You are on page 1of 20

姝 Academy of Management Review

2007, Vol. 32, No. 1, 137–155.

ETHICAL THEORY AND STAKEHOLDER-


RELATED DECISIONS: THE ROLE OF
STAKEHOLDER CULTURE
THOMAS M. JONES
WILL FELPS
GREGORY A. BIGLEY
University of Washington Business School

We use convergent elements of major ethical theories to create a typology of corporate


stakeholder cultures—the aspects of organizational culture consisting of the beliefs,
values, and practices that have evolved for solving problems and otherwise manag-
ing stakeholder relationships. We describe five stakeholder cultures—agency, corpo-
rate egoist, instrumentalist, moralist, and altruist—and explain how these cultures lie
on a continuum, ranging from individually self-interested (agency culture) to fully
other-regarding (altruist culture). We demonstrate the utility of our framework by
showing how it can refine stakeholder salience theory.

Stakeholder theorists view the corporation as trade-offs among competing stakeholder claims
a collection of internal and external groups (e.g., based on the ethical foundations of their corpo-
shareholders, employees, customers, suppliers, rate cultures. Further conceptual development
creditors, and neighboring communities)—that regarding how firms manage stakeholder rela-
is, “stakeholders,” originally defined as those tionships seems warranted for two reasons.
who are affected by and/or can affect the First, several distinct ethical frameworks have
achievement of the firm’s objectives (Freeman, been advanced as potential foundations for
1984). A major theme of stakeholder theory is the managerial decision making with respect to
nature of the relationships between the firm stakeholder matters (e.g., Burton & Dunn, 1996;
(typically represented by its top managers) and Evan & Freeman, 1988; Wicks, Gilbert, & Free-
stakeholders, whose interests often diverge con- man, 1994), raising questions about how these
siderably not only from those of the firm but also ethical frameworks might be used jointly to in-
from each other. Early stakeholder theorizing form a more general model. Second, whereas
was marked by some conceptual confusion, but the focus of attention in stakeholder theory
Donaldson and Preston’s (1995) three-part taxon- mainly has been on top managers, understood
omy—normative (How should the firm relate to as relatively autonomous decision makers,
its stakeholders?), instrumental (What happens these managers are often profoundly influenced
if the firm relates to its stakeholders in certain by the organizational context in which they are
ways?), and descriptive (How does the firm re- embedded (Daft & Weick, 1984; Katz & Kahn,
late to its stakeholders?)— helped focus and 1978; March & Simon, 1958). This suggests a need
clarify much stakeholder thinking. The norma- to identify organization-level factors that could
tive questions are particularly important be- help us predict how firms manage stakeholder
cause they differentiate stakeholder theory from relationships.
other prominent theories in organization sci- Our paper addresses these two points. We
ence, such as resource dependence, managerial first review the diverse ethical theories that
cognition, and institutional theories. have been applied to business and identify a
Although we do not take a normative stance convergent theme—a concern for the interests of
per se, we do focus on the ways that firms man- others, as opposed to self-interest. We note that
age relationships with stakeholders and handle managers often feel tension between these two
sentiments when they make stakeholder-related
We gratefully acknowledge constructive comments on
decisions, a tension frequently linked to and
earlier versions of this paper by Robert Phillips, Shawn emanating from stakeholder attributes: power
Berman, and three anonymous AMR reviewers. and legitimacy. Next, we describe an ethically
137
138 Academy of Management Review January

based organization-level construct—stake- This view posits that a person is obligated only
holder culture—that, we argue, helps resolve to enhance his or her own long-term welfare and
this tension and, more generally, influences that commitments to others are not binding and
managerial thinking and behavior with respect should be reneged on if they cease to be advan-
to stakeholder relationships. We then develop a tageous to the individual (Beauchamp & Bowie,
punctuated continuum of five stakeholder cul- 2004). The welfare of others is relevant to an
tures, ranging from fundamentally amoral cul- egoist only if it affects his or her welfare; it has
tures based on individual self-interest to limited no independent moral standing.
morality cultures based on the advancement of Few moral philosophers endorse ethical ego-
shareholder interests and then to broadly moral ism, and some would deny that it constitutes a
cultures based on concern for the interests of all normative theory at all (e.g., Barry & Stephens,
stakeholders. We explain how ethical theory 1998). As noted below, a great deal of scholar-
might be linked, conceptually if not semanti- ship in moral philosophy and applied ethics is
cally, to the ethical frameworks commonly un- devoted to arguing that people (and organiza-
derstood by corporate managers and, thus, to tions) ought to take the interests of others into
stakeholder cultures. Finally, to illustrate the account in their decision-making processes and
value of the stakeholder culture construct, we behavior. Although the foundational principles,
show how it would alter the predictions yielded the arguments, the conclusions, and the behav-
by Mitchell, Agle, and Wood’s (1997) stakeholder ioral prescriptions vary greatly among these
salience model. theories, it is not much of an intellectual stretch
to say that ethics is about other-regarding,
rather than self-regarding, thought and behav-
ETHICAL FOUNDATIONS
ior. Our focus is on the extent to which an or-
To explore possible elements of convergence ganizational culture adopts self-interest or re-
in ethical theory, we briefly review the promi- jects it in favor of other-regarding sentiments, as
nent perspectives, most of them the work of reflected in the following theories.
moral philosophers. We begin with a discussion Utilitarianism, based on the work of Hume
of egoism, an approach to ethics that is essential (1740/2000), Bentham (1789/1996), and Mill (1863/
to an understanding of ethical theory in general, 1998), admonishes moral agents to promote over-
followed by outlines of the basic tenets of utili- all human welfare by acting in ways that result in
tarianism, Kantian principles, Rawlsian fair- the greatest total beneficial consequences minus
ness, rights, the ethics of care, virtue ethics, and harmful consequences. Utilitarian theory applies
integrated social contracts theory (ISCT). Later, this “cost-benefit” calculus universally—that is, to
we argue that corporate cultures, although they all who are affected by the decision, not just an
may not use the precise language of ethical individual (as in egoism) or an organization (as in
theory, do have core values that roughly match corporate profit maximization). Utilitarianism
those of these theories. Where available, we takes two forms: act utilitarianism and rule utili-
present evidence of common language versions tarianism. Act utilitarianism involves maximizing
of these ethical sentiments among managers benefits relative to costs for the discrete decision
and in firms. in question. Rule utilitarianism involves following
rules that are established in order to achieve the
greatest net positive consequences over time.
A Brief Review of Ethical Theory
Kantian ethics departs significantly from util-
Egoism involves acting exclusively in one’s itarianism’s focus on consequences; the focus
own self-interest. Two forms of egoism are rele- instead is on principles—a deontological ap-
vant to our discussion: psychological egoism proach. Kant argued that human beings should
and ethical egoism. On the one hand, psycho- be treated not simply as a means to one’s own
logical egoism—a descriptive theory of human ends but also as ends in themselves. This em-
behavior— holds that people are innately self- phasis on “respect for persons” stems from the
interested and routinely act to advance their view that human beings should be regarded as
interests. Ethical egoism, on the other hand, is a independent agents, with interests of their own
normative perspective that holds that people and the judgment to act on them. In other words,
ought to act exclusively in their self-interest. they should be accorded the freedom to act au-
2007 Jones, Felps, and Bigley 139

tonomously. Kant gave great importance to mo- result in benefits for everyone, with particular
tives for acting—making the right decisions for emphasis on the least advantaged.
the right reasons being the ultimate goal. Kant Rights theories have to do with securing or
was quite explicit regarding appropriate rea- preserving certain liberties (negative rights) or
sons for moral actions—that is, moral obliga- benefits (positive rights) for their holders. The
tion. An act performed for reasons of personal possession of a right by one party implies the
satisfaction (or the benefit of the firm) carries existence of a corresponding duty or obligation
less moral weight than it would if it were per- on others’ part. In the case of negative rights,
formed because of a duty to do so. Kant also that duty is to allow the party to act freely (not be
argued that the principles ought to be universal- interfered with) within the domain covered by
izable; that is, if everyone adopted the principle, the right. In the case of positive rights, the obli-
it should not be self-defeating. For example, if gation is to provide the party with a benefit of
promise breaking were to become universal some kind. Since rights often conflict with one
law, promises would have no meaning. The idea another and there is no widely accepted hierar-
behind this prescription is that no moral code chy of rights, some moral philosophers have
ought to apply only to oneself. Kant is also cred- concluded that rights should be accorded prima
ited with the idea that principles ought to be facie validity. That is, rights should be re-
reversible, a notion well-captured by the Golden spected unless there are good moral reasons for
Rule: “Do unto others as you would have them violating them; the moral force of a right de-
do unto you.” pends on its “strength” in relation to other moral
Rawlsian fairness considerations also entail a considerations applicable to the context in
question.
regard for others. In A Theory of Justice (1971a),
The ethics of care derives from “feminist eth-
Rawls regards justice for the individual, not ag-
ics” in general and the work of Gilligan (1982) in
gregate welfare, as the “first virtue” of social
particular. This perspective focuses on personal
institutions. In colloquial terms, he is concerned
relationships and the traits of personal charac-
more with how the pie is divided than with how
ter that create and sustain them—friendship,
large it is, a utilitarian concern. Although his
compassion, sympathy, empathy, faithfulness,
arguments regarding distributive justice as fair-
and loyalty, for example. The focus on these
ness are intended to apply to social institutions
human traits, which certainly qualify as virtues
(e.g., governmental policies), they may have im-
(as discussed below), deliberately eschews the
plications for individuals and firms that make emphasis on rules and calculations that charac-
decisions regarding the distribution of economic terize Kantian and utilitarian thought. Also ab-
benefits and burdens. Using the “social con- sent are notions of universality and impartiality;
tract” as a heuristic device, Rawls argues that the ethics of care regards actual relationships
principles of justice ought to be arrived at by and the social contexts in which they are em-
individuals making choices behind a “veil of bedded as valid and important elements of eth-
ignorance”—an imaginary situation wherein ical decision making. An ethical “dilemma” is
the parties are ignorant of their own character- not seen as an abstract problem with only one
istics (advantages and disadvantages), thus ethically “correct” solution that can be agreed
rendering improbable the choice of principles on by impartial observers applying universally
that favor their own strengths and discount their accepted principles. Instead, solutions can and
weaknesses. The use of this device, intended to should emerge from mutually caring relation-
mitigate the effects of inequalities of initial cir- ships and the contexts in which the problems
cumstances over which people have no control are embedded. Particular human beings in par-
and are, hence, undeserved, leads individuals to ticular settings should generate “caring” solu-
prefer a state of basic equality. This state of tions appropriate to unique situations.
equality is then used as a point of comparison Virtue ethics also focuses on human virtues,
for alternative (unequal) states to determine albeit a much longer list. For example, Pincoffs,
their fairness. If everyone prefers an alternative giving new life to the ideas of Aristotle, offers a
distributive state to one of equality, it is consid- list of over six dozen virtues (1986: 85). He argues
ered just. Rawls’ difference principle reflects his that the development of virtuous character
conclusion that inequalities are just only if they should be a primary goal of the human condi-
140 Academy of Management Review January

