You are on page 1of 8

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/295258158

Objectivity in Moral Discourse

Chapter · December 2006


DOI: 10.1016/B0-08-044854-2/01266-9

CITATIONS READS

2 216

1 author:

Mark Timmons
The University of Arizona
72 PUBLICATIONS   1,063 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Moral Phenomenology View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Mark Timmons on 13 September 2019.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Provided for non-commercial research and educational use only.
Not for reproduction or distribution or commercial use

This article was originally published in the Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics,
Second Edition, published by Elsevier, and the attached copy is provided by Elsevier
for the author's benefit and for the benefit of the author's institution, for non-
commercial research and educational use including without limitation use in
instruction at your institution, sending it to specific colleagues who you know, and
providing a copy to your institution’s administrator.

All other uses, reproduction and distribution, including without limitation commercial
reprints, selling or licensing copies or access, or posting on open internet sites, your
personal or institution’s website or repository, are prohibited. For exceptions,
permission may be sought for such use through Elsevier's permissions site at:

http://www.elsevier.com/locate/permissionusematerial

Timmons M (2006), Objectivity in Moral Discourse. In: Keith Brown, (Editor-in-


Chief) Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics, Second Edition, volume 9, pp. 5-10.
Oxford: Elsevier.
Objectivity in Moral Discourse 5

McDowell J (1986). ‘Singular thought and the extent of Russell B (1912). The problems of philosophy. Oxford:
inner space.’ In Pettit P & McDowell J (eds.) Subject, Oxford University Press.
thought and context. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Russell B (1918). ‘The philosophy of logical atomism.’
McDowell J (1991). ‘Intentionality de re.’ In Lepore & Van Monist 28, 495–527. Reprinted in Russell B (1956).
Gulick (eds.). Logic and knowledge London: George Allen and Unwin.
Noonan H (1986). ‘Russellian thoughts and methodologi- Schiffer S (1978). ‘The basis of reference.’ Erkenntnis 13,
cal solipsism.’ In Butterfield J (ed.) Language, mind, and 171–206.
logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Searle J (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge
Noonan H (1991). ‘Object-dependent thoughts and psy- University Press.
chological redundancy.’ Analysis 51, 1–9. Searle J (1991). ‘Response: reference and intentionality.’ In
Russell B (1910–1911). ‘Knowledge by acquaintance and Lepore & Van Gulick (eds.).
knowledge by description.’ Proceedings of the aristote- Segal G (1989). ‘The return of the individual.’ Mind 98,
lian society, new series 11, 108–128. [Reprinted in Mys- 39–57.
ticism and logic. London: George Allen and Unwin,
1917.]

y
op
C
Objectivity in Moral Discourse
M Timmons, University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ, USA Convergence: Ideally, use of the proper methods of
inquiry (which may differ from discourse to dis-

al
ß 2006 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
course) may be expected to lead individuals (at least
under suitably ideal conditions) to converge in a great
Does moral discourse purport to be objective? If
on many of their judgments about the subject matter of
so, can its objectivist pretensions be justified? Rough- the discourse in question.
ly speaking, to say that some form of discourse is
rs
Discourse satisfying these four theses involves sen-
objective is to say that there is a single set of truths
tences that are (or may be) objectively true and
about whatever subject matter the discourse is about.
hence we may say that the discourse itself is objective.
Pe

We can make this rough characterization more


Of course, it is possible for some realm of discourse to
precise by formulating a number of related theses –
feature claims that purport to be objectively true
objectivity theses – that collectively capture this idea
but fail to be so because one or more of the above
of objectivity:
theses fail to hold in relation to the discourse in
's

Cognitivism: Declarative sentences of the discourse question – a possibility to which we shall return
in question are used by speakers to make genuine below.
or

assertions and function mainly to express the speak- Moral objectivism, then, at least as it is commonly
er’s beliefs. Given that (sincere) belief and assertion understood by philosophers, is the view that all four
aim at representing what is true, such sentences are theses hold in relation to moral discourse: not only
th

capable of being true or false. does moral discourse purport to be objective, it satis-
Truth: Some affirmative sentences of the discourse fies the objectivity requirements in question and thus
Au

are true. some moral judgments are objectively true. Some-


Independence: What makes some sentence of the times this is put by saying that there is a single true
discourse true is that it corresponds to some fact – morality. As we shall see, some philosophers have
where the existence and nature of the specific fact to denied one or more of the four theses in relation
which the sentence corresponds is independent of the to moral discourse and thus denied that morality is
attitudes and beliefs that individuals and groups have objective.
toward the fact in question. It is common to use the Determining whether moral objectivism is correct
word ‘stance’ to refer to the beliefs and attitudes of requires an examination of fundamental philosophical
individuals and groups, so using this terminology we questions about the meaning, truth, and justification
may express the independence thesis by saying that of moral judgments – questions central to that branch
for the discourse in question there is a stance-inde- of ethics called ‘meta-ethics.’ But it also requires an
pendent reality (realm of facts) that the discourse is examination of the very notion of objectivity. And
about, and the facts comprising that reality are what here we find two models of objectivity. One of them
make certain sentences of that discourse true. is inspired by discourse about the physical world

Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics (2006), vol. 9, pp. 5–10


6 Objectivity in Moral Discourse

(including ordinary nonscientific discourse about the inquirers, using proper methods of inquiry, to con-
world as well as scientific discourse) and which I will verge in their beliefs about this realm of objective fact
refer to as the model of ‘ontological objectivity’ – so since their inquiries are being constrained by an
called because the central idea is that there is an objective, stance-independent reality.
ontological realm of ‘really’ existing objects and
properties that sentences from a particular discourse Ontological Objectivity and Moral
purport to be about and which serve to make true Discourse
certain of those sentences. An alternate, more modest
form of objectivity, which I will call ‘methodological Does moral discourse have the trappings of ontolog-
objectivity,’ is less focused on matters of ontology and ically objective discourse? Indeed, is it a form of
more focused on methods of reasoning that govern descriptive discourse – discourse about a special sub-
the discourse in question. ject matter, but nevertheless a discourse that is prop-
In what follows, we begin with a brief characteri- erly interpreted as representing a realm of objective
zation of the ontological model of objectivity and moral facts? Those who think so often point to a

y
then proceed in the next four sections to consider number of ‘markers’ – features that are deeply em-

op
some of the evidence for and controversy about bedded in moral thought and discourse – that either
whether moral discourse is ontologically objective. reflect or at least seem to support the various objec-
After reviewing the pros and cons of the claim that tivity theses. Let us consider some of them in more
detail.

C
moral discourse is ontologically objective, we turn to
the second model of objectivity – a model that pro- Grammatical and Semantic Markers
mises to make sense of objectivity without ontology.

al
Perhaps the most obvious markers of objectivity con-
cern matters of grammar and semantics.
Ontological Objectivity
In meta-ethical discussion over the objectivity of
on O1: Moral sentences such as ‘John’s lying to
Brenda was wrong,’ in which a moral term appears,
moral discourse, discourse about ordinary common-
are in the indicative mood and are used to make
sense objects and their properties as well as scien-
rs
genuine assertions that express a (sincere) speaker’s
tific discourse – often referred to as descriptive
beliefs.
discourse – is taken to be paradigmatic of objec-
O2: Moreover, because moral sentences are typi-
Pe

tive discourse. Roughly, the idea is that descriptive


cally used to make assertions they are truth apt: they
discourse is (or at least purports to be) about a realm
are candidates for semantic evaluation in terms
of objects and properties in certain combinations
of their truth and falsity. Sentences which predicate
(facts) whose nature and existence is independent of
the truth or falsity of a moral sentence seem to
's

our beliefs, conventions, attitudes, and other mental


make perfect sense (e.g., ‘It is true that John’s
stances we might take toward those facts. Here, the
lying to Brenda is morally wrong,’ ‘It is false that
or

emphasis is on considerations of ontology – on what


contraception is morally wrong,’ and so on).
exists – hence the label ‘ontological objectivity.’ More-
O3: Moreover, logically simple moral sentences
over, the ontological objectivist typically embraces a
th

(e.g., ‘It is wrong to steal’) can embed in all sorts of


strong form of the independence thesis, viz.,
logically complex grammatical constructions, most
What makes some sentence true is that it corresponds to notably truth-functional and quantificational con-
Au

some sort of stance-independent fact – where the exis- structions (e.g., ‘If it is wrong to steal, then it is
tence and nature of the fact in question is independent of wrong to encourage others to steal.’) It would seem
the actual and ideal stances of individuals or groups. that such logically complex sentences have truth
The significance of this thesis of strong independence values that are determined by the truth values of
(SI) will emerge later on when we turn to methodo- their simpler constituents.
logical objectivity.
So the model of ontological objectivity (using Ontological Markers
descriptive discourse about objects and properties in
The following two markers have to do with the
the world as an example) clearly involves the first
ontological status of the subject matter of moral
three objectivity theses: descriptive discourse serves
discourse.
to express beliefs (cognitivism), some of which are
true (truth) when they correspond to stance-indepen- O4: Moral terms that appear in moral sentences
dent facts (independence). Barring epistemological (e.g., ‘good,’ ‘right,’ ‘virtuous,’ and their opposites)
skepticism, we may also expect suitably motivated seem to be used to denote properties that are (or may

Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics (2006), vol. 9, pp. 5–10


Objectivity in Moral Discourse 7

be) possessed by items of moral evaluation. For ex- But ontological moral objectivism is controversial:
ample, to say of an action that it is wrong appears we find a variety of meta-ethical positions that deny
to attribute the property of wrongness to the action. one or more of the four objectivist theses and among
Furthermore, some moral sentences are used with the moral objectivists we find a variety of specific meta-
apparent intention of picking out moral properties ethical positions that differ over questions of seman-
and talking about them, as when one utters the sen- tics, metaphysics, and epistemology in relation to
tence ‘It was the badness of the practice of American moral discourse. Let us now briefly survey some of
slavery that eventually led to its abolishment.’ these positions.
O5: Moral truth and moral error are genuine pos-
sibilities. When we disagree over some moral issue,
we take ourselves to be engaged in a genuine dispute Moral Realism
where not all parties to the dispute are correct in their
One very straightforward way to accommodate
moral convictions. What is apparently being assumed
O1–O6 is simply to affirm the four objectivist theses
in such disagreements is that there is a fact of the

y
and, in particular, the idea that there is a realm of
matter about the issue in dispute – that there is an
moral properties (and moral facts) that are strongly

op
objective truth about the matter. This makes it natu-
independent of our attitudes and beliefs about them
ral to think that the truth (or falsity) of a moral
and which serve as an objective basis for the truth and
sentence is a matter of its correspondence (or lack
falsity of moral sentences. This meta-ethical position

C
of correspondence) to some moral fact. The puta-
is known as moral realism and the task of this kind of
tive fact that an action is wrong (supposing it is)
realist view is to explain what sorts of fact serve as
would seem to be what makes true a sentence
truth makers for moral judgments and how it is pos-

al
expressing this fact. Moral error results when what
sible to have justified belief and perhaps knowledge
one says or believes fails to properly record moral
of moral truths. Ontological naturalists, who are
reality.
on moral realists (Sturgeon, 1984; Railton, 1986, 1996;
Boyd, 1988; Brink, 1989; Bloomfield, 2001), claim
Epistemological Marker
that moral properties and facts are identical to certain
rs
Finally, the following marker has to do with matters natural properties and facts – properties and facts
of justification and knowledge. that are the proper subject matter for empirical sci-
ence to investigate. In the history of meta-ethical
Pe

O6: We dispute moral claims by offering reasons


inquiry, we find various attempts by philosophers to
for their truth or falsity and thus take such claims as
‘reduce’ moral properties and facts to some species
being susceptible to justification. One can be justified
of biological, psychological, or sociological fact.
or unjustified in claiming that John’s action was mor-
For instance, Spencer (1895) held that the property
's

ally wrong depending on one’s evidence for the claim –


of being better than, which he took to be basic in
evidence that can be offered, disputed, and discussed
ethics, could be reduced to the property of being
or

with others. Moreover, in some cases we at least


more highly evolved. Ontological nonnaturalists in
suppose that we have some moral knowledge. Surely
ethics (Moore, 1903; Ross, 1930; Shafer-Landau,
we take ourselves to know that torturing puppies for
th

2003) hold that moral properties and facts are of


fun is morally wrong. Since justification and knowl-
a special nonnatural kind; that rightness, for exam-
edge in ethics (as elsewhere) seems to require that
ple, is not identical to any natural property, but is
Au

there be reliable methods of inquiry suitable to the


nonetheless a real property.
form of inquiry, one would expect there to be a moral
Naturalist realists face the challenge of explaining
methodology that would enable inquirers using it to
why some specific set of natural properties and facts
reach a high level of interpersonal convergence in
is identical to moral properties and facts. This in turn
moral belief.
would seem to require a plausible semantic account
Thus, moral discourse, at least at first glance, of moral judgments that fits with naturalist real-
seems to possess all of the characteristic marks of ism, something which has proved difficult to do.
objectivity – indeed ontological objectivity. Many Nonnaturalists, by contrast, propose to bloat our
philosophers go one step further and claim that ontological commitments: in addition to being meta-
moral discourse is genuinely ontologically objective physically committed to those entities in the natural
and that moral discourse is a kind of descriptive world that common sense and natural science com-
discourse whose primary function is to represent a mits us to, the nonnaturalist wants to add a realm of
realm of moral facts. nonnatural properties and facts. Such metaphysical

Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics (2006), vol. 9, pp. 5–10


8 Objectivity in Moral Discourse

extravagance has been met with strong resistance ‘repaying one’s debts is morally right’ purports to attri-
from philosophers who think that such properties bute the property of moral rightness to the activity of
and facts are mysterious metaphysical accretions repaying debts, but since there are no such moral prop-
and that there are serious epistemological worries erties this sentence and all affirmative moral sentences
accompanying any such view. (taken literally) are false.
Finally, versions of moral relativism (Harman,
Denying Ontological Objectivity in Moral 1984; Wong, 1984) typically affirm the theses of
cognitivism and truth, but maintain that moral truth
Discourse
is not independent of the attitudes of individuals
Some philosophers deny moral objectivism because and groups. Rather, for a typical relativist, what
they deny the thesis of cognitivism in relation to makes a moral claim true is that some group accepts
moral discourse. They claim that although the surface some set of moral principles and these principles are
grammar strongly suggests that moral judgments ex- the very standard (for that group) that determine
press beliefs and thus are used to make truth-apt asser- (together with nonmoral facts) which further moral

y
tions, nevertheless all of this is misleading. Rather, sentences are true. The idea is that the sentences

op
according to the meta-ethical position known as expressing moral principles are counted as true in
noncognitivism (Stevenson, 1937, 1944; Ayer, 1946) virtue of being accepted by some group and the
and more recently as expressivism (Gibbard, 1990, more specific moral sentences that (together with

C
2003; Blackburn, 1993, 1998; Horgan and Timmons, nonmoral facts) follow from these principles express
2006), moral judgments are not really in the business derivative moral truths. So, if some group accepts as a
of expressing beliefs that purport to represent or de- basic moral principle that eating meat is morally

al
scribe moral facts; rather they instead function to wrong, then the sentence ‘Eating meat is wrong’ is
express some noncognitive attitude toward the object true – relative to their moral outlook. If some animal
of evaluation. Thus, for instance, according to emoti-
on (or its remains) is as a matter of fact meat, then this
vism (one kind of noncognitivism), uttering a sentence fact together with the general moral principle in ques-
such as ‘Abortion is wrong’ really functions primarily tion implies specific moral truths about eating this or
to express one’s negative feeling toward abortion and that animal or its remains. Now, if some other indi-
rs
is roughly equivalent to saying, ‘Abortion: boo!’ So, vidual or group does not have any such principle
the noncognitivist denies both the theses of cogniti- against meat eating, or has a principle that requires
Pe

vism and truth (in relation to moral discourse) and eating meat, then the sentence ‘Eating meat is wrong’
hence denies the independence and convergence theses is false – relative to their outlook. Thus, for the rela-
as well. What makes this view fairly radical is that it tivist, conflicting moral sentences may be equally
distinguishes between the surface trappings of moral true.
's

discourse and its true, deep semantic working, and There is a variety of ways to develop this basic rela-
claims that a proper semantic interpretation of the tivist idea, but all of them are committed to denying
or

discourse reveals that it really does not even purport the idea that there is some realm of moral fact that is
to be objective, that, to repeat, moral sentences are not independent of the stances of individuals and groups; in
really used in thought and discourse to express beliefs short, for the moral relativist, there is no single true
th

capable of being true or false. objective morality.


A slightly less radical view, the error theory (Mackie, Noncognitivism, the error theory, and relativism
Au

1977), maintains that although moral discourse is have their able defenders, but of course embracing
properly interpreted as at least purporting to be objec- one of these positions means having to claim either
tive, its various objective pretensions result from mas- that at least some of the various objectivist markers
sive error. More precisely, the error theorist accepts the (O1–O6) are illusory – not really characteristic of
thesis of cognitivism in relation to moral discourse, but the discourse – or that they are genuine but deeply
denies the thesis of independence and so denies the error ridden. Such views strike many philosophers as
claim that affirmative moral sentences are ever objec- meta-ethical options we should try to avoid in making
tively true. This position is analogous to atheism. That sense of moral thought and discourse (Wright, 1992;
is, an atheist holds that religious discourse involving Timmons, 1999).
affirmative claims about God or gods purports to be
objectively true, but, claims the atheist, there are no Methodological Objectivism
theological facts of the relevant sort that can make true
affirmative claims about God or gods, and so no such In light of the metaphysical and epistemological pro-
claims are objectively true. The error theorist in ethics blems that beset realist (ontological) accounts of
is saying something similar. The moral judgment moral objectivity, some philosophers are attracted to

Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics (2006), vol. 9, pp. 5–10


Objectivity in Moral Discourse 9

a different model of objectivity – a model that looks modest form of this thesis in contrast to the strong
to the realm of mathematics and logic for a way form embraced by the ontological objectivist:
of understanding how moral discourse can be objec-
Although the truth of a moral sentence is independent
tive even if there are no dedicated moral properties
of the stances of actual individuals and groups, moral
and facts (of the sort associated with ordinary de-
truth is ultimately constituted by the stances of ideal
scriptive discourse) that would serve as truth-makers individuals or groups – call them ‘ideal stances.’
for moral sentences. Such meta-ethical views are
often called ‘constructivist.’ A central idea behind Granted, some moral constructivists introduce
versions of moral constructivism, then, is that just as ontological talk of moral properties and facts at this
we need not suppose that there is a mystical realm of point (Rawls, 1980; Scanlon, 1998), understanding
numbers and mathematical relations that make cer- such properties and facts to be ‘constructions’
tain mathematical sentences true, so we need not grounded in facts about moral convergence. But a
make any heavy-duty ontological assumptions in moral constructivist need not make these ontological
making sense of the apparent objectivity of moral claims; she can rest content in emphasizing the impor-

y
discourse (Putnam, 2004). For both sorts of discourse tance of there being a method of moral inquiry that

op
– mathematical and moral – so long as there are would lead all or most ideal agents (agents who are
methods of reasoning governing these types of dis- engaged in moral thinking under ideal circumstances)
course that would lead properly motivated indivi- to converge in a great many of their moral convictions

C
duals to converge in their views on a large enough (Smith, 1994). What the constructivist hopes to do,
number of claims within those areas, then we have a then, is develop a meta-ethical view that satisfies the
proper basis for affirming the objective pretensions of four main objectivist theses without (apparently) hav-

al
both realms. So, in contrast to the ontological model ing to embrace heavy-duty ontological assumptions,
of objectivity that emphasizes an SI thesis, the present onand thereby vindicate the objectivity of moral dis-
model takes the thesis of convergence as central course. In short: moral objectivity without (moral)
to moral objectivity. Let us explore this model in a ontology.
bit more detail. Of course, any constructivist view carries the bur-
Suppose, then, that associated with moral discourse den of spelling out a moral methodology or process of
rs
is a method of moral thought and reasoning that moral reasoning that would lead ideal moral
would (if properly applied) ideally lead to interperson- inquirers to converge in their moral views. The task
Pe

al convergence over a wide range of moral issues; in of doing so poses a seeming dilemma for the moral
other words, suppose the convergence thesis holds for constructivist (Timmons, 2004). On the one hand, if
moral discourse. Then, according to this line of the favored moral methodology that is to be a basis
thought about objectivity, we would have the materi- for moral truth is characterized in morally neutral
's

als to vindicate the other objectivity theses – cogniti- terms, then the constraints on such reasoning will be
vism, truth, and a modest form of independence. How insufficient to lead those following the method to
or

might this view be developed? reach the level of convergence in their moral verdicts
The general constructivist idea is that there are bet- that a vindication of objectivism requires. This would
ter and worse methods of moral thinking – methods mean, according to the constructivist, that there is
th

that involve constraints on moral deliberators and on no objective moral truth about those moral matters
the circumstances in which they deliberate. For regarding which moral methodology fails to yield
Au

instance, according to one variety of constructiv- convergence under ideal conditions. Hence, the
ism, called the ‘ideal observer’ theory (Firth, 1952; view would be committed to a kind of moral error
Carson, 1984), the proper method of moral thinking theory – there is no fact of the matter in relation to a
requires that moral deliberators thinking about a great many moral issues, contrary to what we
certain moral issue must for example have certain suppose. On the other hand, if, in order to make
intellectual virtues and sufficient knowledge of non- the moral methodology yield substantive moral ver-
moral facts to be in a position to arrive at moral dicts, one characterizes the methodology making
verdicts that have the status of being true. But what use of moral assumptions, then relative to one set of
is crucial to the ideal observer view and constructivist moral assumptions the method will yield one set
views generally is that it is the attitudes of ideal obser- of moral ‘truths,’ but relative to a competing set of
vers that constitute or make true certain moral judg- moral assumptions the method will yield a different
ments. So, although the constructivist accepts the and perhaps conflicting set of moral ‘truths.’ But this
independence thesis (in addition to cognitivism, commits the constructivist to moral relativism, which,
truth, and convergence), she embraces the following as we have seen, is at odds with the idea that moral

Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics (2006), vol. 9, pp. 5–10


10 Objectivity in Moral Discourse

discourse is objective – that with respect to a large Hare R M (1993). ‘Objective prescriptions.’ Philosophy 35,
number of moral issues there is a single truth of 1–17.
the matter. Avoiding the error theory and relativism Harman G (1984). ‘Is there a single true morality?’ In
and thereby preserving objectivity is thus the main Copp D & Zimmerman D (eds.). 27–48.
Horgan T & Timmons M (2006). ‘Cognitivist expressi-
challenge for the moral constructivist.
vism.’ In Horgan T & Timmons M (eds.) Meta-ethics
after Moore. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Leiter B (ed.) (2001). Objectivity in law and morals.
Conclusion Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
The issue of moral objectivity, involving, as we have Mackie J L (1977). Ethics: inventing right and wrong. New
seen, semantic, metaphysical, and epistemological York: Penguin.
McNaughton D (1988). Moral vision. Oxford: Blackwell.
issues, is the central topic of meta-ethics. About the
Moore G E (1903). Principia ethica. Oxford: Oxford
objectivity of moral discourse there are two questions University Press.
to be distinguished. First, what sorts of objective Putnam H (2004). Ethics without ontology. Cambridge,

y
features or markers are genuinely possessed by MA: Harvard University Press.
moral discourse? Second, assuming that moral dis- Railton P (1986). ‘Moral realism.’ Philosophical Review

op
course does genuinely possess such markers, how 95, 163–207.
should they be interpreted? In particular, do they Railton P (1996). ‘Moral realism: prospects and problems.’
require, for their vindication, some version of moral In Sinnott-Armstrong W & Timmons M (eds.) Moral

C
objectivism? In response to these questions, we have knowledge? New readings in moral epistemology.
surveyed a number of currently debated meta-ethical Oxford: Oxford University Press. 48–81.
options, including two conceptions of objectivity. Rawls J (1980). ‘Kantian constructivism in ethics.’ Journal

al
of Philosophy 77, 512–572.
Ross W D (1930). The right and the good. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Bibliography
on Scanlon T (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge,
Ayer A J (1946). Language, truth and logic (2nd edn.). New MA: Harvard University Press.
York: Dover. Shafer-Landau R (2003). Moral realism: a defence. Oxford:
rs
Blackburn S (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. Oxford: Ox- Oxford University Press.
ford University Press. Smith M (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.
Spencer H (1895). The principles of ethics (2 vols). New
Pe

Blackburn S (1998). Ruling passions. Oxford: Oxford Uni-


versity Press. York: Appleton.
Bloomfield P (2001). Moral reality. Oxford: Oxford Uni- Stevenson C L (1937). ‘The emotive meaning of ethical
versity Press. terms.’ Mind 46, 14–31.
Boyd R (1988). ‘How to be a moral realist.’ In Sayre- Stevenson C L (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven:
's

McCord G (ed.) Essays on moral realism. Ithaca, NY: Yale University Press.
Cornell University Press. Sturgeon N (1984). ‘Moral explanations.’ In Copp D &
or

Brink D O (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of Zimmerman D (eds.). 49–78.
ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Timmons M (1999). Morality without foundations: a
Carson T (1984). The status of morality. Dordrecht: Reidel. defense of ethical contextualism. New York: Oxford
th

Copp D & Zimmerman D (eds.) (1984). Morality, reason, University Press.


and truth. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield. Timmons M (2004). ‘The limits of moral constructivism.’
In Stratton-Lake P (ed.) On what we owe to each other.
Au

Dworkin R (1996). ‘Objectivity and truth: you’d better


believe it.’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, 87–139. Oxford: Blackwell. 90–122.
Firth R (1952). ‘Ethical absolutism and the ideal observer.’ Wong D (1984). Moral relativity. Berkeley/Los Angeles:
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12, 317–345. University of California Press.
Gibbard A (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings. Cambridge, Wright C (1992). Truth and objectivity. Cambridge, MA:
MA: Harvard University Press. Harvard University Press.
Gibbard A (2003). Thinking how to live. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.

Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics (2006), vol. 9, pp. 5–10

View publication stats

You might also like