You are on page 1of 25

Feeling and Thinking

Preferences Need No Inferences

R. B. ZAJONC University of Michigan

ABSTRACT: Affect is considered by most contempo- since feeling is first


rary theories to be postcognitive, that is, to occur only who pays any attention
to the syntax of things
after considerable cognitive operations have been ac- will never wholly kiss you (p. 160)
complished. Yet a number of experimental results on
preferences, attitudes, impression formation, and de-_ In it, Cummings takes for granted that feelings
cision making, as well as some clinical phenomena, are primary and, by implication, that they are
suggest that affective judgments may be fairly inde- fundamental. They are precedent to the intellec-
pendent of, and precede in time, the sorts of percep- tive qualities and elements of experience, and they
tual and cognitive operations commonly assumed to be are nearer to its essence: They are nearer to an
the basis of these affective judgments. Affective re- inner "truth."
actions to stimuli are often the very first reactions of
In contrast, contemporary psychology regards
the organism, and for lower organisms they are the
feelings as last. Affect is postcognitive. It is
dominant reactions. Affective reactions can occur
without extensive perceptual and cognitive encoding,
elicited only after considerable processing of in-
are made with greater confidence than cognitive judg- formation has been accomplished (see Figure 1).
ments, and can be made sooner. Experimental evi- An affective reaction, such as liking, disliking, pref-
dence is presented demonstrating that reliable affec- erence, evaluation, or the experience of pleasure
tive discriminations (like-dislike ratings) can be made or displeasure, is based on a prior cognitive pro-
in the total absence of recognition memory (old-new cess in which a variety of content discriminations
judgments). Various differences between judgments are made and features are identified, examined for
based on affect and those based on perceptual and their value, and weighted for their contributions.
cognitive processes are examined. It is concluded Once this analytic task has been completed, a
that affect and cognition are under the control of sepa- computation of the components can generate an
rate and partially independent systems that can influ-
overall affective judgment. Before I can like
ence each other in a variety of ways, and that both
constitute independent sources of effects in information
something I must have some knowledge about it,
processing. and in the very least, I must have identified some
of its discriminant features. Objects must be
cognized before they can be evaluated,
The intellectual contact between psychology and
Most of us will not be deeply distressed by dis-
poetry is scarce and, when it takes place, often
covering that our current theories are in conflict
tends to be exploitative. If we happen to come
across a poem that appears to support one of our
favorite generalizations, we are tempted to cite
it (not as evidence, of course, but more in the This article was the Distinguished Scientific Contribution
form of a testimonial). Or we might confer upon Award address given at the meeting of the American
Psychological Association, New York, New York, Sep-
it the status of an epigraph in one of our forth- tember 2, 1979. It was prepared with the support of a
coming chapters (commonly, to the detriment of John Simon Guggenheim Fellowship.
both the poem and the chapter), But when poetry I benefited greatly by discussing these ideas with several
people, and I am very indebted to them. I am especially
disagrees with us we are apt to ignore the conflict grateful to Hazel Markus, Phoebe Ellsworth, Allan Paivio,
altogether. Nevertheless, this paper begins with and Robyn Dawes, who all made extensive and helpful
a poem by E. E. Cummings (1973), the first comments on an earlier draft.
Requests for reprints should be sent to R. B. Zajonc,
stanza of which affirms a premise tacitly rejected Research Center for Group Dynamics, University of Michi-
by psychology many decades ago: gan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48106.

Vol. 35, No. 2, 1S1-17S AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 1S1


Copyright 1980 by the American Psychological Association, Inc.
0003 -066X/80/3 S02-0151 $00.7 5
with a controversial poet of the 1920s. But con- preferences. These aspects are reflected in the
temporary psychology not only contradicts Cum- answers to such questions as "Do you like this
mings, it also contradicts one of its very own person?" "How do you feel about capital punish-
founding fathers. Thirty years before Cummings ment?" "Which do you prefer, Brie or Camem-
published his poem on feelings, Wundt (1907) bert?" "Are you pleased with the review your
wrote in a similar vein: recent book received?" In short, I deal with some
hot cognitions (as Abelson [1963] christened
When any physical process rises above the threshold of them) and try to distinguish them from the cold
consciousness, it is the affective elements which as soon ones. The class of feelings considered here is that
as they are strong enough, first become noticeable. They
begin to force themselves energetically into the fixation involved in the general quality of behavior that
point of consciousness before anything is perceived of the underlies the approach-avoidance distinction.
ideational elements^. . . . They are sometimes states of Thus, for the present purposes, other emotions
pleasurable or unpleasurable character, sometimes they
are predominantly states of strained expectation. . . . such as surprise, anger, guilt, or shame, which
Often there is vividly present . . . the special affective have been identified in the literature and exten-
tone of the forgotten idea, although the idea itself still sively analyzed by Tomkins (1962, 1963), Izard
remains in the background of consciousness. . . . In a
similar manner . . . the clear apperception of ideas in (1977), and others, are ignored.
acts of cognition and recognition is always preceded by Unlike experimental psychologists,3 social psy-
feelings, (pp. 243-244) chologists are deeply concerned with affect and
with hot cognitions. The extensive work on atti-
Whatever happened to Wundt's affective pri-
tudes, research on cognitive dissonance and cog-
macy idea? Is there compelling evidence to reject
it? - Or to accept it, for that matter? Strictly
speaking, we have no better evidence today than
3
Wundt had in 1896. Perhaps a bit better. Contemporary cognitive psychology simply ignores af-
fect. The words affect, attitude, emotion, feeling, and
In part, my concern in this paper is with sentiment do not appear in the indexes of any of the
Wundt's assertion. More specifically, building on major works on cognition (Anderson, 1976; Anderson &
the scanty evidence we now have, I have tried to Bower, 1973; Bobrow & Collins, 1975; Crowder, 1976;
Kintsch, 1974; Lachman, Lachman, & Butterfield, 1979;
develop some notions about the possible ways in Norman & Rumelhart, 1975; Schank & Abelson, 1977;
which affect is processed as part of experience and Tulving & Donaldson, 1972). Nor do these concepts
have attempted to distinguish affect from process- appear in Neisser's (1967) original work that gave rise to
the cognitive revolution in experimental psychology. And
ing of information that does not have affective in the six volumes and the 2,133 pages of the Handbook
qualities. This article is confined to those aspects of Learning and Cognitive Processes (Estes, 1975-1978),
of affect and feeling that are generally involved in there is only one entry for affect and only one for attitude.
It is worth noting that both of these entries are in Volume
3 in a contribution written by a social psychologist. In
the last three volumes—those principally devoted to cog-
1
The italics are mine. The original is even more to nition—there are no references to affect whatsoever.
the point. "Affective elements" were "Gefuhlselemente," The notable exceptions are Handler's (1975) work on
and the italicized part of the citation was "ehe noch von thought and emotion, Neisser's 1976 essay, and Miller and
den Vorstellungselementen irgend etwas wahrgenommcn Johnson-Laird's (1976) recent volume on language and
wird" (Wundt, 1905, p. 262). perception from which the following revealing quotation
2 is taken:
It is a fact that only 12 years after the first edition
of Wundt's Grundriss was published, Nakashima (1909a; The information-processing system that emerges from
1909b) tested Wundt's assertion by collecting reaction these remarks is fearfully cognitive and dispassionate.
times of psychophysical (pitch, hue, temperature, etc.) and It can collect information, remember it, and work
affective (preference) judgments made on the same sets toward objectives, but it would have no emotional re-
of stimuli. He did not find shorter reaction times for action to what is collected, remembered, or achieved.
judgments of preference than for judgments of pitch, hue, Since in this respect it is a poor model of a person, we
temperature, etc., and thus disagreed with Wundt with should add at least one more predicate to this list of
regard to the primacy of feelings. But his study alone those that take "person" as their first argument. We
could not have buried Wundt's idea. Actually, Naka- will use Feel (person, x) to indicate that people have
shima's data were rather inconclusive, since he failed to feelings as well as perceptions, memories, and intentions.
control for levels of discriminability associated with the It might be possible to subsume Feel under Perceive on
two types of judgments. Thus, for example, subjects can the grounds that our feelings are a special class of per-
detect very small differences in hue yet feel quite indif- ception of inner states. Or we might discuss feelings
ferent in their preference for stimuli that differ so little. under Remember, the recognition that some word or
Since reaction times for comparisons vary with the size object is familiar, is after all, a matter of feeling a
of the difference, these times can be compared meaning- certain way about it. Or, since we have already jecog-
fully only if the stimuli are preselected so that difference nized that there is a strong affective component to our
thresholds for the two types of judgments are the same. intentions, we might link Feel to Intend. . . . All these

1S2 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


COGNITIVE
HIGHER
PHYSICAL REPRESENTATIONS AFFECTIVE1
ORDER I p+(JUDGMENTJ
ENCODING OF STIMULUS REACTION
ENCODING
INFORMATION

Figure 1. Typical information-processing model of affect.

nitive balance, the Schachter and Singer (1962) information about affect. It is much less impor-
studies on emotion, and Heider's (1958) attempts tant for us to know whether someone has just said
to describe the cognitive representation of affect "You are a friend" or "You are a fiend" than to
that characterizes interpersonal relationships are know whether it was spoken in contempt or with
all clear manifestations of this concern.4 There affection. Argyle and his colleagues (Argyle, Sal-
are practically no social phenomena that do not ter, Nicholson, Williams, & Burgess, 1970) found
implicate affect in some important way. Affect that 22 times more variance is accounted for by
dominates social interaction, and it is the major the tone of one's voice than by the content of
currency in which social intercourse is transacted. the utterance when people are asked to interpret
The vast majority of our daily conversations entail utterances. In fact, even when the content of
the exchange of information about our opinions, recorded utterances is nearly completely obliter-
preferences, and evaluations. And affect in these ated by means of electronic masking, filtering, or
conversations is transmitted not only by the verbal random splicing of the tape, subjects still can
channel but by nonverbal cues as well-—cues that encode the emotions expressed in these utterances
may, in fact, carry the principal components of quite reliably (Dawes & Kramer, 1966; Scherer,
Koivumaki, & Rosenthal, 1972). And we have no
difficulty in identifying emotions expressed by
considerations testify to the systematic importance of members of unknown cultures speaking unknown
this psychological predicate. Nevertheless, we will have languages. In a recent volume on person per-
little to say about Feel in the following pages, (pp.
111-112) ception, Schneider, Hastorf, and Ellsworth (1979)
Thus, Miller and Johnson-Laird explicitly acknowledge noted that "inferences based on nonverbal cues
the significance of feelings as part of experience, yet they are primarily inferences about relationships and
decide to devote minimal attention to them. Their de-
cision is noteworthy in the light of their belief that "Feel feelings, and thus are among the most important
is an indispensable predicate for any complete psychology inferences we make" (p. 142). One cannot be
and that it probably lies much closer than Perceive, Re- introduced to a person without experiencing some
member, and Intend to the basic sources of energy that
keep the whole system running" (p. 112). immediate feeling of attraction or repulsion and
Beyond these volumes there are some isolated theoreti- without gauging such feelings on the part of the
cal attempts directed toward the understanding of the other. We evaluate each other constantly, we
role of motivational and emotional factors in perception
and cognition (Broadbent, 1977; Erdelyt, 1974; Posner & evaluate each others' behavior, and we evaluate
Snyder, 197Sa). the motives and the consequences of their behavior.
4
While such studies as those of Byrne (1961), Berscheid And you have already made up your mind about
and Walster (1978), or Rubin (1973), which deal with
interpersonal attraction, also have a concern with-affect, this paper!
they do not contain specific analyses of how affect is Nor is the presence of affect confined to social
represented as part of experience. And in studies that
compare the effects of conditions that differ on the affec- perception. There are probably very few percep-
tive dimension (such as self- vs. nonself-relevance, ego- tions and cognitions in everyday life that do not
involvement), it is generally not the affective quality per have a significant affective component, that aren't
se in these conditions that is examined as the major source
of variation. - hot, or in the very least tepid, And perhaps all

