You are on page 1of 8

TH E S E LF AN D TH E O TH E R

something reductive ( a specifc element) , something identifable, and


something immutable. ESSENTIALISM
VERSUS
Philosophical terms EXISTENTIALISM
 C onsciousness Essentialism is oten
contrasted with
Awareness or experience o the world See also the discussion o
existentialism. These
C onsciousness in Human Nature ( C hapter 2 )
approaches can be
 E ssence explained by highlighting
An essence is the intrinsic or indispensable property or properties that the existentialist
that characterize or identiy an entity. understanding does not
ocus on conceiving
 Material
identity in the same way
The substance or substances out o which a thing is or can be made we understand an entity.
 S ubstance Rather, existentialism is
a concept o the sel that
That which has mass and occupies or is extended space
ocuses on relationships,
 Temporality thus rej ecting the
The condition o being temporal or bounded in time as in past, notion o a predefned
present and uture. entity as the defnitive
aspect o identity. A
 S patiality
valid question to ask is
The conditions o being involved in, or having the nature o space. What is an essence?
It has characteristics or
properties but does it exist
The ancient positions: Plato, Aristotle, and Augustine in time and space? Is it
The oundational concept o the sel has been an enduring one. immutable? Essentialists
Essentialism has been the dominant ramework or Western philosophy requently believe that the
or over 2 ,5 00 years. Plato is regarded as the frst signifcant essentialist essence is metaphysical
as a result o his argument or the Form o the Good as an outcome o and accessible through
his amous Theory o the Forms in various dialogues throughout his lie. 5 introspection. This
These include Timaeus, Phaedo, The Republic, Hippias Major, The Symposium, approach was established
and Parmenides. It was not a perect concept, oten remaining vague with in the western tradition
limited analysis and justifcation. In Parmenides, a later dialogue, Plato even by Plato.
oers six o his own objections to his Theory o the Forms. Nonetheless,
the idea o a metaphysical essence was very attractive and, partly because
o the overall inuence o Platos works, became the defning conceptual
ramework or later philosophical debate and integrated in a C hristian
worldview rom around 400 C E onwards. C onsequently, it has been the
dominant concept in the Western tradition until the mid to late
1 9th century. The original concept is quite simple  the sel is a soul that
is immortal and only exists within a body or a limited amount o time.

The self as psyche or soul


The p syche or soul is an immaterial, thinking substance, which exists
so long as some orm o thought is going on in this substance. It usually
involves a rej ection o the body ( soma) . Plato and D escartes are the key

5
Platos Republic is one of the prescribed titles for Paper 2. The best-known discussion of his Theory of the Forms
is found in this text, and in particular through his famous Allegory of the Cave.

187
5 B E I N G H U M AN

philosophers who have held this view. I we start with Plato we can see
how he establishes the notion o the sel as a metaphysical issue.
Plato agrees with pre-S ocratic philosophers such as Pythagoras and
Heraclitus that psyche or soul is the source or our rational and moral
sel, as well as our biological sel. This concept o the sel already had
a long history. It was present in ancient Greek thought through the
inuence o O rphism, a set o religious belies and practices o the
Thracians and requently associated with literature ascribed to the
mythical poet O rpheus. Platos own philosophical understanding also
reects this view, and the inuence o Plato meant that this concept o
the sel became a common reerence point in debates about the sel.

Understanding the context


The philosophical ambition throughout Platos philosophical writings
was to fnd certainty. This desire, arguably determined by the turbulent
political times he was experiencing, drove him to create a philosophical
system aimed at establishing this certainty. As a consequence, Plato was
unwilling to include anything that could not provide this oundation.
In the ollowing extract rom Phaedo, Socrates, the Athenian philosopher
and teacher eatured in Platos dialogues, is arguing or the existence o the
soul. In the process, he displays a distinct attitude towards other concepts
such as purity, eternity, immortality, and unchangeableness, indicating
clearly an evaluative ramework or determining the source o truth.

Socrates: And were we not saying long ago that Socrates: And to which class is the soul more
the soul when using the body as an instrument nearly alike and akin, as ar as may be inerred
o perception, that is to say, when using the rom this argument, as well as rom the
sense o sight or hearing or some other sense (or preceding one?
the meaning o perceiving through the body is
Cebes: I think, S ocrates, that, in the opinion
perceiving through the senses) were we not
o everyone who ollows the argument,
saying that the soul too is then dragged by the body
the soul will be ininitely more like the
into the region o the changeable, and wanders and
unchangeab leeve n the most stupid person
is conused; the world spins round her, and she is
will not deny that.
like a drunkard, when she touches change?
Socrates: And the body is more like the changing?
Cebes: Very true.
Cebes: Yes.
Socrates: B ut when returning into hersel
she reects, then she passes into the other Plato 6
world, the region o purity, and eternity, and
immortality, and unchangeableness, which are
her kindred, and with them she ever lives, when Questions
she is by hersel and is not let or hindered; then
According to Socrates, what is the relationship
she ceases rom her erring ways, and being in
between the body and the soul?
communion with the unchanging is unchanging.
And this state o the soul is called wisdom? Based on this passage, how does he argue/
Cebes: That is well and truly said, S ocrates. justify this position?