tion, and he identifies four classes of virtues: concern for others can differ as well, particularly
aesthetic, ameliorating, instrumental, and in a corporate context, in a later section we
moral. Virtue ethics is about conditioning one- develop a continuum of stakeholder cultures
self to act morally as a matter of habit. ranging from individually self-interested to ex-
ISCT is a very recent addition to the normative clusively other-regarding. Although we are the
ethics literature. Unlike other ethical theories first to propose such a continuum at the organi-
that must be adapted to business settings, ISCT zation level, theories of identity, leadership, and
is intended to apply directly to them. Its most cooperation employ similar distinctions at the
formal and complete articulation is found in micro level. Identity theories posit that people
Donaldson and Dunfee’s book entitled Ties That can think of themselves as individuals or as part
Bind: A Social Contracts Approach to Business of larger collectives (Ashforth & Mael, 1989), with
Ethics (1999). These authors use a social con- only one level being active at a time (Lord,
tracts perspective to show how individual com- Brown, & Freiberg, 1999). Walzer (1994) makes a
munities can be allowed to develop their own distinction between “thin selves,” concerned
(local) standards, within a “moral free space,” as with narrow, short-term interests, and “thick
long as they (1) meet certain standards involv- selves,” embedded in larger historical and so-
ing acceptance by community members and (2) cial developments. In his view, moral reasoning
do not violate broad, universal standards, called and behavior are facilitated only by “thick” in-
“hypernorms.” As such, the theory attempts to terpretations of self.
simultaneously allow for a substantial diversity Similarly, some models of managerial leader-
of adaptation to local conditions without allow- ship also contain references to collective-level
ing these developed norms to violate higher eth- versus self-level concepts. Transformational,
ical standards. charismatic, and visionary leaders may achieve
In fact, the theory establishes an elaborate set success by activating their followers’ sense of
of standards by which the propriety of these self at the collective level through articulation of
local norms should be judged. In order to be a compelling moral mission (Shamir, House, &
authentic, local norms must (1) have the consent Arthur, 1993). Shamir, Zakay, Breinin, and Pop-
of most members of the community, (2) allow exit per (1998), Paul, Costley, Howell, Dorfman, and
from the community, and (3) allow “voice” in Trafimow (2001), and Sparks and Schenk (2001)
order to permit change in the norms, thus assur- provide additional support for this view. Models
ing that most members of the community regard of cooperation also feature a prominent distinc-
them as binding. In turn, authentic norms are tion between self-oriented and other-regarding
judged legitimate if they do not violate any hy- behavior. Under the rubric of “social value ori-
pernorms. Hypernorms are the result of “a con- entation” (McClintock, 1978; Messick & Mc-
vergence of religious, political, and philosophi- Clintock, 1968), cooperation researchers have
cal thought” across a broad number of nations identified four profiles in situations involving
and cultures (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999: 44). potential cooperation. Competitors try to maxi-
Finally, these authors offer a set of priority mize their outcomes relative to others. Individu-
rules for choosing between/among competing alists seek to maximize their absolute, not rela-
legitimate norms. Legitimate norms that either tive, outcomes. Cooperators try to maximize joint
do not conflict with or have priority over other outcomes without being cheated themselves.
legitimate norms are considered binding ethical And altruists try to maximize the other party’s
standards. ISCT is quite different from the other outcome with less concern for their own.
theories described here, but, as discussed in the Clearly, scholars in other fields have found
next section, it shares one important perspective the contrast between narrow self-interest and a
with those theories. concern for others, narrow or broad, useful in
explaining human behavior. We develop an
analogous concept at the organization level—a
Convergent Elements in Ethical Theory
continuum of stakeholder cultures based on the
Although the ethical theories reviewed above extent to which they are other-regarding. We
differ in important ways, they converge on one propose that stakeholder culture is a potent or-
essential point—their emphasis on concern for ganizational factor, profoundly influencing the
others over self-interest. Because the extent of way in which managers understand, prioritize,
2007 Jones, Felps, and Bigley 141

and respond to stakeholder issues and, as an ual), and moral (positive normative evaluation).
example, how they establish stakeholder sa- For most authors who address the issue of stake-
lience. As an introduction to these arguments, holder legitimacy, however, the term is morally
we offer a discussion of the moral tension be- grounded. Mitchell et al. (1997) found that sev-
tween self-interest and the interests of stake- eral (but not all) authors offered moral bases for
holders in managerial decision making. stakeholder legitimacy (e.g., Carroll, 1979;
Clarkson, 1995; Donaldson & Preston, 1995; Evan
& Freeman, 1988; Langtry, 1994). This conclusion
ETHICS, STAKEHOLDERS, AND MANAGERIAL
is not surprising, since basing legitimacy on
DECISION MAKING
power and/or habit would run counter to a cen-
Decision making with respect to stakeholder tral tenet of stakeholder theory—moral justifica-
relationships can be fraught with tension. tions for firm/stakeholder relationships (Donald-
Trade-offs between firm interests and stake- son & Preston, 1995; Jones & Wicks, 1999). Indeed,
holder interests, as well as those between or Donaldson and Preston conclude that “the cen-
among the interests of different stakeholders, tral core of the [stakeholder] theory is, however,
inherently involve the allocation of benefits and normative” (1995: 183). We highlight the moral
burdens among human beings and, hence, in- foundation of stakeholder legitimacy because,
volve moral questions. Commonly, the tension as argued above, not all firms will treat moral
that arises in this context is one of deciding claims in the same manner.
whether to act in a self-regarding manner or in Our preferred account of stakeholder legiti-
an other-regarding manner. Hendry (2004) not macy is provided by Phillips (2003), whose anal-
only captures this tension quite nicely but also ysis includes a compelling account of the link
mirrors our points of convergence in ethical the- between legitimacy and power, a connection
ory, arguing that managers face two sets of con- that becomes important in our discussion of the
flicting prescriptions about how to act: tradi- impact of stakeholder cultures on stakeholder
tional morality (obligation and duty, honesty salience. Phillips bases his notion of normative
and respect, fairness and equity, care and assis- legitimacy on “stakeholder fairness” (Phillips,
tance) or market morality (self-interest). 1997), which, in turn, draws on the work of Hart
In relationships with stakeholders, firms’ self- (1955) and Rawls (1964, 1971a,b). In this formula-
interest is often related to the exercise of power, tion, “obligations of fairness” are created when-
without regard for moral concerns—a “might ever parties accept benefits of a mutually ben-
makes right” perspective. Power is well-defined eficial cooperative arrangement (Phillips, 1997:
for stakeholder relationships, by Willer, Lova- 57). Phillips (1997) also stipulates that partici-
glia, and Markovsky, as “the structurally deter- pants make contributions and/or sacrifices to
mined potential for obtaining favored payoffs in effect the arrangement and that “free riding” by
relations where interests are opposed” (1997: participants is possible. When these conditions
573). To increase favorable outcomes for them- are met, stakeholders have normatively legiti-
selves, self-interested firms with power over mate claims on the corporation (and vice versa).
their stakeholders will wield it with impunity. Although not all stakeholder theorists adopt this
When confronted with stakeholder power, which particular account of stakeholder legitimacy, al-
may stem from resources that (1) are concen- most all believe that corporations have moral
trated or tightly controlled, (2) are essential to obligations to address, in some way, the norma-
operational performance, or (3) have no viable tively legitimate claims of stakeholders.
substitutes, self-interested firms will be respon- Phillips (2003) also introduces the notion of
sive. derivative legitimacy. Derivative legitimacy is
In contrast, traditional (other-regarding) mo- generated from a stakeholder group’s power to
rality may require that firms respond to stake- affect the firm and its normatively legitimate
holders with legitimacy, which many stake- stakeholders, even though that group has no
holder scholars consider a fundamentally moral normatively legitimate claims on the firm. Man-
phenomenon. In an integrative review of the agerial attention to derivatively legitimate
legitimacy literature, Suchman (1995) posits the claims is morally justified by the responsibility
existence of three potential bases of legitimacy: managers have to protect the interests of the
pragmatic (similar to power), cognitive (habit- firm and its normatively legitimate stakehold-
142 Academy of Management Review January