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 153


perceptions contain some affect. We do not just feeling is not free of thought, nor is thought free
see "a house": we see "a handsome house," "an of feelings. Considerable cognitive activity most
ugly house," or "a pretentious house." We do often accompanies affect, and Schachter and Singer
not just read an article on attitude change, on (1962) consider it a necessary factor of the emo-
cognitive dissonance, or on herbicides. We read an tional experience. Thoughts enter feelings at vari-
"exciting" article on attitude change, an "impor- ous stages of the affective sequence, and the con-
tant" article on cognitive dissonance, or a "trivial" verse is true for cognitions. Feelings may be
article on herbicides. And the same goes for a aroused at any point of the cognitive process:
sunset, a lightning flash, a flower, a dimple, a registration, encoding, retrieval, inference, etc. But
hangnail, a cockroach, the taste of quinine, Sau- this converse relation is not totally symmetrical.
mur, the color of earth in Umbria, the sound of I will later argue for Wundt's conjecture that
traffic on 42nd Street, and equally for the sound affect is always present as a companion to thought,
of a 1000-Hz tone and the sight of the letter Q.5 whereas the converse is not true for cognition.
In fact, it is entirely possible that the very first
stage of the organism's reaction to stimuli and the
Feeling and Thinking
very first elements in retrieval are affective. It is
According to the prevalent models for affect (e.g., further possible that we can like something or be
Figure 1), preferences are formed and expressed afraid of it before we know precisely what it is
only after and only as a result of considerable and perhaps even without knowing what it is.
prior cognitive activity. How fully and completely And when we try to recall, recognize, or retrieve
must objects be cognized before they can be evalu- an episode, a person, a piece of music, a story,
ated? I argue, along with Wundt and Cummings, a name, in fact, anything at all, the affective
that to arouse affect, objects need to be cognized quality of the original input is the first element
very little—in fact, minimally. to emerge. To be sure, the early affective reaction
In order to consider this possibility more spe- is gross and vague. Nevertheless, it is capable of
cifically it is important to distinguish between influencing the ensuing cognitive process to a sig-
thoughts and feelings. At the genotypic level, this nificant degree. Needless to say, after some cog-
distinction is not an easy one to make, for it nitive activity has been executed, there may be
hovers dangerously near the mind-body duality. new feeling to the stimulus. But the fact that
Some conceptual elements of this distinction, how- cognitions can produce feelings—as in listening
ever, may be identified for purposes of clarity. to a joke, for example, where affect comes at the
While feelings and thoughts both involve energy end with a punch line or as a result of post-
and information, the first class of experiences is decision dissonance—need not imply that cogni-
heavier on energy, whereas the second is heavier tions are necessary components of affect. What I
on information (e.g., Inhelder & Piaget, 1QS8; want to argue is that the form of experience that
pp. 347-348). In the pure case, the analysis of we came to call feeling accompanies all cognitions,
feelings attends primarily to energy transforma- that it arises early in the process of registration
tions, for example, the transformation of chemical and retrieval, albeit weakly and vaguely, and that
or physical energy at the sensory level into auto- it derives from a parallel, separate, and partly in-
nomic or motor output. In contrast, the analysis dependent system in the organism.
of thoughts focuses principally on information At the phenotypic level, we can support Wundt's
transformations. In nearly all cases, however, conjecture by spelling out in somewhat greater
detail some of the ways in which affective judg-
ments and reactions, or hot cognitions, differ from
5
This conjecture probably does not apply to incidental their cold cognitive counterparts, keeping in mind
perceptions where the attentive processes are at minimum, that the first category is represented by the proto-
although it is not inconceivable that the traces of these
incidental perceptions still might recruit affect upon re- type "I like Joe," and the second by "Joe is a
trieval and thus become hot. In fact, Izard (1979) as- boy."
sumes that some emotion is always present in conscious- Affective reactions are primary. Wundt and
ness. Normally, it is the emotion of "interest" that domi-
nates behavior. This emotion, which directs and sustains Cummings are joined by Bartlett and Osgood in
attention and exploration, is absent only when other emo- the view that feelings come first. Bartlett (1932)
tions such as distress or anger "achieve consciousness"
(p. 16S). observes in his book on remembering,

1S4 • FEBRUARY 1Q80 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


Attitude names a complex psychological state or process tremely difficult to demonstrate that there has
which .it is very hard to describe in more elementary actually been any prior cognitive process whatso-
psychological terms. It is, however, as I have often
indicated, very largely a matter of feeling, or affect. . . . ever. One might argue that these are cases in
[When] a subject is being asked to remember, very which one alternative so overwhelmingly dominates
often the first thing that emerges is something of the
nature of attitude. The recall is then a construction,
all the others that only a minimum of cognitive
made largely on the basis of this attitude, and its gen- participation is required and that that is why the
eral effect is that of a justification of the attitude, (pp. cognitive involvement preceding such decisions is
206-207)
so hard to detect. But this argument must con-
front the observation that if all decisions involve
In his analysis of environments as perceptual
the evaluation of alternatives, then when choices
targets, Ittelson (1973) asserts that "the first level
appear quite lopsided to the decision maker, it is
of response to the environment is affective. The
even more important to scrutinize the alternatives
direct emotional impact of the situation, perhaps
that appear inferior, for it is entirely possible that
largely a global response to the ambiance, very
one of them possesses some hidden but overriding
generally governs the directions taken by subse- virtue. It is therefore not without merit to sup-
quent relations with the environment. It sets
pose that in many decisions affect plays a more
the motivational tone and delimits the kinds of
important role than we are willing to admit. We
experiences one expects and seeks" (p. 16). Pref-
sometimes delude ourselves that we proceed in a
erences influence language comprehension and lan-
rational manner and weigh all the pros and cons
guage production as well (Premack, 1976). Os-
of the various alternatives. But this is probably
good (1962) was impressed with the primacy of
seldom the actual case. Quite often "I decided in
affect in a different way:
favor of X" is no more than "I liked X." Most
of the time, information collected about alterna-
First, I must confess that, when we began this research
over ten years ago, I had the expectation that the major tives serves us less for making a decision than for
factors of the semantic space would represent the ways justifying it afterward. Dissonance is prevalent
in which our sensory apparatus divides up the world— just because complete and thorough computation
e.g., would parallel Boring's "dimensions of consciousness."
. . . The accumulating data have proved my expectation is not performed before the decision (Festinger,
wrong . . . the dominant factors of evaluation, potency 1964). We buy the cars we "like," choose the
and activity that keep appearing certainly have a re- jobs and houses that we find "attractive," and
sponse-like character, reflecting the ways we can react to
meaningful events rather than .the ways we can receive then justify those choices by various reasons that
them. might appear convincing to others who never fail
But these major factors also seem to have an affective to ask us, "Why this car?" or "Why this house?"
as well as a response-like character. As a matter of fact,
the similarity of our factors to Wundt's (1896) tridimen- We need not convince ourselves.8 We know what
sional theory o f . jeeling—pleasantness-unpleasantness, we like.
strain-relaxation, and excitement-quiescence—has been In a study of consumer behavior, Quandt
pointed out to me." (pp. 19-20)
(1956) found that buyers often do not attend to
It is significant also that at least three social- the features of the article that they consider cri-
terial for their decisions and often base their
psychological conceptions labeled "cognitive" con-
choices on features that they previously dismissed
sistency theories focus not on consistency of con-
as irrelevant, And Kahneman and Tversky (1979)
tent but on the consistency of affect (Abelson & have demonstrated that numerous axioms of de-
Rosenberg, 1958; Heider, 1958; Osgood & Tan- cision theory that give decisions their rational
nenbaum, 1955). flavor are blatantly contradicted by experimental
Decisions are another area where thought and results.
affect stand in tension to each other. It is gen-
erally believed that all decisions require some
conscious or unconscious processing of pros and
cons. Somehow we have come to believe, tauto- »Phoebe Ellsworth (Note 1) illustrates the role of
affect in her own recent decision experience. In trying
logically, to be sure, that if a decision has been to decide whether to accept a position at another uni-
made, then a cognitive process must have pre- versity, she says, "I get half way through my Irv Janis
balance sheet and say, 'Oh hell, it's not coming out right!
ceded it. Yet there is no evidence that this is Have to find a way to get some pluses over on the other
indeed so. In fact, for most decisions, it is ex- side!' "

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 155


Affect is basic. In one of her last books, which ing), and it is these components which provide us with
what might most appropriately be called the "feeling-
bears the provocative title of Mind: An Essay on tones" of concepts as a part of their total meaning, (p.
Human Peeling, Susan K. Langer (1967) tried to 195)
show "that the entire psychological field—includ-
ing human conception, responsible action, ration- Affective reactions are inescapable. Unlike
ality, knowledge—is a vast and branching develop- judgments of objective stimulus properties, affec-
ment of feeling" (p. 23). Affect is the first link tive reactions that often accompany these judg-
in the evolution of complex adaptive functions that ments cannot always be voluntarily controlled.
eventually differentiated animals from plants. And Most often, these experiences occur whether one
unlike language or cognition, affective responsive- wants them to or not. One might be able to con-
ness is universal among the animal species. A trol the expression of emotion but not the experi-
rabbit confronted by a snake has no time to con- ence of it itself. It is for this very reason that
sider all the perceivable attributes of the snake law, science, sports, education, and other institu-
in the hope that he might be able to infer from tions of society keep devising ever new means of
them the likelihood of the snake's attack, the making judgments "objective." We wish some
timing of the attack, or its direction. The rabbit decisions to be more independent of these virtually
cannot stop to contemplate the length of the inescapable reactions.
snake's fangs or the geometry of its markings. If We may completely fail to notice a person's
the rabbit is to escape, the action must be under- hair color or may hardly remember what it was
taken long before the completion of even a simple shortly after meeting the person. But we can
cognitive process—before, in fact, the rabbit has seldom escape the reaction that the person im-
fully established and verified that a nearby move- pressed us as pleasant or unpleasant, agreeable or
ment might reveal a snake in all its coiled glory. disagreeable, as someone to whom we were drawn
The decision to run must be made on the basis of or someone by whom we were repelled. And these
minimal cognitive engagement. affective reactions—and, more important, the re-
It is thus significant that in categorizing facial trieval of affect—occur without effort. In con-
expressions, about 50% of the variance is ex- trast, some cognitive judgments require substan-
plained by the pleasant-unpleasant dimension tial effort. Chess contestants typically lose sev-
(Abelson & Sermat, 1962; Hastorf, Osgood, & Ono, eral pounds of their weight in the course of a
1966), and the same value is obtained for the tournament.
multidimensional scaling of similarities among pho- Because affective judgments are inescapable,
tographs of faces (Milord, 1978). Similarly, it they cannot be focused as easily as perceptual and
is a typical result in semantic differential studies cognitive processes. They are much more influ-
that among the three factors Evaluation, Potency, enced by the context of the surround, and they
and Activity, all of which Osgood considers to be are generally holistic. Affective reactions are thus
affective components of meaning, it is the first less subject to control by attentive processes.8
that accounts for about 50% of the variance.7
And it is no accident, according to Osgood (1969),
that these three factors of the semantic space are 7
It is therefore something of a paradox that so little
found repeatedly among diverse sets of concepts: attention is paid to affect in information-processing studies.
Most of the tasks in experiments on information process-
In my opinion, it is the innatcness of the emotional re- ing are verbal. Most of them involve some forms of
action system of the human animal that underlies the semantic memory. If the semantic space is primarily an
universality of the affective E-P-A components of mean- affective space, as Osgood argues, then the affective com-
ing. In other words, the "innateness" of E-P-A . . . is ponents and qualities of information need to be given as
really the pan-humanes of emotional reactions, and these much attention as their phonemic, graphemic, lexical,
obviously have evolutionary significance for the survival semantic, conceptual, or pictorial counterparts.
8
of any species. Organisms without other specialized adap- The existentialists (e.g., Sartre, 1947) ascribe a sub-
tive mechanisms (e.g., armor, coloration, poisons, etc.) stantial voluntary component to emotion. "The existen-
which were unable to represent for themselves the good tialist does not believe in the power of passion. He will
versus bad implications of things (antelope versus saber- never agree that a sweeping passion is a ravaging torrent
toothed tiger), the strong versus weak of things (saber- which fatally leads a man to certain acts and is therefore
toothed tiger versus mosquito), and the quick versus slow an excuse. He thinks that man is responsible for his pas-
of things (saber-toothed tiger versus quicksand) would sion" (pp. 27-28). Because of the participation of sen-
have little chance of survival. In the human species sory, cognitive, and motor processes, the argument that
these "gut" reactions to things appear as the affective emotions have some voluntary component is not without
meaning system (the E-P-A components of total mean- basis.

