MIT Press.
Valsiner, J. & van der Veer, R. (2000). The social mind: Construction of the idea. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
van der Veer, R., & Arievitch, I. M. (1994). Reception of Piotr Ya. Galperin’s ideas in the West. Perceptual and
Motor Skills, 78, 117–118.
van der Veer, R., & Valsiner, J. (1991). Understanding Vygotsky: A quest for synthesis. Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers.
van der Veer, R. & Van Ijzendoorn, M. H. (1985). Vygotsky’s theory of the higher psychological processes: Some
criticisms. Human Development, 28, 1-9.
van Geert, P. (1987). The structure of Galperin’s model of the formation of the mental acts. Human Development,
30, 355–381.
van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91, 345-381.
van Oers, B., Wardekker , W. , Elbers, E. , & van der Veer , R. (Eds.) ( 2008). The transformation of learning:
Advances in cultural– historical activity theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Varela, F.,Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Varma, S., McCandliss, B., & Schwartz, D. (2008). Scientific and pragmatic challenges for bridging education and
neuroscience. Educational Researcher, 37 (3), 140-152.
Verenikina, I. (2008). Scaffolding and learning: Its role in nurturing new learners. In P. Kell, W. Vialle, D. Konza,
& G. Vogl (Eds), Learning and the learner: Exploring learning for new times (pp. 161-180). Sydney, AU:
University of Wollongong Press.
Vianna, E., & Stetsenko, A. (2011). Connecting learning and identity development through a Transformative
Activist Stance: Application in adolescent development in a child welfare program. Human Development,
54(5), 313-338.
Vonèche, J. (2008). Action as the solution to the mind-body problem in Piaget theory. In W. F. Overton, U. Müller, &
J. Newman (Eds.), Developmental perspectives on embodiment and consciousness (pp. 69-98). New York, NY:
Erlbaum.
Vygotsky, L.S. (1978). Interaction between learning and development. In M. Cole, V. John-Steiner, S. Scribner, & E.
Souberman (Eds.), L. S. Vygotsky: Mind in society. The development of higher psychological processes. (pp. 79-
91). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Original work published 1935)
Vygotsky, L. S. (1981). The genesis of higher mental functions. In J. V. Wertsch (Ed.), The concept of activity in
Soviet psychology (pp. 144–188). Armonk, NY: Sharpe.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1987). Thinking and speech. In R. Rieber, & A. Carton (Eds.), The collected works of L. S.
Vygotsky. Vol. 1. (pp. 39-284). New York and London: Plenum Press. (Original work published 1934)
Vygotsky, L. S. (1997). The history of the development of higher mental functions. In R. W. Rieber (Ed.), The
collected works of L. S. Vygotsky. Vol. 4. New York and London: Plenum Press. (Original work published
1960)
Vygotsky, L. S. (1999). Tool and sign in the development of the child. In R. Rieber (Ed.), The collected works of L. S.
Vygotsky. Vol. 6 (pp. 3-68). New York: Plenum Press. (Original work published 1984)
Vygotsky, L. S., & Luria, A. R. (1993). Essays on the History of Behavior: Ape, primitive, and child. Hillsdale NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. (Original work published 1930)
Weisberg, D. S., Keil, F. C., Goodstein, J., Rawson, E., & Gray, J. (2008). The seductive allure of neuroscience
explanations. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20(3), 470-477.
Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wegner, D. M., & Bargh, J. A. (1998). Control and automaticity in social life. In D. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G.
Lindzey (Eds.), The handbook of social psychology (4th ed., Vol. 1, pp. 446–496). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Westerman, M. A. (2013). Making sense of relational processes and other psychological phenomena: The
participatory perspective as a post-Cartesian alternative to Gergen’s relational approach. Review of General
Psychology, 17 (4), 358 –373.
Wertsch, J. V. (1979). From social interaction to higher psychological process: A clarification and application of
Vygotsky’s theory. Human Development, 22, 1–22.
Wertsch, J. V. (1981). Trends in Soviet cognitive psychology. Storia e critica della psicologia, 2, 219–295.
Wertsch, J. V. (1984). The Zone of Proximal Development: Some conceptual issues. In B. Rogoff, & J. Wertsch
(Eds.), Children’s Learning in the Zone of Proximal Development (pp.7–18). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Wertsch, J. V. (1985). Vygotsky and the social formation of mind. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
Wertsch, J. V. (1993). Commentary on J. A. Lawrence and J. Valsiner, Conceptual roots of internalization: from
transition to transformation. Human Development, 36 (3), 168-171.
Wertsch, J. V. (1998). Mind as action. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wertsch, J. V. (1996). Foreword. In J. Haenen, Piotr Galperin: Psychologist in Vygotsky’s footsteps (pp. xi–xii).
New York: Nova Science.
Wertsch, J. V. (2002). Voices of collective remembering. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Wertsch, J. V. (2007). Mediation. In H. Daniels, M. Cole & J. V. Wertsch (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to
Vygotsky (pp. 178-192). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Whitson, J. A. (1997). Cognition as a semiotic process: from situated mediation to critical reflective transcendence. In
D. Kirshner and J. A. Whitson (Eds.), Situated cognition: Social, semiotic, and psychological perspectives (pp.
97-150). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Willis, J. (2015). The high cost of neuromyths in education. Edutopia, January 16, 2015.
http://www.edutopia.org/blog/high-costs-neuromyths-in-education-judy-willis
Winnicott, D. W. (1964). The child, the family, and the outside world. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books.
Wittgenstein, L. (1978). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Wohlwill, J. F., & Lowe, R. C. (1962). An expermental analysis of development of the conservation of number.
Child Development, 33, 153–167.
Wood, D. J., Bruner J. S., & Ross, G. (1976). The role of tutoring in problem solving. Journal of Child Psychology
and Psychiatry, 17, 89–100.
Zak, A. Z. (1984). Razvitie teoreticheskogo mishleniya u mladshikh shkolnikov [Development of theoretical thinking
in primary schoolers]. Moscow: Pedagogika.
Zaporozhets, A. V. (1977). Some of the psychological problems of sensory training in early childhood and the
preschool period. In M. Cole & I. Maltzman (Eds.), A handbook of contemporary Soviet psychology. (87-
121). New York: Basic Books. (Original work published 1959)
Zaporozhets, A. V. (1986). Umstvennoe razvitie rebenka [Mental development of the child]. In V.P. Zinchenko &
V. V. Davydov (Eds.), Izbrannye psykhologicheskie trudy A. V. Zaporozhtsa [Selected psychological works
of A. V. Zaporozhets]. Vol.1. Moscow: Pedagogika.
Zaporozhets, A. V. & Elkonin, D. B. (1971). The psychology of preschool children. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Zhdan, A. N. (1968). Eksperimentalnoe primenenie psikhologicheskoj teorii o tipakh uchenija k postroeniju
uchebnogo predmeta (na materiale morfologii russkogo jazika) [Implementation of the psychological theory
of the types of instruction in designing a subject-domain curriculum in school (the case of morphology of the
Russian language)]. Unpublished Doctoral dissertation, Moscow State University.
Zinchenko, P. I. (1983). The problem of involuntary memory. Soviet Psychology, 4, 9-33. (Original work published
1939)
Zukerman, G. (2014). Developmental education. In A. Yasnitsky, R. van der Veer, & M. Ferrari (Eds.), The
Cambridge handbook of cultural-historical psychology (pp.177-202). New York: Cambridge University
Press.

You might also like