ers. Derivatively legitimate stakeholders—for making decisions, called values; and (3) the
example, the media, radical activist groups (ter- practices or ways of working together that fol-
rorists, in the extreme case), and competitors— low from the aforementioned assumptions and
can affect the corporation in either beneficial or values, called artifacts (e.g., Geertz, 1973; Hatch,
harmful ways. Indeed, most firms grant substan- 1993; Pettigrew, 1979; Schein, 1985, 1990; Trice &
tial salience to their competitors, even though Beyer, 1984). Organizational culture reflects a
they are certainly not normatively legitimate sort of negotiated order (Fine, 1984) that arises
stakeholders. As Phillips puts it, normative le- and evolves as members work together, express-
gitimacy provides an answer to the question ing preferences, exhibiting more-or-less effec-
“For whose benefit . . . should the firm be man- tive problem-solving styles (Swidler, 1986), and
aged?” (2003: 30) and is a primary form of legit- managing, at least satisfactorily, external de-
imacy. From a moral perspective, the claims of mands and internal needs for coordination and
derivatively legitimate stakeholders are sec- integration (Schein, 1990). Common experience
ondary and should be addressed only when they in this regard can lead people, over time, to form
affect the interests of normatively legitimate shared and deeply ingrained (Denison, 1996) un-
stakeholders. Firms concerned about their moral derstandings about the way the organizational
obligations will attend to the claims of both nor- world works and the practices and standards
matively and derivatively legitimate stakehold- that are appropriate and effective within that
ers. Moral obligations are central to our stake- reality. In effect, culture represents an aspect of
holder culture construct, the topic to which we the organizational environment that helps mem-
now turn. bers make sense of their own and others’ behav-
ior (Golden, 1992).
Corporate cultures are certainly made up of
STAKEHOLDER CULTURES
more than one cultural dimension; formalism,
We argued above that when managers are adaptability, and time horizon are prominent
faced with ethical decisions, they experience a examples. However, a firm’s stakeholders are
tension between self-interest, often bolstered by the source of its most critical contingencies
a “market morality” (Hendry, 2004), and other- (Freeman, 1984). Indeed, Barney links successful
regarding sentiments, as reflected in traditional corporate cultures to strong core values “about
moral principles. This tension is particularly in- how to treat employees, customers, suppliers,
tense in firm/stakeholder relationships because and others”—that is, stakeholders (1986: 656). In
they are a critical venue for morally significant addition, although it departs from our model
interactions. How can the tension be resolved? somewhat by omitting employees, “external ori-
We contend that stakeholder culture, which, we entation” shows up as a central feature of most
argue, is a central facet of organizational cul- typologies of corporate cultures (Denison &
ture, can provide managers with guidance re- Mishra, 1995; Detert, Schroeder, & Mauriel, 2000;
garding how this tension should be resolved. Schein, 1990; VandenBerg & Wilderom, 2004).
Stakeholder culture represents a firm’s collec- Furthermore, the very inclusive inventory of
tive reconciliation of these contradictory mo- stakeholders advanced by most stakeholder the-
tives in the past and, as such, consists of its orists—for example, Barney’s (1986) list, plus
shared beliefs, values, and evolved practices shareholders and neighboring communities—
regarding the solution of recurring stakeholder- indicates that stakeholder relationships lie at
related problems. Often, the “solution,” found in the core of corporate operations. Consequently,
the firm’s stakeholder culture, is a relatively solving stakeholder-related problems will be an
clear set of prescriptions about whether self- important element of a company’s overall cul-
regarding or other-regarding norms will prevail, ture.
or whether some compromise between the two In this paper, our focus is on what we call
will hold sway. “stakeholder culture,” which we define as the
In general, culture is a property of an organi- beliefs, values, and practices that have evolved
zation constituted by (1) its members’ taken-for- for solving stakeholder-related problems and
granted beliefs regarding the nature of reality, otherwise managing relationships with stake-
called assumptions; (2) a set of normative, holders. Although the extent to which organiza-
moral, and functional guidelines or criteria for tional values and assumptions are widely
2007 Jones, Felps, and Bigley 143

shared and deeply held by organization mem- mation overload and make shared sense of (and
bers—that is, culture strength— can vary (e.g., take coordinated action in) complex and ambig-
Schein, 1985), the following arguments should uous situations. The practices constituting
gain force in proportion to culture strength. In stakeholder culture reflect the collectively
addition, subcultures often exist within organi- learned behavioral responses to problems that
zations (e.g., Martin, 2002). However, we focus on the organization has encountered as its mem-
the organization-level variable and leave exam- bers have worked together to manage complex
ination of stakeholder subcultures, and possible stakeholder relationships. As such, these prac-
differential treatment of stakeholders across tices provide agreed upon heuristics that help
firm subunits, to future research. managers take action, despite substantial com-
Stakeholder culture is grounded in ethics and plexity and ambiguity. Taken-for-granted ele-
is based on a continuum of concern for others ments within the culture give rise to a sort of
that runs from self-regarding to other-regarding. “automaticity” (e.g., Bargh & Ferguson, 2000) in
We argue that firms vary with respect to the the enactment of practices and routines in re-
extent and nature of their moral concern for their sponse to stakeholder issues and attributes.
stakeholders and that this variation will often Furthermore, the assumptions and values
be linked, conceptually if not semantically, to making up stakeholder culture may influence
the different moral philosophies. Importantly, the nature and sophistication of the organiza-
we do not argue that corporate managers know- tional practices used to monitor and interact
ingly subscribe to, for example, utilitarian or with stakeholders (Hatch, 1993). For example,
Kantian ethical theories. However, many man- people tend to expend more time and effort col-
agers are aware of and subscribe to common lecting and interpreting data to elaborate on
language understandings of these ethical theo- mental models relevant to important matters
ries— understandings drawn from the norms of (Weick, 2004), such as for those directly related
society at large and revealed in the ethical log- to core values of the culture. Consequently, or-
ics of organizations (e.g., Victor & Cullen, 1988). ganization members can be expected to (1) focus
Hence, these theories may become important more specifically on, (2) collect more information
sensemaking and sensegiving conduits through about, (3) develop more comprehensive under-
which stakeholder culture is communicated. standings of, and (4) create more sophisticated
Furthermore, as with cultures in general, stake- response routines around stakeholder issues
holder cultures are simultaneously the products germane to their firm’s core values.
of employee sentiments and reified “social Stakeholder culture has antecedents in the
facts” that have an independent effect on man- literature on ethical context in business set-
agerial decision making (e.g., Hatch, 1993). tings. Ethical climate refers to the prevailing
Stakeholder culture is likely to affect how perceptions of organizational values and the
company employees assess and respond to typical practices and procedures that have eth-
stakeholder issues in two related ways: (1) by ical content or pertain to moral behavior
constituting a common interpretive frame on the (Cullen, Parboteeah, & Victor, 2003; Victor &
basis of which information about stakeholder Cullen, 1988). Ethical culture consists of the “for-
attributes and issues is collected, screened, and mal” (e.g., policies and procedures) and “infor-
evaluated and (2) by motivating behaviors and mal” (e.g., peer behavior and norms) systems of
practices—and, by extension, organizational behavioral control that are capable of promot-
routines—that preserve, enhance, or otherwise ing either ethical or unethical behavior (Treviño,
support the organization’s culture. To begin 1990; Treviño & Weaver, 2003). Clearly, ethical
with, collective cognitive structures, such as climate and ethical culture are related concepts.
those derived from culture (e.g., assumptions In fact, much of the research done under one
and values), influence what data about the tradition can inform the other, and, in combina-
firm’s external environment are noticed and tion, they address many topics of interest to or-
what meaning is given to those data (e.g., Daft & ganization scholars. Indeed, until Denison (1996)
Weick, 1984). These structures filter and shape sorted out some of the key differences—“deep
the enormous amount of stakeholder-related in- structure” values, beliefs, and assumptions (cul-
formation that comes to bear on organizational ture) versus surface-level understandings of or-
participants. Culture helps people avoid infor- ganization members (climate), qualitative field
144 Academy of Management Review January