156 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


Affective judgments tend to be irrevocable. embert to Brie" are judgments on J-scales. Thus,
Once a cognitive judgment has been made—for affective judgments are always about the self.
example, that at the forthcoming social hour there They identify the state of the judge in relation to
will be more scotches drunk than bourbons-—one the object of judgment.
can still be persuaded that it may turn out other- Affective reactions are difficult to verbalize. The
wise. It can be pointed out, say, that the dis- remarkable aspect of first impressions of persons
tribution of ages of the guests is different than is their immediacy. When we meet a stranger, we
that we really like scotch better than bourbon, know within a fraction of a second whether we
is greater than the supply of scotch. We can like the person or not. The reaction is instan-
readily accept the fact that we can be wrong. taneous and automatic. Perhaps the feeling is
But we are never wrong about what we like or not always precise, perhaps we are not always
dislike. Hot cognitions are seldom subjectively aware of it, but the feeling is always there. If our
false. It would be much harder to persuade us later experience with the stranger conflicts with
that we really like scotch better than bourbon, the first impression, we are terribly surprised. We
given that we feel otherwise. Once formed, an consider it an exception. Paradoxically, this sub-
evaluation is not readily revoked. Experiments jective validity of affective reaction, this certainty
on the perseverance effect, the strong primacy that we "know what we like," is often accom-
effects in impression formation, and the fact that panied by our inability to verbalize the reasons for
attitudes are virtually impervious to persuasion by our attraction or repulsion to the person.11 When
communication all attest to the robust strength asked why we like someone, we say that we like
and permanence of affect. Affect often persists the person because he or she is "nice," "pleasant,"
after a complete invalidation of its original cog- or "interesting." But these adjectives describe
nitive basis, as in the case of the perseverance our reactions to the person, not the person. There
phenomenon when a subject is told that an initial simply aren't very effective verbal means to com-
experience of success or failure has been totally municate why we like people and objects or what
fabricated by the experimenter (Ross, Lepper, & it is that we like about them.
Hubbard, 1975). The communication of affect, therefore, relies
The reason why affective judgments seem so much more on the nonverbal channels (Ekman &
irrevocable is that they "feel" valid. We are not Friesen, 1969; Schneider, Hastorf, & Ellsworth,
easily moved to reverse our impression of a person 1979). Yet it is remarkably efficient. And it is
or of a piece of music. We trust our reactions, in the realm of nonverbal expression of feelings
we believe that they are "true" and that they ac- that their basic nature is again revealed. The
curately represent an internal state or condition. universality of emotional expression strongly sug-
Perhaps the subjective validity of affective judg- gests our evolutionary continuity with other spe-
ments and reactions and our confidence in these cies and the fundamental nature of affect. The
judgments derive from the Cartesian tradition B facial expressions of humans upon biting into a
that allows us to doubt everything except our own
feelings, especially the feelings of doubt. Perhaps
it reflects a basic reality. 10 9
Hume (1898), too, held that emotions (passions) can-
not be false. "A passion must be accompanied with some
Affective judgments implicate the selj. When false judgment, in order to its being unreasonable; and
we evaluate an object or an event, we are describ- even then 'tis not the passion properly speaking, which is
ing not so much what is in the object or in the unreasonable, but the judgment" (p. 196).
10
event, but something that is in ourselves. Cog- Because nonverbal cues exchanged in social inter-
action are dominated by affect, they are perceived as hav-
nitive judgments deal with qualities that reside in ing such properties as trustworthiness and freedom from
the stimulus: "This cat is black," "Camembert voluntary control (Schneider, Hastorf, & Ellsworth, 1979,
pp. 123-127).
and Brie are soft-ripened cheeses." These judg- "Mandler (197S), Neisser (1967), and Nisbett and
ments are made on I-scales that are orders of Wilson (1977) pointed out that individuals have no access
stimuli (Coombs, 1964). Affective judgments, to the cognitions that occasion, mediate, or cause their
actions, that are parts of their attitudes, or that deter-
however, are made on J-scales, that is, scales on mine their preferences. On the basis of an extensive re-
which are located jointly the various stimuli view of the social psychological literature, Nisbett and
Wilson (1977) concluded that introspective reports about
as well as the ideal preference point of the per- influences on the subjects' evaluations, decisions, and ac-
son. "I dislike this black cat" or "I prefer Cam- tions Were so unreliable as not to be trusted.

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 157


sour apple and their expressions of surprise, anger, primacy conjecture by comparing reaction times
delight, or serenity are remarkably similar across for psychophysical judgments and for preferences.
all cultures and are not far removed from the He failed. But he did find evidence that judg-
expressions of the great apes. Perhaps we have ments of pleasantness were independent of sensory
not developed an extensive and precise verbal qualities and that these judgments could not have
representation of feeling just because in the pre- been mediated by these qualities. Similar inde-
linguistic human this realm of experience had an pendence, based on multidimensional scaling, has
adequate representation in the nonverbal channel. been reported more recently, for example, in study-
The role of affective communication is par- ing the perceptions of and preferences for soft
ticularly significant in the social interaction among drinks. Cooper (1973) found that similarity scal-
animals. The effectiveness of communication of ing yielded a space dominated by a "cola-ness"
affect and the accuracy of recognition of affective dimension, whereas preference scaling generated a
expression are illustrated by the results of Pratt space dominated by popularity of the drinks.
and Sackett (1967). They raised rhesus monkeys Generally, it appears that similarity judgments
in conditions that allowed complete contact with predict preferences only when the similarity judg-
peers, in conditions that allowed only visual and ments are themselves highly evaluative, as in the
auditory access, and in complete isolation. The case of admissions officers judging college candi-
monkeys were then examined for the kinds of dates (Klahr, 1969) or art-trained students judg-
animals they preferred to approach. Those raised ing paintings (Berlyne, 197S; O'Hare, 1976). Os-
under the same conditions preferred each other good (1962) took it as a given that the affective
twice as much as those raised under different con- reaction system "is independent of any particular
ditions, even when the stimulus animals were total sensory modality" (p. 21).
strangers to the test monkeys. While it could not If there is indeed a separation between affect
be determined what sorts of cues allowed the ani- and cognition, then it is not surprising that re-
mals to make these fine discriminations, it is very search on preferences, attitudes, attractions, im-
likely that the three groups developed during the pressions, aesthetic judgments, and similar affec-
course of their previous experience distinct pat- tive responses—research that commonly has in-
terns of emotional responding to new stimuli and voked cognitive mediators—has not been terribly
to strange individuals, and that the animals raised successful. If overall preferences were simply a
under the same conditions found each other more matter of calculating the combination of weighted
attractive because of the familiarity of these emo- component preferences, and if component prefer-
tional patterns. ences were nothing more than cognitive representa-
The reliance of affect on nonverbal means of tions of object features marked with affect, then
communication has, I believe, implications for the the problems of predicting attitudes, decisions,
way it is processed. For if affect is not always aesthetic judgments, or first impressions would
transformed into semantic content but is instead have been solved long ago. After all, these prob-
often encoded in, for example, visceral or muscular lems have been around for nearly a century. Yet
symbols, we would expect information contained except for trivial cases or cases in which the
in feelings to be acquired, organized, categorized, responses are highly cognitive (e.g., Yntema &
represented, and retrieved somewhat differently Torgerson's [1961] study of judgments of ellip-
than information having direct verbal referents. ses), the cognition-based solutions to these prob-
Recent electromyographic research provides strong lems have rarely predicted more than 20% of the
evidence for the participation of muscular activity total variance.
in the imagination, recall, and production of emo- The dismal failure in achieving substantial atti-
tional states (Lang, 1979; Schwartz, Fair, Salt, tude change through various forms of communica-
Mandel, & Klerman, 1976). In light of these tion or persuasion is another indication that affect
intuitions, it is not unreasonable to speculate that is fairly independent and often impervious to cog-
the processing of affect is closer to the acquisition nition. If attitudes consist of information units
and retention of motor skills than of word lists. that have affect or utilities attached to them, then
Affective reactions need not depend on cognition. to change an individual's attitude, what could be
At the turn of the century, Nakashima (1909a, simpler than providing the individual with'alter-
1909b) tried to find support for Wundt's affective- native information units that have the same sort

158 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


of affect as that attached to the desired attitude? basis for most cognitive judgments—judgments
If a person believes that Candidate A is honest, even as primitive as recognition, for example. In
we can simply give the person information proving order to distinguish this class of features from
that A is not honest. Or, we could change the simple discriminanda, I call them preferenda (Za-
centrality or the weight of honesty. Yet this jonc, Note 2).
approach has been the least successful in attitude I cannot be very specific about preferenda. If
change, Even the most convincing arguments on they exist they must be constituted of interactions
the merits of spinach won't reduce a child's aver- between some gross object features and internal
sion to this vegetable. Direct persuasion effects states of the individual—states that can be altered
have been so weak that researchers have instead while the object remains unchanged, as, for ex-
turned to more pernicious avenues of attitude ample, when liking for a stimulus increases with
change, such as insufficient justification, persuasion repeated experience. Color preferences are a case
through distraction, the foot-in-the-door technique, in point. Similarity scaling of color yields three
or the bogus pipeline. dimensions—brightness, hue, and saturation—that
It is unlikely that calculations based on dis- explain almost all of the variance in similarity
criminable component features and their affective judgments. But on the basis of Nakashima's
values will reliably predict our overall affective (1909a) research and according to unpublished
reactions to objects and events. These reactions work of Premack and Kintsch (Note 3), the scal-
do not seem to be composites of such elements. ing of color for preference would not reveal these
An affective reaction to a person we meet emerges three factors. If we did not know from other
long before any of these features can be identified, sources that brightness, hue, and saturation ex-
let alone evaluated. The assumption that com- haust the entire range of differences among colors,
ponent affect, utilities, or values attach themselves then we would not discover them by means of
to the very same features that the subject attends preference scaling. Abstract preferences for color
to in a typical detection, recognition, discrimina- and color preferences for classes of objects, such
tion, or categorization task is likely to be wrong.12 as hair, cars, or houses, are still more problematic
The analysis of preferences is not simply an analy- if we insist on using brightness, hue, and satura-
sis of cold cognitive representations that have be- tion in quantifying them. And the same applies
come hot, that is, cognitive representations that to face recognition: Physical features do not serve
have some affect attached to them.13 The stimulus as discriminanda for faces (Milord, 1978; Patter-
features that serve us so well in discriminating, son & Baddeley, 1977). It is therefore an inter-
recognizing, and categorizing objects and events esting problem to discover what it is in color that
may not be useful at all in evaluating these ob- "holds" affect if it isn't brightness, hue, and satu-
jects. If this is indeed the case, then there must ration and what it is in a face that "holds" affect
exist a class of features that can combine more if it isn't physical features. The answer to this
readily with affect and thereby allow us to make problem is probably that some physical aspects,
these evaluations, to experience attraction, repul- perhaps vague, gross, or configural, are involved,
sion, pleasure, conflict, and other forms of affect, but not alone. Preferenda must consist of an
and to allow us to have these affective reactions interaction of these global features with some in-
quite early after the onset of the sensory input. ternal state or condition of the individual.
These features might be quite gross, vague, and Affective reactions may become separated from
global. Thus, they might be insufficient as a content. It sometimes happens that we are re-
minded of a movie or of a book whose contents •
12
1 did not have the slightest doubt of this assumption, we are unable to recall. Yet the affect present
however, when I wrote my dissertation (Zajonc, 1955), when leaving the movie or our general impression
which employed it without question. of the book are readily accessible. Or we are re-
13
The term hot cognition has been used fairly indis-
criminately, although it generally refers to cases wheh minded of an interpersonal conflict of long ago.
affect accompanies or qualifies information. "I have a The cause of the conflict, the positions taken, the
malignant tumor" is a hot cognition. However, the
emotional experience of listening to one's favorite piece
matter at issue, who said what, may have all been
of music performed by one's favorite artist is less likely forgotten, and yet the affect that was present dur-
to receive the label of hot cognition. It is even less mean- ing the incident may be readily retrieved. Such
ingful to speak of hot cognitions when affect becomes sepa-
rated from the original cognitions. experiences, together with such clinical phenomena

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 1S9


as free-floating anxiety, hysteria, or posthypnoti- jects that can be induced by virtue of mere re-
cally induced moods, all point to the possibility peated exposure (Harrison, 1977; Zajonc, 1968).
that some aspects of affective processes might well While the empirical results that established the
be separate and partly independent of cold cog- phenomenon were quite consistent, their explana-
nitions. Occasions when they are not include those tion continued to be very elusive. Theories that
when an affective experience has been communi- attempted to account for the mere exposure effect,
cated to someone else or when it has been thought such as Harrison's (1968) response competition
of a great deal. On such occasions an elaborate hypothesis or Berlyne's (1970) optimal arousal
cognitive representation of affect occurs that may theory, treated affect as resulting from a prior
be processed very much like any other type of cognitive process. Both theories contained the
information. It is important to observe, however, remnants of Titchener's (1910) thesis on familiar-
that not all affective experiences are accompanied ity. In explaining the preference for familiar ob-
by verbal or other cognitive representations and jects, Titchener attributed a critical role to recog-
that when they are, such representations are im- nition, which he thought gave the individual a
precise and ambiguous. "glow of warmth, a sense of ownership, a feeling
of intimacy" (p. 411). The majority of subse-
Preferences Need No Inferences: quent findings bearing on the explanation of the
Empirical Evidence exposure effect, however, have revealed that recog-
nition must play a relatively minor role, as must
The prevalent approach to the study of prefer-
the subjective feeling of recognition.
ences and related affective phenomena holds that
Matlin (1971) was the first to discover that
affective reactions follow a prior cognitive process:
the role of recognition in the exposure effect may
Before I can like something I must first know
have been overstated. During an initial experi-
what it is. According to this prevalent view,
mental session, she presented Turkish-like words
therefore, such cold cognitive processes as recog-
either three times or six times. Subsequently,
nition or categorization are primary in aesthetic
these words, together with others that were not
judgments, in attitudes, in impression formation,
shown at all, were rated for liking and also for
and in decision making: They come first. If we
familiarity. That is, for each word the subjects
say, for example, that we like John because he is
had to decide whether they saw it previously in
intelligent, rich, and compassionate, it follows that
the exposure series and to report how much they
we must have gained some impression of John's
liked it. Table 1 shows Matlin's results. Liking
intelligence, wealth, and compassion, and combined
is averaged as a function of objective familiarity
them, before we formed an attraction to him. This
and as a function of subjective familiarity. Note
must be especially so in the case of judgments of
that there is an effect due to subjective familiarity,
novel stimuli before the component units become
that is, when the subjects thought a stimulus was
fused into an integrated structure. Thus, if the
old they rated it more positively than when they
complexity of polygons is an important basis of
thought it was new. However, the objective his-
their attractiveness, then polygons that are judged
tory of the individual's experience with the stimu-
pleasing (or displeasing) must have previously
lus is just as effective in influencing liking. Stim-
been somehow examined for their complexity.
Otherwise, the calculus of preferences makes little
sense.14 TABLE 1
The first indication that affect may not require Average Stimulus Affect Ratings as a Function of
extensive participation of cold cognitive processes Objective Familiarity (Old-New) and Subjective
appeared in studies of the exposure effect, that is, Familiarity ("Old"-"New")
the phenomenon of increasing preference for ob-
Subjective familiarity
14
Affective reactions to objects that have been en- Objective familiarity "Old" "New"
countered and evaluated many times may become auto-
mated, thus gaining some independence from the compo- Old 4.90 4.20 4.47
nent processes (Shiffrin & Schneider, 1977). As such, they New 4.20 3.90 4.01
may have different properties than first reactions, It is
those first affective reactions (that is, those elicited when M 4.55 4.05
individuals are asked to evaluate objects totally novel to
them) that I wish to consider at this point. Note. Data are from Matlin (1971).