6
Plato, Phaedo, p. 65; see also Plato, The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues, edited by Shane Weller
(New York: Dover Publications, 1992) , pp. 7879.

188
TH E S E LF AN D TH E O TH E R

Plato argued that the sel was an entity that existed in the metaphysical
world. This concept is an abstract concept o the sel and also a rej ection
o the body. As Plato states in Phaedo, the body flls us with all kinds
o lusts, desires, ears, phantoms and a great deal o nonsense, with
the result that we really and truly never ever get a chance to think
about anything at all. 7 This cannot, Plato suggests, be the oundation
o the true sel and the search or knowledge: it has been well and
truly proved to us that i we are ever going to gain pure knowledge
o anything, we must get rid o the body. And we must look at things
themselves with the soul itsel. 8 This claim existed within Platos
broader philosophical system and urther analysis is required to ully
understand the claim Plato is making about the sel.
Plato argues that reality is dualistic, or consists o two dierent realms o
being. One is a realm o change and the other is a realm o permanence.
The frst realm, the realm o change, is transient, where things come and
go. This makes it imperect and unreliable. Socrates suggests that when
the soul touches this region it becomes like a drunkard. This is the
realm o particulars, the realm we perceive with our senses.
The second realm is the opposite; it is the realm o  purity, and
eternity, and immortality, and unchangeableness . I we were to
look or our  sel , as Plato did, we would surely preer it to be
present in the permanent ( even perect) realm. This was Platos
assumption. C onsequently the sel must exist in the permanent
realm, or as he labelled it, the metap hysical realm, or the realm
 beyond the physical .
This view o reality initially seems speculative, even mystical. This is
especially the case when viewed by the modern scientifc mind, an
approach that looks or observable evidence to determine whether
something exists. However, it underpins the Western view o reality.
Plato explained, but did not argue, his theory o metaphysics in his
amous Allegory o the C ave ound in The Republic. In terms o the sel,
Plato identifes the physical realm with the body, and the metaphysical
realm with the true sel or the psyche. In doing so Plato rej ects the body,
even argues that it hinders the sel:

Those who rightly love wisdom are practicing dying, and death to
them is the least terrible thing in the world. Look at it in this way:
I they are everywhere at enmity with the body, and desire the soul
to be alone by itsel, and i, when this very thing happens, they shall
ear and obj ect  would not that be wholly unreasonable? S hould
they not willingly go to a place where there is good hope o fnding
what they were in love with all through lie ( and they loved wisdom)
and o ridding themselves o the companion which they hated?
Plato 9

7
In Plato, Great Dialogues of Plato, translated by W. H. D. Rouse (New York: Signet Classic, 1999) , p. 145.
8
Ibid., p. 146.
9
Ibid., pp. 182183.

189
5 B E I N G H U M AN

Plato clearly discriminates between the physical body and the metaphysical
sel based on a distrust o the body as a changing orm. This attitude
pervades Platos concept o the body.

The Mind/Soul The Body

1. must be the ruler 1. must be ruled

2. is rational 2. is irrational

3. is the crown o virtue/ 3. is shameul/degraded


knowledge and existence

4. is the path to all that is good 4. is an obstacle to all that is good

5. is temporarily imprisoned 5. is a tomb, a prison

6. is important 6. is insignifcant

When looking or a defnitive expression o Platos concept o the sel,


it is not always clear what he means by the psyche. The inuence o
C hristian scholarship has usually interpreted the ancient Greek notion o
psyche as soul. Neither is Platos psyche a mind in the modern sense o
the word. However, there is greater conceptual clarity i it is translated as
inner sel as it avoids the religious overtones that are incorporated into
the notion o the soul.
Further investigation indicates that there are essentially two aspects to
the Platonic inner sel. The frst is that it is the seat of knowledge,
perorming the unctions that we attribute to minds. The second is that
it is the bringer of life; having an inner sel distinguishes a living
thing rom a non- living thing. ( This is where calling the psyche a soul
becomes attractive or C hristian interpretations.) Plato has defned his
sel as the essence o an individual lie.
Plato details the particular eatures o this sel by using reason to
draw an interesting conclusion. In the ollowing dialogue he explains
why the sel is not a unitary sel. Instead the sel is divided and
these divisions are in conict. Again, Plato has S ocrates explain his
j ustifcation o this claim:

Socrates: Isnt it sometimes true that the thirsty person also, or some
reason, may want not to drink?
Glaucon: Yes, oten.
Socrates: What can we say, then, i not that in his soul there is a part
that desires drink and another part that restrains him? This latter part
is distinct rom desire and usually can control desire.
Glaucon: I agree.