studies (culture) versus quantitative surveys stakeholder relationships from an ethical per-
(climate), sociological basis (culture) versus psy- spective.
chological basis (climate)—scholars sometimes
conflated organizational culture and organiza-
A Continuum of Stakeholder Cultures
tional climate. For Victor and Cullen (1988), eth-
ical climate represents the ethical aspect of or- Although concern for others may be a concep-
ganizational culture. tually continuous phenomenon, we argue that
Our stakeholder culture construct differs from there are critical qualitative differences among
ethical climate/culture in two important ways. firms that make a classification scheme mean-
First, it is simpler. It focuses only on what mat- ingful. Our “punctuated” continuum (Table 1) is
ters to corporate stakeholders—whether or not based on critical differences in the culture-
the firm takes their interests into account— based solutions that firms may use to resolve
rather than trying to separate out the precise the conceptual tension between self-interest
ethical foundation of that concern. We allow for and concern for others—sometimes made man-
multiple possible foundations. ifest by power and legitimacy, respectively.
Second, unlike previous work, stakeholder We posit the existence of five categories of
culture represents a clearly defined continuum corporate stakeholder cultures, each character-
of concern for stakeholder interests. Victor and ized by a unique managerial orientation, pre-
Cullen (1998) employ a 3 ⫻ 3 matrix of catego- sented in order of ascending concern for others.
ries, with “locus of analysis”—individual, local, First, an amoral culture—agency culture—is
and cosmopolitan— on the horizontal axis and based on managerial egoism and involves no
concern for others. Next, two limited morality
“ethical criterion”— egoism, benevolence, and
cultures—corporate egoist and instrumentalist
principle— on the vertical axis. Locus of analysis
(under the umbrella term moral stewardship)—
might suggest a continuum of concern for others,
involve concern for the interests of shareholders
but the authors actually mean something quite
but not for those of other stakeholders. Finally,
different: sources of reference for ethical reason-
two broadly moral cultures (another umbrella
ing within the organization. Individual applies
term)—moralist and altruist—involve concern
to personal moral standards, local to internal
for all corporate stakeholders.
organizational sources, and cosmopolitan to
sources outside the organization.
The three ethical criteria have different mean- An Amoral Culture
ings across the three loci of analysis and, when Agency cultures are characterized by mana-
combined with each locus, yield criteria that are gerial egoism, the pursuit of self-interest at the
quite ambiguous from a stakeholder group’s individual level, even if the interests of the cor-
point of view. While local egoism (“company poration and its shareholders, for whom manag-
profit”) and cosmopolitan benevolence (“social ers nominally work, must be sacrificed. Agency
responsibility”) seem to be analogous to two of cultures are essentially amoral, differentiated
our categories (below), others clearly are not. from other stakeholder cultures by an absence
For example, cosmopolitan egoism suggests a of moral concern for other economic actors. In
broad concern for stakeholders, but one form of agency theory, the “agency problem” stems from
this category is “efficiency,” which, according to the separation of ownership and control, first
economic theory, would mean firm profit maxi- documented by Berle and Means (1932). Self-
mization without regard for the interests of non- interest on the part of managers (agents) and
shareholder stakeholders. Similarly, an exam- shareholders (principals) is assumed, and
ple of cosmopolitan principles is “laws and agency theory (1) helps us better understand
professional codes,” which again may have and predict the behavior of firms and their man-
nothing to do with the interests of many stake- agers under various circumstances and (2) helps
holders. Although these authors offer a credible us design incentive structures and monitoring
typology of ethical climates/cultures, its impli- mechanisms that will better control managerial
cations for stakeholder relationships are un- opportunism. Under this view, managers who
clear. Thus, we believe that stakeholder culture fail to act in the interests of shareholders are not
offers a better means of understanding firm/ morally deficient. Rather, they are responding to
2007

TABLE 1
Stakeholder Cultures: A Punctuated Continuum from Self-Regarding to Other-Regarding
Amoral Limited Morality: Moral Stewardship Broadly Moral

Stakeholder Culture
Type Agency Corporate Egoist Instrumentalist Moralist Altruist

Alternative descriptors • Amoral management • Short-term profit maximization • Enlightened self-interest • Intrinsic morality tempered with • Pure intrinsic morality; concern for
• Managerial egoism • Short-term self-interest at the • Corporate self-interest with guile pragmatism; genuine concern for welfare of normative stakeholders
corporate level • Instrumental or strategic welfare of normative stakeholders is primary
• Short-term stewardship morality • Moral pragmatism • Moral purism
• “Moral” impression management
• Enlightened stewardship

Moral orientation; self- • Pure egoism • Regard for others extends to Same as corporate egoist Morally based regard for normative Morally based regard for normative
versus other- • Purely self-regarding shareholders; belief in stakeholders; pragmatic regard for stakeholders only
regarding efficiency of the market; honor derivative stakeholders
contract with shareholders; OR
• Egoistic at the corporate level

Relevant stakeholders None Shareholders only • Shareholders only, but other All normative and derivative Normative stakeholders only
stakeholders as means to stakeholders
shareholder ends
• Instrumentally useful
stakeholders

Possibly relevant • Psychological See below See below See below See below
moral foundations egoism
(below) • Ethical egoism

Utilitarianism Not relevant Rule utilitarian—market Rule utilitarian—market efficiency Act utilitarian—consider the interests Act utilitarian—consider the interests
efficiency of all affected parties of all affected parties

Kantian principles Not relevant Honor the widely accepted Honor the widely accepted Treat stakeholders as ends as well Treat stakeholders as ends as well
contract with shareholders only contract with shareholders only; as means; universalizable and as means; universalizable and
Jones, Felps, and Bigley

adhere to principles when reversible principles; adherence to reversible principles; adherence to


instrumentally advantageous principles important and rarely principles imperative and not
contingent on consequences contingent on consequences

Rawlsian fairness Not relevant Not relevant Not relevant “Veil of ignorance” relevant; “Veil of ignorance” important;
adherence to difference principle adherence to difference principle
desirable important

Rights Not relevant Shareholder rights only Shareholder rights only; respect Prime facie respect for stakeholder Stakeholder rights of primary
rights of other stakeholders when rights—violate only when good importance
instrumentally advantageous moral reasons for doing so

Ethics of care Not relevant “Care” for shareholders “Care” for shareholders; Genuine “care” for normative “Care” for normative stakeholders is
instrumental “care” for other stakeholders primary
stakeholders

Virtue ethics Instrumental virtues Some moral virtues (loyalty, Virtues of corporate egoists plus Moral virtues of corporate egoists Moral virtues of moralists plus
only (persistence, reliability, diligence, and additional instrumental virtues plus honesty, sincerity, truthfulness, benevolence, altruism, selflessness,
alertness, carefulness, dependability) (cooperativeness and practical and trustworthiness and forgiveness
prudence, and cool- wisdom)
headedness)

ISCT Selective adherence to General adherence to local General adherence to local norms; Genuine concern for the authenticity Adherence to legitimate norms
local norms norms instrumental concern for the and legitimacy of only—must be compatible with
authenticity and legitimacy of norms—compatibility with hypernorms
norms hypernorms important
145
146 Academy of Management Review January

poorly designed incentive structures, or they are into collective welfare. Milton Friedman, the No-
subject to inadequate monitoring mechanisms. bel Prize–winning economist, endorses this per-
“Moral” failures are attributed to faulty corpo- spective in his provocative essay “The Social
rate governance, not faulty managerial ethics. Responsibility of Business Is to Increase Its Prof-
Shareholders may benefit from the actions of its” (1970). Managers who have made informed
egoistic managers, but only as by-products of judgments regarding the ability of (even highly
self-interested actions taken under incentive competitive) markets to produce socially opti-
and monitoring regimes that properly align mal outcomes over time will regard moral stew-
managerial and shareholder interests. Other ardship as morally justified.
stakeholders may benefit as well, depending on Moral stewardship may also be based on com-
managerial incentives, but not in predictable pliance with the terms of the principal/agent
ways based on the moral intentions of manag- contractual arrangement, a Kantian moral per-
ers. Managerial egoists may have some instru- spective, wherein corporate managers (agents)
mental virtues (Pincoffs, 1986), such as persis- are morally bound to advance the interests of
tence, alertness, carefulness, prudence, and their ultimate employers—the firm’s sharehold-
cool-headedness, but (in their managerial roles) ers (principals). Similarly, moral stewards may
will lack moral virtues found in managers in be concerned with the rights of shareholders
other-regarding cultures. Agency cultures are at and may even exhibit a form of empathetic
the purely self-regarding end of our continuum (though not very proximate) “care” for their
of ethically grounded stakeholder cultures. shareholders. In addition to the instrumental
Self-interest will certainly play a major role in virtues listed above for egoistic managers,
the stakeholder cultures of many firms, without moral stewards, who aim to maximize profits (or
any support from moral philosophers, perhaps shareholder wealth), might be loyal, reliable,
taking the form of an “every person for him/ diligent, and dependable in protecting and ad-
herself” mentality. Two studies have shown am- vancing shareholder interests.
ple empirical evidence of individual egoism in Managers in moral stewardship cultures have
organizations (Fritzsche & Becker, 1984; Victor & a conceptually uncomplicated moral posture at
Cullen, 1988). We now turn to discussions of four the organization level—self-regarding and
other-regarding stakeholder cultures. geared to maximize firm welfare. They are not
guided by (1) act utilitarianism, which would
require them to take into account possible con-
Limited Morality Cultures: Moral Stewardship
sequences for all stakeholders, (2) the Kantian
Moral stewardship (Davis, Schoorman, & principles of universalizability, reversibility, or
Donaldson, 1997) is our umbrella term for two regarding stakeholders as ends as well as
stakeholder cultures—corporate egoist and in- means, (3) Rawlsian fairness, (4) stakeholder
strumentalist—where managers have a limited rights, (5) “care” for stakeholders, or (6) the au-
moral commitment—protecting and advancing thenticity (let alone the legitimacy) of local com-
the interests of the owners of the corporation, its munity norms. They may consider the interests
shareholders—rather than the amoral perspec- of nonshareholder stakeholders in an instru-
tive of agency cultures. mental sense (depending on the form of stew-
One of the moral foundations of market capi- ardship involved, as described below) in mak-
talism is based on microeconomic models that ing company decisions, but there is no moral
have economic efficiency, a utilitarian concept, commitment to these other stakeholders. Stake-
as their underlying goal. Managers who believe holders (other than shareholders) are seen as
in “role responsibility” are implicitly invoking a means (or impediments) to the ends of the cor-
form of rule utilitarianism under which they, poration. Managerial stewards behave accord-
acting in the interests of the firm and its share- ing to the lessons taught in many business
holders by maximizing profits (or share value), school classes: maximize shareholder wealth.
play their appropriate role in an economy char- A concentrated focus on company profitability
acterized by competitive markets, private prop- certainly describes a significant number of
erty, perfect information, and so on. In short, firms in modern economies and, hence, de-
they believe that Adam Smith’s (1937) “invisible scribes some corporate stakeholder cultures.
hand” is indeed able to transform self-interest Empirical evidence of thinking along steward-
2007 Jones, Felps, and Bigley 147