160 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


V, -39

E 2 ={.24)

Subjective Familiarity

Recognition Confidence(•<—E4=-81

Recognition Accuracy p E5=.56


V2-.48
Figure 2. Causal model for independent affect; goodness of fit is x 2 (5) = 39.0. V = variable; E =
error. (From "Exposure Effects May Not Depend on Stimulus Recognition" by R. L. Moreland
and R. B. Zajonc, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1979, 37, 1085-1089. Copyright
1979 by the American Psychological Association, Reprinted by permission.)
uli that the subjects had actually seen were liked different roles to the recognition factor. The
better than stimuli not seen, independently of program distinguishes between latent variables
whether the subjects thought of them as "old" (constructs) and their observed indicators (mea-
or "new," sures). By estimating the unknown coefficients
Similar results were obtained recently by More- in a system of simultaneous equations for any
land and Zajonc (1977, 1979), using Japanese particular model, the program describes the pat-
ideographs. Subjects were given 0, 1, 3, 9, and tern of relations among the latent variables, dis-
27 prior exposures, counterbalanced, of course, tinguishing causal effects from unexplained varia-
with the stimuli. Following these exposures, the tion in each case.
subjects made a variety of recognition and liking The results of this analysis are shown in Figure
judgments. A number of findings are of interest. 2. Latent variables are shown in ellipses, while
Many stimuli shown in the first series, some of measures of those variables are shown in rec-
them 27 times, were not recognized as familiar tangles. The coefficients linking the ellipses with
when shown later. Taking only those stimuli that the boxes represent the validities with which par-
were so judged, and relating the rated attractive- ticular latent variables were assessed by their mea-
ness of these stimuli to their actual number of sures. Path coefficients linking the latent vari-
exposures, we obtained correlations of .43 in one ables to each other represent causal relations.
experiment and of ,50 in another. An objective Unexplained variation in the latent variables (Vi
history of exposure influenced liking of stimuli for and V 2 ) and error in the various measures (Ei
which the subjects could not have felt a "glow of through E 5 ) are also shown. Some parameters
warmth" or a "sense of ownership." (shown in parentheses) had to be set equal to
We also performed another type of analysis. some a priori value in the maximum likelihood
Because we had a sufficient number of measures, solution so that variance in all of the latent vari-
we were able to use linear structural equation ables could be identified,
analyses to evaluate various causal models of our The first model tested was one postulating that
data. We used the LISREL III program (see stimulus exposure has two mutually independent
Joreskog & Sorbom, 1977) to calculate maximum effects, one cognitive and one affective, or one
likelihood estimates for causal models that assign cold and one hot. We supposed that under the

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 161


-Ev=.45
Ef(.00>*"
Recognition Confidence *"—£4=82
Recognition Accurocyp—E5=.68

V, =.33
Figure 3. Causal model for mediated affect; goodness of fit is x 2 (6) =83.6. V = variable; E =
error. (From "Exposure Effects May Not Depend on Stimulus Recognition" by R. L. Moreland and
R. B. Zajonc, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1979, 37, 1085-1089. Copyright 1979 by
the American Psychological Association. Reprinted by permission.)

impact of repeated exposure, people gain an in- jective recognition and the likelihood of recogni-
creasing ability to recognize the stimulus—They tion were controlled by statistical techniques. And
achieve a feeling of subjective familiarity and an the results showing that stimulus recognition was
awareness of recognition, which authors since not a necessary condition for the exposure effect
Titchener have thought to be the necessary condi- were correlational.
tions for an increased positive affect toward the Much firmer evidence, however, that hot cogni-
stimulus. This is the purely cold effect that is tion is quite short on cognition was collected by
capable of generating the eventual "glow of W. R. Wilson (197S), who controlled for recogni-
warmth." However, we wanted to know as well tion experimentally by means of an ingenious tech-
whether, quite independently of this cold cogni- nique. He employed the method of dichotic lis-
tive effect, there is also an affective change, or tening in order to reduce recognition to a chance
hot effect—that is, whether subjects acquire a level. Random sequences of tones, such as those
more positive attitude toward the object as ex- constructed by Vitz (1964), were presented to one
posure increases, independently of recognition. ear, and a story was simultaneously presented to
They do. While the path coefficient from stimulus the other. Subjects were asked to track the story
exposure to subjective recognition is substantial on a written page to verify whether what they
(.53), indicating that recognition improves with heard corresponded to the printed text. The melo-
exposure, there also is a hot effect: There is a dies were played five times each. The subjects
strong path from stimulus exposure to subjective were subsequently given a recognition memory
affect that is independent of recognition (.66). test in which the earlier melodies and other melo-
We can compare this model with one that is dies that they had never heard were played. But
entirely cold, that is, with one that requires the now there was no interference from the other chan-
entire process to be mediated by cognitive factors, nel, and no other task was required of the sub-
by the discriminanda. This model, shown in Fig- ject. The subjects also rated all the melodies for
ure 3, says essentially that whatever affective liking, some subjects giving their recognition mem-
changes take place as a result of exposure are ory judgments before, others after, the ratings
entirely mediated by stimulus recognition. The for liking. The procedure succeeded in reducing
result of requiring affect to be mediated by recog- recognition memory nearly to the chance level.
nition is a substantial reduction in the efficiency The accuracy of recognition was 59% in one ex-
of prediction. The x2 in the previous model was periment and only 53% in another.
39.0 (df - 5) and in this model is 83.6 (df = 6), Table 2 shows the results of these experiments.
generating a significant (p < .01) difference be- Again, as in the case of previous results, liking
tween the two models of x 2 ( l ) = 44.6. varies with subjective recognition. But apart from
The experiments just described all involved pre- this effect, liking also varies with the objective his-
sentation of stimuli under optimal conditions; tory of stimulus exposure. With recognition reduced
that is, there was nothing to prevent the subjects nearly to the chance level, differential affective
from registering what was shown and from memo- reaction to the stimuli is obtained as a consequence
rizing the information presented to them. Sub- of mere repeated exposure. Random melodies

162 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


presented five times were liked better than melo- These experiments establish, I believe, that af-
dies never heard, even though the subjects could fective reactions to a stimulus may be acquired
not discriminate the former from the latter for by virtue of experience with that stimulus even if
familiarity. not accompanied by such an elementary cold cog-
In a follow-up of these studies, Kunst-Wilson nitive process as conscious recognition. Thus, a
(who is the same person as W. R. Wilson) and I theory that assumes that subjective experiences of
tried to reproduce the effect in a visual mode novelty and familiarity mediate the affective re-
(Kunst-Wilson & Zajonc, 1980). Random poly- sponse acquired during the course of exposures
gons were constructed and presented for an ex- must contend with the results showing that with
tremely brief time interval—in fact, only 1 milli- the subjective experience of novelty held constant,
second. Subsequently, the subjects rated the poly- systematic variations in affect can be obtained
gons for liking and were tested for their recogni- just by means of an objective manipulation of ex-
tion memory. Judgments were made in paired posure.
comparisons to avoid possible response bias. However, one should not assume that no form
Again, recognition was at a chance level: 48%. of recognition occurred. Obviously, some discrimi-
However, of the stimuli that were liked, 60% nation, however primitive or minimal, must have
were old and 40% were new. Sixteen of 24 sub- taken place, even though it must have been at
jects liked objectively old stimuli better than new a level not accessible to the subject's awareness.
stimuli, but only 5 of 24 recognized them as such It is somewhat surprising that any effect at all
at better than chance level. And of the 24 sub- was obtained with exposures as short as 1 milli-
jects, 17 showed better discrimination between second, but it should be noted that the stimuli
objectively old and objectively new stimuli in their were high contrast (black on white) and that no
affective judgments than in their recognition re- mask was used. Detectable effects with 1-milli-
sponses, while only 4 showed such superiority of second exposures were also obtained by Shevrin
recognition over affective judgments. Thus, the and Fritzler (1968) and by Shevrin, Smith, and
subjects were able to distinguish between the old Fritzler (1971). These authors reported differ-
and new stimuli if they used liking as their re- ential evoked potentials and word associations to
sponse, but they were not able to distinguish be- critical and control stimuli presented for 1 milli-
tween them if they had to identify them as "old" second—stimuli that the subject could neither
or "new." This result may be taken as, evidence recognize nor identify. Even more pertinent is
that a Class of features (preferenda) exists that the work of Marcel (Note 4). He presented over
allows individuals to experience affect toward ob- a large number of trials either a single word or
jects but does not allow them to accomplish cog- a blank always followed by a mask. The exposure
nitive tasks as simple as those in recognition duration of the word was varied. The subjects
memory tests. were then asked whether anything had been pre-
sented before the mask. If they answered yes,
TABLE 2 two words were then presented to them under
optimal conditions. The subjects were then asked
Average Stimulus Afeet Ratings as a Function of
which of these two words was more visually simi-
Objective Familiarity (Old-New) and Subjective
lar to the one shown before the mask. Finally,
Familiarity ("Old"-"New")
they were asked which of these same two words
Subjective familiarity was more semantic ally similar to the stimulus
Objective familiarity "Old" "New" M shown before the mask. With decreasing stimu-
lus exposure, all three types of judgments tended
Old
4.20 4.12
to become less accurate, and eventually all three
Experiment I 4.03
Experiment II 3.51 3.85 3.66 reached the chance level. But the first to become
New totally unreliable were judgments regarding the
Experiment I 3.7S 3.07 3.30 actual presence of the stimulus words. The second
Experiment II 3.03 3.02 3.03
M type of judgment to be reduced to a chance level
Experiment I 4.02 3.52 by the decreasing exposures was that concerned
Experiment II 3.29 3.40 with physical similarity. And when the subjects
Note. Data are from Wilson (1975). were totally unable to rise above chance in com-

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 163


ate liking, in that objects and events are liked
a ..IKE-DISLIKE just because they are optimally complex or simple,
novel or familiar, then the judgments of objects
OLD- NEW along these dimensions should, in general, be more
SURE
stable, more consistent, and made sooner than
affective judgments. At the very least, these judg-
ments should not be slower, more inconsistent,
to 2.5 unstable, or inefficient than affective ratings. In
i
particular, we would expect that recognition judg-
Ul ments, for example, which reflect the operation of
z 2.0 the collative variable of novelty, should be made
UJ
with greater confidence than liking judgments.