190
TH E S E LF AN D TH E O TH E R

Socrates: And isnt it true in such cases such control originates in


reason, while the urge to drink originates in something else?
Glaucon: So it seems.
Socrates: Then we can conclude that there are in us two distinct parts.
O ne is what we call reason, and the other we call the nonrational
appetites. The latter hungers, thirsts, desires sex, and is subj ect to
other desires.
Glaucon: Yes, that is the logical conclusion.
Socrates: B ut what about our emotional or spirited element: the part
in us that eels anger and indignation?  Anger sometimes opposes
our appetites as i it is something distinct rom them  Yet this
emotional part o ourselves is [also] distinct rom reason.
Plato 1 0

In other writings, Plato indicates that the inner sel is divided into three
parts: a rational part, an appetitive part, and a spirited part. This is called
his trip artite soul. This is where Plato urther develops the concept o
the sel as an inner sel. The sel is now dynamic, sometimes in conict
that can only be resolved by the dominance o one part ( though,
notably, not the exclusion o the others) . This is a seminal concept o the
sel in the Western tradition.

The tripartite soul


Plato communicates this concept o the sel with a very vivid metaphor:
the chariot.

READING ACTIVITY
Read the ollowing passage. Draw and label the images being described.

Let me speak briey about the nature o the soul knowledge is concerned: the Forms which are
by using an image. Let the image have three visible only to the mind and have no color,
parts: two winged horses and a charioteer  shape, or hardness. The souls that are most like
O ne o the horses is o noble breed, the other gods are carried up there by their charioteer,
ignoble. The charioteer controls them with although troubled by their steeds and only with
great difculty  The vicious steedwhen it great difculty beholding true being  Other
has not been thoroughly trainedgoes heavily, souls rise only to all again, barely glimpsing it
weighing down the charioteer to the earth and then altogether ailing to see because their
steeds are too unruly.
Above them, in the heaven above the heaven 
there abides the true reality with which real Plato 1 1

10
From Platos Republic, Book IV; quote taken from Manuel Velasquez, Philosophy: A Text with Readings, 12th
edition (Wadsworth: Cengage Learning, 2014) , p. 56.
11
From Platos Phaedrus, selections from 246a247e; quoted in Velasquez, Philosophy, p. 5657.

191
5 B E I N G H U M AN

It should look something like this:

Ration al self Desire & Spirit

An ancient critique: Diotima of Mantinea


Platos views were not immediately accepted. In his dialogue The Symposium,
Plato reers to the views o a emale philosopher Diotima who, it has been
suggested, was Socrates teacher. She argued or a dierent perspective on
the nature o the sel:

Although we speak o an individual as being the same so long as he


continues to exist in the same orm, and thereore assume that a man
is the same person in his old age as in his inancy, yet although we
call him the same, every bit o him is dierent, and every day he is
becoming a new man, while the old man is ceasing to exist, as you can
see rom his hair, his esh, his bones, his blood, and all the rest o his
body. And not only his body, or the same thing happens to his soul.
And neither his manners, nor his dispositions, nor his thoughts, nor
his desires, nor his pleasures, nor his suerings, nor his ears are
the same throughout his lie, or some o them grow, while others
disappear  Thus, unlike the gods, a mortal creature cannot remain
the same throughout eternity; it can only leave behind new lie to fll
the vacancy that is let as it passes away  . And so it is no wonder
that every creature prizes its own ospring, since everything is
inspired by this love, this passion or immortality.
Plato 1 2

D iotima, a character in a dialogue and possibly a real philosopher, rej ects


the idea o the sel as a constant and thereore the oundation o identity.
It was not until Locke explored the issue o personal identity ( see
C hapter 7: Identity) in the 1 7th century that philosophy systematically
explored the issue o the enduring sel.