ship lines was found in two studies: (1) cosmo- Instrumentalist cultures subscribe to the doc-
politan egoism—striving for efficiency—and lo- trine of “enlightened self-interest”—a voluntar-
cal egoism—profit maximization (Victor & ily adopted “morality” that extends to those
Cullen, 1988) and (2) rule utilitarianism stakeholders that can enhance the firm’s finan-
(Fritzsche & Becker, 1984). We now turn to de- cial well-being.1 Friedman’s (1970) classic arti-
scriptions of the two forms of stewardship cul- cle rejecting a broad social responsibility for
tures: corporate egoist and instrumentalist. corporations allowed for corporate actions pro-
Corporate egoists are those firms whose cul- viding broader social benefits, as long as these
tures stress short-term profit maximization or its actions are undertaken in the service of share-
more recent manifestation, shareholder wealth holder interests. More recently, Jensen and
maximization. Such firms regard the interests of Fuller (2002) wrote of “enlightened stakeholder
stakeholders as important only to the extent that
theory,” an approach that recognizes and advo-
these stakeholders can contribute to the firm’s
cates the management of firm/stakeholder rela-
short-term economic success, a perspective in-
tionships for the long-term enhancement of com-
creasingly in evidence in today’s quarterly re-
pany economic performance.
sults– driven corporate environment. Corporate
self-interest without guile may be the best short- Managers in instrumentalist cultures recog-
hand description of egoistic corporations. Cor- nize that moral behavior (or the appearance
porate egoists aggressively contract with stake- thereof) is often beneficial to the firm, and they
holders (employees, suppliers, creditors, and practice a form of strategic morality where they
customers) to compete effectively with other act “morally,” but only to the extent that it is
firms in their product markets. Stakeholder economically advantageous to do so. Such firms
groups that can affect the firm’s short-term prof- differ from corporate egoists in that they are
itability are dealt with in ways that work to the opportunistic; self-interest with guile character-
best advantage of the firm, through arm’s- izes their behavior. Guile is Williamson’s (1985)
length transacting, zero-sum bargaining, highly term for behavior intended to appear moral but
specified contracting, litigation of contract dis- with the underlying goal of advancing economic
putes and ambiguities, opportunistic exploita- interests—that is, subtlety in the pursuit of eco-
tion of contracting failures, and aggressive ex- nomic gain (Frank, 1988; Quinn & Jones, 1995).
ploitation of power imbalances. Examples Put differently, the instrumentalist firm “in-
include hard bargaining (including soliciting vests” in longer-term benefits by foregoing the
competitive bids) over the prices suppliers re- short-term opportunities of self-interested be-
ceive for inputs to the firm’s production pro- havior. In contrast, the corporate egoist exploits
cesses and/or the prices customers pay for its short-term opportunities as they arise.
products. Employees in egoistic cultures will be Instrumentalists are strategically “moral”
treated in ways that minimize labor costs, with- only with respect to nonshareholder stakehold-
out falling too far short of industry norms in
ers. Like corporate egoists, they do have a moral
order to retain a competent workforce. Such
commitment to the stewardship of shareholder
firms will interpret laws in ways that favor com-
interests and may be cooperative and “practi-
pany profitability. When the expected value of
cally wise” (Pincoffs, 1986) in support of those
law breaking is positive, egoistic firms may con-
sider law breaking a viable option. interests—instrumental virtues that set them
Although egoistic firms exhibit amoral behav- apart from corporate egoists. However, since op-
ior to nonshareholder stakeholders, they are portunism may ultimately involve deceit, the
guided by the standards of moral stewardship of moral virtues of honesty, sincerity, and truthful-
shareholder interests described above. Moral ness are unlikely to characterize instrumentalist
virtues such as loyalty, reliability, and depend- stakeholder cultures.
ability in the pursuit of shareholder interests
could also characterize managers in corporate
egoist cultures. Adherence to local norms (an 1
We present the terms moral and morality here in quotes
ISCT concept), particularly those involving because, as we explained above, not all moral philosophers
shareholders, may characterize egoistic firms as (Kant, in particular) would regard “good” actions taken for
well. the wrong reasons as moral.
148 Academy of Management Review January

Broadly Moral Cultures decision making. That might mean expressing


act utilitarian sentiments either at the personal
We also posit the existence of two stakeholder
level—“Are benefits for a few (including me)
cultures—moralist and altruist— under the um-
really worth burdens for many others?”— or at
brella term broadly moral cultures. These cul-
the public policy level—“This policy is good for
tures are extensively other-regarding in their
the country, even if some are harmed (perhaps
decision making and attempt to adhere to moral
including me).” Therefore, taking the interests of
principles that apply to all stakeholders, not just
others into account and aiming for the welfare of
shareholders. Although moralist and altruist
society as a whole might become elements of a
firms differ in terms of the compromises that
corporate stakeholder culture. Indeed, two em-
sometimes must be considered under extreme pirical studies show evidence of act utilitarian
circumstances, both try to take stakeholder in- ethical sentiments in firms (Fritzsche & Becker,
terests into account, even when doing so does 1984; Victor & Cullen, 1988).
not appear to be in their self-interest—short or In a similar vein, managers may doubt the
long term. They value honoring their commit- overriding sanctity of the contract between prin-
ments, adhering to the spirit and the letter of cipals/shareholders and agents/managers,
contractual obligations, and treating all stake- where shareholder interests trump the interests
holders fairly and with respect. One possible of all other stakeholders. Quinn and Jones (1995)
way to distinguish instrumentalist cultures (de- have questioned the credibility of this position
scribed above) from broadly moral cultures is by arguing that it is logically incoherent and
that the former may retain practices that explic- that other moral obligations take precedence
itly weigh moral considerations against eco- over wealth-producing duties to shareholders.
nomic benefits. A classic example of these “ta- For these or other reasons, managers may feel
boo trade-offs” is putting a dollar value on that implicit contracts with other stakeholders
human life (Tetlock, Kristel, Elson, Green, & Ler- are no less binding than the shareholder/
ner, 2000). manager contract, and, therefore, they may
Broadly moral stakeholder cultures may orig- adopt broader moral standards.
inate with skepticism regarding (1) the ability of The Kantian notion of treating stakeholders as
competitive markets to provide utilitarian out- ends in themselves, as well as means to corpo-
comes over time and/or (2) the sanctity of the rate economic ends, also constitutes a broader
principal/agent contract. Examples that call the morality for corporations. Striving to uphold uni-
utilitarian results of market mechanisms into versally applicable principles (“What if all com-
question are not difficult to find, but isolated panies acted this way?”), behaving according to
examples do not render profit maximization an the Golden Rule, taking obligations seriously,
inappropriate application of rule utilitarianism, and not acting as if conventional rules apply
which focuses on costs and benefits over time. only to others are also Kantian notions that
However, competitive markets actually create might resonate with the managers of broadly
incentives to develop arrangements that allow moral corporate cultures, as is the idea that wor-
firms to capture the benefits and force someone thy “principles” cannot be discarded simply be-
else to bear the costs. Ultimately, there can be cause potential consequences to the firm may
no assurance that maximal social welfare will be negative. Victor and Cullen (1988) found that
result. Managers who reach this conclusion may some managers regarded cosmopolitan princi-
turn instead to act utilitarianism, where social ples as important elements of the ethical cli-
welfare is pursued directly through discrete de- mates of their firms. Thus, Kantian principles
cisions rather than through obedience to rules. might become a part of a stakeholder culture as
The role of their firms would then be to directly well.
strive for overall economic and social well- Some managers may respond to common lan-
being by considering the interests of all corpo- guage variants of Rawlsian notions, such as the
rate stakeholders. veil of ignorance (“there but for fortune go I”) or
Although relatively few managers are likely the difference principle (“help those less fortu-
to accept utilitarian theory wholesale, it is not nate than yourself”). Many people do believe
uncommon for people to regard consequences that the rights of others should be respected,
for others as important elements in their moral creating the possibility of prima facie stake-
2007 Jones, Felps, and Bigley 149