6
Q
U- Figure 4 shows the results from our previous
study with Kunst-Wilson using 1-millisecond ex-
8 1.5 posures. The results show that compared to
liking judgments, recognition judgments are made
with much less confidence. The differences are,
GUESS w, in fact, huge—more than 6 times their standard
LIKING RECOGNITION errors. Even if we take only the recognition judg-
FIRST FIRST
ments on which the subject was correct, this effect
Figure 4. Confidence in liking and recognition remains true.1-"1
judgments. (Drawn from data reported by Kunst- One more bit of data. According to the preva-
Wilson & Zajonc, 1980.) lent view, attending to discriminanda alone should
be easier and quicker than attending to discrimi-
paring physical similarities of the words, they nanda tagged with values. Since the latter in-
were still judging their semantic similarities quite volve more information, more detail must be at-
reliably. tended to, and the subject would consequently
Marcel's results are reminiscent of those re-
ported by Broadbent and Gregory (1967), who
found that unpleasant words (such as "blood")
were more often misperceived as other unpleasant lr
' We suspected that these results may be due to the
words (such as "death") than as equally probable fact that the subjects knew they could be wrong on
neutral words. Marcel's results, moreover, are of the old-new judgments, and awareness of this fact might
have induced caution in them. But they could not be
particular interest if we consider the consistent "wrong" on their liking judgments. These latter judg-
findings from the semantic differential literature ments express opinions, and people generally feel free to
showing that meaning is very highly saturated with hold any opinions whatsoever. We tried, therefore, to
"objectify" affective judgments and to "subjectify" recog-
affect. If it is indeed affect that allows subjects nition judgments in order to determine whether the con-
to make a semantic match in the absence of con- fidence ratings would be reversed. To obtain "objectified"
scious recognition, then deciding which of two affective ratings, subsequent to stimulus exposures, we
asked subjects in another experiment to rate the polygons
given words is emotionally more similar to a stim- for their "aesthetic value." We told them also in this
ulus word should be at least as easy as deciding connection that our polygons had all been rated for aes-
which is semantically more similar. This experi- , thetic value by art critics. To obtain "subjectified" recog-
nition judgments, we told the subjects that one of the
ment, in fact, is now being carried out by More- two polygons in each slide might appear more "familiar"
land and myself. than the other and asked the subjects to indicate which
Another consequence derives from the prevalent one did in fact appear more familiar. Thus, the subjects
could now be "wrong" in their affective judgments, where-
approach to affect and cognition. Prevalent the- as, recognition became much more a matter of subjective
ories, especially the one developed by the late impression. The results did not change a great deal.
Confidence was a little greater for subjective familiarity
Daniel Berlyne (1967), generally assume that the judgments than for the old-new judgments and a little
affective reaction occurs in response to the level weaker for aesthetic judgments than for judgments of
of arousal, which in turn is mediated by collative outright liking. But these differences were quite small.
variables such as complexity, novelty, or congru- The means were 2.01 and 2.41 for familiarity and aes-
thetic judgments, whereas they were 1.60 and 2.29 for
ity. If complexity, congruity, and novelty medi- recognition and liking.

164 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


require more processing time. If familiarity medi- tions the subjects were required to engage in ex-
ates the affective reaction generated as the result tensive semantic processing of the adjectives: In
of repeated exposures, then judgments of famili- one they checked the adjectives to see if they
arity should be made quicker than judgments of meant the same as comparison words (semantic)
liking. If anything, however, our results showed and in another to see whether they described the
the opposite. Although of only borderline signifi- subject (self-reference). Note that while these
cance, affective judgments of polygons were made last two conditions both activate semantic struc-
faster than recognition judgments. tures within which the adjectives are imbedded,
the self-reference condition brings the subject into
Feeling and Thought: Two Systems? a cognitive domain greatly charged with affect.
Rogers, Kuiper, and Kirker's findings are espe-
About 10 years ago, Hyde and Jenkins (1969) cially significant in view of the virtual discontinu-
carried out an experiment in which subjects were ity of the self-reference effects. Of the 10 self-
tested for recall of word lists to which they were reference adjectives, 2.84 were correctly recalled.
exposed under different conditions. Some sub- In contrast, only .34, .68, and 1.33 adjectives were
jects were simply exposed to the words with the correctly recalled in the structural, phonemic, and
instruction to pay close attention. Of three other semantic treatments, respectively.
groups^ one was instructed to count the number
Another group of similar studies that used rec-
of letters in each word, another to report the
ognition memory rather than recall also suggests
presence of the letter E, and a third to rate each
strong participation of affect in information pro-
word for pleasantness. In some groups the sub-
cessing. Formulating their experimental problem
jects were warned that they would be tested for
in depth-of-processing terms (Craik & Lockhart,
recall; in others they were not warned. Hyde and
1972), Bower and Karlin (1974) showed photo-
Jenkins's results were quite strong. Among both
graphs of faces to subjects with instructions to
the subjects who were warned about a future recall
judge the photographs for gender, honesty, or
test and those who were not warned, those asked
likeability. Following exposures, subjects were
to rate pleasantness showed the best recall. Hyde
tested for recognition memory in two experiments.
and Jenkins took their data to mean that items
The hit rate was higher when the subjects rated
are "arranged" differently in storage depending
photographs for honesty or likeability than when
on the context prevailing during acquisition. The
they reported gender. Strnad and Mueller (1977)
superior performance of subjects who rated the
replicated Bower and Karlin's results in a between-
words for pleasantness was due to the fact that
subjects design, and Warrington and Ackroyd
these subjects acquired the words as "units of
(197S) found parallel effects when comparing these
meaning" and could therefore recruit for them
effects for faces and words, also in a between-sub-
supportive components of associative structures.
jects design. According to Bower and Karlin
When words are examined for number of letters
(1974), deeper processing facilitates recognition
or the presence of the letter E, such "structures
because it forces the subject to attend to a greater
are not activated and the recall is unorganized"
variety of detail. "Judgment of honesty of face
(Hyde & Jenkins, 1969, p. 480).
would appear to require comparison to an idiosyn-
Since, as we have seen earlier, the semantic con-
cratic set of vague prototype criteria regarding
tent of verbal material is saturated with affect, the patterning of features such as distance be-
the facilitation that occurred as a result of prior
tween the eyes, size of pupils, curvature of the
pleasantness ratings in the Hyde and Jenkins ex-
mouth, thickness of lips, and so on" (p. 7S6).
periment could have strong affective components.
They went on to say that "if you want to re-
Two conditions of a recent experiment by Rogers, member a person's face, try to make a number of
Kuiper, and Kirker (1977) are of particular in-
difficult personal judgments about his face when
terest in this respect. In all conditions, their sub-
jects were tested for recall of previously shown you are first meeting him" (pp. 756-757). Pat-
adjectives. In one condition, the subjects had to terson and Baddeley (1977) asked subjects to do
check the adjectives to see if they were printed in just that: In one condition their subjects rated
the same or different type as a sample print (struc- photographs of faces for the length of nose, dis-
tural), and in another whether they rhymed with tance between the eyes, roundness of face, or full-
comparison words (phonemic). But in two condi- ness of lips. In another condition the ratings

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 16S


were vague and less detailed but much more likely jects were asked whether the given adjective de-
to recruit affect: nice-nasty, reliable-unreliable, scribed themselves, a best friend, a parent, an-
intelligent-dull, and lively-stolid. Recognition other friend, a teacher or boss, a favorite TV
memory, as reflected by d' and by hit- and false- character, or Jimmy Carter. Also asked for some
alarm rates, was clearly superior for what Patter- adjectives was a semantic encoding question:
son and Baddeley called "personality" ratings. "Means the same as ?" Following the
Patterson and Baddeley (1977) thus disagreed initial series, subjects were given a recognition
with Bower and Karlin and concluded that their memory task in which the original adjectives were
own "results clearly did not implicate analysis of interspersed among an equal number of similar
facial features as a critical or optimal basis for distractor items. Keenan and Bailett's results are
face recognition" (p. 411). Instead, they believed very clear. Self-reference generated by far the
that should they "ever find an optimum strategy highest recognition performance (over 90%),
for encoding of faces, analysis of individual fea- whereas reference to Jimmy Carter produced a
tures is unlikely to be its focus" (p. 4 1 7 ) . recognition rate of less than 65%. The other
There seems to be general agreement that when recognition rates were arranged according to the
judgments of pleasantness are made of faces or of social signfkance that the target had for the sub-
adjectives, individuals engage in forms of deeper ject: best friend, parent, friend, and teacher.
information processing. What is not agreed upon If the superior recognition memory for the self-
is the type of content that is accessed at these reference items was due to deeper processing, one
deeper levels. Patterson and Baddeley (1977) would expect that response times for these items
doubt that face recognition is based on the sorts would be longer than response times for items
of discriminanda that we would intuitively suspect processed at shallow levels. However, the results
of serving recognition. But if these discriminanda were quite the opposite and very strikingly so.
are not the basis of face recognition, what is? Encoding times for self-reference items were by
Is face recognition, then, based on preferenda? far the shortest. The longest reaction time was
Recall in this respect that the scaling of faces for found for items referred to Jimmy Carter (note
similarity yields pleasantness as the major factor, that the experiment was run in 1977 when Carter
explaining about 50% of the variance, whereas was not quite as well known as he is now). More-
physical features play a relatively minor role. over, the other targets had response times that
Clearly, the contribution of affect to face recogni- varied directly with the proportion of correct rec-
tion has been underestimated. Early face dis- ognitions.
crimination is based primarily on affective reac- Keenan and Bailett (1979) attempt a variety
tions. Infants smile at an approaching face as of cognitive interpretations, but at the conclusion
early as 10 weeks of age, and at 12 weeks they of what is truly a valiant effort, they offer the
smile differently at familiar and unfamiliar faces possibility that in the course of processing self-
(Izard, 1978). referent information, "the crucial dimension un-
Curiously enough, none of the above studies derlying memory is not what the subject knows
mention the possible role of affect in processing or the amount of knowledge that is used in en-
face information. And none of the studies on coding the item, but rather what the subject feels
recognition memory of faces collected reaction about what he knows" (p. 2 5 ) , It is no longer
time data to verify whether the assumed deeper clear that deeper processing necessarily requires
processing was accompanied by longer response more time. Structures that are highly integrated
latencies. However, in one recent study, Keenan and that have been frequently "tuned in" may
and Bailett (1979) used methods similar to those process information quite rapidly. The relation
of Rogers, Kuiper, and Kirker (1977) but instead between reaction time and depth of processing can-
administered recognition memory tests. They re- not be predicted, therefore, for all tasks (Bad-
port results that have an important bearing on deley, 1978). Keenan and Bailett's study may be
the form of information processing that may taken as evidence against the levels-of-processing
emerge when affect is involved. As in the previous approach. But it may also be taken as evidence
studies, a number of adjectives were presented, that the participation of affect in processing in-
and the subjects were required to check them formation of some types may increase efficiency
against a number of criteria. For example, sub- to a remarkable degree. The beneficial role of

166 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


affect in memory is dramatically illustrated in a Hubert (1963) and by Posner and Snyder (1975b).
paired-associates study in which Sadalla and Loft- In a typical impression formation task, the first
ness (1972) asked subjects to form pleasant, un- authors found strong primacy effects for impres-
pleasant, and nonemotional images for each pair sions (i.e., the overall affective rating of the per-
and found considerably poorer performance for the son was influenced more by early trait adjectives
neutral pairs than for either the pleasant or the in the list) and an equally strong recency effect
unpleasant pairs. for the recall of the adjectives. Anderson and
It is this type of result that suggests the possi- Hubert (1963) suggested that "the impression
bility of some separation between affect and cog- response is based on a different memory system
nition. Consider the task in those experiments than that which underlies the verbal recall" (p.
where the subject is asked to verify if a given 388). They did not go on to specify how these
adjective, say "honest," describes him or her. It two systems might differ except to say that "as
is most unlikely that the process of this verifica- each adjective is received, its meaning is extracted
tion involves checking the item for its presence and combined with the current impression, thus
in a list, as some information-processing models yielding a changed impression. Once this is done,
would have it. For one thing, no evidence sug- memory for the adjective per se is no longer neces-
gests even vaguely that the self is represented as sary for the impression process" (pp. 390-391).
a list of trait adjectives (Markus, 1977). For Dreben, Fiske, and Hastie (1979) found similar
another, the question is probably not interpreted order effects for impressions, and Hamilton, Katz,
by the subject to mean "Is the trait 'honest' true and Leirer (in press) obtained better recall when
of you?" but more likely to mean "Is the trait subjects organized items into an impression of a
'honest' consistent with your perception of your- person than when subjects regarded these items
self?" If this is indeed the interpretation that as discrete units. More important for the dual-
the subject imposes upon the task, then we must process hypothesis, however, is the finding of
inquire what may be meant by "consistent with Dreben, Fiske, and Hastie that the weights calcu-
your perception of yourself?" To some extent lated for the adjectives did not predict their recall.
this consistency may involve absence of content That is, the adjectives assumed to be contributing
that is mutually contradictory; for example, the the most to impression are not necessarily also the
person could not be both tall and short. But ones that are best recalled. Following his cogni-
more important, some form of affective consistenc}' tive response theory, Greenwald (1980) suggested
is probably involved. That is, the self as used that cues effective in helping the individual re-
in this task is probably some global and general trieve content may not be the same ones that are
impression suffused with affective quality. What effective in helping retrieve the evaluative aspects
is matched is primarily the affective quality of the of the content. It is not unreasonable to suppose
item with the affective quality of the impression. that the major difference between these two types
Of course, the shorter processing times for self- of cues may be the difference between discrimi-
referent items may be due to the fact that we nanda and preferenda. And it is perhaps the differ-
have more integrated and better structured im- ence between these cues that is also involved in
pressions of ourselves and of people who are im- the perseverance effect (Ross, Lepper, & Hubbard,
portant to us. But it is equally true that the 1975), in that details of initial information about
self is a target charged with strong, widespread, success (or failure) are used only to construct an
and clear affect, and an emotional match would overall impression of one's own task competence
therefore be quite easy for the subject to verify. and are soon discarded. Thus, in debriefing, when
There is a need in these studies to separate the the experimenter tells the subjects that their suc-
elaboration and integration of the cognitive struc- cess (or failure) was rigged, this new information
ture from the affect that pervades it, but such a may no longer be capable of making contact with
control procedure is difficult, for the two proper- the original input (which by then has been re-
ties are highly correlated. coded and discarded) and may therefore have
That the affective qualities in impression forma- little effect on its original affective consequences.
tion are processed differently and perhaps sepa- Posner and Snyder (197Sb) also argue for a
rately from the cognitive content that "carries" dual memory. In their experiments, subjects are
that impression is shown both by Anderson and shown a sentence such as "James is honest, loyal,