12
Plato, The Symposium; quote taken from Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (eds) , The Collected Dialogues
of Plato, including the Letters, translated by Michael Joyce (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1961) ,
pp. 559560.
192
TH E S E LF AN D TH E O TH E R

A modern critique: a feminist critique of Platos view of the self


There are three dominant eminist perspectives when considering the body:
1 . B ody as nature  biological entity.
2 . B ody as socially constructed  this ocuses on the sex/gender
distinction and theories o socialization.
3 . Embodiment  this reers to the lived body and the position that
we are our bodies.
All o these are relevant to the discussion o What is human? and the
concept o the sel. However, the last is most relevant or an evaluation
o Platos concept o the sel. Elizabeth V. S pelman highlights in her
article Woman as B ody a concern about Platos emphasis on the
metaphysical at the expense o the physical. Spelman argues that Plato
raised the worth o the soul above that o the body:

Platos dialogues are flled with lessons about knowledge, reality, and
goodness, and most o the lessons carry with them strong praise or the
soul and strong indictments against the body. According to Plato, the
body, with its deceptive senses, keeps us rom real knowledge; it rivets
us in a world o material things which is ar removed rom the world o
reality; and it tempts us away rom the virtuous lie. It is in and through
the soul, i at all, that we shall have knowledge, be in touch with reality,
and lead a lie o virtue. Only the soul can truly know, or only the soul
can ascend to the real world, the world o the Forms or Ideas. 1 3

To illustrate the superiority o the soul Plato used examples o perceived


emale behaviours:

For example, how are we to know when the body has the upper
hand over the soul, or when the lower part o the soul has managed
to smother the higher part? We presumably cant see such conict,
so what do such conicts translate into, in terms o actual human
lives? Well, says Plato, look at the lives o women. It is women who
get hysterical at the thought o death; obviously, their emotions have
overpowered their reason, and they cant control themselves. 1 4

While this demonstrates clearly that Platos position on the role


o women as Philosopher Queens in The Republic requires urther
investigation, it also demonstrates that he was constructing his position
rom a specifc perspective. How viable is this perspective that involves
wholesale the rejection o the body? Perhaps the body is the source o
our sel due to the importance o the lived experience? As Adrienne Rich
suggests, [i] n order to live a ully human lie we require not only control
o our bodies ( though control is a prerequisite) ; we must touch the

13
Elizabeth V. Spelman, Woman as Body: Ancient and Contemporary Views, Feminist Studies 8, No. 1 (Spring
1982) : 111.
14
Ibid., p. 115.
193
5 B E I N G H U M AN

unity and resonance o our physicality, our bond with the natural order,
the corporeal grounds o our intelligence. 1 5 The physical ( corporeal)
dimension o our existence is being ignored in Platos argument due to
its changeability yet isnt this central to your sel, especially i you are
a women? For example, the power o birth means that change begins
about lie. Spelman questions whether or not Plato could understand this
possibility. This provides a strong indication as to why essentialism in this
orm was rej ected and a position on the embodied sel ( the sel embedded
in the body) was welcomed as an alternative. ( This is a position that will
be explored in more detail in the section on existentialism.)

Aristotle and the body


Aristotle, the most amous student o Plato, continued the momentum
initiated by Plato (and Socrates) but also reacted to his mentors philosophy in
a number o ways and especially its reliance on rationalism as a methodology
and the infuence o Pythagoras. He has a more empirical approach to
philosophical issues, resulting in a dierent emphasis in the analysis and
thereore some dierent conclusions. Whereas Plato had been dismissive o
the body, Aristotle saw it as essential. He rejected the premise that there were
two distinct and separable types o entity: soul and body. He still retained the
basic outline o the mind/body but he changed the relationship. As Aristotle
states in On the Soul (known also as De Anima) , The soul must be a substance
in the sense o the orm o a material body having lie potentiality within it.
But substance is actuality, and thus soul is the actuality o a body. 1 6
When this short explanation is analysed the ollowing connections are
evident:

Soul = Substance similar to Form (of a Body) with life potentiality


Substance is Actuality
Thereore
Soul = Actuality (of the Body)

As part o Aristotles overall philosophical ramework, he regarded a


thing as a combination o substance, 1 7 matter, and orm. A thing
exists ( with an ontological or metaphysical reality) and is thereore
not nothing because it has a substance. A substance equals matter
in a orm. The concept o substance is at the oundation o Aristotles
philosophical understanding and thereore essential to his conceptual
ramework. Aristotle argues that substance is the undamental
building block o the universe. A modern belie is that it is elementary
particles. These seem similar. However, Aristotles notion o substance
is somewhat dierent rom our modern one. For Aristotle, substance is
the whatness o a thing. It is primary. All other eatures o our reality
such as quantity, quality, relation, place, time, position, state, action, and
aection are dependent on the category o substance.

15
Adrienne Rich, Of Woman Born: Motherhood as Experience and Institution (New York: W. W. Norton, 1976) , p. 62.
16
Aristotle, On the Soul, Book II, Part 1, available at http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/soul.2.ii.html (accessed
23 October 2014) .
17
This is the frst ever recorded philosophical account o substance.
194

You might also like