holder rights. A genuine “care” for stakeholders, Preston, and Sachs have noted that “stakehold-
at least in a nonproximate empathetic sense, er-oriented firms often seem to be motivated by
may also motivate broadly moral managers, as normative considerations that underlie a perva-
might the importance of such moral virtues as sive organizational commitment to humanistic
honesty, sincerity, truthfulness, and trustworthi- values for their own sake” (2002: 79). In addition,
ness. Hence, Rawlsian notions of fairness, empirical work has identified elements of social
rights, care for others, and certain moral virtues responsibility and respect for laws and profes-
could become elements of a stakeholder culture. sional codes (Victor & Cullen, 1988), along with
Finally, from an ISCT perspective, although respect for rights and justice or fairness
the standards and evidence that would authen- (Fritzsche & Becker, 1984) among corporate man-
ticate and then legitimize norms are certainly agers. We now turn to descriptions of the two
subject to debate (the proponents of ISCT offer broadly moral cultures themselves: moralist and
many possibilities on both fronts) and are un- altruist.
likely to be known to managers, a concern for Moralist cultures share the characteristics of
the authenticity and legitimacy of norms is itself broadly moral cultures: concern for all stake-
a revealing process. Managers may have moral holders and adherence to principles regardless
reasons to question either the authenticity of the of economic temptations to discard them. They
rules they play by (“Have other community will violate their moral standards only when it
members consented to these norms?”) or their is necessary to ensure firm survival. In sharp
legitimacy (“Are these norms compatible with contrast, instrumentalist firms will violate such
broader ethical standards?”). Managers who standards whenever it is economically advanta-
care about the propriety of the norms they ad- geous to do so. Whatever their source—act util-
here to would seem to have made a major step itarianism, Kantian principles, Rawlsian fair-
toward ethical behavior and a greater concern ness concerns, respect for rights, “care” for
for their stakeholders. In contrast, managers stakeholders, ICST considerations, or a desire to
who subscribe to norms simply because “that’s be morally virtuous— ethical standards come
the way things are done around here” have not first for moralist firms and are not trumped by
adopted an other-regarding morality. Thus, a economic considerations, except under the most
concern for the authenticity and the legitimacy dire circumstances.
of behavioral norms, like concerns for the When moralist firms make moral compro-
broadly ethical perspectives described above, mises in the face of financial crises, they do so
may be important elements of a firm’s stake- for moral reasons. Tetlock et al. (2000) call the
holder culture. weighing of conflicting moral considerations a
Although the language and details of these “tragic trade-off”— unfortunate, but necessary.
moral philosophies may not be known to moral These firms understand that the failure to re-
managers, the underlying sentiments of at least spond to problems that threaten corporate sur-
some of them will be. All of these notions are vival will imperil all their stakeholders, whose
substantially other-regarding perspectives and well-being depends on the firm’s economic via-
involve attempts to “do the right thing,” regard- bility. Moralist firms are moral, but pragmatic.
less of the consequences for the agent or firm. Altruist cultures are included for the sake of
They differ from the stewardship-based cultures completeness. In altruist cultures other-regard-
where the calculus of corporate self-interest is ing concerns are dominant. Moral principles
always present—straightforward in corporate trump all other decision-making criteria, even
egoist firms and more subtle in instrumentalist when firm survival is at stake, setting such firms
firms. Broadly moral firms do not routinely apply apart from moralist firms. Altruist firms will
this calculus, because other-regarding concerns honor obligations, explicit and implicit, and will
are paramount in their cultures. always treat all of their stakeholders fairly and
Some firms do seem to have broadly moral with respect. Moral standards— be they based
cultures. Kotter and Hesket (1992) concluded that on utilitarian, Kantian, Rawlsian, rights, care,
the managers of several highly successful firms virtue, or ISCT foundations—are decisive and
tended to have a strong and genuine concern for not subordinate to pragmatic considerations.
such stakeholders as employees, customers, These firms are likely to regard as worthy the
and suppliers, as well as shareholders. Post, virtues of benevolence, altruism, selflessness,
150 Academy of Management Review January

and forgiveness, in addition to the virtues found counts.” In this typology the three principal
in other cultures. Adherence to moral principles determinants of salience—power (the ability
alone, regardless of threats from powerful stake- of the stakeholder group to bring about out-
holders, might be considered the “most moral” comes that it desires, despite resistance), le-
of our stakeholder cultures. However, our dis- gitimacy (the extent to which the stakeholder
cussion of derivative legitimacy (above) clouds group’s relationship with the firm is socially
this conclusion; responding to derivatively legit- accepted and expected), and urgency (the de-
imate stakeholders (powerful, but with no moral gree to which the stakeholder group’s claim is
claim on the firm) when the interests of legiti- time sensitive and of critical importance to the
mate stakeholders are threatened may consti- group)— combine linearly to produce seven
tute a higher morality. We are agnostic on this different types of stakeholder groups, each
issue. with a predicted level of salience for manag-
The altruist culture completes our continuum, ers of the firm in question. The left side of
which now extends from fully self-regarding to Table 2 presents the same information as
fully other-regarding. As a practical matter, con- Mitchell et al.’s (1997) Venn diagram; the right
ditions of economic competition make signifi- side represents our modification of their stake-
cant growth or proliferation of fully other- holder salience theory.
regarding companies improbable. Table 2 makes the additive nature of the
We have now discussed the characteristics of model apparent; the more attributes possessed
five stakeholder cultures based on variation in by the stakeholder group, the greater the sa-
the extent to which their moral standards are lience for managers. All three attributes (defin-
other-regarding. As in Table 1, adjacent cultures itive stakeholders) result in high salience. Two
differ in terms of moral regard for an increasing attributes (dominant, dangerous, and dependent
number of stakeholder groups or a change in the stakeholders) result in moderate salience. One
subtlety with which their managers advance attribute (dormant, discretionary, and demand-
stakeholder interests. To illustrate the value of ing stakeholders) results in low salience.
our general theory, we turn to a discussion of Groups with none of these attributes are not
stakeholder salience (Mitchell et al., 1997). considered stakeholders and possess no sa-
lience.
STAKEHOLDER SALIENCE REVISITED
Incorporating Stakeholder Culture into the
Mitchell et al.’s (1997) stakeholder salience
Salience Model
theory is an attempt to “get inside the heads of
corporate managers” to determine what they This model is parsimonious and has intuitive
really pay attention to as they weigh stake- appeal. Nevertheless, a closer look at its impli-
holder concerns in their corporate policy de- cations suggests some possibilities for exten-
liberations— colloquially, “who or what really sion and refinement. As noted above, managers

TABLE 2
Comparison of Stakeholder Salience Models

Stakeholder Attributes Mitchell et al. Mitchell et al. Stakeholder Culture Type


(1997) (1997)
Stakeholder Stakeholder
Power Legitimacy Urgency Type Salience Corporate Egoist Instrumentalist Moralist

Yes Yes Yes Definitive High High High High


Yes Yes No Dominant Moderate Moderate Moderate Moderate
No Yes Yes Dependent Moderate None Moderate High
Yes No Yes Dangerous Moderate High High Moderate
Yes No No Dormant Low Moderate Moderate Low
No Yes No Discretionary Low None Low Moderate
No No Yes Demanding Low None None None
No No No Nonstakeholder None None None None
2007 Jones, Felps, and Bigley 151

of firms with different stakeholder cultures may short-term shareholder wealth maximization.
prioritize power and legitimacy differently, sug- Since powerful stakeholders are most able to
gesting the value of an extended model of stake- adversely affect corporate outcomes, power will
holder salience that includes the effects of be the primary driver of stakeholder salience for
stakeholder culture. In our extension we retain corporate egoists. Shareholders with large hold-
the three-attribute structure—power, legitimacy, ings, workers with strong unions, high-volume
and urgency— developed by Mitchell et al. customers with alternative sources of supply,
(1997). However, the moral nature of legitimacy, and governmental agencies with relevant reg-
developed above, is given more prominence ulatory powers are likely to be salient to these
here. We also agree with these authors’ conten- firms. Corporate egoist firms are likely to have
tion that stakeholder salience is the result of sophisticated mechanisms in place dedicated
managerial perceptions—psychological con- to gathering and processing information re-
structions of reality by managers, based partly lated to powerful stakeholders. Consequently,
on features of their environments. However, we they will understand power considerations
classify these psychological constructions more quite well. If their stockholders include insti-
specifically in terms of stakeholder culture. tutional investors with large holdings, then
In the following sections we describe how routines and systems, such as an office of in-
stakeholder cultures differentially influence the vestor relations, will be created to manage
perceptions of managers regarding the ascrip- and influence these investors. However, dif-
tion and subsequent weighting of the three at- fused stock ownership represents less power
tributes (power, legitimacy, and urgency) of the and will warrant less attention.
claims of stakeholder groups. In general, our
Furthermore, powerful stakeholders with
analysis posits that responding to power is sim-
time-sensitive and critically important claims
ply rational self-regarding behavior, whereas
(urgency) merit special consideration, since they
responding to legitimacy derives from other-
are the ones most likely to place intense de-
regarding (moral) sentiments. We focus on the
mands on the firm. Thus, urgency is a booster of
three “central” culture types—corporate egoist,
salience based on power. Claims combining
instrumentalist, and moralist—for two reasons.
power and urgency (i.e., definitive and danger-
First, the agency culture, grounded in the prin-
ous stakeholders) are predicted to be highly sa-
cipal/agent relationship and its assumption of
lient to corporate egoists. Since powerful stake-
self-interest, is extensively described in the fi-
nancial economics/agency theory literature. The holders can hinder the pursuit of profit
salience of stakeholder claims will depend on maximization on grounds other than urgent
the incentive structures faced by managers as claims on the company (Frooman, 1999), power
individuals and will be unpredictable at the or- without urgency (dominant and dormant stake-
ganization level. Other than placing agency cul- holders) will generate moderate salience. Legit-
tures on our stakeholder culture continuum, we imate claims are irrelevant in the corporate ego-
have nothing to add. Second, altruist cultures, ist’s culture, as are urgent claims in the absence
those that take uncompromisingly principled of power. Hence, dependent, discretionary, and
moral positions in stakeholder relationships, demanding stakeholders will not merit atten-
will play a small role in a competitive economy. tion, because neither they nor their claims are
The three central culture types, because they particularly valued or well-understood. Manag-
place differential importance on the three at- ers in egoistic cultures are “blind” to these is-
tributes, have stakeholder salience hierarchies sues because of (1) a clear prioritization of pow-
that differ from one another and from those of erful stakeholders and (2) underdeveloped
the original model, as shown on the right side of systems for dealing with them.
Table 2.
Proposition 1: Managers in corporate
egoist cultures will always regard the
Corporate Egoist Cultures and Stakeholder
interests of powerful stakeholders as
Salience
at least moderately salient; they will
As noted above, the defining ethical feature of regard these interests as highly sa-
the corporate egoist culture is the primacy of lient when the claims are also urgent.
152 Academy of Management Review January