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 167


and mature," and in a subsequent display a probe are linguistic components (logogens). He also
word such as "foolish" is flashed. Two tasks are proposed that pictorial information is organized
studied. In one the subject is asked to verify if in a synchronous and spatially parallel manner,
the word itself was among those in the preceding whereas verbal information is discrete and se-
sentence. In another, the required match is be- quential. Finally, he suggested that the process-
tween the emotional tone of the word and that of ing of pictures is more likely to be the business of
the preceding sentence. The interesting result the right-brain hemisphere, whereas the processing
these authors obtain is that, as the length of the of words is the business of the left. Paivio's pro-
list increases, reaction times increase for word posal for a dual coding theory kindled a contro-
matching and decrease for emotional tone match- versy of some vigor. While Anderson (1978) has
ing. Posner and Snyder (197Sb) agree with An- recently argued that the controversy cannot be
derson and Hubert about the two memory systems resolved with what we now know about these
for the component adjectives and for the overall processes, it has nevertheless stimulated some ex-
impression, but they doubt that the "emotional citing empirical and theoretical work (e.g., Banks
information concerning impression is handled in & Flora, 1977; Kerst & Howard, 1977; Kosslyn &
any different way than other semantic dimensions Pomerantz, 1977; Paivio, 1978b; Pylyshyn, 1973;
in the memory system" (p, 80). Their doubts Shepard, 1978).
should be weakened by a recent impression-forma- Most relevant for my discussion, however, is
tion experiment in which the pattern of recall of Paivio's (1978c) finding that reaction times for
individual adjectives was effectively manipulated pleasant-unpleasant ratings are faster for pictures
in the hope of thereby affecting the primacy of than for words. Paivio takes this result to indi-
impressions. Riskey (1979) was able to change cate that "the analog information involved in
the recall of adjectives, but the primacy of impres- pleasantness and value judgments is more closely
sions nevertheless remained unchanged. associated with the image system than with the
While these authors propose separate systems, verbal system" (p. 207). This
it is always separate cognitive systems that they analog pleasantness information is "carried by" affective
propose. In contrast, the separation being con- and motor processes that are closely associated with visual
memory representations of things. Such processes pre-
sidered here is between an affective and a cogni- sumably originate as reactions to things and persist as
tive system—a separation that distinguishes be- affective or motor memories that can be activated' by
tween cliscriminanda and preferenda and that takes pictures of the referent objects, or, more indirectly, by their
names when accompanied by the appropriate contextual
us back to Wundt and Bartlett, who speculated cues. More specifically, pleasantness and value judgments
that the overall impression or attitude has an might be based on continuously variable interoceptive re-
existence of its own, independent of the compo- actions and approach or avoidance tendencies that are
activated jointly by the comparison stimuli and the task
nents that contributed to its emergence. The instructions, (p. 207)
question that cannot be answered with the data
However, the specific responses of the autonomic
thus far collected is whether the affect-content
nervous system are not readily discriminable, since
separation is simply a matter of separate storage
there are not many receptors to register the fine
(as Anderson and Hubert, on the one hand, and
changes in autonomic processes (Averill, 1969;
Posner and Snyder, on the other, have proposed)
Mandler, Mandler, Kremen, & Sholiton, 1961).
or whether there isn't some separation already at
Moreover, interoceptive process and motor memo-
the point of registration and encoding. The rapid
ries are slower than the affective responses they
processing times of affect suggest a more complete
are presumed to activate.
separation of the two processes at several junc-
It is a fact, of course, that all sorts of judg-
tures.
ments are faster and more efficient for pictures
One is necessarily reminded in this context of
than for words, and this may be so just because
the dual coding hypothesis proposed by Paivio
pictures are able to evoke an affective reaction
(1975) for the processing of pictures and words. more directly and faster than words. An affective
Paivio (1978a) suggested a number of differences reaction aroused early in the encoding process—
between the processing of these types of content, earlier than it is possible for the interoceptive and
for example, that representations of pictures motor memories to become effective—might facili-
emerge as perceptual isomorphs or analogs (ima- tate a complex cognitive encoding sequence by an
gens), whereas parallel units in the verbal system initial categorization along affective lines, which,

168 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


as we have seen, requires minimal stimulus in- sented in the left visual field (De Renzi Si Spinn-
formation. Such facilitation through early affec- ler, 1966; Moscovitch, Scullion, & Christie, 1976),
tive sorting that relies not only on discriminanda and (b) that the recognition of emotional ex-
but on preferenda as well may also induce a con- pressions shows the same right-brain superiority
structive process that can more readily recruit (Suberi & McKeever, 1977).
stored content by searching for congruent affective It has also been suggested to me by Richard J.
tags,10 Katz (Note 5) that there exists a network in the
This review suggests that a separation between central nervous system, the locus coeruleus, which
affect and cognition may well have a psychological is ideally suited for the kind of partially inde-
and a biological basis.17 Recall that in contrast pendent processing of affect that I have suggested
with cold cognitions, affective responses are effort- here. The potential sensitivity of the locus coeru-
less, inescapable, irrevocable, holistic, more diffi- leus to preferenda can be inferred from a number
cult to verbalize, yet easy to communicate and to of interesting properties and features of this sys-
understand. Consider also that the processing of tem. Above all, it is excited differently by novel
affect is probably an even stronger candidate for and by familiar stimuli. Second, self-stimulation
the right hemisphere than the processing of pic- studies have demonstrated that the locus coeruleus
tures (Carmon & Nachson, 1973: Dimond, Far- is sensitive to incentives. It is further known
rington, & Johnson, 1976; Ley & Bryden, 1979; that it is capable of innervating sensory areas
Milner, 1968; Safer & Leventhal, 1977; Schwartz, (such as the colliculi and geniculate bodies), emo-
Davidson, & Maer, 1975). In the context of this tional areas (the amygdala and hypothalamus),
review it is especially interesting (a) that face mnestic areas (the hippocampus), and the cere-
recognition is superior when the stimuli are pre- bral cortices. Most important, however, is the
fact that the locus coeruleus is capable of very
fast responding. Finally, Katz also noted that the
18
Another area of research • in which affect may be enkephalenergic system, which controls the action
implicated (although it had not been so suspected) is the
frequency-judgment paradigm. Typically, in these ex- of enkephalins (naturally occurring opiates) and
periments .subjects are shown stimuli in different fre- is situated at the locus coeruleus, is also involved
quencies, and two types of judgments are collected after- in reinforcement and in different reactions to
wards. In one condition, the subjects are shown the old
stimuli interspersed among new ones and are asked to novelty and familiarity. All of this means, at the
report for each item whether it is new or old. In the very least, that what I have proposed about the
other condition, the subjects must say how often each processing of affect is not inconsistent with recent
stimulus occurred. It turns out that the frequency judg-
ment generates greater accuracy than the binary recogni- knowledge about the relevant neurophysiological
tion memory judgment (e.g., Proctor, 1977; Proctor & mechanisms. It means that the organism is
Ambler,'1975). equipped with a neurochemical apparatus capable
Two findings are of interest in the present context.
First, subjects have remarkable confidence in their fre- of telling the new from the old and the good from
quency judgments (Howell, 1971). Second, warning the the bad, of remembering the old, the good, and
subjects that they will be estimating frequencies of events the bad, and of making all these decisions rapidly
(vs. simply recalling them) and varying the length of
the list both influence free recall but have little if any without having to wait for the slow feedback from
effect on frequency estimation (Howell, 1973). It thus the autonomic system.
appears that frequency judgments behave like affective Affective reactions are primary in ontogeny.
judgments. It is possible, therefore, that frequency esti-
mation is more likely to invoke an underlying affective The infant knows to cry and to smile long before
reaction (which accrues from repeated stimulus exposures) it acquires any semblance of verbal skills (Izard,
than the binary recognition memory task. It may be 1978, 1979). Meltzoff and Moore (1977) report
hotter. Since frequency judgment makes exposure effects
salient and since it requires finer discrimination than that human infants can imitate emotional expres-
recognition memory, it may recruit affect as an auxiliary sions at 12 days of age, long before they acquire
source of information. In fact, it has been suggested language. And good-bad is one of the very first
that recognition memory responses and frequency estima-
tion are not made from the same sources of information discriminations that children learn.
(Wells, 1974), although what these sources are and how More important, however, affect is clearly pri-
they differ from each other is not altogether clear (Hintz-
man, 1976). mary in philogeny. Affect was there before we
17
Multiple processing systems and multiple channel con- evolved language and our present form of thinking.
ceptions are today more the rule than the exception in The limbic system that controls emotional reac-
the study of sensory processes (Graham & Nachmias,
1971; Trevarthen, 1968). tions was there before we evolved language and

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 169


with the newly evolved system to carry out some
adaptive functions jointly. These conjectures
make a two-system view more plausible than one
that relegates affect to a secondary role mediated
and dominated by cognition.
Because it is so heavily rooted in verbal skills,
the cognitive system in humans has properties that
are quite distinct from those of affect. Above all,
the cognitive system is infinitely more diverse and
flexible than the affective system. Anything at
all can be said and thought with various degrees
of precision, and these things can be said and
thought in an infinite variety of ways. But there
are only a handful of emotions and feelings that
can be felt, and they can be felt only in some
few, very constrained ways. And for reasons that
must be rooted in the partial separation of the
two systems, affect can be communicated much
more efficiently and accurately than thought in
spite of the fact that its vocabulary is quite lim-
ited. It was a wise designer who provided sepa-
rately for each of these processes instead of pre-
senting us with a multiple-purpose appliance that,
Figure 5. Time course of the stimulus, sensa- like the rotisserie-broiler-oven-toaster, performs
tion, affect, and cold cognitions (R = response). none of its functions well.

our present form of thinking. It was there before


the neocortex, and it occupies a large proportion Conclusion
of the brain mass in lower animals. Before we
evolved language and our cognitive capacities, It is too early to write a model for affect and for
which are so deeply dependent on language, it was the various ways that it interacts with cold cog-
the affective system alone upon which the organ- nitions. The important pieces of evidence are still
ism relied for its adaptation. The organism's re- missing. However, we can begin to specify the
sponses to the stimuli in its environment were facts that such a model must accommodate. Fig-
selected according to their affective antecedents ure 5 summarizes these facts by schematizing the
and according to their affective consequences. time course of the stimulus together with the
Thus, if the most recent version of homo sapiens ensuing sensory process, the affective response,
specifies that affective reactions are mediated by and some simple aspects of the cognitive process
prior cognitive processes—as contemporary cog- (recognition and feature identification). A stimu-
nitive views would have it—then at some point lus is presented for a fixed time interval. The
in the course of evolution, affect must have lost stimulus triggers a number of processes that can
its autonomy and acquired an intermediary in the vary in their onset times and offset times. I have
form of cold cognition. This scenario seems most shown these processes as ranges of their onset
unlikely. When nature has a direct and autono- times, ignoring the offset times altogether for the
mous mechanism that functions efficiently—and present purposes. (I have also ignored the fact
there is no reason to suppose that the affective that under some conditions, stimulus onset can
system was anything else—it does not make it be anticipated by the response process.) The on-
indirect and entirely dependent on a newly evolved set times of these four processes are influenced by
function. It is rather more likely that the affec- stimulus conditions and by subject states (e.g.,
tive system retained its autonomy, relinquishing previous experience with stimuli of the given class,
its exclusive control over behavior slowly and exposure to immediately preceding stimuli that
grudgingly. At most, the formerly sovereign af- may generate contrast or assimilation, knowledge,
fective system may have accepted an alliance mood states, priming, or expectation.

170 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


Note that a variety of temporal relations holds cisions about affect require the least information
among affect, recognition, and feature identifica- and are often based on a different decision scheme
tion. Of course, sensory process must have the than either recognition or feature identification.
earliest onset. Its onset times, too, differ depend- Each of the three, affect, recognition, and feature
ing on the stimulus, level of attention of the or- identification, is a form of categorization. Affec-
ganism, the peripheral processes that are activated, tive reactions of the type considered here are for
context, etc. Also, an affective reaction always the most part unidimensional and sometimes just
directly follows the sensory input. In RI this binary: safe-dangerous, good-bad, or nice-nasty.
reaction is strong and salient, and it might domi- Such binary decisions can under some circum-
nate the ensuing cognitive process. In R2 and R3, stances be made quite reliably, even in the ab-
affect .(shown in broken circles) is also aroused sence of reliable bases. Moore and Shannon
immediately following the sensory process, but it is (1956) have shown that reliable circuits can be
weak and does not significantly influence the sub- constructed using arbitrarily unreliable relays, pro-
sequent stages of the cognitive process. But for af- vided the relays form parallel circuits that are
fect, recognition, and feature discrimination, all com- mutually redundant. Zajonc and Smoke (1959)
binations are possible. I have given examples of applied this principle to group performance, and
three of the six possible response patterns. In RI, Smoke and Zajonc (1962) to group decisions.
affect is first, recognition occurs later, and fea- That is, given certain group decision processes,
ture discrimination is last. The primacy of affect groups can make judgments much more reliably
over recognition in RI reflects our own data than the average group member. An analogous
(Kunst-Wilson & Zajonc, in press) and the results situation may well exist for affect where the stimu-
of typical subliminal perception experiments (e.g., lus triggers several parallel responses and the de-
Blum & Barbour, 1979; Shevrin & Fritzler, 1968). cision scheme can well be a minimal quorum. 10
The difference between recognition and feature Recognition, however, even though it also consti-
discrimination that favors the former reflects the tutes a binary choice (old-new), does not have a
results of Patterson and Baddeley (1977), who, similar advantage because the redundancy of the
it will be recalled, found that subjects could recog- component criteria (e.g., features of configural
nize photographs better when they judged them properties) is seldom as high as in the case of
on "personality" characteristics than when they affect. Moreover, minimal quorum is seldom a
judged them on specific physical features. The decision basis. In fact, in experimental work on
results of Marcel (1976) and of Keenan and recognition memory, great care is taken to assure
Bailett (1979) also suggest that recognition can that criterial features are fairly independent of
precede feature identification.18 each other. Just because a photograph shows the
RQ presents the case typically considered by face of a male is not sufficient for calling it "old"
information-processing models: The cognitive pro- or rejecting it as "new," unless previous expo-
cess begins with the individual first discriminating sures have shown only female faces.
a critical feature that allows recognition. And Each of the responses in Figure 5 can facili-
finally it is recognition that gives rise to the af- tate the ones succeeding it. An affective reaction
fective response. In Rs, recognition precedes fea- can thus act to precategorize the stimulus for the
ture identification, as is the case when letters subject trying to decide whether it is "old" or
that form words are recognized better than letters "new." And recognition may facilitate feature
that do not form words (Johnston & McClelland, identification by a similar prior selection process.
1974) or when meaning is apprehended while the Each operation reduces the universe of alterna-
word itself cannot be identified, as in the para- tives for the next choice. It is therefore entirely
lexic response of certain aphasic patients (Mar- possible for stimuli that have a strong effective
shall & Newcombe,. 1966). potential to evoke affective reactions rapidly, to be
Figure 5 shows the lower temporal limits of recognized sooner than neutral stimuli, and to be
these reactions. Except for the sensory process, remembered better. Thus, Figure S also shows
affect is assumed to be capable of the earliest on- 18
Similar effects are obtained in vision (e.g., Graham
set. How can that be? & Nachmias, 1971).
10
Perhaps the following analysis, speculative to In the case of decisions or parallel signalling circuits
such as may be involved in affective reactions, the mini-
be sure, may point to some possible answers. De- mal quorum is equivalent to a veto decision or its inverse.

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 171


the representations in memory that are left by the influence the important outcomes in our lives, we
three processes (affect, recognition, and feature cannot but agree that affective phenomena deserve
identification), To the extent that these traces are far more attention than they have received from
redundant, the likelihood of a later retrieval would cognitive psychologists and a closer cognitive
be facilitated. scrutiny from social psychologists,
I began this paper with a quotation from Wundt,
REFERENCE NOTES
and it must be apparent that another spirit has
emerged as I have developed my arguments— 1. Ellsworth, P. Personal communication, May 13,- 1979.
that of Freud. The separation of affect and cog- 2. Zajonc, R. B. Preferenda and discriminanda: Process-
ing of affect. Paper presented at the First Ontario
nition, the dominance and primacy of affective Symposium on Personality and Social Psychology, Lon-
reactions, and their ability to influence responses don, Ontario, Canada, August 1978.
when ordinary perceptual recognition is at chance 3. Premack, D., & Kintsch, W. Personal communication,
July 1979.
level are all very much in the spirit of Freud, the
4. Marcel, J. Unconscious reading: Experiments on people
champion of the unconscious. In terms of my who do not know that they are reading. Paper pre-
formulation, there seem to be at least two different sented to the British Association for Advancement of
forms of unconscious processes. One emerges Science, Lancaster, England, 1976.
where behavior, such as that occurring in discrimi- 5. Katz, R. J. Personal communication, February 1979.
nation among stimuli, is entirely under the influ- REFERENCES
ence of affective factors without the participation
Abelson,- R. P. Computer simulation of "hot cognitions."
of cognitive processes. Included here are such In S. Tomkins & S. Mesick (Eds.), Computer simula-
phenomena as perceptual defense and vigilance, tion of personality. New York: Wiley, 1963.
subliminal perception and discrimination, state de- Abelson, R. P., & Rosenberg, M. J. Symbolic psycho-
logic: A model of attitudinal cognition. Behavioral
pendent recall, and mood and context effects. An- Science, 1958, J, 1-13.
other form of unconscious process is implicated in Abelson, R. P., & Sermat, V. Multidimensional scaling
highly overlearned, and thus automated, sequences of facial expressions. Journal of Experimental Psy-
chology, 1962, 63, 546-554.
of information processing; this form includes cog- Anderson, J. R. Language, memory, and thought. Hills-
nitive acts but has collapsed them into larger dale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1976.
molar chunks that may conceal their original com- Anderson, J. R. Arguments concerning representations
for mental imagery. Psychological Review, 1978, 85,
ponent links (cf. Shiffrin & Schneider, 1977). And 249-277.
there may be other forms of process in which the Anderson, J. R., & Bower, G. H. Human associative
separation between affect and cognition prevents memory. Washington, D.C.: Winston, 1973.
Anderson, N. H., & Hubert, S. Effects of concomitant
the individual from apprehending the potential verbal recall on order effects in personality impression
connection between them. formation. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Be-
Because the language of my paper has been havior, 1963, 2, 379-391.
Argyle, M., Salter, V., Nicholson, H., Williams, M., &
stronger than can be justified by the logic of the Burgess, P. The communication of inferior and su-
argument or the weight of the evidence, I hasten perior attitudes by verbal and non-verbal signals.
to affirm that one of my purposes was to convince British Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 1970,
9, 222-231.
you that affect should not be treated as unalter- Averill, J. R. Autonomic response patterns during sad-
ably last and invariably postcognitive. The evo- ness and mirth. Psychophysiology, 1969, S, 399-414.
lutionary origins of affective reactions that point Baddeley, A. D. The trouble with levels: A re-examina-
tion of Craik and Lockhart's framework for memory
to their survival value, their distinctive freedom research. Psychological Review, 1978, 85, 139-152.
from attentive control, their speed, the importance Banks, W. P., & Flora, J. Semantic and perceptual pro-
of affective discriminations for the individual, the cesses in symbolic comparisons. Journal of Experi-
mental Psychology: Human Perception and Perform-
extreme forms of action that affect can recruit— ance, 1977, 3, 278-290.
all of these suggest something special about affect. Bartlett, F. C. Remembering: A study in experimental
People do not get married or divorced, commit and social psychology. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press, 1932.
murder or suicide, or lay down their lives for free- Berlyne, D. E. Arousal and reinforcement. In D. Le-
dom upon a detailed cognitive analysis of the pros vine (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation (Vol.
15). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1967.
and cons of their actions. If we stop to consider Berlyne, D. E. Novelty, complexity, and hedonic value.
just how much variance in the course of our lives Perception and Psychophysics, 1970, 8, 279-286.
Berlyne, D. E. Dimensions of perception of exotic and
is controlled by cognitive processes and how much pre-renaissance paintings. Canadian Journal of Psy-
by affect, and how much the one and the other chology, 1975, 29, 151-173.

172 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


Berscheid, E., & Walster, E. Interpersonal attraction. Carlston (Eds.), Person memory. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erl-
Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1978. baum, in press.
Blum, G. S., & Harbour, J. S. Selective inattention to Harrison, A. A. Response competition, frequency, ex-
anxiety-linked stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psy- ploratory behavior, and liking. Journal of Personality
chology: General, 1979, 108, 182-224. and Social Psychology, 1968, 0, 363-368.
Bobrow, D. G., & Collins, A. Representation and under- Harrison, A. A. Mere exposure. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.),
standing. New York: Academic Press, 1975, Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 10),
Bower, G. H., & Karlin, M. B. Depth of processing pic- New York: Academic Press, 1977.
tures of faces and recognition memory. Journal of Ex- Hastorf, A. H., Osgood, C. E,, & Ono, H. The semantics
perimental Psychology, 1974, 103, 751-757. of facial expressions and the prediction of the meanings
Broadbent, D. E. The hidden preattentive processes. of stereoscopically fused facial expressions. Scandinavian
American Psychologist, 1977, 32, 109-118. Journal of Psychology,- 1966, 7, 179-188.
Broadbent, D. E., & Gregory, M. H. P. The perception Heider, F. The psychology of interpersonal relations.
of emotionally toned words. Nature, 1967, 215, 581- New York: Wiley,-1958.
584. Hintzman, D. L. Repetition and memory. In G. H.
Byrne, D. Interpersonal attraction and attitude simi- Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motiva-
larity. Journal o.f Abnormal and Social Psychology, tion (Vol. 10). New York: Academic Press, 1976.
1961, 62, 713-715.
Howell, W. C. Uncertainty from internal and external
Carmon, A., & Nachson, I. Ear asymmetry in perception
sources: A clear case of overconfidence. Journal of
of emotional non-verbal stimuli. Acta Psychologica, Experimental Psychology, 1971, 89, 240-243.
1973, 37, 351-357.
Howell, W. C. Representation of frequency in memory.
Coombs, C. H. A theory of data. New York: Wiley,
Psychological Bulletin, 1973, 80, 44-53.
1964.
Cooper, L. G. A multivariate investigation of preferences. Hume, D. A treatise on human nature (Vol. 2). Lon-
Multivariate Behavioral Research, 1973, 8, 253-272. don: Longmans, Green, 1898.
Craik, F. I. M., & Lockhart, R. S. Levels of processing: Hyde, T. W., & Jenkins J. J. The differential effects of
A framework for memory research. Journal of Verbal incidental tasks on the organization of recall of a list
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1972, 11, 671-684. of highly associated words. Journal of Experimental
Crowder, R; G. Principles of learning and memory. Psychology, 1969, 82, 472-481.
Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1976. Inhelder, B., & Piaget, J. The growth of logical thinking
Cummings, E. E. Complete poems (Vol. I). Bristol, from childhood to adolescence. New York: Basic Books,
England: McGibbon & Kee, 1973. 1958.
Dawes, R. M., & Kramer, E. A proximity analysis of Ittelson, W. H. Environment perception and contempo-
vocally expressed emotion. Perceptual and Motor Skills, rary perceptual theory. In W. H. Ittelson (Ed.), En-
1966,.22, 571-574, vironment and cognition. New York: Seminar Press,
De Renzi, E., & Spinnler H. Facial recognition in brain- 1973.
damaged patients. Neurology, 1966, 16, 145-152. Izard, C. E. Human emotions. New York: Plenum
Dimond, S. J., Farrington, L., & Johnson, P. Differing Press, 1977.
emotional response from right and left hemisphere. Izard, C. E. On the development of emotions and emo-
Nature, 1976, 261,,690-692. tion-cognition relationship in infancy. In M. Lewis &
Dreben, E. K., Fiske, S, T., & Hastie, R. The. inde- L. Rosenblum (Eds.), The development of affect. New
pendence of evaluative and item information: Impres- York: Plenum Press, 1978.
sion and recall order effects in behavior-based impres- Izard, C. E. Emotions as motivations: An evolutionary-
sion formation. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- developmental perspective. In R. Dienstbier (Ed.),
chology, 1979, 37, 1758-1768. Nebraska Symposium on Motivation (Vol. 27). Lin-
Ekman, P., & Friesen, W. V. The repertoire of nonverbal coln: University of Nebraska Press, 1979.
behavior: Categories, origins, usage, and coding. Semi- Johnston, J. C., & McClelland, J. L. Perception of let-
otica, 1969,1, 49-98. ters: Seek not and ye shall find. Science, 1974, 184,
Erdelyi, M. H. A new look at the New Look: Perceptual 1192-1194,
defense and vigilance. Psychological Review, 1974, 81, Joreskog, K. G., & Sb'rbom, D. Statistical models and
1-25. _ . . methods for analysis of longitudinal data. In D. J. Aig-
Estes, W. K. (Ed.). Handbook of learning and cognitive ner & A. S. Goldberger (Eds.), Latent variables in
. processes (Vols. 1-6). Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1975- socio-economic models. Amsterdam: North-Holland,
1978. 1977.
Festinger, L. Conflict., decision, and dissonance. Stanford, Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. Prospect theory: An anal-
Calif.: Stanford University - Press, 1964. . ysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 1979, 47,
Gainotti, G. Emotional behavior and hemispheric side of 263-291.
the lesion. Cortex, 1972, 8, 41-55. Kcenan, J. M., & Bailett, S. D. Memory for personally
Graham, N., & Nachmias, J. Detection of grating pat- and socially significant events. In R. S. Nickerson
terns containing two spatial frequencies: A comparison (Ed.), Attention and performance VIII. Hillsdale, N.J.:
of single-channel and multiple-channels models. Vision Erlbaum, 1979.
Research, 1971, 11, 251-259. Kerst, S. M., & Howard, J. H., Jr. Mental comparisons
Greenwald, A. G, Cognitive response analysis: An ap- for ordered information on abstract and concrete di-
praisal. In R. E. Petty, T. M. Qstrom, & T. C. Brock mensions. Memory and Cognition, 1977, 5, 227-234.
(Eds.), Cognitive responses in persuasive communica- Kintsch, W. The representation of meaning in memory.
tion. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1980. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1974.
Hamilton, D. L., Katz, L. B., & Leirer, V. 0. Organiza- Klahr, D. Decision making in a complex environment:
tional processes in impression formation. In R. Hastie, The use of similarity judgments to predict preferences,
T. Qstrom, E. Ebbesen, R. Wyer, D. Hamilton, & D. Management Science, 1969, 15, 595-618.