Instrumentalist Cultures and Stakeholder salience); they will regard these inter-
Salience ests as moderately salient when the
claims are also urgent.
Instrumentalist firms place preeminent value
on the pursuit of corporate self-interest with
guile. Other terms used to convey this orienta- Moralist Cultures and Stakeholder Salience
tion are enlightened self-interest, pragmatic mo-
rality, and strategic morality. Instrumentalist Moralist firms have a genuine concern for
firms will try to capture the benefits of moral stakeholder interests, making legitimacy the
behavior (Frank, 1988; Jones, 1995) without aban- primary driver of salience for their managers.
doning their fundamental self-interest. Conse- However, moralist firms are also sensitive to
quently, power will be a primary driver of sa- power issues, since power may give stakehold-
lience, because corporate self-interest lies at the ers derivative legitimacy (discussed above), a
heart of the firm’s instrumentalist posture. How- secondary driver of salience. Since urgency pro-
ever, because the firm sees moral behavior as vides impetus for stakeholders and firms alike
instrumentally useful (up to a point), it will re- to deal with legitimate concerns, it is a booster
gard legitimacy as a secondary determinant of of salience generated by either legitimacy or
salience as well. Again, urgency is a booster of power. Combinations of legitimacy and urgency
salience generated from either power or legiti- (definitive and dependent) will be highly salient
macy. Hence, definitive and dangerous stake- to moralist firms. Stakeholders with these at-
holders will certainly be highly salient to man- tributes include shareholders, when profitabil-
agers of instrumentalist firms because of their ity is threatened; customers affected by product
power and urgency. quality; local communities affected by plant op-
Unlike corporate egoists, however, firms with erations; and employees, when threats to their
instrumentalist cultures will regard the claims livelihood are present. Legitimacy without ur-
of dependent stakeholders (legitimate and ur- gency still carries moral weight, so dominant,
gent) as moderately salient as well and may pay dependent, and discretionary stakeholders will
some attention (low salience) to discretionary be viewed as moderately salient. Note that if
(legitimate, but not urgent) stakeholders, simply instrumentalist firms (above) are good at strate-
because of the perceived long-term benefits as- gic “morality,” their behavior may be similar to
sociated with moral behavior. These benefits that of moralist firms for a time. Both are likely
might include currying favor with other power- to be responsive to power and legitimacy, albeit
ful groups that have a strong preference for from different sources—self-interest/opportun-
trustworthy companies (e.g., customers, govern- ism in the former case and a moral concern for
mental agencies) or, conversely, avoiding the legitimacy (normative or derivative) in the latter.
negative public relations that might come from Proposition 3a: Managers in moralist
treating legitimate stakeholders poorly. In a cultures will always regard the inter-
sense, instrumentalist firms may grant legiti- ests of legitimate stakeholders as at
mate stakeholders a form of “derivative power,” least moderately salient; they will re-
analogous to derivative legitimacy as discussed gard these interests as highly salient
above. when the claims are also urgent.
Proposition 2a: Managers in instru- Proposition 3b: Managers in moralist
mentalist cultures will always regard cultures will always regard the inter-
the interests of powerful stakeholders ests of powerful stakeholders as at
as at least moderately salient; they least somewhat salient (low salience);
will regard these interests as highly they will regard these interests as
salient when the claims are also ur- moderately salient when the claims
gent. are also urgent.
Proposition 2b: Managers in instru- The right-hand side of Table 2 pulls all of
mentalist cultures will always regard these revised predictions together for corporate
the interests of legitimate stakehold- egoist firms, instrumentalist firms, and moralist
ers as at least somewhat salient (low firms and summarizes our theoretical contribu-
2007 Jones, Felps, and Bigley 153

tions to stakeholder salience. A simple overview and respond to different stakeholder issues,
of this part of the table is as follows. Acting moving us beyond the individual values of
alone, attributes that are of primary importance CEOs, as used in previous research (Agle,
to a firm (power or legitimacy), based on its Mitchell, & Sonnenfeld, 1999). In addition, our
stakeholder culture, generate moderate sa- approach explains an empirical result discov-
lience. Derivative attributes (legitimacy or ered by these authors; urgency is really a sec-
power) are secondary drivers and, acting alone, ondary attribute that merely provides the “extra
generate low salience. In either case, urgency push” needed to make already salient issues
acts as a booster of salience (low to moderate; more so. While power and legitimacy both have
moderate to high), determined by primary or their champions—corporate egoist and moralist
derivative attributes, but generates no salience firms, respectively— urgency does not. In sum-
by itself. mary, this theoretical contribution, especially in
It is clear from this table that our predictions conjunction with subsequent empirical work,
of stakeholder salience are significantly af- could be an important element in the larger
fected by stakeholder culture and that they dif- cause of understanding ways for stakeholders
fer substantially from those advanced in Mitch- and firms to cooperate for mutual gain (Free-
ell et al.’s (1997) original work. Particularly man, 1984).
noteworthy are the differential responses to
power by corporate egoist firms and moralist
firms. Without power, no stakeholder group can REFERENCES
expect to be at all salient to the corporate egoist, Agle, B. R., Mitchell, R. K., & Sonnenfeld, J. A. 1999. Who
whereas two stakeholder groups without pow- matters to CEOs? An investigation of stakeholder at-
er— dependent and discretionary— can expect tributes and salience, corporate performance, and CEO
values. Academy of Management Journal, 42: 507–525.
high and moderate salience, respectively, from
moralist firms, based on their legitimacy. Ashforth, B. E., & Mael, F. 1989. Social identity theory and the
organization. Academy of Management Review, 14: 20 –
39.
DISCUSSION AND CONCLUSIONS Bargh, J. A., & Ferguson, M. J. 2000. Beyond behaviorism: On
the automaticity of higher mental processes. Psycholog-
There are three major contributions of this pa- ical Bulletin, 126: 924 –945.
per. First, we identified and developed a frame- Barney, J. B. 1986. Organizational culture: Can it be a source
work that highlights points of convergence— of sustained competitive advantage? Academy of Man-
self-regarding versus other-regarding—in agement Review, 11: 656 – 665.
several otherwise diverse approaches to busi- Barry, B., & Stephens, C. U. 1998. Objections to an objectivist
ness ethics. Second, we used this framework to approach to integrity. Academy of Management Review,
create a continuum punctuated by five corporate 23: 162–169.
stakeholder cultures— organization-level phe- Beauchamp, T. L., & Bowie, N. E. 2004. Ethical theory and
nomena that guide managerial thinking and de- business. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
cision making with respect to stakeholder rela- Bentham, J. 1996. (First published in 1789.) An introduction to
tionships. Third, as an illustrative example, we the principles of morals and legislation. (Edited by J. H.
Burns & H. L. A. Hart.) New York: Oxford University Press.
applied our stakeholder culture construct to
stakeholder salience theory and noted the emer- Berle, A. A., & Means, G. C. 1932. The modern corporation and
private property. New York: Commerce Clearing House.
gence of significantly revised predictions of sa-
lience. Burton, B. K., & Dunn, C. P. 1996. Feminist ethics as moral
grounding for stakeholder theory. Business Ethics Quar-
With respect to contributions of specific inter-
terly, 6: 133–148.
est for stakeholder theorists, the combination of
Carroll, A. B. 1979. A three-dimensional conceptual model of
points one and two above represents an impor-
corporate social performance. Academy of Management
tant integration of normative and descriptive Review, 4: 497–505.
elements of the theory. That is, the way a firm’s
Clarkson, M. 1995. A stakeholder framework for analyzing
managers actually respond to stakeholder is- and evaluating corporate social performance. Academy
sues is interwoven with notions of how they of Management Review, 20: 92–117.
should respond. Also, with a firm-level perspec- Cullen, J. B., Parboteeah, K. P., & Victor, B. 2003. The effects of
tive on salience, we can understand how a col- ethical climates on organizational commitment: A two-
lection of managers in a firm will think about study analysis. Journal of Business Ethics, 46: 127–141.
154 Academy of Management Review January

Daft, R. L., & Weick, K. E. 1984. Toward a model of organiza- Hume, D. 2000. (First published in 1740.) A treatise of human
tions and interpretation systems. Academy of Manage- nature. (Edited by D. F. Norton & M. J. Norton.) New York:
ment Review, 9: 284 –295. Oxford University Press.
Davis, J. H., Schoorman, F. D., & Donaldson L. 1997. Toward a Jensen, M. C., & Fuller, J. 2002. What’s a director to do? Best
stewardship theory of management. Academy of Man- practices: Ideas and insights from the world’s foremost
agement Review, 22: 20 – 47. business thinkers: 1–18. Cambridge, MA: Perseus.
Denison, D. R. 1996. What is the difference between organi- Jones, T. M. 1995. Instrumental stakeholder theory: A synthe-
zational culture and organizational climate? A native’s sis of ethics and economics. Academy of Management
point of view on a decade of paradigm wars. Academy of Review, 20: 404 – 437.
Management Review, 21: 619 – 654.
Jones, T. M., & Wicks, A. C. 1999. Convergent stakeholder
Denison, D. R., & Mishra, A. K. 1995. Toward a theory of theory. Academy of Management Review, 24: 206 –222.
organizational culture and effectiveness. Organization
Science, 6: 204 –223. Katz, D., & Kahn, R. L. 1978. The social psychology of organi-
zations (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley.
Detert, J. R., Schroeder, R. G., & Mauriel, J. J. 2000. A frame-
work for linking culture and improvement initiatives in Kotter, J. R, & Heskett, J. L. 1992. Corporate culture and per-
organizations. Academy of Management Review, 25: formance. New York: Free Press.
850 – 863. Langtry, B. 1994. Stakeholders and the moral responsibilities
Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. 1999. Ties that bind: A social of business. Business Ethics Quarterly, 4: 431– 443.
contracts approach to business ethics. Boston: Harvard Lord, R. G., Brown, D. J., & Freiberg, S. J. 1999. Understanding
Business School Press. the dynamics of leadership: The role of follower self-
Donaldson, T., & Preston, L. E. 1995. The stakeholder theory of concepts in the leader follower relationship. Organiza-
the corporation: Concepts, evidence, and implications. tional Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 78: 167–
Academy of Management Review, 20: 65–91. 203.
Evan, W. M., & Freeman, R. E. 1988. A stakeholder theory of March, J. G., & Simon, H. A. 1958. Organizations. New York:
the modern corporation: Kantian capitalism. In Wiley.
T. Beauchamp & N. Bowie (Eds.), Ethical theory and
Martin, J. 2002. Organizational culture: Mapping the terrain.
business (2nd ed.): 75–93. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-
Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Hall.
McClintock, C. G. 1978. Social values: Their definition, mea-
Fine, G. A. 1984. Negotiated orders and organizational cul-
tures. Annual Review of Sociology, 10: 239 –262. surement, and development. Journal of Research and
Development in Education, 12(1): 121–137.
Frank, R. 1988. Passion within reason: The strategic control of
the emotions. New York: Norton. Messick, D. M., & McClintock, C. G. 1968. Motivational bases
of choice in experimental games. Journal of Experimen-
Freeman, R. E. 1984. Strategic management: A stakeholder tal Social Psychology, 4: 1–25.
approach. Boston: Pitman
Mill, J. S. 1998. (First published in 1863.) Utilitarianism. (Ed-
Friedman, M. 1970. The social responsibility of business is to
ited by R. Crisp.) New York: Oxford University Press.
increase its profits. New York Times, September 13: 32–
33, 122–126. Mitchell, R. K., Agle, B. R., & Wood, D. J. 1997. Toward a theory
of stakeholder identification and salience: Defining the
Fritzsche, D. J., & Becker, H. 1984. Linking management be-
principle of who and what really counts. Academy of
havior to ethical philosophy. Academy of Management
Management Review, 22: 853– 886.
Journal, 27: 166 –175.
Paul, J., Costley, D. L., Howell, J. P., Dorfman, P. W., & Trafi-
Frooman, J. 1999. Stakeholder influence strategies. Academy
mow, D. 2001. The effects of charismatic leadership on
of Management Review, 24: 191–214.
followers’ self-concept accessibility. Journal of Applied
Geertz, C. 1973. The interpretation of cultures: Selected es- Social Psychology, 31: 1821–1844.
says. New York: Basic Books.
Pettigrew, A. M. 1979. On studying organizational cultures.
Gilligan, C. 1982. In a different voice. Cambridge, MA: Har- Administrative Science Quarterly, 24: 570 –581.
vard University Press.
Phillips, R. A. 1997. Stakeholder theory and a principle of
Golden, B. R. 1992. The past is the past or is it—The use of fairness. Business Ethics Quarterly, 7: 51– 66.
retrospective accounts as indicators of past strategy.
Academy of Management Journal, 35: 848 – 860. Phillips, R. A. 2003. Stakeholder legitimacy. Business Ethics
Quarterly, 13: 24 – 41.
Hart, H. L. A. 1955. Are there any natural rights? Philosophi-
cal Review, 64: 175–191. Pincoffs, E. L. 1986. Quandaries and virtues: Against reduc-
tivism in ethics. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.
Hatch, M. J. 1993. The dynamics of organizational culture.
Academy of Management Review, 18: 657– 693. Post, J. E., Preston, L. E., & Sachs, S. 2002. Redefining the
corporation: Stakeholder management and organization-
Hendry, J. 2004. Between enterprise and ethics: Business and
al wealth. Stanford. CA: Stanford University Press.
management in a bimoral society. London: Oxford Uni-
versity Press. Quinn, D. P., & Jones, T. M. 1995. An agent morality view of
2007 Jones, Felps, and Bigley 155

business policy. Academy of Management Review, 20: Swidler, A. 1986. Culture in action: Symbols and strategies.
22– 42. American Sociological Review, 51: 273–286.
Rawls, J. 1964. Legal obligation and the duty of fair play. In Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Elson, S. B., Green, M. C., &
S. Hook (Ed.), Law and philosophy: 3–18. New York: New Lerner, J. S. 2000. The psychology of the unthinkable:
York University Press. Taboo trade-offs, forbidden base rates, and heretical
counterfactuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
Rawls, J. 1971a. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap chology, 78: 853– 870.
Press of Harvard University Press.
Treviño, L. 1990. A cultural perspective on changing and
Rawls, J. 1971b. Justice as reciprocity. In S. Freeman (Ed.), developing organizational ethics. Research on Organi-
John Rawls: Collected papers: 190 –224. Cambridge, MA: zational Change and Development, 4: 195–230.
Harvard University Press.
Treviño, L. K., & Weaver, G. R. 2003. Managing ethics in
Schein, E. H. 1985. Organizational culture and leadership. business organizations: A social science perspective.
San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Stanford, CA: Stanford Business Books.
Schein, E. H. 1990. Organizational culture. American Psychol- Trice, H. M., & Beyer, J. M. 1984. Studying organizational
ogist, 45: 109 –119. cultures through rites and ceremonials. Academy of
Management Review, 9: 653– 669.
Shamir, B., House, R. J., & Arthur, M. B. 1993. The motivational
effects of charismatic leadership—A self-concept based VandenBerg, P. T., & Wilderom, C. P. M. 2004. Defining, mea-
theory. Organization Science, 4: 577–594. suring, and comparing organisational cultures. Applied
Psychology: An International Review, 53: 570 –582.
Shamir, B., Zakay, E., Breinin, E., & Popper, M. 1998. Corre-
lates of charismatic leader behavior in military units: Victor, B., & Cullen, J. B. 1988. The organizational bases of
Subordinates’ attitudes, unit characteristics, and supe- ethical work climates. Administrative Science Quar-
riors’ appraisal of leader performance. Academy of Man- terly, 33: 101–125.
agement Journal, 41: 387– 409. Walzer, M. 1994. Thick and thin: Moral argument at home and
Smith, A. 1937. (First published in 1776.) An inquiry into the abroad. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
nature and causes of the wealth of nations. New York: Weick, K. E. 2004 Mundane poetics: Searching for wisdom in
Modern Library. organization studies. Organization Studies, 25: 653– 668.
Sparks, J. R., & Schenk, J. A. 2001. Explaining the effects of Wicks, A. C., Gilbert, D. R., Jr., & Freeman, R. E. 1994. A
transformational leadership: An investigation of the ef- feminist reinterpretation of the stakeholder concept.
fects of higher-order motives in multilevel marketing Business Ethics Quarterly, 4: 475– 498.
organizations. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 22: Willer, D., Lovaglia, M. J., & Markovsky, B. 1997. Power and
849 – 869. influence: A theoretical bridge. Social Forces, 76: 571–
Suchman, M. C. 1995. Managing legitimacy: Strategic and 603.
institutional approaches. Academy of Management Re- Williamson, O. E. 1985. The economic institutions of capital-
view, 20: 571– 610. ism. New York: Free Press.

Thomas M. Jones (rebozo@u.washington.edu) is the Boeing Professor of Business


Management at the University of Washington. He received his Ph.D. from the Univer-
sity of California, Berkeley. His research interests include business ethics and com-
petitive strategy, stakeholder theory, corporate social performance, and alternative
objective functions for corporations.

Will Felps (willf@u.washington.edu) is pursuing a doctorate in organizational behav-


ior at the University of Washington. His research focuses broadly on how to build
better organizational theories and includes the role of moral identity in organizational
decision making, the asymmetric effects of “bad apple” teammates, and the perfor-
mance implications of stakeholder cultures.

Gregory A. Bigley (gbigley@u.washington.edu) is an associate professor of human


resource management and organizational behavior at the University of Washington.
He received his Ph.D. from the University of California, Irvine. His research focuses on
trust, motivation, leadership, the self, and the social psychological foundations of
high-reliability and high-performance organizing.

You might also like