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 173


Kosslyn, S. M., & Pomerantz, J. R. Imagery, proposi- Norman, D. A., & Rumelhart, D. E. Explorations in cog-
tions, and the form of internal representations. Cogni- nition. San Francisco: Freeman, 1975.
tive Psychology, 1977, 9, 52-76. O'Hare, D. Individual differences in perceived similarity
Kunst-Wilson, W. R., & Zajonc, R. B. Affective dis- and preference for visual art: A multidimensional scaling
crimination of stimuli that cannot be recognized. Sci- analysis. Perception & Psychophysics, 1976, 20, 445-452.
ence, 1980, 207, 5S7-SS8. Osgood, C. E. Studies on the generality of affective
Lachman, R., Lachman, J. L., & Butterfield, E. C. Cog- meaning systems. American Psychologist, 1962, 17, 10-
nitive psychology and information processing. Hills- 28.
dale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1979. Osgood, C. E. On the whys and wherefores of E, P, and
Lang, P. J. A bio-informational theory of emotional A. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1969,
imagery. Psychophysiology, 1979, 16, 495-512. 12, 194-199.
Langer, S. K. Mind: An essay on human feeling (Vol. 1). Osgood, C. E., & Tannenbaum, P. H, The principle of
Baltimore, .Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1967. congruity in the prediction of attitude change. Psy-
Ley, R. G., & Bryden, M. P. Hemispheric differences in chological Review, 1955, 62, 42-55.
processing emotions and faces. Brain and Language, Paivio, A. Perceptual comparisons through the mind's
1979, 7, 127-138. eye. Memory and Cognition, 1975, 3, 635-647.
Handler, G. Mind and emotion. New York: Wiley, 1975. Paivio, A. Dual coding: Theoretical issues and empirical
Mandler, G., Handler, J. M., Kremen, I., & Sholiton, evidence. In J. M. Scandura & C. J. Brainerd (Eds.),
R. D. The response to threat: Relations among verbal Structural/process models of complex human behavior.
and physiological indices. Psychological Monographs, Leiden, The Netherlands: Nordhoff, 1978. (a)
1961, 75(9, Whole No. 513). Paivio, A. Images, propositions, and knowledge. In J.
Markus, H. Self-schemata and processing of information M. Nicholas (Ed.), Images, perception, and knowledge.
about the self. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science
chology, 1977, 35, 63-78. (No. 8). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel, 1978. (b)
Marshall, J. C., & Newcombe, F. Syntactic and semantic Paivio, A. Mental comparisons involving abstract attri-
errors in paralexia. Neuropsychologia, 1966, 4, 169-176. butes. Memory and Cognition, 1978, 3, 199-208. (c)
Matlin, M. W. Response competition, recognition, and Patterson, K. E., & Baddeley, A. D. When face recogni-
affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, tion fails. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Hu-
1971, 19, 295-300. man Learning and Memory, 1977, 3, 406-417.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. Imitation of facial and Posner, M. L, & Snydcr, C. R. R. Attention and cognitive
manual gestures by human neonates. Science, 1977, 198, control. In R. L. Solso (Ed.), Information processing
75-78. and cognition: The Loyola Symposium. Hillsdale,N.J.:
Miller, G. A., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. Language and Erlbaum, 1975. (a)
perception. Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press of Posner, M. L, & Snyder, C. R. R. Facilitation and in-
Harvard University Press, 1976. hibition in the processing of signals. In P. M. A.
Milner, B. Visual recognition and recall after right Rabbitt & S. Dornic (Eds.), Attention and performance
temporal-lobe excision in man. Neuropsychologia, 1968, V. New York: Academic Press, 1975. (b)
6, 191-209. Pratt, C. L., & Sackett, G. P. Selection of partners as a
Milord, J. T. Aesthetic aspects of faces: A (somewhat) function of peer contact during rearing. Science, 1967,
phenomenological analysis using multidimensional scal- 155, 1133-1135.
ing methods. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- Premack, D. Intelligence in ape and man. Hillsdale,
chology, 1978, .3(5, 205-216. N.J.: Erlbaum, 1976.
Moore, E. F., & Shannon, C. E. Reliable circuits using Proctor, R. W. The relationship of frequency judgments
less reliable relays. Part I. Journal of the Franklin to recognition: Facilitation of recognition and compari-
Institute, 1956, 262, 191-208. son to recognition-confidence judgments. Journal of
Moreland, R. L., & Zajonc, R. B. Is stimulus recognition Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Mem-
a necessary condition for the occurrence of exposure ory, 1977, 3, 679-689.
effects? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Proctor, R. W., & Ambler, B, A. Effects of rehearsal
1977, 35, 191-199. strategy on memory for spacing and frequency. Jour-
Moreland, R. L., & Zajonc, R. B. Exposure effects may nal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and
not depend on stimulus recognition. Journal of Per- Memory, 1975, 1, 640-647.
sonality and Social Psychology, 1979, 37, 1085-1089. Pylyshyn, Z. W. What the mind's eye tells the mind's
Moscovitch, M., Scullion, D., & Christie, D. Early versus brain: A critique of mental imagery. Psychological
late stage of processing and their relation to functional Bulletin, 1973, 80, 1-24.
hemispheric asymmetries in face recognition. Journal of Quandt, R. E. A probabilistic theory of consumer be-
Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Per- havior. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1956, 70, 507-
formance, 1976, 2, 401-416. 536.
Nakashima, T. Contribution to the study of the affective Riskey, D. R. Verbal memory process in impression
processes. American Journal of Psychology, 1909, 20, formation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Hu-
157-193. (a) man Learning and Memory, 1979, 5, 271-281.
Nakashima, T. Time-relations of the affective process. Rogers, T. B., Kuipcr, N. A., & Kirker, W. S. Self-refer-
Psychological Review, 1909, 16, 303-339. (b) ence and the encoding of personal information. Journal
Neisser, U. Cognitive psychology. Englewood Cliffs, of Personality and Social Psychology, 1977, 35, 677-688.
N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1967. Ross, L., Lepper, M. R., & Hubbard, M. Perseverance in
Neisser, U. Cognition and reality. San Francisco: Free- self-perception and social perception: Biased attribu-
man, 1976. tional processes in the debriefing paradigm. Journal of
Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. Telling more than we Personality and Social Psychology, 1975, 32, 880-892.
can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psycho- Rubin, Z. Liking and loving. New York: Holt, Rine-
logical Review, 1977, 84, 231-259. hart & Winston, 1973.

174 • FEBRUARY 1980 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST


Sadalla, E. K,, & Lo.ftness, S. Emotional images as medi- facial recognition memory. Bulletin of the Psyc/ionomic
ators, in one-trial paired-associates learning. Journal of Society, 1977, 9, 17-18.
Experimental Psychology, 1972, 95, 295-298. Suberi, M., & McKeever, W. F. Differential right hemi-
Safer, N. A., & Leventhal, H. Ear differences in evaluat- spheric memory storage of emotional and non-emotional
ing emotional tones of voice and verbal content. Jour- faces. Nemopsychologia, 1977, 15, 757-768.
nal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Titchener, E. B. A textbook of psychology. New York:
Performance, 1977, 3, 75-82. Macmillan, 1910.
Sartre, J. P. Existentialism. New York: Philosophical Tomkins, S. S. Affect, imagery, consciousness: Vol. 1.
Library, 1947. The positive affects. New York: Springer, 1962.
Schachter, S,, & Singer, J. Cognitive, social, and physio- Tomkins, S. S. Affect, imagery, consciousness: Vol. 2.
logical determinants of emotional state. Psychological The negative affects. New York: Springer, 1963.
Review, 1962, 65, 379-399. Trevarthen, C. B. Two mechanisms of vision in primates.
Schank, R. C., & Abelson, R. P. Scripts, plans, goals, and Psychologische Forschimg, 1968, 31, 299-337.
understanding. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1977. Tulving, E., & Donaldson, VV. Organization oj memory.
Scherer, K. R., Koivumaki, J., & Rosenthal, R, Minimal New York: Academic Press, 1972.
cues in the vocal, communication of affect: Judging emo- Vitz, P. C. Preferences for rates of information presented
tions from content-masked speech. Journal of Psycho- by sequences of tones. Journal of Experimental Psy-
linguistic Research, 1972, 1, 269-285. chology, 1964, 68, 176-183.
Schneider, D. J., Hastorf, A. H., & Ellsworth, P. C. Per- Warrington, E. K., & Ackroyd, C. The effect of orienting
son perception. Reading, Mass.; Addison-Wesley, 1979. tasks on recognition memory. Memory and Cognition,
Schwartz, G. E., Davidson, R. J., & Maer, F. Right 1975, 3, 140-142.
hemisphere lateralization for emotion in the human Wells, J. E. Strength theory and judgments of recency
brain: Interactions with cognition. Science, 1975, 190, and frequency. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
286-288. Behavior, 1974, 13, 378-392.
Schwartz, G. E., Fair, P. L., Salt, P., Mandel, M. R., & Wilson, W. R. Unobtrusive induction of positive attitudes.
Klerman, G. L. Facial muscle patterning to affective Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Michi-
imagery in depressed and nondepressed subjects. Sci- gan, 1975.
ence, 1976, 192, 489-491. Wilson, W. R. Feeling more than we can know: Expo-
Shepard, R. N. The mental image. American Psycholo- sure effects without learning. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 1979, 37, 811-821.
gist, 1978, 33, 125-137.
Wundt, W. Grundriss der Psychologic. Leipzig: Wilhelm
Shevrin, H., & Fritzler, D. E. Visual evoked response Engelmann, 1905.
correlates of unconscious mental process. Science, 1968, Wundt, W. Outlines of psychology. Leipzig: Wilhelm
161, 295-298. Englemann, 1907.
Shevrin, H., Smith, W. H., & Fritzler, D. E. Average Yntema, D. B., & Torgerson, W. S. Man-computer co-
evoked response and verbal correlates of unconscious operation in decision requiring common sense. IRE
mental processes. Psychophysiology, 1971, S, 149-162. Transactions of the Professional Group on Human Fac-
Shiffrin, R. M., & Schneider, W. Controlled and auto- tors in Electronics 1961, Vol. HRE-2, No. 1, 20-26.
matic human information processing: II. Perceptual Zajonc, R. B. Cognitive structure and cognitive tuning.
learning, automatic attending, and a general theory. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Michi-
Psychological Review, 1977, 84, 127-190. gan, 1955.
Smoke, W. H., & Zajonc, R. B. On the reliability of Zajonc, R. B. Attitudinal effects of mere exposure. Jour-
group judgments and decisions. In J. Criswell, H. Solo- nal of Personality and Social Psychology Monograph,
mon, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Mathematic methods in small 1968, 9 ( 2 , Part 2, 1-28).
group process. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Zajonc, R. B., & Smoke, W. H. Redundancy in task as-
Press, 1962. . signment and group performance. Psychometrika, 1959,
Strnad, B. N., & Mueller, J, H. Levels of processing in 24, 361-369.

AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • FEBRUARY 1980 • 175

You might also like